메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 96, Issue 4, 2011, Pages 1035-1074

Explanation in legal scholarship: The inferential structure of doctrinal legal analysis

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 79959486815     PISSN: 00108847     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: None     Document Type: Conference Paper
Times cited : (16)

References (363)
  • 1
    • 0011310835 scopus 로고
    • Consideration and form
    • See, 800-03
    • See Lon L. Fuller, Consideration and Form, 41 COLUM. L. REV. 799, 800-03 (1941).
    • (1941) Colum. L. Rev. , vol.41 , pp. 799
    • Fuller, L.L.1
  • 2
    • 33846807440 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Commodification and contract formation: Placing the consideration doctrine on stronger foundations
    • 1299
    • David Carnage & Allon Kedem, Commodification and Contract Formation: Placing the Consideration Doctrine on Stronger Foundations, 73 U. CHI. L. REV. 1299, 1299 (2006).
    • (2006) U. Chi. L. Rev. , vol.73 , pp. 1299
    • Carnage, D.1    Kedem, A.2
  • 3
    • 79959388885 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id
    • See id.
  • 4
    • 79959383896 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 1322
    • See id. at 1322.
  • 12
    • 0040559647 scopus 로고
    • Putting inference to the best explanation in its place
    • defending IBE's role in philosophical argumentation and assessing debates over IBE in arguments for scientific realism
    • Timothy Day & Harold Kincaid, Putting Inference to the Best Explanation in Its Place, 98 SYNTHESE 271 (1994) (defending IBE's role in philosophical argumentation and assessing debates over IBE in arguments for scientific realism);
    • (1994) Synthese , vol.98 , pp. 271
    • Day, T.1    Kincaid, H.2
  • 13
    • 0002469974 scopus 로고
    • The inference to the best explanation
    • arguing that many instances appearing to be enumerative induction are in fact instances of inference to the best explanation
    • Gilbert H. Harman, The Inference to the Best Explanation, 74 PHIL. REV. 88 (1965) (arguing that many instances appearing to be enumerative induction are in fact instances of inference to the best explanation);
    • (1965) Phil. Rev. , vol.74 , pp. 88
    • Harman, G.H.1
  • 14
    • 0040117038 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Inference to the best explanation: Is it really different from mill's methods?
    • concluding that Lipton's account of IBE does not sufficiently distinguish IBE from other models
    • Steven Rappaport, Inference to the Best Explanation: Is It Really Different from Mill's Methods?, 63 PHIL. SCI. 65 (1996) (concluding that Lipton's account of IBE does not sufficiently distinguish IBE from other models);
    • (1996) Phil. Sci. , vol.63 , pp. 65
    • Rappaport, S.1
  • 15
    • 0002085351 scopus 로고
    • The best explanation: Criteria for theory choice
    • developing a set of criteria that enhance accounts of IBE and the justification of scientific theories
    • Paul R. Thagard, The Best Explanation: Criteria for Theory Choice, 75 J. PHIL. 76 (1978) (developing a set of criteria that enhance accounts of IBE and the justification of scientific theories).
    • (1978) J. Phil. , vol.75 , pp. 76
    • Thagard, P.R.1
  • 16
    • 34848866444 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For the role of explanation in the social sciences, see generally, hereinafter ELSTER, EXPLAINING SOCIAL BEHAVIOR advocating for causal explanation
    • For the role of explanation in the social sciences, see generally JON ELSTER, EXPLAINING SOCIAL BEHAVIOR: MORE NUTS AND BOLTS FOR THE SOCIAL SCIENCES 7-74 (2007) [hereinafter ELSTER, EXPLAINING SOCIAL BEHAVIOR] (advocating for causal explanation);
    • (2007) Explaining Social Behavior: More Nuts and Bolts for the Social Sciences , pp. 7-74
    • Elster, J.1
  • 17
    • 0004084217 scopus 로고
    • discussing the role of dialectics in explanation
    • JON ELSTER, MAKING SENSE OF MARX 3-48 (1985) (discussing the role of dialectics in explanation);
    • (1985) Making Sense of Marx , pp. 3-48
    • Elster, J.1
  • 19
    • 0042519566 scopus 로고
    • describing the use of functional explanation in archaeology
    • MERRILEE H. SALMON, PHILOSOPHY AND ARCHAEOLOGY 84-111 (1982) (describing the use of functional explanation in archaeology).
    • (1982) Philosophy and Archaeology , pp. 84-111
    • Salmon, M.H.1
  • 20
    • 61149309937 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 5, at
    • SALMON, FOUR DECADES, supra note 5, at 126-29.
    • Four Decades , pp. 126-129
    • Salmon1
  • 21
    • 0038922382 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Explanatory unification
    • See, in, supra note 5, 169-70, taking the domain of scientific theories as responses to "explanation-seeking why-questions". I am taking this question as the starting point, as opposed to beginning with other problems, such as what we mean by scientific knowledge, in order to avoid numerous issues that are essential to the philosophy of science but not relevant to this inquiry into the metatheory of law. An example would be the debate between scientific realists and critics like Bas van Fraassen over whether scientific theories need only be empirically adequate or whether they must be believed to be true
    • See Philip Kitcher, Explanatory Unification, in THEORIES OF EXPLANATION, supra note 5, 167, 169-70 (taking the domain of scientific theories as responses to "explanation-seeking why-questions"). I am taking this question as the starting point, as opposed to beginning with other problems, such as what we mean by scientific knowledge, in order to avoid numerous issues that are essential to the philosophy of science but not relevant to this inquiry into the metatheory of law. An example would be the debate between scientific realists and critics like Bas van Fraassen over whether scientific theories need only be empirically adequate or whether they must be believed to be true.
    • Theories of Explanation , pp. 167
    • Kitcher, P.1
  • 22
    • 79959433898 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See VAS FRAASSEN, supra note 5 at 9-13
    • See VAS FRAASSEN, supra note 5 at 9-13;
  • 23
    • 61149309937 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 5, at, Another issue not germane to metatheory in law and also explored by van Fraassen is the symmetry between explanation and prediction
    • SALMON, FOUR DECADES, supra note 5, at 135-38. Another issue not germane to metatheory in law (and also explored by van Fraassen) is the symmetry between explanation and prediction.
    • Four Decades , pp. 135-138
    • Salmon1
  • 26
    • 79959423478 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Tort law and tort theory: Preliminary reflections on method
    • 184 Gerald J. Postema ed., rejecting a top-down analysis of tort law and instead looking to whether social practices achieve corrective justice in order to assert the claim that tort law is best explained by corrective justice
    • Jules Coleman, Tort Law and Tort Theory: Preliminary Reflections on Method, in PHILOSOPHY AND THE LAW OF TORTS 183, 184 (Gerald J. Postema ed., 2001) (rejecting a top-down analysis of tort law and instead looking to whether social practices achieve corrective justice in order to assert the claim that tort law is best explained by corrective justice);
    • (2001) Philosophy and the Law of Torts , pp. 183
    • Coleman, J.1
  • 27
    • 0142231545 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Twentieth-century tort theory
    • passim, analyzing five theories of tort law
    • John C. P. Goldberg, Twentieth-Century Tort Theory, 91 GEO. LJ. 513 passim (2003) (analyzing five theories of tort law);
    • (2003) Geo. Lj. , vol.91 , pp. 513
    • Goldberg, J.C.P.1
  • 28
    • 34248536522 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Transparency and determinacy in common law adjudication: A philosophical defense of explanatory economic analysis
    • 287-88, defending explanatory economic analysis of the common law despite criticisms that such an explanation makes no sense given judges' explicit use of deontic moral terms
    • Jody S. Kraus, Transparency and Determinacy in Common Law Adjudication: A Philosophical Defense of Explanatory Economic Analysis, 93 VA. L. REV. 287, 287-88 (2007) (defending explanatory economic analysis of the common law despite criticisms that such an explanation makes no sense given judges' explicit use of deontic moral terms);
    • (2007) Va. L. Rev. , vol.93 , pp. 287
    • Kraus, J.S.1
  • 29
    • 41449101021 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Juridical proof and the best explanation
    • 225, arguing that the process of inference to the best explanation explains the macrostructure of proof at trial and the microlevel issues regarding the relevance and value of particular items of evidence
    • Michael S. Pardo & Ronald J. Allen, Juridical Proof and the Best Explanation, 27 LAW & PHIL. 223, 225 (2008) (arguing that the process of inference to the best explanation explains the macrostructure of proof at trial and the microlevel issues regarding the relevance and value of particular items of evidence).
    • (2008) Law & Phil. , vol.27 , pp. 223
    • Pardo, M.S.1    Allen, R.J.2
  • 30
    • 41449090934 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Abductive reasoning in law: Taxonomy and inference to the best explanation
    • See generally, problematizing abductive explanation in real-life legal processes
    • See generally Kola Abimbola, Abductive Reasoning in Law: Taxonomy and Inference to the Best Explanation, 22 CARDOZO L. REV. 1683 (2001) (problematizing abductive explanation in real-life legal processes).
    • (2001) Cardozo L. Rev. , vol.22 , pp. 1683
    • Abimbola, K.1
  • 31
    • 84933494837 scopus 로고
    • On beyond truth: A theory for evaluating legal scholarship
    • For one general theory of evaluation in legal scholarship, with very different methodological commitments than those defended here, see generally
    • For one general theory of evaluation in legal scholarship, with very different methodological commitments than those defended here, see generally Edward L. Rubin, On Beyond Truth: A Theory for Evaluating Legal Scholarship, 80 CALIF. L. REV. 889 (1992).
    • (1992) Calif. L. Rev. , vol.80 , pp. 889
    • Rubin, E.L.1
  • 32
    • 84936068266 scopus 로고
    • For Dworkin's principal contributions to the metatheory of law, see generally, hereinafter DWORKIN, LAW'S EMPIRE critiquing legal positivism
    • For Dworkin's principal contributions to the metatheory of law, see generally RONALD DWORKIN, LAW'S EMPIRE (1986) [hereinafter DWORKIN, LAW'S EMPIRE] (critiquing legal positivism);
    • (1986) Law'S Empire
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 33
    • 3843116089 scopus 로고
    • Hard cases
    • hereinafter DWORKIN, Hard Cases describing the questions judges must ask themselves in order to determine the rights of litigating parties in difficult cases
    • RONALD DWORKIN, Hard Cases, in TAKING RIGHTS SERIOUSLY 81 (1977) [hereinafter DWORKIN, Hard Cases] (describing the questions judges must ask themselves in order to determine the rights of litigating parties in difficult cases).
    • (1977) Taking Rights Seriously , pp. 81
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 34
    • 0346669619 scopus 로고
    • The forum of principle
    • For a particularly clear statement of Dworkin's position that shows the relationship between his conception of explanation and the arguments considered here, see, in, 35, hereinafter DWORKIN, The Forum of Principle "Each theory claims to provide the most illuminating account of what our actual constitutional tradition, taken as a whole, really 'comes to'-of the 'point' or 'best justification' of the constitutional system that has been developed in our own legal history."
    • For a particularly clear statement of Dworkin's position that shows the relationship between his conception of explanation and the arguments considered here, see RONALD DWORKIN, The Forum of Principle, in A MATTER OF PRINCIPLE 33, 35 (1985) [hereinafter DWORKIN, The Forum of Principle] ("Each theory claims to provide the most illuminating account of what our actual constitutional tradition, taken as a whole, really 'comes to'-of the 'point' or 'best justification' of the constitutional system that has been developed in our own legal history.").
    • (1985) A Matter of Principle , pp. 33
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 35
    • 79959410252 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Coherence, hypothetical cases, and precedent
    • For discussions of metatheory in Dworkin, see, in, 69 Scott Hershovitz ed.
    • For discussions of metatheory in Dworkin, see S. L. Hurley, Coherence, Hypothetical Cases, and Precedent, in EXPLORING LAW'S EMPIRE: THE JURISPRUDENCE OF RONALD DWORKIN 69, 69 (Scott Hershovitz ed., 2006);
    • (2006) Exploring Law'S Empire: The Jurisprudence of Ronald Dworkin , pp. 69
    • Hurley, S.L.1
  • 36
    • 85008145416 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Coherentist methodology is morally better than either its proponents or its critics think (but still not good enough)
    • 83-107, discussing Dworkinian coherentism
    • Ken Kress, Coherentist Methodology is Morally Better Than Either Its Proponents or Its Critics Think (But Still Not Good Enough), 12 CAN. J. L. & JURISPRUDENCE 83, 83-107 (1999) (discussing Dworkinian coherentism);
    • (1999) Can. J. L. & Jurisprudence , vol.12 , pp. 83
    • Kress, K.1
  • 37
    • 0042054673 scopus 로고
    • Legal reasoning and coherence theories: Dworkin's rights thesis, retroactivity, and the linear order of decisions
    • 372-88
    • Kenneth J. Kress, Legal Reasoning and Coherence Theories: Dworkin's Rights Thesis, Retroactivity, and the Linear Order of Decisions, 72 CALIF. L. REV. 369, 372-88 (1984);
    • (1984) Calif. L. Rev. , vol.72 , pp. 369
    • Kress, K.J.1
  • 38
    • 0010054237 scopus 로고
    • The relevance of coherence
    • 303-09, 315-21
    • Joseph Raz, The Relevance of Coherence, 72 B. U. L. REV. 273, 303-09, 315-21 (1992);
    • (1992) B. U. L. Rev. , vol.72 , pp. 273
    • Raz, J.1
  • 39
    • 79959393713 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Introduction: Anti-archimedeanism
    • 10-17 Arthur Ripstein ed.
