메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 61, Issue 244, 2011, Pages 558-576

Sensory phenomenology and perceptual content

(1)  Millar, Boyd a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 79959743016     PISSN: 00318094     EISSN: 14679213     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1111/j.1467-9213.2011.696.x     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (9)

References (33)
  • 1
    • 0003948679 scopus 로고
    • tr. J.N. Findlay (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul)
    • E. Husserl, Logical Investigations [1900], tr. J.N. Findlay (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1970), p. 565.
    • (1900) Logical Investigations , pp. 565
    • Husserl, E.1
  • 2
    • 14744304959 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The representational character of experience
    • B. Leiter (ed.), (Oxford: Clarendon Press), at p. 167
    • See, e.g., D. Chalmers, 'The Representational Character of Experience', in B. Leiter (ed.), The Future for Philosophy (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2004), pp. 153-81, at p. 167.
    • (2004) The Future for Philosophy , pp. 153-181
    • Chalmers, D.1
  • 6
    • 59549083051 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Colour constancy and russellian representationalism
    • at pp. 75-7
    • B. Thompson, 'Colour Constancy and Russellian Representationalism', Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 84 (2006), pp. 75-94, at pp. 75-7.
    • (2006) Australasian Journal of Philosophy , vol.84 , pp. 75-94
    • Thompson, B.1
  • 8
    • 14744283882 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The intentionality of phenomenology and the phenomenology of intentionality
    • D. Chalmers (ed.), (Oxford UP)
    • T. Horgan and J. Tienson, 'The Intentionality of Phenomenology and the Phenomenology of Intentionality', in D. Chalmers (ed.), Philosophy of Mind: Classical and Contemporary Readings (Oxford UP, 2002), pp. 520-41;
    • (2002) Philosophy of Mind: Classical and Contemporary Readings , pp. 520-541
    • Horgan, T.1    Tienson, J.2
  • 9
    • 43949137027 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Intentional inexistence and phenomenal intentionality
    • J. Hawthorne (ed.), (Malden: Blackwell)
    • U. Kriegel, 'Intentional Inexistence and Phenomenal Intentionality', in J. Hawthorne (ed.), Philosophical Perspectives, 21: Philosophy of Mind (Malden: Blackwell, 2007), pp. 307-40.
    • (2007) Philosophical Perspectives, 21: Philosophy of Mind , pp. 307-340
    • Kriegel, U.1
  • 10
    • 34247201571 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Consciousness and intentionality
    • M. Velmans and S. Schneider (eds), (Malden: Blackwell), at p. 468
    • The label 'separatism' is used this way by Horgan and Tienson, p. 520, and by Graham, Horgan and Tienson, in their 'Consciousness and Intentionality', in M. Velmans and S. Schneider (eds), The Blackwell Companion to Consciousness (Malden: Blackwell, 2007), pp. 468-84, at p. 468.
    • (2007) The Blackwell Companion to Consciousness , pp. 468-484
    • Graham1    Horgan2    Tienson3
  • 11
    • 0003434441 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • Husserl (pp. 564-7) also defends moderate separatism by pointing to examples of ordinary perceptual experiences. Peacocke, a more recent defender of this view, presents an example of this sort as well: see C. Peacocke, Sense and Content (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983), p. 16.
    • (1983) Sense and Content , pp. 16
    • Peacocke, C.1
  • 14
    • 0141557890 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Consciousness as sensory quality and as implicit self-awareness
    • Kriegel, 'Consciousness as Sensory Quality and as Implicit Self-Awareness', Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 2 (2003), pp. 1-26.
    • (2003) Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences , vol.2 , pp. 1-26
    • Kriegel1
  • 16
    • 33847659627 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Which properties are represented in perception?
    • T. Gendler and J. Hawthorne (eds), (Oxford: Clarendon Press), at pp. 490-1. Auditory versions of this type of example are presented by Husserl (pp. 566-7), Strawson (pp. 5-13), Siewert (pp. 275-6) and Horgan and Tienson (p. 523)
    • S. Siegel, 'Which Properties are Represented in Perception?', in T. Gendler and J. Hawthorne (eds), Perceptual Experience (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2006), pp. 481-503, at pp. 490-1. Auditory versions of this type of example are presented by Husserl (pp. 566-7), Strawson (pp. 5-13), Siewert (pp. 275-6) and Horgan and Tienson (p. 523).
    • (2006) Perceptual Experience , pp. 481-503
    • Siegel, S.1
  • 17
    • 84920888897 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford UP, forthcoming
    • Whether there is such a thing as cognitive phenomenology continues to be controversial. For the present state of the debate, see the papers in T. Bayne and M. Montague, Cognitive Phenomenology (Oxford UP, forthcoming).
    • Cognitive Phenomenology
    • Bayne, T.1    Montague, M.2
  • 18
    • 0003931945 scopus 로고
    • New York: Harcourt, Brace
    • A number of writers have claimed that when the 'interpretation' of such ambiguous figures changes one's visual sensations change as well. See, e.g., C.D. Broad, Scientific Thought (New York: Harcourt, Brace, 1923), p. 260;
    • (1923) Scientific Thought , pp. 260
    • Broad, C.D.1
  • 20
    • 60949460333 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ambiguous figures and the content of experience
    • at pp. 87-93
    • F. MacPherson, 'Ambiguous Figures and the Content of Experience', Noûs, 40 (2006), pp. 82-117, at pp. 87-93.
    • (2006) Noûs , vol.40 , pp. 82-117
    • MacPherson, F.1
  • 21
