메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 30, Issue 1, 2011, Pages 1-50

What is Tort Law For? Part 1. The Place of Corrective Justice

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 78649909352     PISSN: 01675249     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1007/s10982-010-9086-6     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (169)

References (100)
  • 1
    • 0004106103 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • The Idea of Private Law (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1995), p.4.
    • (1995) The Idea of Private Law , pp. 4
  • 2
    • 0038751705 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • The Practice of Principle (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001), p. 3.
    • (2001) The Practice of Principle , pp. 3
  • 3
    • 78649908055 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Justifications and Reasons'
    • (Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • See my 'Justifications and Reasons', in Gardner, Offences and Defences (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007).
    • (2007) Gardner, Offences and Defences
  • 4
    • 78649908680 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Strictly speaking, justification is but one type of rational explanation. The other type is excuse. Rational explanation is in turn but one type of teleological explanation. Non-rational but teleological explanations include the explanation of plant behaviour as phototropic. Plants are goaloriented creatures with no rationality, and hence the goals of which are not open to rational scrutiny. Teleological explanations are in turn a sub-class of causal explanations, using 'causal' in its broad Aristotelian sense. Often, however, 'causal' is used in a narrow sense to refer only to those broadly causal explanations that are non-teleological. Causal explanations in this narrow sense do not cite a goal to be achieved in the future but an explanatory factor in the past. Many errors in many fields of inquiry come of (a) recasting rational explanations as causal in the narrow sense or (b) treating 'functional' explanation as a tertium quid between rational explanation and causal explanation in the narrow sense, when there is no such tertium quid.
  • 5
    • 78649904085 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'The Purity and Priority of Private Law'
    • See John Gardner, 'The Purity and Priority of Private Law', University of Toronto Law Journal 46 (1996), 459-464.
    • (1996) University of Toronto Law Journal , vol.46 , pp. 459-464
    • Gardner, J.1
  • 7
    • 78649906147 scopus 로고
    • 'Efficiency, Utility, and Wealth Maximisation'
    • Coleman, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • 'Efficiency, Utility, and Wealth Maximisation', in Coleman, Markets, Morals and the Law (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988), 95 at 359, no. 64.
    • (1988) Markets, Morals and The Law , vol.95 , Issue.64 , pp. 359
  • 10
    • 78649903236 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • above footnote
    • The Idea of Private Law, above footnote 1, p. 212.
    • The Idea of Private Law , vol.1 , pp. 212
  • 12
    • 78649903337 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Coleman too dubs them 'functionalists', meaning roughly the same by that as Weinrib does: The Practice of Principle, above footnote 2, 13ff.
    • The Practice of Principle , vol.2
  • 13
    • 78649906225 scopus 로고
    • Note
    • See his 'Prolegomenon to the Principles of Punishment', in Hart, Punishment and Responsibility (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1968).
    • (1968)
  • 14
    • 78649905927 scopus 로고
    • Note
    • This is the thesis that Anthony Quinton was groping towards in 'On Punishment', Analysis 14 (1954), 512.
    • (1954) Analysis , vol.14 , pp. 512
  • 15
    • 78649903643 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • I am grateful to Les Green for helping me to see how my earlier (more unreservedly Humean) understanding of the domain of justice was too narrow in this respect. Green discusses the issue in his so-far unpublished paper 'The Germ of Justice'.
  • 17
    • 0004244925 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • For elaboration of these points see my critical introduction to the second edition of Hart's Punishment and Responsibility (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2008), at xxiv-vi.
    • (2008) Punishment and Responsibility
  • 18
    • 78649904627 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Where the possible answers include 'all of it' and 'none of it'. I spell this out to avoid a misunderstanding that arose in conversation with Ben Zipursky. Ben thought that, if Jones is convicted and punished for Smith's crime, this is not, on my account, an injustice. Why? Because there is no question of how much punishment Jones, as opposed to Smith, should get. But I say there is such a question. There must be such a question because there is an answer: Jones should get is none of it whereas Smith should get all of it. Jones' punishment, in other words, was misallocated to Smith.
  • 19
    • 78649907175 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • EN 1130b30ff
    • EN 1130b30ff.
  • 20
    • 0004048289 scopus 로고
    • This is Rawls' point in, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • This is Rawls' point in A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971), pp. 314-315.