    • Arthur Ripstein, Introduction: Anti-Archimedeanism, in RONALD DWORKIN 1, 10-17 (Arthur Ripstein ed., 2007);
    • (2007) Ronald Dworkin , pp. 1
    • Ripstein, A.1
  • 40
    • 11244272146 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Legal coherentism
    • 1706-07, 1715-17, While they certainly stand on their own as a work of legal theory, Jules Coleman's Clarendon Lectures use Dworkin's theory as a foil throughout, and can therefore be seen as an extended critique of Dworkin
    • Benjamin C. Zipursky, Legal Coherentism, 50 SMU L. REV. 1679, 1706-07, 1715-17 (1997). While they certainly stand on their own as a work of legal theory, Jules Coleman's Clarendon Lectures use Dworkin's theory as a foil throughout, and can therefore be seen as an extended critique of Dworkin.
    • (1997) Smu L. Rev. , vol.50 , pp. 1679
    • Zipursky, B.C.1
  • 42
    • 0004166519 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, supra note 8, at
    • See DWORKIN, LAW'S EMPIRE, supra note 8, at 96-98.
    • Law'S Empire , pp. 96-98
    • Dworkin1
  • 43
    • 79959447337 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 87-113
    • See id. at 87-113.
  • 44
    • 0036332194 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The rules of inference
    • Cf, 3-4, noting that even doctrinal work includes empirical arguments. As discussed in section II below, statistical explanations such as those offered by empirical legal scholars are a recognized subset of scientific explanation. However, the inferential methods under consideration here are, at best, only analogous to explanation in the natural sciences and empirical social sciences
    • Cf. Lee Epstein & Gary King, The Rules of Inference, 69 U. CHI. L. REV. 1, 3-4 (2002) (noting that even doctrinal work includes empirical arguments). As discussed in section II below, statistical explanations such as those offered by empirical legal scholars are a recognized subset of scientific explanation. However, the inferential methods under consideration here are, at best, only analogous to explanation in the natural sciences and empirical social sciences.
    • (2002) U. Chi. L. Rev. , vol.69 , pp. 1
    • Epstein, L.1    King, G.2
  • 45
    • 79959415532 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The word "frankly" is important to differentiate these arguments from what may be a tacit appeal to normative criteria in the type of argument considered here. To use a term that was somewhat more current a decade or two ago, one might refer to frankly normative arguments as pragmatic
    • The word "frankly" is important to differentiate these arguments from what may be a tacit appeal to normative criteria in the type of argument considered here. To use a term that was somewhat more current a decade or two ago, one might refer to frankly normative arguments as pragmatic.
  • 46
    • 0001018693 scopus 로고
    • Symposium, the renaissance of pragmatism in American legal thought
    • See, e.g.
    • See, e.g., Symposium, The Renaissance of Pragmatism in American Legal Thought, 63 S. CAL. L. REV. 1569 (1990);
    • (1990) S. Cal. L. Rev. , vol.63 , pp. 1569
  • 47
    • 0001429259 scopus 로고
    • Holmes and legal pragmatism
    • 790-91, Richard Posner, who calls himself a pragmatist, offers a brief overview and history of pragmatism in American law
    • Thomas C. Grey, Holmes and Legal Pragmatism, 41 STAN. L. REV. 787, 790-91 (1989). Richard Posner, who calls himself a pragmatist, offers a brief overview and history of pragmatism in American law.
    • (1989) Stan. L. Rev. , vol.41 , pp. 787
    • Grey, T.C.1
  • 48
    • 79959429564 scopus 로고
    • So what has pragmatism to offer law?
    • See, in, 387-95
    • See RICHARD A. POSNER, So What Has Pragmatism to Offer Law?, in OVERCOMING LAW 387, 387-95 (1995).
    • (1995) Overcoming Law , pp. 387
    • Posner, R.A.1
  • 49
    • 0002349323 scopus 로고
    • The growing disjunction between legal education and the legal profession
    • The decline of doctrinal legal scholarship has been noted for a long time. See, e.g., 42-43, noting the decline of "practical" legal scholarship, which is doctrinal
    • The decline of doctrinal legal scholarship has been noted for a long time. See, e.g., Harry T. Edwards, The Growing Disjunction Between Legal Education and the Legal Profession, 91 MICH. L. REV. 34, 42-43 (1992) (noting the decline of "practical" legal scholarship, which is doctrinal);
    • (1992) Mich. L. Rev. , vol.91 , pp. 34
    • Edwards, H.T.1
  • 50
    • 79959414731 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The triumphs and travails of legal scholarship
    • see also, in, supra note 12, at, contending that "the legal doctrinalists are being crowded by economic analysts of law, by other social scientists of law, by Bayesians, by philosophers of law, by political theorists, by critical legal scholars, by feminist and gay legal scholars, by the law and literature people, and by critical race theorists, all deploying the tools of nonlegal disciplines". While I have no empirical evidence of the relative proportion of doctrinal, normative, and empirical legal scholarship, there still appears to be a market for doctrinal scholarship, as evidenced by the publication success enjoyed by many producers of it
    • see also RICHARD A. POSNER, The Triumphs and Travails of Legal Scholarship, in OVERCOMING LAW, supra note 12, at 86 (1995) (contending that "[t]he legal doctrinalists are being crowded by economic analysts of law, by other social scientists of law, by Bayesians, by philosophers of law, by political theorists, by critical legal scholars, by feminist and gay legal scholars, by the law and literature people, and by critical race theorists, all deploying the tools of nonlegal disciplines"). While I have no empirical evidence of the relative proportion of doctrinal, normative, and empirical legal scholarship, there still appears to be a market for doctrinal scholarship, as evidenced by the publication success enjoyed by many producers of it.
    • (1995) Overcoming Law , pp. 86
    • Posner, R.A.1
  • 51
    • 31144458448 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf, supra note 8, at, distinguishing claims that tort law ought to produce a certain outcome from explanations that refer to these outcomes as the most plausible explanation of certain features of tort law
    • Cf. COLEMAN, PRACTICE OF PRINCIPLE, supra note 8, at 28-29 (distinguishing claims that tort law ought to produce a certain outcome from explanations that refer to these outcomes as the most plausible explanation of certain features of tort law).
    • Practice of Principle , pp. 28-29
    • Coleman1
  • 52
    • 84928439064 scopus 로고
    • Normativity and the politics of form
    • Insofar as I understand it, this may be a similar aim of a well-known cridcal legal studies paper, 809-11, although our approaches to the problem are quite different
    • Insofar as I understand it, this may be a similar aim of a well-known cridcal legal studies paper, Pierre Schlag, Normativity and the Politics of Form, 139 U. PA. L. REV. 801, 809-11 (1991), although our approaches to the problem are quite different.
    • (1991) U. Pa. L. Rev. , vol.139 , pp. 801
    • Schlag, P.1
  • 53
    • 78650447024 scopus 로고
    • Negative and positive positivism
    • See, in, 4-5, 16, discussing the "rule of recognition", a standard that determines which of the community's norms are legal ones
    • See JULES L. COLEMAN, Negative and Positive Positivism, in MARKETS, MORALS AND THE LAW 3, 4-5, 16 (1988) (discussing the "rule of recognition", a standard that determines which of the community's norms are legal ones);
    • (1988) Markets, Morals and the Law , pp. 3
    • Coleman, J.L.1
  • 54
    • 0043197137 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Too thin and too rich: Distinguishing features of legal positivism
    • 16-19 Robert P. George ed., examining moral judgments in the context of legal positivism
    • Kent Greenawalt, Too Thin and Too Rich: Distinguishing Features of Legal Positivism, in THE AUTONOMY OF LAW: ESSAYS ON LEGAL POSITIVISM 1, 16-19 (Robert P. George ed., 1996) (examining moral judgments in the context of legal positivism);
    • (1996) The Autonomy of Law: Essays on Legal Positivism , pp. 1
    • Greenawalt, K.1
  • 55
    • 3843066125 scopus 로고
    • Legal theory and the obligation of a judge: The Hart/Dworkin dispute
    • 509-18, discussing the relationship between the law and morality
    • E. Philip Soper, Legal Theory and the Obligation of a Judge: The Hart/Dworkin Dispute, 75 MICH. L. REV. 473, 509-18 (1977) (discussing the relationship between the law and morality);
    • (1977) Mich. L. Rev. , vol.75 , pp. 473
    • Soper, E.P.1
  • 56
    • 0347262813 scopus 로고
    • Principles, positivism, and legal theory
    • 416, book review. Raz argues that one should be careful with the term "incorporation" of morality into law
    • David Lyons, Principles, Positivism, and Legal Theory, 87 YALE L. J. 415, 416 (1977) (book review). Raz argues that one should be careful with the term "incorporation" of morality into law.
    • (1977) Yale L. J. , vol.87 , pp. 415
    • Lyons, D.1
  • 57
    • 57149147326 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Incorporation by law
    • See generally, casting doubt on the idea that morals can become a part of the law through incorporation. In some cases, a court or administrative agency may have discretion to consider X, and if Xis a moral principle, the law does not "incorporate" X just by reiterating that an official may take X into account; in that instance, the law is merely being perfecdy clear that X is not excluded
    • See generally Joseph Raz, Incorporation by Law, 10 LEGAL THEORY 1 (2004) (casting doubt on the idea that morals can become a part of the law through incorporation). In some cases, a court or administrative agency may have discretion to consider X, and if Xis a moral principle, the law does not "incorporate" X just by reiterating that an official may take X into account; in that instance, the law is merely being perfecdy clear that X is not excluded.
    • (2004) Legal Theory , vol.10 , pp. 1
    • Raz, J.1
  • 58
    • 79959473503 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 14 "What appears as incorporation is no more than an indication that certain considerations are not excluded.". For Raz, the important tiling is the nonexclusion of morality by law because we are all bound by morality in any event
    • Id. at 14 ("[W]hat appears as incorporation is no more than an indication that certain considerations are not excluded."). For Raz, the important tiling is the nonexclusion of morality by law because we are all bound by morality in any event.
  • 59
    • 79959410253 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 16-17. One may grant this point, however, and still believe there is an open question concerning the role some consideration X plays when there is not an express grant of discretion to the decision maker to take extralegal considerations into account
    • Id. at 16-17. One may grant this point, however, and still believe there is an open question concerning the role some consideration X plays when there is not an express grant of discretion to the decision maker to take extralegal considerations into account
  • 60
    • 79959434465 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In truth the selection principle is more like "works that came to my attention during the years I served on the faculty appointments committee, or that I otherwise ran across in the course of my own scholarship".
    • In truth the selection principle is more like "works that came to my attention during the years I served on the faculty appointments committee, or that I otherwise ran across in the course of my own scholarship".
  • 61
    • 77952109422 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Intellectual property law and the sumptuary code
    • See generally
    • See generally Barton Beebe, Intellectual Property Law and the Sumptuary Code, 123 HARV. L. REV. 809 (2010).
    • (2010) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.123 , pp. 809
    • Beebe, B.1
  • 62
    • 79959471283 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 813 "To be sure, the express purpose and primary effect of intellectual property law remains the prevention of misappropriation and the promotion of technological and cultural progress."
    • See id. at 813 ("To be sure, the express purpose and primary effect of intellectual property law remains the prevention of misappropriation and the promotion of technological and cultural progress.").
  • 63
    • 79959381735 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 814
    • See id. at 814.
  • 65
    • 79959484020 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 64 noting that under the operative conception of property, property law identifies protected individual interests but also recognizes that these interests change as the result of societal needs
    • See id. at 64 (noting that under the operative conception of property, property law identifies protected individual interests but also recognizes that these interests change as the result of societal needs).
  • 66
    • 79959436189 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 75-84 setting forth a model that predicts when claimed rights will and should have trumping power
    • See id. at 75-84 (setting forth a model that predicts when claimed rights will and should have trumping power).
  • 67
    • 79959443476 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 16-33
    • See id. at 16-33.