    • 79959769321 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kriegel, 'Consciousness as Sensory Quality', p. 8, disagrees; but for my purposes it will be preferable to stick with the present broader conception of sensory qualities.
    • Consciousness As Sensory Quality , pp. 8
    • Kriegel1
  • 22
    • 0000679095 scopus 로고
    • The causal theory of perception
    • at p. 142
    • Looking at a pillar in a mirror is a famous example of Grice's: see H.P. Grice, 'The Causal Theory of Perception', Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supp. Vol. 35 (1961), pp. 121-52, at p. 142.
    • (1961) Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society , vol.35 , Issue.SUPPL. , pp. 121-152
    • Grice, H.P.1
  • 23
    • 60949479190 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On a defense of the hegemony of representation
    • E. Villanueva (ed.), (Atascadero: Ridgeview), at p. 107
    • The fact that looking at an object reflected in a mirror can often be phenomenally similar to looking at an object through a window has been noted by at least two different philosophers. Broad (pp. 317-18) says that a visual experience of a light source reflected in a mirror possesses precisely the same 'sensa' as an experience of a similar light source viewed through a thin pane of glass (assuming the light source is in the right position). Robert Stalnaker, 'On a Defense of the Hegemony of Representation', in E. Villanueva (ed.), Philosophical Issues, 7: Perception (Atascadero: Ridgeview, 1996), pp. 101-8, at p. 107, points out that a situation in which you are looking at trees through a window could produce an illusory experience of trees reflected in a mirror.
    • (1996) Philosophical Issues, 7: Perception , pp. 101-108
    • Stalnaker, R.1
  • 24
    • 0030298705 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Three varieties of visual field
    • at pp. 489-90
    • See A. Clark, 'Three Varieties of Visual Field', Philosophical Psychology, 9 (1996), pp. 477-95, at pp. 489-90
    • (1996) Philosophical Psychology , vol.9 , pp. 477-495
    • Clark, A.1
  • 25
    • 0004232163 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Freeman
    • and R. Gregory, Mirrors in Mind (New York: Freeman, 1997), pp. 77-8.
    • (1997) Mirrors in Mind , pp. 77-78
    • Gregory, R.1
  • 26
    • 38349082661 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Through the looking glass: How the relationship between an object and its reflection affects the perception of distance and size
    • L. Jones and M. Bertamini, 'Through the Looking Glass: How the Relationship Between an Object and its Reflection Affects the Perception of Distance and Size', Perception, 36 (2007), pp. 1572-94.
    • (2007) Perception , vol.36 , pp. 1572-1594
    • Jones, L.1    Bertamini, M.2
  • 27
    • 85047670138 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Naive optics: Understanding the geometry of mirror reflections
    • One might suggest that in such situations individuals are subjected to the visual illusion that there is more than one object in front of them, but none the less on the basis of that illusory experience are able to make more accurate judgements about the size and distance of the relevant object based on their knowledge of the relationship between objects and mirror reflections. However, this explanation is less plausible than the alternative, given that it has been well documented that most people's knowledge of the relationship between objects and their mirror reflections is seriously flawed, and given that they make simple mistakes when reasoning about mirror reflections: see C. Croucher et al., 'Naive Optics: Understanding the Geometry of Mirror Reflections', Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 28 (2002), pp. 546-62;
    • (2002) Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance , vol.28 , pp. 546-562
    • Croucher, C.1
  • 28
    • 27744502358 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On what people know about images on mirrors
    • M. Bertamini and T. Parks, 'On What People Know about Images on Mirrors', Cognition, 98 (2005), pp. 85-104;
    • (2005) Cognition , vol.98 , pp. 85-104
    • Bertamini, M.1    Parks, T.2
  • 30
    • 4544353491 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Mirror vision: Perceived size and perceived distance of virtual images
    • Researchers sometimes talk in terms of the perception of virtual objects or images in mirrors (for example, A. Higashiyama and K. Shimono, 'Mirror Vision: Perceived Size and Perceived Distance of Virtual Images', Perception & Psychophysics, 66 (2004), pp. 679-91;
    • (2004) Perception & Psychophysics , vol.66 , pp. 679-691
    • Higashiyama, A.1    Shimono, K.2
  • 32
    • 61449318371 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Senses for senses
    • at pp. 111-12
    • As Thompson, 'Senses for Senses', Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 87 (2009), pp. 99-117, at pp. 111-12, makes clear, it would also be problematic for the Fregean representationalist to claim instead that viewing conditions represented to obtain by the subject can deal with this sort of example (Thompson is discussing the content of colour experience, but analogous points would apply to the present case).
    • (2009) Australasian Journal of Philosophy , vol.87 , pp. 99-117
    • Thompson1
  • 33
    • 79959770432 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This paper is based on material from my dissertation A Defence of Separatism. I would like to thank Mohan Matthen and Evan Thompson for their comments on the relevant material. I owe special thanks to Benj Hellie and Bill Seager for their comments and advice on both the material included in the present paper and my dissertation as a whole.
    • A Defence of Separatism


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.