    • (1971) A Theory of Justice , pp. 314-315
  • 21
    • 34447388676 scopus 로고
    • Retributive Punishment
    • Note
    • Some, taking the point for granted, try to preserve the Aristotelian dichotomy by assimilating retributive justice to corrective justice instead. See e.g. J.P. Day, 'Retributive Punishment', Mind 87 (1978), 498.
    • (1978) Mind , vol.87 , pp. 498
    • Day, J.P.1
  • 22
    • 4043121443 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Virtue of Justice and the Character of Law
    • I replied with a qualified 'yes' in
    • I replied with a qualified 'yes' in 'The Virtue of Justice and the Character of Law', Current Legal Problems 53 (2000), 1.
    • (2000) Current Legal Problems , vol.53 , pp. 1
  • 23
    • 78649906260 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • EN 1131b12-15
    • EN 1131b12-15.
  • 24
    • 78649907425 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • EN 1132a1-6
    • EN 1132a1-6.
  • 25
    • 33745723696 scopus 로고
    • 'Social Justice and Legal Justice'
    • Cf. Wojciech Sadurski, 'Social Justice and Legal Justice', Law and Philosophy 3 (1984), 329.
    • (1984) Law and Philosophy , vol.3 , pp. 329
    • Sadurski, C.W.1
  • 26
    • 78649904319 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Sadurski argues (at 334ff) that corrective justice collapses into distributive justice. His argument proceeds mainly by reading 'distributive' broadly to mean 'allocative', and hence to include all of justice. (He also errs by stretching corrective justice in the characteristic Thomist way so that it becomes unrecognizable as corrective: see footnote 28 below.).
  • 27
    • 27944441392 scopus 로고
    • 'The Mixed Conception of Corrective Justice'
    • Stephen Perry, 'The Mixed Conception of Corrective Justice', Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy 15 (1992), 917-919
    • (1992) Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy , vol.15 , pp. 917-919
    • Perry, S.1
  • 28
    • 0004153161 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 318
    • Coleman, Risks and Wrongs (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992), pp. 310-311 and 318.
    • (1992) Risks and Wrongs , pp. 310-311
    • Coleman1
  • 29
    • 78649908798 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Departing from the usage of most moral philosophers, Coleman labels this the agent-relative/agentneutral distinction, inviting confusion between (b) and (a).
  • 30
    • 78649908868 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • It is best pursued by thinking first about the role of liability insurance in private law. How can my duties of corrective justice be performed on my behalf by my insurer? Armed with an answer to the question we can begin to see how my duties of corrective justice could also, in default of performance by me or my insurer, be performed on my behalf by my bank or my employer or a bailiff etc., acting with the law's authorization.
  • 31
    • 84927072046 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • I have had an initial stab at thinking about what it means to act on behalf of someone in my 'Some Types of Law', in Douglas Edlin (ed.), Common Law Theory (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007).
    • (2007) Common Law Theory
  • 32
    • 78649904178 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • The most sustained defence of this view is by G.A. Cohen. For a good start,
  • 33
    • 73949126258 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • see his 'If You're an Egalitarian, How Come You're So Rich?', Journal of Ethics 4 (2000), 1, especially the critique of Dworkin at 17-19.
    • (2000) Journal of Ethics , vol.4 , pp. 17-19
  • 34
    • 0004273805 scopus 로고
    • New York: Basic Books
    • Anarchy, State, and Utopia (New York: Basic Books, 1974), pp. 153-155.
    • (1974) Anarchy, State, and Utopia , pp. 153-155
  • 35
    • 0004106103 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • above footnote 9, e.g. at
    • The Idea of Private Law, above footnote 9, e.g. at 64-65.
    • The Idea of Private Law , pp. 64-65
  • 36
    • 78649904215 scopus 로고
    • Note
    • See similarly John Finnis's Thomistic reconstruction of corrective justice as 'commutative justice', in Natural Law and Natural Rights (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1981).
    • (1981)
  • 37
    • 78649908649 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • above footnote
    • Anarchy, State, and Utopia, above footnote 27, pp. 230-231.
    • Anarchy, State, and Utopia , vol.27 , pp. 230-231
  • 38
    • 78649903378 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • I will be discussing whether this should be ruled out in a companion essay entitled 'What is Tort Law For? Part 2: The Place of Distributive Justice'.