  • 68
    • 22744437696 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Contract and collaboration
    • See generally
    • See generally Daniel Markovits, Contract and Collaboration, 113 YALE LJ. 1417 (2004).
    • (2004) Yale Lj. , vol.113 , pp. 1417
    • Markovits, D.1
  • 69
    • 79959471284 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 1419
    • See id. at 1419.
  • 70
    • 79959448434 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 1420
    • See id. at 1420.
  • 72
    • 79959462849 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 80
    • See id. at 80.
  • 73
    • 79959474877 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 81
    • See id. at 81.
  • 74
    • 79959414732 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id
    • See id.
  • 75
    • 36849049189 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A theory of justiciability
    • See generally
    • See generally Jonathan R. Siegel, A Theory of Justiciability, 86 TEX. L. REV. 73 (2007).
    • (2007) Tex. L. Rev. , vol.86 , pp. 73
    • Siegel, J.R.1
  • 76
    • 79959472913 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 87
    • See id. at 87.
  • 77
    • 79959478276 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 108
    • See id. at 108.
  • 78
    • 79952014305 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See generally Newdow v. U. S. Cong., 9th Cir
    • See generally Newdow v. U. S. Cong., 328 F.3d 466 (9th Cir. 2003)
    • (2003) F.3d , vol.328 , pp. 466
  • 79
    • 79551472314 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • rev'd on other grounds sub nom. Elk Grove Unified Sch. Dist. v. Newdow
    • rev'd on other grounds sub nom. Elk Grove Unified Sch. Dist. v. Newdow, 542 U. S. 1 (2004).
    • (2004) U. S. , vol.542 , pp. 1
  • 80
    • 79959455977 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Siegel, supra note 32, at 125
    • See Siegel, supra note 32, at 125.
  • 81
    • 31144458448 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 8. Coleman's book is particularly interesting because he first works through methodological issues with some care and uses what I take to be an IBE methodology to defend his preferred conception of the role of tort law
    • COLEMAN, PRACTICE OF PRINCIPLE, supra note 8. Coleman's book is particularly interesting because he first works through methodological issues with some care and uses what I take to be an IBE methodology to defend his preferred conception of the role of tort law.
    • Practice of Principle
    • Coleman1
  • 82
    • 79959422915 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 23
    • See id. at 23.
  • 83
    • 79959471813 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 16
    • See id. at 16.
  • 84
    • 79959387766 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 14
    • See id. at 14.
  • 85
    • 79959450739 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 21
    • See id. at 21.
  • 86
    • 79959460353 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • There is an enormous literature on explanation in history and other social sciences
    • There is an enormous literature on explanation in history and other social sciences.
  • 88
    • 79959471282 scopus 로고
    • Jan van der Dussen ed., rev. ed, exploring the philosophy of history
    • R. G. COLUNGWOOD, THE IDEA OF HISTORY 1-13 (Jan van der Dussen ed., rev. ed. 1993) (exploring the philosophy of history);
    • (1993) The Idea of History , pp. 1-13
    • Colungwood, R.G.1
  • 93
    • 77956983928 scopus 로고
    • Achilles, the tortoise, and explanation in science and history
    • See generally
    • See generally W. W. Bartley III, Achilles, the Tortoise, and Explanation in Science and History, 13 BRIT. J. PHIL. SCI. 15 (1962);
    • (1962) Brit. J. Phil. Sci. , vol.13 , pp. 15
    • Bartley III, W.W.1
  • 94
    • 0040866563 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The arc of the moral universe
    • defending ethical explanations while using slavery as a framework
    • Joshua Cohen, The Arc of the Moral Universe, 26 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 91 (1997) (defending ethical explanations while using slavery as a framework);
    • (1997) Phil. & Pub. Aff. , vol.26 , pp. 91
    • Cohen, J.1
  • 95
    • 36849057828 scopus 로고
    • Explanation in history
    • describing Popper's hypodeductive scheme of causal explanation
    • Alan Donagan, Explanation in History, 66 MIND 145 (1957) (describing Popper's hypodeductive scheme of causal explanation);
    • (1957) Mind , vol.66 , pp. 145
    • Donagan, A.1
  • 96
    • 61149168886 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The ideal explanatory text in history: A plea for ecumenism
    • applying an analysis of scientific explanation to historiography
    • Tor Egil Førland, The Ideal Explanatory Text in History: A Plea for Ecumenism, 43 HIST. & THEORY 321 (2004) (applying an analysis of scientific explanation to historiography);
    • (2004) Hist. & Theory , vol.43 , pp. 321
    • Førland, T.E.1
  • 97
    • 79959426228 scopus 로고
    • Criteria of explanation in history
    • asking what is required methodologically to study historical documents and what the nature of explanation in history is. Interestingly, the philosophy of history is largely derived from the philosophy of the natural sciences. The starting point for much of the analytical literature on the philosophy of history as opposed to works by historians, such as Collingwood is Carl Hempel's 1942 paper
    • E. W. Strong, Criteria of Explanation in History, 49 J. PHIL. 57 (1952) (asking what is required methodologically to study historical documents and what the nature of explanation in history is). Interestingly, the philosophy of history is largely derived from the philosophy of the natural sciences. The starting point for much of the analytical literature on the philosophy of history (as opposed to works by historians, such as Collingwood) is Carl Hempel's 1942 paper.
    • (1952) J. Phil. , vol.49 , pp. 57
    • Strong, E.W.1
  • 98
    • 0011639366 scopus 로고
    • The function of general laws in history
    • See
    • See Carl G. Hempel, The Function of General Laws in History, 39 J. PHIL. 35 (1942)
    • (1942) J. Phil. , vol.39 , pp. 35
    • Hempel, C.G.1
  • 99
    • 0003626641 scopus 로고
    • reprinted in, hereinafter HEMPEL, ASPECTS. Thus, broadening the inquiry here to include the philosophy of history may actually not result in as much of a payoff as one might initially think
    • reprinted in CARL G. HEMPEL, ASPECTS OF SCIENTIFIC EXPLANATION AND OTHER ESSAYS IN THE PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE 231 (1965) [hereinafter HEMPEL, ASPECTS]. Thus, broadening the inquiry here to include the philosophy of history may actually not result in as much of a payoff as one might initially think.
    • (1965) Aspects of Scientific Explanation and Other Essays in the Philosophy of Science , pp. 231
    • Hempel, C.G.1
  • 100
    • 79959482314 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • One might contend that explanation in humanities disciplines like history and humanistically influenced disciplines like cultural anthropology, inevitably involves interpretation
    • One might contend that explanation in humanities disciplines like history and humanistically influenced disciplines like cultural anthropology, inevitably involves interpretation.
  • 102
    • 34848866444 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also, supra note 5, at, As discussed below in section II, the notion of interpretation is central to Dworkin's jurisprudence
    • see also ELSTER, EXPLAINING SOCIAL BEHAVIOR, supra note 5, at 52-74. As discussed below in section II, the notion of interpretation is central to Dworkin's jurisprudence.
    • Explaining Social Behavior , pp. 52-74
    • Elster1
  • 103
    • 0004166519 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, supra note 8, at, 90-92, discussed infra notes 125-32
    • See DWORKIN, LAW'S EMPIRE, supra note 8, at 50, 90-92, discussed infra notes 125-32.
    • Law'S Empire , pp. 50
    • Dworkin1
  • 104
    • 79959443475 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. VAN FRAASSEN, supra note 5, at 6-7
    • Cf. VAN FRAASSEN, supra note 5, at 6-7.
  • 105
    • 79959433229 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 134
    • Id. at 134.
  • 106
    • 79959472355 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See the helpful overview of scientific realism and antirealism in NOLA & SANKEY, supra note 5, at 337-41
    • See the helpful overview of scientific realism and antirealism in NOLA & SANKEY, supra note 5, at 337-41.
  • 110
    • 79959425059 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • VAN FRAASSEN, supra note 5. Note that the argument structure here-namely that science is "about" such-and-such an aim-is the same type of argument with which we are concerned in legal scholarship. Thus, what for philosophy of science is an issue of metamethodology is a second-order metatheoretical question in law
    • VAN FRAASSEN, supra note 5. Note that the argument structure here-namely that science is "about" such-and-such an aim-is the same type of argument with which we are concerned in legal scholarship. Thus, what for philosophy of science is an issue of metamethodology is a second-order metatheoretical question in law.
  • 111
    • 79959451305 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See NOLA & SANKEY, supra note 5, at 81 distinguishing scientific theories, scientific methodologies, and metamethodologies. The metamethodological question is a vigorously contested one in the philosophy of science
    • See NOLA & SANKEY, supra note 5, at 81 (distinguishing scientific theories, scientific methodologies, and metamethodologies). The metamethodological question is a vigorously contested one in the philosophy of science
  • 112
    • 33845325276 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Why ask, "why?"?: An inquiry concerning scientific explanation
    • see, e.g., in, 125, hereinafter SALMON, CAUSALITY, and will not be pursued here, except as an analogy. It is interesting to note, however, that the Supreme Court has called upon judges to determine, in some cases, whether an expert's proffered testimony is based on "scientific knowledge."
    • see, e.g., WESLEY C. SALMON, Why Ask, "Why?"?: An Inquiry Concerning Scientific Explanation, in CAUSALITY AND EXPLANATION 125, 125 (1998) [hereinafter SALMON, CAUSALITY], and will not be pursued here, except as an analogy. It is interesting to note, however, that the Supreme Court has called upon judges to determine, in some cases, whether an expert's proffered testimony is based on "scientific knowledge."
    • (1998) Causality and Explanation , pp. 125
    • Salmon, W.C.1
  • 113
    • 32344452112 scopus 로고
    • Daubert v. Merrell Dow Pharm., Inc., 589-90
    • Daubert v. Merrell Dow Pharm., Inc., 509 U. S. 579, 589-90 (1993).
    • (1993) U. S. , vol.509 , pp. 579
  • 114
    • 79959409153 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • NOLA & SANKEY, supra note 5, at 34, 51. The distinction in the text is between general aims or goals that are constitutive of a certain conception of science and more specific norms that bring about the general aim. As I will argue below, a great deal turns on what ends are assumed to be constitutive of the relevant activity, whether science or academic legal scholarship
    • NOLA & SANKEY, supra note 5, at 34, 51. The distinction in the text is between general aims or goals that are constitutive of a certain conception of science and more specific norms that bring about the general aim. As I will argue below, a great deal turns on what ends are assumed to be constitutive of the relevant activity, whether science or academic legal scholarship.
  • 115
    • 0037619670 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Studies in the logic of confirmation
    • For the classic paper, see generally, in, supra note 42, at, hereinafter HEMPEL, Confirmation
    • For the classic paper, see generally CARL G. HEMPEL, Studies in the Logic of Confirmation, in HEMPEL, ASPECTS, supra note 42, at 3 [hereinafter HEMPEL, Confirmation].
    • Hempel, Aspects , pp. 3
    • Hempel, C.G.1
  • 116
    • 61149309937 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 5, at
    • SALMON, FOUR DECADES, supra note 5, at 8-10.
    • Four Decades , pp. 8-10
    • Salmon1
  • 117
    • 0011418307 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aspects of scientific explanation
    • See, in, supra note 42, at, hereinafter HEMPEL, Aspects. If the idiotic typeface rules in the Bluebook are to have any function at all, here it would be to differentiate Hempel's paper, Aspects of Scientific Explanation from the collection of papers by the same title
    • See CARL G. HEMPEL, Aspects of Scientific Explanation, in HEMPEL, ASPECTS, supra note 42, at 335-47 [hereinafter HEMPEL, Aspects]. If the idiotic typeface rules in the Bluebook are to have any function at all, here it would be to differentiate Hempel's paper, Aspects of Scientific Explanation from the collection of papers by the same title.
    • Hempel, Aspects , pp. 335-347
    • Hempel, C.G.1
  • 118
    • 0004233867 scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., describing the structure of a scientific system as a deductive system that includes a generalization and several levels of empirical hypotheses
    • See, e.g., RICHARD BEVAN BRAITHWAITE, SCIENTIFIC EXPLANATION 12-21 (1955) (describing the structure of a scientific system as a deductive system that includes a generalization and several levels of empirical hypotheses);
    • (1955) Scientific Explanation , pp. 12-21
    • Braithwaite, R.B.1
  • 119
    • 0004006454 scopus 로고
    • hereinafter HEMPEL, PHILOSOPHY noting that an explanation can be formulated as a deductive argument whose conclusion is an explanandum whose premises include the basic laws of science. Background conditions can include very general propositions about the nature of scientific inquiry. For example, an explanation in terms of the positions of the stars for John F. Kennedy's assassination will not even make it past the threshold as a scientific explanation in the twenty-first century
    • CARL G. HEMPEL, PHILOSOPHY OF NATURAL SCIENCE 49-51 (1966) [hereinafter HEMPEL, PHILOSOPHY] (noting that an explanation can be formulated as a deductive argument whose conclusion is an explanandum whose premises include the basic laws of science). Background conditions can include very general propositions about the nature of scientific inquiry. For example, an explanation in terms of the positions of the stars for John F. Kennedy's assassination will not even make it past the threshold as a scientific explanation in the twenty-first century.
    • (1966) Philosophy of Natural Science , pp. 49-51
    • Hempel, C.G.1
  • 120
    • 0042681153 scopus 로고
    • Van fraassen on explanation
    • See, 322
    • See Philip Kitcher & Wesley Salmon, Van Fraassen on Explanation, 84 J. PHIL. 315, 322 (1987).
    • (1987) J. Phil. , vol.84 , pp. 315
    • Kitcher, P.1    Salmon, W.2
  • 121
    • 0000296665 scopus 로고
    • Studies in the logic of explanation
    • See, 136-37
    • See Carl G. Hempel & Paul Oppenheim, Studies in the Logic of Explanation, 15 PHIL. SCI. 135, 136-37 (1948)
    • (1948) Phil. Sci. , vol.15 , pp. 135
    • Hempel, C.G.1    Oppenheim, P.2
  • 122
    • 84875448887 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • reprinted in, supra note 42, at, There must be constraints on what is "admissible" in the explanans
    • reprinted in HEMPEL, ASPECTS, supra note 42, at 247-49. There must be constraints on what is "admissible" in the explanans.
    • Aspects , pp. 247-249
    • Hempel1
  • 123
    • 79959452475 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 137. A significant issue for the Hempel/Oppenheim account is how to understand the requirement that scientific laws be general. The statement, "no gold sphere has a mass greater than 100, 000 kg" is law-like and general in form, but it is nevertheless not a scientific law
    • See id. at 137. A significant issue for the Hempel/Oppenheim account is how to understand the requirement that scientific laws be general. The statement, "[n]o gold sphere has a mass greater than 100, 000 kg" is law-like and general in form, but it is nevertheless not a scientific law.
  • 124
    • 61149309937 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 5, at, Similarly, the argument "crows are the color of coal; coal is black; therefore, crows are black" is deductive, but it clearly is not an explanation of why crows are black
    • SALMON, FOUR DECADES, supra note 5, at 15. Similarly, the argument "[c]rows are the color of coal[;] [c]oal is black[;] [t]herefore, [c]rows are black" is deductive, but it clearly is not an explanation of why crows are black.
    • Four Decades , pp. 15
    • Salmon1
  • 126
    • 79959446219 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It is common to blur the distinction between deductive-nomological D-N explanation and hypothetico-deductive H-D confirmation because they function together in a model of scientific method. When scientists explain something, they take confirmed scientific hypotheses to be true and use them to explain observed phenomena. The correctness of the scientific hypothesis is presupposed by its use in an explanation. When testing a hypothesis, by contrast, scientists are working in the other direction, taking the observations as given and using them to confirm or disconfirm the hypothesis, whose correctness is yet to be established
    • It is common to blur the distinction between deductive-nomological (D-N) explanation and hypothetico-deductive (H-D) confirmation because they function together in a model of scientific method. When scientists explain something, they take confirmed scientific hypotheses to be true and use them to explain observed phenomena. The correctness of the scientific hypothesis is presupposed by its use in an explanation. When testing a hypothesis, by contrast, scientists are working in the other direction, taking the observations as given and using them to confirm or disconfirm the hypothesis, whose correctness is yet to be established.
  • 127
    • 79959448862 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See LIPTON, supra note 5, at 27 "The deductive-nomological model should produce a sense of déjà vu, since it is isomorphic to the hypothetico-deductive model of confirmation."
    • See LIPTON, supra note 5, at 27 ("The deductive-nomological model should produce a sense of déjà vu, since it is isomorphic to the hypothetico-deductive model of confirmation....");
  • 128
    • 61149309937 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 5, at
    • SALMON, FOUR DECADES, supra note 5, at 7.
    • Four Decades , pp. 7
    • Salmon1
  • 129
    • 79959383375 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The qualification here is necessary to bracket questions about scientific realism
    • The qualification here is necessary to bracket questions about scientific realism.
  • 130
    • 79959403407 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See generally VAN FRAASSEN, supra note 5 at 6-13 comparing scientific realism, which aims to give a literally true story of what the world is like, with constructive empiricism, which aims to give theories that are empirically adequate
    • See generally VAN FRAASSEN, supra note 5 at 6-13 (comparing scientific realism, which aims to give a literally true story of what the world is like, with constructive empiricism, which aims to give theories that are empirically adequate).
  • 131
    • 79959445197 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, supra note 51, at, A brief note on the terminology of theory and hypothesis: scientists use the term "theory" to refer to "the total set of those basic theoretical principles that leads to experimentally testable consequences."
    • See HEMPEL, PHILOSOPHY, supra note 51, at 5-11. A brief note on the terminology of theory and hypothesis: scientists use the term "theory" to refer to "the total set of those basic theoretical principles that leads to experimentally testable consequences."
    • Philosophy , pp. 5-11
    • Hempel1
  • 132
    • 79959388884 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 26-27. A theory can be tested by the H-D method, in which case it is appropriate to refer to it as a hypothesis. A great deal of misunderstanding in the public discourse around teaching evolution in public schools arises from the ordinary-language use of the word "theory", which can be understood as meaning something like "conjecture." Thus, opponents of teaching evolution attempt to stigmatize it as something other than accepted scientific knowledge. A better term that would capture the way the word theory is used by scientists would be Lakatos' idea of a scientific research program, which contains a hard core of fundamental postulates that are held to be true and which grows through phases of theoretical development that are empirically progressive with respect to preceding stages
    • Id. at 26-27. A theory can be tested by the H-D method, in which case it is appropriate to refer to it as a hypothesis. A great deal of misunderstanding in the public discourse around teaching evolution in public schools arises from the ordinary-language use of the word "theory", which can be understood as meaning something like "conjecture." Thus, opponents of teaching evolution attempt to stigmatize it as something other than accepted scientific knowledge. A better term that would capture the way the word theory is used by scientists would be Lakatos' idea of a scientific research program, which contains a hard core of fundamental postulates that are held to be true and which grows through phases of theoretical development that are empirically progressive with respect to preceding stages.
  • 133
    • 79959466074 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See NOLA & SANKEY, supra note 5, at 274-81 discussing Lakatos. But this is obviously not suitable for a bumpersticker description of what science is all about, and it is hard to come up with a term that captures both the confidence in the fundamental postulates of a research program and the virtue of science much emphasized by Popper that it is nondogmatic and always open to revision
    • See NOLA & SANKEY, supra note 5, at 274-81 (discussing Lakatos). But this is obviously not suitable for a bumpersticker description of what science is all about, and it is hard to come up with a term that captures both the confidence in the fundamental postulates of a research program and the virtue of science (much emphasized by Popper) that it is nondogmatic and always open to revision.
  • 134
    • 79959401785 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 253 citing Popper's views on the virtues of scientific inquiry
    • See id. at 253 (citing Popper's views on the virtues of scientific inquiry).
  • 135
    • 79959465534 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See NOLA & SANKEY, supra note 5, at 170-76
    • See NOLA & SANKEY, supra note 5, at 170-76.
  • 136
    • 79959449433 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 51, at, Hardcore jurisprudence geeks will recognize the allusion here to Dworkin's argument that integrity is the yet-unappreciated third political-moral value along with fairness and justice that was needed to explain our intuition that unprincipled legislative compromises were illegitimate
    • HEMPEL, PHILOSOPHY, supra note 51, at 52. Hardcore jurisprudence geeks will recognize the allusion here to Dworkin's argument that integrity is the yet-unappreciated third political-moral value (along with fairness and justice) that was needed to explain our intuition that unprincipled legislative compromises were illegitimate.
    • Philosophy , pp. 52
    • Hempel1
  • 137
    • 84936068266 scopus 로고
    • See, "Integrity is our Neptune."
    • See RONALD DWORKIN, LAW'S EMPIRE 183 (1986) ("Integrity is our Neptune.").
    • (1986) Law'S Empire , pp. 183
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 138
    • 79959426229 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Comets, pollen, and dreams: Some reflections on scientific explanation
    • supra note 46, at, 59-60 hereinafter SALMON, Comets explaining how the ideal gas law does not provide a causal explanation of the events that are subsumed under it
    • WESLEY C. SALMON, Comets, Pollen, and Dreams: Some Reflections on Scientific Explanation, in SALMON, CAUSALITY, supra note 46, at 55, 59-60 [hereinafter SALMON, Comets] (explaining how the ideal gas law does not provide a causal explanation of the events that are subsumed under it).
    • Salmon, Causality , pp. 55
    • Salmon, W.C.1
  • 139
    • 79959469199 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id
    • See id.
  • 140
    • 79959415531 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a simple example, consider Pascal's demonstration that twenty-five is the minimum number of tosses required to yield a better than 50% chance of getting double sixes with a pair of standard dice
    • For a simple example, consider Pascal's demonstration that twenty-five is the minimum number of tosses required to yield a better than 50% chance of getting double sixes with a pair of standard dice.
  • 141
    • 79959427324 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Scientific explanation: How we got from there to here
    • See, in, supra note 46, at, 307
    • See WESLEY C. SALMON, Scientific Explanation: How We Got From There to Here, in SALMON, CAUSALITY, supra note 46, at 302, 307.
    • Salmon, Causality , pp. 302
    • Wesley, C.S.1
  • 142
    • 84875448887 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 50, at 381-82
    • HEMPEL, Aspects, supra note 50, at 381-82.
    • Aspects
    • Hempel1
  • 143
    • 61149309937 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 5, at
    • SALMON, FOUR DECADES, supra note 5, at 58-59.
    • Four Decades , pp. 58-59
    • Salmon1
  • 144
    • 79959406012 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sophisticated statistical techniques for testing causal explanations underpin contemporary empirical social science disciplines, including empirical studies of law
    • Sophisticated statistical techniques for testing causal explanations underpin contemporary empirical social science disciplines, including empirical studies of law.
  • 145
    • 79959420822 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Epstein & King, supra note 11, at 19-114 proposing rules to help empirical researchers
    • See Epstein & King, supra note 11, at 19-114 (proposing rules to help empirical researchers).
  • 147
    • 79959445197 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 51, at
    • HEMPEL, PHILOSOPHY, supra note 51, at 7.
    • Philosophy , pp. 7
    • Hempel1
  • 148
    • 79959429563 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 48, at 14-20. This is obviously only a suggestive example because it does not express a scientific law that is of much interest, but the same kind of relationship between a universal and its instantiations holds for laws like "all metals expand when heated" or "all planets move in ellipses."
    • HEMPEL, Confirmation, supra note 48, at 14-20. This is obviously only a suggestive example because it does not express a scientific law that is of much interest, but the same kind of relationship between a universal and its instantiations holds for laws like "[a]ll metals expand when heated" or "[a]ll planets move in ellipses."
    • Confirmation
    • Hempel1
  • 149
    • 4344686569 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, hereinafter PSILLOS, CAUSATION AND EXPLANATION emphasis omitted
    • See STATHIS PSILLOS, CAUSATION AND EXPLANATION 162-67 (2002) [hereinafter PSILLOS, CAUSATION AND EXPLANATION] (emphasis omitted).
    • (2002) Causation and Explanation , pp. 162-167
    • Psillos, S.1
  • 150
    • 79959447889 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See NOLA & SANKEY, supra note 5, at 182-83 for a clear explanation of the ravens paradox
    • See NOLA & SANKEY, supra note 5, at 182-83 for a clear explanation of the ravens paradox.
  • 151
    • 79959481784 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • LIPTON, supra note 5, at 15
    • LIPTON, supra note 5, at 15.
  • 152
    • 79959426230 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See also NOLA & SANKEY, supra note 5, at 183 "The task for any theory of confirmation will be to remove the ravens paradox."
    • See also NOLA & SANKEY, supra note 5, at 183 ("The task for any theory of confirmation will be to remove the [ravens] paradox.").
  • 153
    • 79959456770 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Harman, supra note 5, at 90-91 "If. we think of the inference as an inference to the best explanation, we can explain when a person is and when he is not warranted in making the inference from 'All observed A's are B's' to 'All A's are B's.'"
    • See Harman, supra note 5, at 90-91 ("If... we think of the inference as an inference to the best explanation, we can explain when a person is and when he is not warranted in making the inference from 'All observed A's are B's' to 'All A's are B's.'").