  • 39
    • 0031506933 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Justice as Constancy'
    • who denies (e.g. at 569) that unjust acts are analytically objectionable.
    • Cf Matthew Kramer, 'Justice as Constancy', Law and Philosophy 16 (1997), 561 who denies (e.g. at 569) that unjust acts are analytically objectionable.
    • (1997) Law and Philosophy , vol.16 , pp. 561
    • Kramer, C.M.1
  • 40
    • 78649903336 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • ] I say 'occasion' rather than 'cause' to accommodate the huge late-twentieth century extension of personal (as opposed to vicarious) tort liability that was heralded by Dorset Yacht Co. v. Home Office 1970] AC 1004. I tend to think this was a wrong turning in the law - that Dorset Yacht should have been treated as a vicarious liability case - but the argument is irrelevant here.
  • 42
    • 0041931911 scopus 로고
    • The Concept of Corrective Justice in Recent Theories of Tort Law'
    • 'The Concept of Corrective Justice in Recent Theories of Tort Law', Journal of Legal Studies 10 (1981), 187.
    • (1981) Journal of Legal Studies , vol.10 , pp. 187
  • 43
    • 78649904626 scopus 로고
    • The Concept of Corrective Justice in Recent Theories of Tort Law'
    • Ibid, p. 206.
    • (1981) Journal of Legal Studies , vol.10 , pp. 206
  • 44
    • 78649904942 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • above footnote
    • The Idea of Private Law, above footnote 1, p. 110.
    • The Idea of Private Law , vol.1 , pp. 110
  • 46
    • 78649906683 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Tort law could be an expression of some attitude or ideology, which would give it an external end that it serves non-instrumentally.
  • 48
    • 0003740191 scopus 로고
    • On the two types of self-defeatingness, see, Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • On the two types of self-defeatingness, see Derek Parfit, Reasons and Persons (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984), chaps. 1-4.
    • (1984) Reasons and Persons , pp. 1-4
    • Parfit, D.1
  • 50
    • 1642556354 scopus 로고
    • 'Theories of Compensation',
    • emphasis added
    • Robert E. Goodin, 'Theories of Compensation', Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 9 (1989), 56 (emphasis added).
    • (1989) Oxford Journal of Legal Studies , vol.9 , pp. 56
    • Goodin, R.E.1
  • 51
    • 78649905027 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Coleman denies this, dividing the 'restitutionary justice' of unjust enrichment from the truly corrective justice of tort law: Risks and Wrongs, above footnote 24, at 371.
    • Risks and Wrongs , vol.24 , pp. 371
  • 52
    • 78649907951 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Weinrib, by contract, joins me in regarding both tort law and the law of unjust enrichment as sites for the doing of corrective justice: The Idea of Private Law, above footnote 1, pp. 140-141.
    • The Idea of Private Law , vol.1 , pp. 140-141
  • 53
    • 0002310270 scopus 로고
    • Commands and Authoritative Legal Reasons
    • The words are H.L.A. Hart's, from, Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • The words are H.L.A. Hart's, from 'Commands and Authoritative Legal Reasons', in his Essays on Bentham (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1982), p. 254.
    • (1982) Essays On Bentham , pp. 254
  • 54
    • 78649908119 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • above footnote
    • The Idea of Private Law, above footnote 9, p. 76.
    • The Idea of Private Law , vol.9 , pp. 76
  • 55
    • 78649906527 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Again Coleman contents himself with a more modest proposal, viz. that corrective justice 'imposes constraints on what [the torts themselves] can be': The Practice of Principle, above footnote 2, p. 34.
    • The Practice of Principle , vol.2 , pp. 34
  • 56
    • 78649903582 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Coleman's proposal is sound but does not help to answer the objection currently under consideration.
  • 57
    • 85011437017 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'The First Virtue of the Law Courts and the First Virtue of the Law',
    • For searching discussion, see
    • For searching discussion, see Hanoch Sheinman, 'The First Virtue of the Law Courts and the First Virtue of the Law', Legal Theory 13 (2007), 101.
    • (2007) Legal Theory , vol.13 , pp. 101
    • Sheinman, H.1
  • 58
    • 78649907066 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • The 'chilling effect' is most often mentioned in connection with the inhibition of free speech, e.g. by the tort of libel. But the problem is a broader one that afflicts tort law in general, and tort law in particular. For analysis,
  • 59
    • 0009305817 scopus 로고
    • 'Fear, Risk and the First Amendment: Unraveling the "Chilling Effect'
    • see Frederick Schauer, 'Fear, Risk and the First Amendment: Unraveling the "Chilling Effect"', Boston University Law Review 58 (1978), 685.
    • (1978) Boston University Law Review , vol.58 , pp. 685
    • Schauer, F.1
  • 60
    • 80052496954 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Backwards and Forwards with Tort Law',
    • Michael O'Rourke and Joseph Keim-Campbell (eds.), Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
    • In 'Backwards and Forwards with Tort Law', in Michael O'Rourke and Joseph Keim-Campbell (eds.), Law and Social Justice (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2005).
    • (2005) Law and Social Justice
  • 61
    • 78649905836 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • This is the special feature of morality, or at any rate of the morality of justice, championed by G.A. Cohen in his Rescuing Justice and Equality (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2008), part II.
    • (2008) Rescuing Justice and Equality , Issue.PART. II
  • 62
    • 0037646102 scopus 로고
    • 'The Obligation of Reparation'
    • in MacCormick, Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • 'The Obligation of Reparation', in MacCormick, Legal Right and Social Democracy (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1982), p. 212.
    • (1982) Legal Right and Social Democracy , pp. 212
  • 63
    • 78649905425 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • MacCormick is unfortunately distracted by special features of the example - particularly that the breaking of the promise was justified - and is drawn to conclusions somewhat at odds with mine.
  • 64
    • 78649907522 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • e.g. Photo Production Ltd v Securicor Transport Ltd 1980] AC 827 per Lord Diplock at 850. On a more sceptical note, at least in respect of torts, Peter Birks,
  • 66
    • 78649903729 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • This should not be read as a denial of the existence of so-called 'imperfect obligations', here meaning those which leave the obligation-holder with discretion as to the mode of performance. These too are individuated according to the action that they make obligatory. I have an obligation to meet the children out of school. Shall I go by bus or by bicycle? Either way it is the action of meeting the children out of school that is obligatory. The example helps us to see that all obligations are (more or less) imperfect in the relevant sense. I have an obligation to lock the door at 7 p.m. precisely. Shall I do it with my left hand or my right hand? Quickly or slowly? While humming La Marseillaise or not? For a fuller argument,
  • 67
    • 34547258140 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Perfect and Imperfect Obligations'
    • see George Rainbolt, 'Perfect and Imperfect Obligations', Philosophical Studies 98 (2000), 233.
    • (2000) Philosophical Studies , vol.98 , pp. 233
    • Rainbolt, G.1
  • 68
    • 78649908150 scopus 로고
    • Note
    • So substantial performance is only possible, in the common law of contract, when a contract is 'severable': Hoenig v Isaacs [1952] 2 All ER 176.
    • (1952) Hoenig V Isaacs , vol.2 , pp. 176
  • 69
    • 78649903790 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • I endorse Joseph Raz's view according to which the fact that one has an obligation to/is a protected reason to /, meaning a reason to/that is also a reason not to act for at least some reasons not to /. Raz, 'Promises and Obligations', in P.M.S. Hacker and J. Raz (eds.), Law, Morality, and Society (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1977). (The fact that I have an obligation to/is also a categorical reason to/but that feature affects its scope, not its force.).
  • 70
    • 36749009731 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Normative Requirements'
    • Note
    • One important formalization of the difference - he presents it as a difference between reasons and requirements - is that of John Broome in 'Normative Requirements' Ratio 12 (1999), 398. Unfortunately his formalization leads him to the conclusion that being required does not entail having a reason.
    • (1999) Ratio , vol.12 , pp. 398
    • Broome, J.1
  • 71
    • 78649907808 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • I include this caveat because (I tend to think) it is derivatively obligatory to do whatever is both necessary and sufficient to do whatever one already has an obligation to do. To rule out an obligation derived in this way, I am ruling the sufficient acts in the example to be unnecessary. For the problem, if not the solution,
  • 72
    • 0345913879 scopus 로고
    • Practical Inference
    • see A.J. Kenny, 'Practical Inference', Analysis 26 (1966), 65.