  • 154
    • 79959398905 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • NOLA & SANKEY, supra note 5, at 121
    • NOLA & SANKEY, supra note 5, at 121.
  • 155
    • 79959482883 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Harman, supra note 5, at 89 "Such a judgment will be based on considerations such as which hypothesis is simpler, which is more plausible, which explains more, which is less ad hoc, and so forth."
    • Cf. Harman, supra note 5, at 89 ("[S]uch a judgment will be based on considerations such as which hypothesis is simpler, which is more plausible, which explains more, which is less ad hoc, and so forth.").
  • 156
    • 79959444035 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Thagard, supra note 5, at 79
    • See Thagard, supra note 5, at 79.
  • 157
    • 79959384673 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This example is from NOLA & SANKEY
    • This example is from NOLA & SANKEY.
  • 158
    • 79959422912 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 5, at 124. Harman talks about these background beliefs as lemmas that are obscured by seeing experimental confirmation as enumerative induction
    • See supra note 5, at 124. Harman talks about these background beliefs as lemmas that are obscured by seeing experimental confirmation as enumerative induction.
  • 159
    • 79959392030 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Harman, supra note 5, at 93
    • See Harman, supra note 5, at 93;
  • 160
    • 79959382864 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also LIPTON, supra note 5, at 59 "It is important to notice that the live options version of potential explanation already assumes an epistemic 'filter' that limits the pool of potential explanations to plausible candidates."
    • see also LIPTON, supra note 5, at 59 ("[I]t is important to notice that the live options version of potential explanation already assumes an epistemic 'filter' that limits the pool of potential explanations to plausible candidates.").
  • 161
    • 79959451862 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See NOLA & SANKEY, supra note 5, at 122-23 noting that "Rescher argues that we should not draw the conclusion that H is true, or that it is reasonable to suspect that H is true", but that we should rather conclude "only that H has greater verisimilitude than its rivals"
    • See NOLA & SANKEY, supra note 5, at 122-23 (noting that "Rescher argues that we should not draw the conclusion that H is true, or that it is reasonable to suspect that H is true", but that we should rather conclude "only that H has greater verisimilitude than its rivals").
  • 162
    • 79959386835 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See LIPTON, supra note 5, at 59-61
    • See LIPTON, supra note 5, at 59-61.
  • 163
    • 79959447336 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 60
    • Id. at 60.
  • 164
    • 79959421298 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 60-61
    • See id. at 60-61.
  • 165
    • 79959423477 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 61
    • See id. at 61.
  • 166
    • 79959462608 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., NOLA & SANKEY, supra note 5, at 129-30
    • See, e.g., NOLA & SANKEY, supra note 5, at 129-30;
  • 167
    • 79959466073 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • VAN FRAASSEN, supra note 5, at 88 discussing the virtues of a theory beyond empirical adequacy
    • VAN FRAASSEN, supra note 5, at 88 (discussing the virtues of a theory beyond empirical adequacy);
  • 168
    • 84936060926 scopus 로고
    • Book review
    • see also, 679, "The fact that S, if true, would be a better explanation than T cannot establish either that S is true or an actual explanation."
    • see also Jesse Hobbs, Book Review, 60 PHIL. SCI. 679, 679 (1993) ("[T]he fact that S, if true, would be a better explanation than T cannot establish either that S is true or an actual explanation....");
    • (1993) Phil. Sci. , vol.60 , pp. 679
    • Hobbs, J.1
  • 169
    • 79959448433 scopus 로고
    • Book review
    • 971, noting challenges to Lipton's theories in the course of reviewing his book
    • Peter Milne, Book Review, 53 PHIL. & PHENOMENOLOGICAL RES. 970, 971 (1993) (noting challenges to Lipton's theories in the course of reviewing his book);
    • (1993) Phil. & Phenomenological Res , vol.53 , pp. 970
    • Milne, P.1
  • 170
    • 79959422913 scopus 로고
    • Book review
    • 420, noting in reviewing Lipton's book the common view that "it would be foolhardy or dogmatic to assume that explanatory adequacy and truth coincide"
    • Jonathan Vogel, Book Review, 102 PHIL. REV. 419, 420 (1993) (noting in reviewing Lipton's book the common view that "it would be foolhardy or dogmatic to assume that explanatory adequacy and truth coincide").
    • (1993) Phil. Rev. , vol.102 , pp. 419
    • Vogel, J.1
  • 171
    • 79959397233 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., LIPTON, supra note 5, at 206
    • See, e.g., LIPTON, supra note 5, at 206;
  • 172
    • 79959471812 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • NOLA & SANKEY, supra note 5, at 120
    • NOLA & SANKEY, supra note 5, at 120;
  • 173
    • 79959407694 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Thagard, supra note 5, at 77
    • Thagard, supra note 5, at 77;
  • 175
    • 79959422914 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See NOLA & SANKEY, supra note 5, at 120
    • See NOLA & SANKEY, supra note 5, at 120.
  • 176
    • 79959410776 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See LIPTON, supra note 5, at 64
    • See LIPTON, supra note 5, at 64.
  • 177
    • 79959413669 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For example, when fitting a curve to observed data, an experimenter may prefer a curve that passes through more data points or is simpler. Two potential rules, "always choose the simple curve" and "always choose the more complex curve", have opposing virtues and vices. The "always simple" rule may lack empirical accuracy while the "always complex" rule will deviate from the true curve because of noise in the data. Thus, some judgment will be required to make the best tradeoff between considerations of fit and simplicity
    • For example, when fitting a curve to observed data, an experimenter may prefer a curve that passes through more data points or is simpler. Two potential rules, "always choose the simple curve" and "always choose the more complex curve", have opposing virtues and vices. The "always simple" rule may lack empirical accuracy while the "always complex" rule will deviate from the true curve because of noise in the data. Thus, some judgment will be required to make the best tradeoff between considerations of fit and simplicity.
  • 178
    • 79959392032 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See NOLA & SANKEY, supra note 5, at 141
    • See NOLA & SANKEY, supra note 5, at 141.
  • 179
    • 79959452474 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Paul Thagard insists that "theories must not achieve consilience at the expense of simplicity", Thagard, supra note 5, at 89, but in some cases, the tradeoff may be inevitable
    • Paul Thagard insists that "[t]heories must not achieve consilience at the expense of simplicity", Thagard, supra note 5, at 89, but in some cases, the tradeoff may be inevitable.
  • 180
    • 79959445197 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, supra note 51, at
    • See HEMPEL, PHILOSOPHY, supra note 51, at 42.
    • Philosophy , pp. 42
    • Hempel1
  • 181
    • 79959481783 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 44 considering Popper's view
    • Id. at 44 (considering Popper's view).
  • 182
    • 79959413095 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id
    • See id.
  • 183
    • 79959445197 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 51, at, "If the earlier cases have all been obtained by tests of the same kind, but the new finding is the result of a different kind of test, the confirmation of the hypothesis may be significantly enhanced."
    • HEMPEL, PHILOSOPHY, supra note 51, at 34 ("If the earlier cases have all been obtained by tests of the same kind, but the new finding is the result of a different kind of test, the confirmation of the hypothesis may be significantly enhanced.");
    • Philosophy , pp. 34
    • Hempel1
  • 184
    • 79959387769 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Thagard, supra note 5, at 79 "One theory is more consilient than another if it explains more classes of facts than the other does."
    • Thagard, supra note 5, at 79 ("[O]ne theory is more consilient than another if it explains more classes of facts than the other does.");
  • 185
    • 0003971095 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also, arguing for the unification of all human knowledge, including science and the humanities. For the value of consilience in legal explanation
    • see also EDWARD O. WILSON, CONSILIENCE: THE UNITY OF KNOWLEDGE 266 (1998) (arguing for the unification of all human knowledge, including science and the humanities). For the value of consilience in legal explanation
    • (1998) Consilience: The Unity of Knowledge , pp. 266
    • Wilson, E.O.1
  • 188
    • 79959408308 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Thagard, supra note 5, at 77-78, 81
    • Thagard, supra note 5, at 77-78, 81.
  • 189
    • 79959488493 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • KUHN, supra note 88, at 71
    • KUHN, supra note 88, at 71.
  • 190
    • 79959487927 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Thagard, supra note 5, at 86
    • Thagard, supra note 5, at 86.
  • 191
    • 79959404492 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., NOLA & SANKEY, supra note 5, at 42
    • See, e.g., NOLA & SANKEY, supra note 5, at 42.
  • 192
    • 79959460354 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • KUHN, supra note 88, at 68-69. As Kuhn notes, Copernicus showed considerable insight in seeing as disconfirming evidence what other astronomers viewed only as puzzles to be solved by the application of Ptolemaic principles
    • KUHN, supra note 88, at 68-69. As Kuhn notes, Copernicus showed considerable insight in seeing as disconfirming evidence what other astronomers viewed only as puzzles to be solved by the application of Ptolemaic principles.
  • 193
    • 79959466668 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 79
    • Id. at 79.
  • 194
    • 79959487199 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 68-69
    • See id. at 68-69.
  • 195
    • 79959454372 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Thagard, supra note 5, at 87
    • Thagard, supra note 5, at 87.
  • 196
    • 79959486435 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • KUHN, supra note 88, at 70-72
    • KUHN, supra note 88, at 70-72.
  • 197
    • 79959381734 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See NOLA & SANKEY, supra note 5, at 41-43 questioning whether we are in a world in which maximum parsimony is the best guide to truth
    • See NOLA & SANKEY, supra note 5, at 41-43 (questioning whether we are in a world in which maximum parsimony is the best guide to truth).
  • 198
    • 79959415530 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See NOLA & SANKEY, supra note 5, at 337-41
    • See NOLA & SANKEY, supra note 5, at 337-41.
  • 199
    • 79959387212 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See KUHN, supra note 88, at 104
    • See KUHN, supra note 88, at 104;
  • 200
    • 79959432670 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • LIPTON, supra note 5, at 122
    • LIPTON, supra note 5, at 122.
  • 201
    • 79959413096 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See KUHN, supra note 88, at 103-04
    • See KUHN, supra note 88, at 103-04.
  • 202
    • 61149309937 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, supra note 5, at 124-26 describing experiments to measure Avogadro's number
    • See SALMON, FOUR DECADES, supra note 5, at 124-26 (describing experiments to measure Avogadro's number).
    • Four Decades
    • Salmon1
  • 204
    • 79959410777 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id
    • See id.
  • 205
    • 79959445197 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, supra note 51, at, "What scientific explanation. aims at is... an objective kind of insight that is achieved by a systematic unification, by exhibiting the phenomena as manifestations of common underlying structures and processes that conform to specific, testable, basic principles."
    • See HEMPEL, PHILOSOPHY, supra note 51, at 83 ("What scientific explanation... aims at is... an objective kind of insight that is achieved by [a] systematic unification, by exhibiting the phenomena as manifestations of common underlying structures and processes that conform to specific, testable, basic principles.");
    • Philosophy , pp. 83
    • Hempel1
  • 206
    • 0038922382 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Explanatory unification
    • supra note 5, at, 167
    • Philip Kitcher, Explanatory Unification, in THEORIES OF EXPLANATION, supra note 5, at 167, 167.
    • Theories of Explanation , pp. 167
    • Kitcher, P.1
  • 207
    • 79959488494 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • NOLA & SANKEY, supra note 5, at 127
    • NOLA & SANKEY, supra note 5, at 127.
  • 208
    • 0040107718 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Explanation and scientific understanding
    • supra note 5, at, 195
    • Michael Friedman, Explanation and Scientific Understanding, in THEORIES OF EXPLANATION, supra note 5, at 188, 195.
    • Theories of Explanation , pp. 188
    • Friedman, M.1
  • 209
    • 79959454927 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See NOLA & SANKEY, supra note 5, at 55-56, 74-77
    • See NOLA & SANKEY, supra note 5, at 55-56, 74-77.
  • 210
    • 79959437520 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 341
    • See id. at 341.
  • 211
    • 79959469198 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 341-44 discussing Putnam's "no miracles argument" and considering whether it is IBE, only at the metamethodological level
    • Id. at 341-44 (discussing Putnam's "no miracles argument" and considering whether it is IBE, only at the metamethodological level).
  • 212
    • 79959395376 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 55
    • See id. at 55.
  • 213
    • 79959418539 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The principle of demarcation, differentiating science from nonscience, is associated with the work of Karl Popper, although it is an important background norm in the philosophy of science overall
    • The principle of demarcation, differentiating science from nonscience, is associated with the work of Karl Popper, although it is an important background norm in the philosophy of science overall.