    • (1966) Analysis , vol.26 , pp. 65
    • Kenny, A.J.1
  • 73
    • 78649907911 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • I should perhaps say 'an operative reason for action' because it may still serve in the minor or auxiliary premises of a practical syllogism. It may also, of course, serve as a presupposition of another operative reason for action. For example, that I breached an obligation (an operative reason for action after my breach) presupposes that I had an obligation. In such a case I might report just part of the nowoperative reason by saying 'But I had an obligation!'.
  • 74
    • 84927012473 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Personal Practical Conflicts'
    • Note
    • My earlier interpretation of the continuity thesis, in previous drafts of this paper and elsewhere, was much improved by reading Joseph Raz, 'Personal Practical Conflicts', in Peter Baumann and Monika Betzler (eds.), Practical Conflicts: New Philosophical Essays (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004), p. 172 at pp. 189-193, and also by reading unpublished work by Matthew Henken.
    • (2004) Practical Conflicts: New Philosophical Essays , pp. 189-193
    • Raz, J.1
  • 75
    • 0004264409 scopus 로고
    • Note
    • In other words, breach-plus-correction cannot be the rational equivalent of performance. Here we bid farewell to the 'efficient breach' fallacy made popular by O.W. Holmes in The Common Law (Boston: Little Brown, and Co., 1881), pp. 300-301.
    • (1881) The Common Law , pp. 300-301
    • Holmes, O.W.1
  • 76
    • 33645732706 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Yet we also cast doubt on anti-Holmesian attempts, e.g. in Ruxley Electronics and Construction Ltd v Forsyth [1996] AC 344, to fill the gap between breach-pluscorrection and performance with an extra measure of damages to reflect the so-called 'performance interest'. The gap cannot be filled.
    • (1996) Ruxley Electronics and Construction Ltd V Forsyth , pp. 344
  • 77
    • 78649909389 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • I am not suggesting, of course, that there are no practical consequences of having such emotions. There can be reasons to express such emotions to others, e.g. by confessing or apologizing. Such expression should not be mistaken for further correction according to the continuity thesis. See further Raz, 'Personal Practical Conflicts', above footnote 56 at 189-190.) The case for expressing an emotion depends on whether one has that emotion to express, or at least a case to feign it. Not so the case for correction under the continuity thesis. Some quasi-reparative acts (e.g. sending flowers) are best understood as ways of apologizing, and hence depend for their success on the having or feigning of a suitable emotion. There is little use in the law's getting involved here as it cannot do the having or feigning on the wrongdoer's behalf.
  • 78
    • 70350769106 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Logic of Excuses and the Rationality of Emotions'
    • I have criticized this view at length in
    • I have criticized this view at length in 'The Logic of Excuses and the Rationality of Emotions', Journal of Value Inquiry 43 (2009), 315.
    • (2009) Journal of Value Inquiry , vol.43 , pp. 315
  • 79
    • 78649907743 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Politics and Moral Character'
    • Note
    • A view of the significance of rational remainders similar to mine, and to which I owe a great deal, is that of Bernard Williams. See, for example, his 'Politics and Moral Character' in Williams, Moral Luck (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004, 1981).
    • (2004) Williams, Moral Luck
  • 80
    • 0009272154 scopus 로고
    • 'Is It Reasonable to Regret Things One Did?'
    • For a defence free of utilitarian trappings, see
    • For a defence free of utilitarian trappings, see Rudiger Bittner, 'Is It Reasonable to Regret Things One Did?', Journal of Philosophy 89 (1992), 262.
    • (1992) Journal of Philosophy , vol.89 , pp. 262
    • Bittner, R.1
  • 81
    • 0009021920 scopus 로고
    • 'Obligation and Performance'
    • Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
    • See Barbara Herman, 'Obligation and Performance' in her The Practice of Moral Judgment (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1993).
    • (1993) The Practice of Moral Judgment
    • Herman, B.1
  • 82
    • 78649908930 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'factual loss' from his or her 'normative loss'
    • Note
    • This challenge can also be addressed to Weinrib, who distinguishes the plaintiff's 'factual loss' from his or her 'normative loss': The Idea of Private Law, above footnote 1, 115ff.
    • The Idea of Private Law , vol.1
  • 83
    • 78649907119 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • The response that follows seems, however, to be unavailable to Weinrib (he seems to deny the factual loss both a constitutive and a justificatory role in relation to the normative loss). I am not clear what his alternative response to the challenge is.
  • 85
    • 60949463908 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Wrongdoing that Gets Results'
    • And further in
    • And further in 'The Wrongdoing that Gets Results', Philosophical Perspectives 18 (2004), 53.
    • (2004) Philosophical Perspectives , vol.18 , pp. 53
  • 86
    • 78649908899 scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Where the common law tort of breach of statutory duty is concerned, the consequences to be protected against are determined, not by the purpose of the tort's existence, but by the purpose of the particular statutory duty, a.k.a. the 'mischief of the statute': Gorris v. Scott [1874] 9 LR (Exch) 125.
    • (1874) Gorris V. Scott , vol.9 , pp. 125
  • 87
    • 25844512412 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'The Mysterious Case of the Reasonable Person'
    • I argued for this equation in
    • I argued for this equation in 'The Mysterious Case of the Reasonable Person', University of Toronto Law Journal 51 (2001), 373.
    • (2001) University of Toronto Law Journal , vol.51 , pp. 373
  • 88
    • 0004240210 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • The Right and the Good (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1930), p. 45.
    • (1930) The Right and The Good , pp. 45
  • 89
    • 78649906297 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • This is the lesson of Vincent v. Lake Erie Transportation Co. 109 Minn. 456, 124 N.W. 221 (1910), interpreted as a trespass case, which in my view is what it is. There are those who interpret it as an unjust enrichment case in order to resist its lesson. For a good catalogue of possible interpretations (siding, ultimately, with the same one as me)
  • 90
    • 77956384620 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Tort Law in a Liberal State'
    • article 3, downloadable at
    • see Arthur Ripstein, 'Tort Law in a Liberal State', Journal of Tort Law 1 (2007), issue 2, article 3, downloadable at http://www.bepress.com/jtl/vol1/iss2/art3.
    • (2007) Journal of Tort Law , vol.1 , Issue.2
  • 92
    • 78649907118 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Weinrib, above footnote
    • Weinrib, The Idea of Private Law, above footnote 1, p. 76.
    • The Idea of Private Law , vol.1 , pp. 76
  • 93
    • 0009430406 scopus 로고
    • 'Rights and Individual Well-being'
    • Note
    • On the significance of the parenthetical words, see Joseph Raz, 'Rights and Individual Well-being', in his Ethics in the Public Domain (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1994).
    • (1994) Ethics In the Public Domain
    • Raz, J.1
  • 95
  • 96
    • 4043138349 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'The Virtue of Charity and its Foils'
    • Note
    • For a defence of this view, see my 'The Virtue of Charity and its Foils', in Charles Mitchell and Sue Moody (eds.), Foundations of Charity (Oxford: Hart Publishing, 2000).
    • (2000) Foundations of Charity
  • 97
    • 78649906614 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Compare Finnis, Natural Law and Natural Rights, above footnote 28, pp. 163-164, discussing the torture example and placing it under the 'justice' heading.
    • Natural Law and Natural Rights , vol.28 , pp. 163-164
  • 98
    • 78649386246 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Two Conceptions of Tort Damages: Fair v. Full Compensation'
    • For full articulation of this doubt, see
    • For full articulation of this doubt, see John Goldberg, 'Two Conceptions of Tort Damages: Fair v. Full Compensation', DePaul Law Review 55 (2006), 435.
    • (2006) DePaul Law Review , vol.55 , pp. 435
    • Goldberg, J.1
  • 99
    • 78649909388 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • above footnote
    • The Idea of Private Law, above footnote 9, p. 135.
    • The Idea of Private Law , vol.9 , pp. 135
  • 100
    • 78649903198 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'As If It Had Never Happened'
    • Similarly, [t]he normative situation is unchanged' by the wrong
    • Similarly, Arthur Ripstein, 'As If It Had Never Happened', William and Mary Law Review 48 (2007), 1957-1979: '[t]he normative situation is unchanged' by the wrong.
    • (2007) William and Mary Law Review , vol.48 , pp. 1957-1979
    • Ripstein, A.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.