  • 214
    • 0003699334 scopus 로고
    • See generally, For an overview of the history of the demarcation principle
    • See generally KARL POPPER, THE LOGIC OF SCIENTIFIC DISCOVERY (1959). For an overview of the history of the demarcation principle
    • (1959) The Logic of Scientific Discovery
    • Popper, K.1
  • 215
    • 79959447888 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see NOLA &: SANKEY, supra note 5, at 253-74. In popular culture, TV shows like Mythbusters and Penn and Teller: Bullshit are dedicated to policing the boundary between science and, well, bullshit
    • see NOLA &: SANKEY, supra note 5, at 253-74. In popular culture, TV shows like Mythbusters and Penn and Teller: Bullshit are dedicated to policing the boundary between science and, well, bullshit
  • 216
    • 0002248585 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The logic of functional analysis
    • See, in, supra note 42, 304 hereinafter HEMPEL, Functional Analysis
    • See CARL G. HEMPEL, The Logic of Functional Analysis, in HEMPEL, ASPECTS, supra note 42, at 297, 304 [hereinafter HEMPEL, Functional Analysis];
    • Hempel, Aspects , pp. 297
    • Hempel, C.G.1
  • 217
    • 61149309937 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 5, at, 26
    • SALMON, FOUR DECADES, supra note 5, at 4, 26;
    • Four Decades , pp. 4
    • Salmon1
  • 218
    • 0001005675 scopus 로고
    • Functions
    • 141
    • Larry Wright, Functions, 82 PHIL. REV. 139, 141 (1973).
    • (1973) Phil. Rev. , vol.82 , pp. 139
    • Wright, L.1
  • 219
    • 79959436188 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The example is from SALMON, Comets, supra note 58, at 60-61
    • The example is from SALMON, Comets, supra note 58, at 60-61.
  • 220
    • 61149309937 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, supra note 5, at, discussing how behavior or a feature of an organism can be understood causally if it has been causally efficacious in the past at bringing about some goal
    • See SALMON, FOUR DECADES, supra note 5, at 111-14 (discussing how behavior or a feature of an organism can be understood causally if it has been causally efficacious in the past at bringing about some goal).
    • Four Decades , pp. 111-114
    • Salmon1
  • 223
    • 79959398904 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. Leaving aside the problem of aggregating individual intents, a statute may sometimes be explained functionally or purposively in terms of some problem in response to which it was enacted. As English lawyers would say, a statute makes sense in light of the "mischief" it was designed to remedy
    • Id. Leaving aside the problem of aggregating individual intents, a statute may sometimes be explained functionally (or purposively) in terms of some problem in response to which it was enacted. (As English lawyers would say, a statute makes sense in light of the "mischief" it was designed to remedy.
  • 224
    • 79959471811 scopus 로고
    • See Heydon's Case, K. B. 638, 3 Co. Rep. 7a, 7b. The examples given in the introduction, however, do not appeal to the intent of an individual lawmaker or legislature and thus pose the problem we are interested in here, namely what it means to explain something more general, like a legal doctrine
    • See Heydon's Case, (1584) 76 Eng. Rep. 637 (K. B.) 638, 3 Co. Rep. 7a,
    • (1584) Eng. Rep , vol.76 , pp. 637
  • 225
    • 79959457908 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Coleman, supra note 7, at 193
    • Coleman, supra note 7, at 193.
  • 226
    • 79959414949 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id
    • See id.
  • 227
    • 79959442940 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., id. at 194 noting that "if economic analysis is an interpretive theory in the Dworkinian sense, then it is a particularly bad one on the dimension of fit"
    • See, e.g., id. at 194 (noting that "if economic analysis is an interpretive theory in the Dworkinian sense, then it is a particularly bad one on the dimension of fit").
  • 228
    • 79959412506 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra notes 111-13 and accompanying text
    • See supra notes 111-13 and accompanying text
  • 230
    • 79959435597 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 27
    • See id. at 27.
  • 231
    • 79959463406 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 27-28
    • See id. at 27-28.
  • 232
    • 79959392033 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Unless these criteria can be specified with some degree of precision, there is a danger that the evaluation of doctrinal legal scholarship is inherently subjective and, therefore, susceptible to unconscious biases
    • Unless these criteria can be specified with some degree of precision, there is a danger that the evaluation of doctrinal legal scholarship is inherently subjective and, therefore, susceptible to unconscious biases.
  • 233
    • 79959390878 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Rubin, supra note 7, at 894 & n. 13, 895-96 arguing that the evaluation of legal scholarship tends to be mostly intuitive, in that readers find a work "insightful" or creative without being able to specify exacdy what these terms mean and with the resulting danger that idiosyncratic personal reactions may determine the reputation of a scholar
    • See Rubin, supra note 7, at 894 & n. 13, 895-96 (arguing that the evaluation of legal scholarship tends to be mostly intuitive, in that readers find a work "insightful" or creative without being able to specify exacdy what these terms mean and with the resulting danger that idiosyncratic personal reactions may determine the reputation of a scholar).
  • 234
    • 0004166519 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 8, at, 225-28, 230-31, 239-40, 248-49, 255
    • DWORKIN, LAW'S EMPIRE, supra note 8, at 217-18, 225-28, 230-31, 239-40, 248-49, 255.
    • Law'S Empire , pp. 217-218
    • Dworkin1
  • 235
    • 46749102755 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Philosophy of the common law
    • For a helpful summary of Dworkin's position, see, in, 608 Jules Coleman & Scott Shapiro eds., "The methodology requires that the deliberator seek that set of general principles theory that makes the best overall sense of law, such that the principles not only imply the more specific rules or decisions under review but also show them to be justified for this the principles must approximate true or rationally warranted principles of morality. Alternative principles are ranked according to the extent to which they 'fit' the legal data and 'appeal' from a moral point of view."
    • For a helpful summary of Dworkin's position, see Gerald J. Postema, Philosophy of the Common Law, in THE OXFORD HANDBOOK OF JURISPRUDENCE AND PHILOSOPHY OF LAW 588, 608 (Jules Coleman & Scott Shapiro eds., 2002) ("[T]he methodology requires that the deliberator seek that set of general principles (theory) that makes the best overall sense of law, such that the principles not only imply the more specific rules or decisions under review but also show them to be justified (for this the principles must approximate true or rationally warranted principles of morality). Alternative principles are ranked according to the extent to which they 'fit' the legal data and 'appeal' from a moral point of view.").
    • (2002) The Oxford Handbook of Jurisprudence and Philosophy of Law , pp. 588
    • Postema, G.J.1
  • 236
    • 0004166519 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, supra note 8, at, "Law as integrity asks judges to assume, so far as this is possible, that the law is structured by a coherent set of principles about justice and fairness and procedural due process. But... integrity does not recommend... that we should all be governed by the same goals and strategies... and it does not frown on this diversity."
    • See DWORKIN, LAW'S EMPIRE, supra note 8, at 243 ("Law as integrity asks judges to assume, so far as this is possible, that the law is structured by a coherent set of principles about justice and fairness and procedural due process.... But... integrity does not recommend... that we should all be governed by the same goals and strategies... and [it] does not frown on this diversity.").
    • Law'S Empire , pp. 243
    • Dworkin1
  • 238
    • 0004166519 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, supra note 8, at
    • See DWORKIN, LAW'S EMPIRE, supra note 8, at 244.
    • Law'S Empire , pp. 244
    • Dworkin1
  • 239
    • 79959476583 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 247 arguing that his ideal judge Hercules "must take into account not only the numbers of decisions counting for each interpretation i.e. enumerative induction, but whether the decisions expressing one principle seem more important or fundamental or wide-ranging than the decisions expressing the other."
    • See id. at 247 (arguing that his ideal judge Hercules "must take into account not only the numbers of decisions counting for each interpretation [i.e. enumerative induction], but whether the decisions expressing one principle seem more important or fundamental or wide-ranging than the decisions expressing the other.").
  • 240
    • 79959387768 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 249
    • Id. at 249.
  • 241
    • 79959390284 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 166, 185-90, 198-202, 211-15 noting that "we have a duty to honor our responsibilities under social practices that define groups and attach special responsibilities to membership"
    • Id. at 166, 185-90, 198-202, 211-15 (noting that "[w]e have a duty to honor our responsibilities under social practices that define groups and attach special responsibilities to membership").
  • 242
    • 79959469748 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 211
    • Id. at 211.
  • 243
    • 79959433897 scopus 로고
    • See, at, 6th prtg, A Reply to Critics
    • See RONALD DWORKIN, TAKING RIGHTS SERIOUSLY app. at 325-26 (6th prtg. 1979) (A Reply to Critics).
    • (1979) Taking Rights Seriously App , pp. 325-326
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 244
    • 79959447887 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • GARFINKEL, supra note 5, at 21
    • GARFINKEL, supra note 5, at 21.
  • 245
    • 79959469747 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 246
    • 79959397232 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • An example to which all parents can relate is from LIPTON, supra note 5, at 33. When the author asked his three-year-old son why he threw his food on the floor, his son answered that he was full. The author, of course, was asking why the three-year-old threw his food on the floor rather than leaving it on his plate, so the explanation failed to satisfy the relevant "why?" question
    • An example to which all parents can relate is from LIPTON, supra note 5, at 33. When the author asked his three-year-old son why he threw his food on the floor, his son answered that he was full. The author, of course, was asking why the three-year-old threw his food on the floor rather than leaving it on his plate, so the explanation failed to satisfy the relevant "why?" question.
  • 247
    • 79959472354 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See GARFINKEL, supra note 5, at 28-41 noting that when we ask why the sky is blue, we "are really asking of the sky why it is blue rather than some other color"
    • See GARFINKEL, supra note 5, at 28-41 (noting that when we ask why the sky is blue, we "are really asking of the sky why it is blue rather than some other color");
  • 248
    • 0004113842 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 5, at, noting that the correct general, underlying structure of a why-question is "Why is it the case that P in contrast to other members of A?", where X is a set of alternatives
    • VAN FRAASSEN, THE SCIENTIFIC IMAGE, supra note 5, at 126-29 (noting that the correct general, underlying structure of a why-question is "Why (is it the case that) P in contrast to (other members of) A?", where X is a set of alternatives).
    • The Scientific Image , pp. 126-129
    • Van Fraassen1
  • 249
    • 79959474876 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. NOLA & SANKEY, supra note 5, at 32 noting that our values enter into our decisions about science, particularly our acceptance or rejection of theories
    • Cf. NOLA & SANKEY, supra note 5, at 32 (noting that our values enter into our decisions about science, particularly our acceptance or rejection of theories).
  • 250
    • 79959481346 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., id. at 123-30 exploring different theories of "what is meant by being a better explanation"
    • See, e.g., id. at 123-30 (exploring different theories of "what is meant by being a better explanation").
  • 251
  • 252
    • 79959463947 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra notes 106-10 and accompanying text
    • See supra notes 106-10 and accompanying text
  • 254
    • 79959435032 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 46 noting the development of the word "tort" to cover a range of concepts
    • See id. at 46 (noting the development of the word "tort" to cover a range of concepts).
  • 255
    • 79959419115 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 48-56
    • Id. at 48-56.
  • 259
    • 3142736107 scopus 로고
    • Wealth maximization and tort law: A philosophical inquiry
    • 111 David G. Owen ed., showing that a system of tort law guided toward wealth maximization is consistent with the moral traditions of society
    • Richard A. Posner, Wealth Maximization and Tort Law: A Philosophical Inquiry, in PHILOSOPHICAL FOUNDATIONS OF TORT LAW 99, 111 (David G. Owen ed., 1995) (showing that a system of tort law guided toward wealth maximization is consistent with the moral traditions of society).
    • (1995) Philosophical Foundations of Tort Law , pp. 99
    • Posner, R.A.1
  • 260
    • 79959468075 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Posner, supra note 145, at 103 noting that wealth maximization resonates well with several moral theories and offends none
    • Posner, supra note 145, at 103 (noting that wealth maximization resonates well with several moral theories and offends none).
  • 262
    • 27844524218 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Is wealth a value?
    • See, e.g., in, supra note 8, at, 237 noting that the "normative failures of economic analysis of the law are so great that they cast doubt on its descriptive claims"
    • See, e.g., RONALD M. DWORKIN, Is Wealth a Value?, in A MATTER OF PRINCIPLE, supra note 8, at 237, 237 (noting that the "normative failures of [economic analysis of the law] are so great that they cast doubt on its descriptive claims").
    • A Matter of Principle , pp. 237
    • Dworkin, R.M.1
  • 264
    • 0004106103 scopus 로고
    • noting that some theorists "instead of emphasizing goals such as wealth maximization or market deterrence. champion liberty or community" footnotes omitted
    • ERNEST J. WEINRIB, THE IDEA OF PRIVATE LAW 3-4 (1995) (noting that some theorists "[i]nstead of emphasizing goals such as wealth maximization or market deterrence... champion liberty or community" (footnotes omitted));
    • (1995) The Idea of Private Law , pp. 3-4
    • Weinrib, E.J.1
  • 265
    • 78649266067 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Torts as wrongs
    • 918, arguing that tort law is a law of wrongs and recourse
    • John C. P. Goldberg & Benjamin C. Zipursky, Torts as Wrongs, 88 TEX. L. REV. 917, 918 (2010) (arguing that tort law is a law of wrongs and recourse);
    • (2010) Tex. L. Rev. , vol.88 , pp. 917
    • Goldberg, J.C.P.1    Zipursky, B.C.2
  • 266
    • 3042598392 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawlsian fairness and regime choice in the law of accidents
    • 1858, examining tort law from a fairness perspective
    • Gregory C. Keating, Rawlsian Fairness and Regime Choice in the Law of Accidents, 72 FORDHAM L. REV. 1857, 1858 (2004) (examining tort law from a fairness perspective);
    • (2004) Fordham L. Rev. , vol.72 , pp. 1857
    • Keating, G.C.1
  • 267
    • 21144478652 scopus 로고
    • The moral foundations of tort law
    • 450, examining the moral foundations of tort law
    • Stephen R. Perry, The Moral Foundations of Tort Law, 77 IOWA L. REV. 449, 450 (1992) (examining the moral foundations of tort law).
    • (1992) Iowa L. Rev. , vol.77 , pp. 449
    • Perry, S.R.1
  • 268
    • 21144460921 scopus 로고
    • Substantive corrective justice
    • See generally, discussing corrective and distributive justice
    • See generally Richard W. Wright, Substantive Corrective Justice, 77 IOWA L. REV. 625 (1992) (discussing corrective and distributive justice).
    • (1992) Iowa L. Rev. , vol.77 , pp. 625
    • Wright, R.W.1
  • 269
    • 0000625557 scopus 로고
    • Wide reflective equilibrium and theory acceptance in ethics
    • See, 271, The methodology of reflective equilibrium was made prominent by Rawls
    • See Norman Daniels, Wide Reflective Equilibrium and Theory Acceptance in Ethics, 76 J. PHIL. 256, 271 (1979). The methodology of reflective equilibrium was made prominent by Rawls.
    • (1979) J. Phil. , vol.76 , pp. 256
    • Daniels, N.1
  • 271
    • 0001333853 scopus 로고
    • Outline of a decision procedure for ethics
    • See generally
    • See generally John Rawls, Outline of a Decision Procedure for Ethics, 60 PHIL. REV. 177 (1951).
    • (1951) Phil. Rev. , vol.60 , pp. 177
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 272
    • 79959433324 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Considered" moral judgments are not merely intuitions, but those initial judgments that have been "filtered" to screen out judgments made under conditions that may be conducive to errors. Daniels, supra note 150, at 258, 266. In this way they are quite different from the moral intuitions studied by social psychologists
    • "Considered" moral judgments are not merely intuitions, but those initial judgments that have been "filtered" to screen out judgments made under conditions that may be conducive to errors. Daniels, supra note 150, at 258, 266. In this way they are quite different from the moral intuitions studied by social psychologists.
  • 273
    • 84909358155 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The emotional dog and its rational tail: A social intuitionist approach to moral judgment
    • See, e.g., 814, arguing that moral intuitions come before moral judgments. The reactions observed in Haidt's subjects have not been subjected to rational reflection and thus do not count as considered moral judgments. I am not claiming here that reasoning is the cause of moral judgments, and in fact, I am not making any causal claims at all
    • See, e.g., Jonathan Haidt, The Emotional Dog and Its Rational Tail: A Social Intuitionist Approach to Moral Judgment, 108 PSYCHOL. REV. 814, 814 (2001) (arguing that moral intuitions come before moral judgments). The reactions observed in Haidt's subjects have not been subjected to rational reflection and thus do not count as considered moral judgments. I am not claiming here that reasoning is the cause of moral judgments, and in fact, I am not making any causal claims at all.
    • (2001) Psychol. Rev. , vol.108 , pp. 814
    • Haidt, J.1
  • 274
    • 79959485152 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. id. at 815 claiming that the social intutionist model is "an antirationalist model only in one limited sense: It says that moral reasoning is rarely the direct cause of moral judgment". The analysis here is of theory construction, not moral decision making
    • Cf. id. at 815 (claiming that the social intutionist model is "an antirationalist model only in one limited sense: It says that moral reasoning is rarely the direct cause of moral judgment"). The analysis here is of theory construction, not moral decision making.
  • 275
    • 79959427856 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Daniels, supra note 150, at 262
    • Daniels, supra note 150, at 262.
  • 276
    • 79959399560 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • RAWLS, supra note 150, at 49 noting that "moral philosophy is Socratic: we may want to change our present considered judgments once their regulative principles are brought to light"
    • RAWLS, supra note 150, at 49 (noting that "[m]oral philosophy is Socratic: we may want to change our present considered judgments once their regulative principles are brought to light").
  • 277
    • 79959455430 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Daniels, supra note 150, at 267. Daniels righdy says that this is a Quinean view about the relationship between facts in this case, considered moral judgments instead of nonmoral observation reports and theories
    • Daniels, supra note 150, at 267. Daniels righdy says that this is a Quinean view about the relationship between facts (in this case, considered moral judgments instead of nonmoral observation reports) and theories.
  • 278
    • 79959411347 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 267 n. 16
    • Id. at 267 n. 16.
  • 279
    • 0003799915 scopus 로고
    • See generally, Coherence and holism about truth and meaning is also associated with the work of Davidson
    • See generally WILLARD VAN ORMAN QUINE, WORD AND OBJECT (1960). Coherence (and holism) about truth and meaning is also associated with the work of Davidson.
    • (1960) Word and Object
    • Van Orman Quine, W.1
  • 281
    • 84935464287 scopus 로고
    • Legal formalism: On the immanent rationality of law
    • See, e.g., 967
    • See, e.g., Ernest J. Weinrib, Legal Formalism: On the Immanent Rationality of Law, 97 YALE L. J. 949, 967 (1988).
    • (1988) Yale L. J. , vol.97 , pp. 949
    • Weinrib, E.J.1
  • 282
    • 31144458448 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Coleman argues, for example, that there is an intuitive difference between "misfortunes owing to human agency and those which are no one's responsibility", and this helps explain features of tort law such as the malfeasance vs. nonfeasance distinction, supra note 8, at 44
    • Coleman argues, for example, that there is an intuitive difference between "misfortunes owing to human agency and those which are no one's responsibility", and this helps explain features of tort law such as the malfeasance vs. nonfeasance distinction. COLEMAN, PRACTICE OF PRINCIPLE, supra note 8, at 44.
    • Practice of Principle
    • Coleman1
  • 283
    • 79959480762 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See e.g. Posner, supra note 145, at 111
    • See e.g. Posner, supra note 145, at 111.
  • 284
    • 79959428424 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra notes 111-13 and accompanying text
    • See supra notes 111-13 and accompanying text.
  • 285
    • 79959402841 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Zipursky, supra note 8, at 1704
    • Zipursky, supra note 8, at 1704.
  • 286
    • 10844221660 scopus 로고
    • The law wishes to have a formal existence
    • Cf, in, 141, imputing to law-metaphorically, obviously, while literally referring to legal theorists-the desire not "to have recourse to any supplementary discourse" that would compromise the law's autonomy
    • Cf. STANLEY FISH, The Law Wishes to Have a Formal Existence, in THERE'S NO SUCH THING AS FREE SPEECH AND IT'S A GOOD THING, TOO 141, 141 (1994) (imputing to law-metaphorically, obviously, while literally referring to legal theorists-the desire not "to have recourse to [any] supplementary discourse" that would compromise the law's autonomy).
    • (1994) There'S No Such Thing as Free Speech and It'S A Good Thing, Too , pp. 141
    • Fish, S.1
  • 287
    • 0004166519 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, supra note 8, at
    • See DWORKIN, LAW'S EMPIRE, supra note 8, at 243.
    • Law'S Empire , pp. 243
    • Dworkin1
  • 289
    • 23844434692 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Professionalism as interpretation
    • 1198
    • W. Bradley Wendel, Professionalism as Interpretation, 99 NW. U. L. REV. 1167, 1198 (2005).
    • (2005) Nw. U. L. Rev. , vol.99 , pp. 1167
    • Wendel, W.B.1
  • 290
    • 79959390876 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Zipursky, supra note 8, at 1714-16
    • Zipursky, supra note 8, at 1714-16.
  • 291
    • 0004166519 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, supra note 8, at 225-75
    • See DWORKIN, LAW'S EMPIRE, supra note 8, at 225-75.
    • Law'S Empire
    • Dworkin1
  • 292
    • 79959453819 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra notes 125-33 and accompanying text
    • See supra notes 125-33 and accompanying text
  • 293
    • 79959416108 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Beebe, supra note 18, at 815
    • See Beebe, supra note 18, at 815.
  • 294
    • 79959445196 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 813, 820. This observation requires its own IBE argument, inferring from the existence of sumptuary laws throughout history to an explanation in terms of a social need for consumption-based systems of creating class distinctions
    • Id. at 813, 820. This observation requires its own IBE argument, inferring from the existence of sumptuary laws throughout history to an explanation in terms of a social need for consumption-based systems of creating class distinctions.
  • 295
    • 79959405069 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 812-13
    • See id. at 812-13.
  • 296
    • 79959417184 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 814, 825-27
    • Id. at 814, 825-27.
  • 297
    • 79959465084 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 818 & n. 33 also referring to super copies as "genuine fakes". California and other New World winemakers' "Champagne" presents a similar problem
    • Id. at 818 & n. 33 (also referring to super copies as "genuine fakes"). California and other New World winemakers' "Champagne" presents a similar problem.
  • 298
    • 79959449430 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 832
    • See id. at 832.
  • 299
    • 79959441042 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Beebe describes the problem as follows: "The majority of consumers would likely confront a marketplace consisting of goods that will set them apart only briefly, if at all, before quickly being copied and rendered commonplace."
    • Beebe describes the problem as follows: "[T]he majority of consumers would likely confront a marketplace consisting of goods that will set them apart only briefly, if at all, before quickly being copied and rendered commonplace."
  • 300
    • 79959430972 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 837
    • Id. at 837.
  • 301
    • 79959407692 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 816, 869-71. Antidilution protection prevents the use of a trademark even if there is no possibility of confusion regarding the origin of the good or service, for example in the marketing of "Tylenol snowboards, Netscape sex shops, and Harry Potter dry cleaners."
    • Id. at 816, 869-71. Antidilution protection prevents the use of a trademark even if there is no possibility of confusion regarding the origin of the good or service, for example in the marketing of "Tylenol snowboards, Netscape sex shops, and Harry Potter dry cleaners."
  • 302
    • 79959390877 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 846 quoting Mattel, Inc. v. MCA Records, Inc
    • Id. at 846 (quoting Mattel, Inc. v. MCA Records, Inc.
  • 303
    • 84865434181 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 903 9th Cir, Geographic origin designations protect descriptions such as Champagne and Burgundy from being appropriated by producers outside a particular area, using unapproved processes
    • F.3d 894, 903 (9th Cir. 2002)). Geographic origin designations protect descriptions such as Champagne and Burgundy from being appropriated by producers outside a particular area, using unapproved processes.
    • (2002) F.3d , vol.296 , pp. 894
  • 304
    • 79959421849 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 869-70
    • Id. at 869-70.
  • 305
    • 79959469746 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Beebe concedes that one purpose of intellectual property law remains the prevention of misappropriation and thus the creation of incentives for technological and artistic innovation
    • Beebe concedes that one purpose of intellectual property law remains the prevention of misappropriation and thus the creation of incentives for technological and artistic innovation.
  • 306
    • 79959407691 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 813. It is clear, however, that he wants to claim pride of place for his explanation in terms of sumptuary regulation. Antidilution and authenticity protection, he writes, "operate according to assumptions that run contrary to nearly everything we conventionally believe about the nature of intellectual property and the purposes of intellectual property law."
    • Id. at 813. It is clear, however, that he wants to claim pride of place for his explanation in terms of sumptuary regulation. Antidilution and authenticity protection, he writes, "operate according to assumptions that run contrary to nearly everything we conventionally believe about the nature of intellectual property and the purposes of intellectual property law."
  • 307
    • 79959480192 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 817
    • Id. at 817.
  • 308
    • 79959415529 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 847
    • See id. at 847.
  • 309
    • 79959394263 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra notes 69-72 and accompanying text
    • See supra notes 69-72 and accompanying text.
  • 310
    • 79959427323 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Beebe, supra note 18, at 886-87
    • Beebe, supra note 18, at 886-87.
  • 312
    • 73049117279 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The failure of economic interpretations of the law of contract damages
    • For a similar criticism of the economic analysis of contract law based on its inability to account for bilateralism of remedies, see, 851-53
    • For a similar criticism of the economic analysis of contract law based on its inability to account for bilateralism of remedies, see Nathan B. Oman, The Failure of Economic Interpretations of the Law of Contract Damages, 64 WASH. & LEE L. REV. 829, 851-53 (2007).
    • (2007) Wash. & Lee L. Rev. , vol.64 , pp. 829
    • Oman, N.B.1
  • 313
    • 79959394262 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., 8th ed, discussing workers' compensation
    • See, e.g., MARC A. FRANKLIN ET AL., TORT LAW AND ALTERNATIVES 816-38 (8th ed. 2006) (discussing workers' compensation).
    • (2006) Tort Law and Alternatives , pp. 816-838
    • Franklin, M.A.1
  • 314
    • 79959407693 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 863-65 discussing the National Childhood Vaccine Injury Act of 1986, Pub. L. No. 99-660
    • Id. at 863-65 (discussing the National Childhood Vaccine Injury Act of 1986, Pub. L. No. 99-660
  • 315
    • 84939146215 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Stat 3755
    • Stat. , vol.100 , pp. 3755
  • 316
    • 79959434463 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • codified as amended at, §§
    • (codified as amended at 42 U. S. C. §§ 300aa-1-300aa-34 (2006))).
    • (2006) U. S. C. , vol.42
  • 317
    • 79959465533 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a description of the program, see the ACC website, last visited Oct. 6, 2010
    • For a description of the program, see the ACC website, http://www.acc.co.nz/ (last visited Oct. 6, 2010).
  • 318
    • 79959387767 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Coleman, supra note 7, at 186
    • Coleman, supra note 7, at 186.
  • 320
    • 79959414187 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • KUHN, supra note 88, at 64, 68-72 recounting examples of crisis and paradigm shift within astronomy and chemistry
    • KUHN, supra note 88, at 64, 68-72 (recounting examples of crisis and paradigm shift within astronomy and chemistry).
  • 321
    • 79959487198 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 79 pointing out that certain astronomical observations were counterinstances for Copernicus but merely puzzles for adherents to Ptolemaic cosmology
    • See id. at 79 (pointing out that certain astronomical observations were counterinstances for Copernicus but merely puzzles for adherents to Ptolemaic cosmology).
  • 322
    • 79959428423 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Daniels, supra note 150, at 257
    • See Daniels, supra note 150, at 257.
  • 323
    • 72749126022 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The language here is borrowed from, and is meant to underscore the distinction between explaining existing law and seeking to change existing law
    • The language here is borrowed from FED. R. CIV. P. 11 and is meant to underscore the distinction between explaining existing law and seeking to change existing law.
    • Fed. R. Civ. P , pp. 11
  • 324
    • 79959420821 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • LUBAN, supra note 28, at 80
    • LUBAN, supra note 28, at 80.
  • 325
    • 79959392591 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. noting that the "familiar justification of these doctrines lies in the concern that without confidentiality, clients will be chilled from telling their lawyers what the lawyers need to know to represent them"
    • See id. (noting that the "familiar justification of these doctrines lies in the concern that without confidentiality, clients will be chilled from telling their lawyers what the lawyers need to know to represent them").
  • 326
    • 0042644990 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The most powerful argument along these lines is Monroe Freedman's. See, 2d ed
    • The most powerful argument along these lines is Monroe Freedman's. See MONROE H. FREEDMAN & ABBE SMITH, UNDERSTANDING LAWYERS' ETHICS 127-40 (2d ed. 2002).
    • (2002) Understanding Lawyers' Ethics , pp. 127-140
    • Freedman, M.H.1    Smith, A.2
  • 327
    • 79959486434 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • LUBAN, supra note 28, at 81-82
    • LUBAN, supra note 28, at 81-82.
  • 328
    • 79959392031 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 83
    • Id. at 83.
  • 329
    • 79959452473 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 85-86
    • Id. at 85-86.
  • 330
    • 84863886218 scopus 로고
    • The original case is North Carolina v. Alford
    • The original case is North Carolina v. Alford, 400 U. S. 25 (1970).
    • (1970) U. S. , vol.400 , pp. 25
  • 331
    • 79959483452 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • LUBAN, supra note 28, at 83
    • LUBAN, supra note 28, at 83.
  • 332
    • 0004292576 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 51-53, 72-73 Naomi Goldblum trans.
    • AVISHAI MARGALIT, THE DECENT SOCIETY 43-46, 51-53, 72-73 (Naomi Goldblum trans., 1996).
    • (1996) The Decent Society , pp. 43-46
    • Margalit, A.1
  • 333
    • 79959382337 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See LUBAN, supra note 28, at 88
    • See LUBAN, supra note 28, at 88.
  • 334
    • 65149083012 scopus 로고
    • The lawyer as friend: The moral foundations of the lawyer-client relation
    • See, e.g., describing the popular concept of a lawyer as a client's legal friend
    • See, e.g., Charles Fried, The Lawyer as Friend: The Moral Foundations of the Lawyer-Client Relation, 85 YALE LJ. 1060 (1976) (describing the popular concept of a lawyer as a client's legal friend).
    • (1976) Yale Lj. , vol.85 , pp. 1060
    • Fried, C.1
  • 335
    • 79959393142 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Gamage & Kedem, supra note 2, at 1302-03
    • Gamage & Kedem, supra note 2, at 1302-03.
  • 336
    • 79959420282 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The authors cite Carol Rose for the proposition that one can and should bring a botde of wine to the host of a dinner party but to bring an equivalent amount of cash would cause serious offense
    • The authors cite Carol Rose for the proposition that one can (and should) bring a botde of wine to the host of a dinner party but to bring an equivalent amount of cash would cause serious offense.
  • 337
    • 79959455976 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 1325
    • See id. at 1325
  • 338
    • 77954943839 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • citing, Yale Law Sch. Pub. Law & Legal Theory Research Paper Series, Paper No. 84; Ctr. for Law, Econ. and Pub. Policy, Research Paper No. 308, available at
    • (citing Carol M. Rose, Whither Commodification? (Yale Law Sch. Pub. Law & Legal Theory Research Paper Series, Paper No. 84; Ctr. for Law, Econ. and Pub. Policy, Research Paper No. 308, 2005), available at http://papers.ssrn. com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract-id=706644#%23.
    • (2005) Whither Commodification?
    • Rose, C.M.1
  • 339
    • 79959450028 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1321
    • Id. at 1321.
  • 340
    • 0343717418 scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., §, one vol. ed
    • See, e.g., ARTHUR LINTON CORBIN, CORBIN ON CONTRACTS § 127 (one vol. ed. 1952).
    • (1952) Corbin on Contracts , pp. 127
    • Corbin, A.L.1
  • 341
    • 27844589093 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Moments of carelessness and massive loss
    • See, e.g., in, supra note 145, at, 398
    • See, e.g., Jeremy Waldron, Moments of Carelessness and Massive Loss, in PHILOSOPHICAL FOUNDATIONS OF TORT LAW, supra note 145, at 387, 398.
    • Philosophical Foundations of Tort Law , pp. 387
    • Waldron, J.1
  • 342
    • 0003726685 scopus 로고
    • See, Cass Sunstein talks about "fixed points" in legal doctrine, referring to the same phenomenon as a paradigm case
    • See ALBERT R. JONSEN & STEPHEN TOULMIN, THE ABUSE OF CASUISTRY: A HISTORY OF MORAL REASONING 252 (1988). Cass Sunstein talks about "fixed points" in legal doctrine, referring to the same phenomenon as a paradigm case.
    • (1988) The Abuse of Casuistry: A History of Moral Reasoning , pp. 252
    • Jonsen, A.R.1    Toulmin, S.2
  • 344
    • 79959439942 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 75 and accompanying text
    • See supra note 75 and accompanying text.
  • 345
    • 79959410251 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Judicial opinions as literature
    • See, e.g., in, 255 rev. and enlarged ed
    • See, e.g., RICHARD A. POSNER, Judicial Opinions as Literature, in LAW AND LITERATURE 255, 255 (rev. and enlarged ed. 1998);
    • (1998) Law and Literature , pp. 255
    • Posner, R.A.1
  • 347
    • 79959430417 scopus 로고
    • The poetics of legal interpretation
    • 269, Sanford Levinson & Steven Mailloux eds., Although the word "interpretation" is perhaps more common, I use the term "criticism" to distinguish the problem of interpretation in most analytic jurisprudence, which is concerned more with questions such as the relationship between texts and meaning, the problem of objectivity, and whether intention is relevant to interpretation
    • Jessica Lane, The Poetics of Legal Interpretation, in INTERPRETING LAW AND LITERATURE 269, 269 (Sanford Levinson & Steven Mailloux eds., 1988). Although the word "interpretation" is perhaps more common, I use the term "criticism" to distinguish the problem of interpretation in most analytic jurisprudence, which is concerned more with questions such as the relationship between texts and meaning, the problem of objectivity, and whether intention is relevant to interpretation.
    • (1988) Interpreting Law and Literature , pp. 269
    • Lane, J.1
  • 348
    • 0345569989 scopus 로고
    • See generally, Andrei Marmor ed., examining whether recent methodological developments in interpretation are good
    • See generally LAW AND INTERPRETATION: ESSAYS IN LEGAL PHILOSOPHY (Andrei Marmor ed., 1995) (examining whether recent methodological developments in interpretation are good).
    • (1995) Law and Interpretation: Essays in Legal Philosophy
  • 349
    • 79959447886 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • POSNER, supra note 203, at 272
    • POSNER, supra note 203, at 272.
  • 351
    • 0003623151 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Still wrong after all these years
    • See, in, supra note 205, at, 357
    • See STANLEY FISH, Still Wrong After All These Years, in DOING WHAT COMES NATURALLY, supra note 205, at 356, 357.
    • Doing What Comes Naturally , pp. 356
    • Fish, S.1
  • 352
    • 65849303422 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dennis martinez and the uses of theory
    • See, in, supra note 205, at, 372 reporting that Dennis Martinez, a baseball pitcher, had received advice from his manager to "throw strikes and keep 'em off the bases. What else could he say?" internal quotation marks omitted
    • See STANLEY FISH, Dennis Martinez and the Uses of Theory, in DOING WHAT COMES NATURALLY, supra note 205, at 372, 372 (reporting that Dennis Martinez, a baseball pitcher, had received advice from his manager to "[t]hrow strikes and keep 'em off the bases... What else could he say?" (internal quotation marks omitted)).
    • Doing What Comes Naturally , pp. 372
    • Fish, S.1
  • 353
    • 79959408307 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra notes 125-27 and accompanying text
    • See supra notes 125-27 and accompanying text.
  • 354
    • 0010915611 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Objectivity and truth: You 'd better believe it
    • See, 87-88, This is a theme of his recent book, Justice for Hedgehogs
    • See Ronald Dworkin, Objectivity and Truth: You 'd Better Believe It, 25 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 87, 87-88 (1996). This is a theme of his recent book, Justice for Hedgehogs.
    • (1996) Phil. & Pub. Aff. , vol.25 , pp. 87
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 355
    • 77954341794 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Truth and metaethics: The possibility of metaethics
    • See also, e.g., 479, criticizing this aspect of Dworkin's book
    • See also, e.g., Russ Shafer-Landau, Truth and Metaethics: The Possibility of Metaethics, 90 B. U. L. REV. 479, 479 (2010) (criticizing this aspect of Dworkin's book).
    • (2010) B. U. L. Rev. , vol.90 , pp. 479
    • Shafer-Landau, R.1
  • 356
    • 79959449429 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • DWORKIN, LAW'S EMPIRE, supra note 8, at 225
    • DWORKIN, LAW'S EMPIRE, supra note 8, at 225.
  • 357
    • 79959476582 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 256
    • See id. at 256.
  • 358
    • 79959425652 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Weinrib, supra note 155, at 956, 963-65
    • See Weinrib, supra note 155, at 956, 963-65.
  • 359
    • 79959414731 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The triumphs and travails of legal scholarship
    • supra note 12, at, 88
    • RICHARD A. POSNER, The Triumphs and Travails of Legal Scholarship, in OVERCOMING LAW, supra note 12, at 81, 88.
    • Overcoming Law , pp. 81
    • Posner, R.A.1
  • 360
    • 79959413094 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See NOLA & SANKEY, supra note 5, at 128
    • See NOLA & SANKEY, supra note 5, at 128.
  • 361
    • 79959410775 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., id. at 129-30
    • See, e.g., id. at 129-30.
  • 362
    • 79959468074 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • VAN FRAASSEN, supra note 5, at 20-21
    • VAN FRAASSEN, supra note 5, at 20-21.
  • 363
    • 79959388883 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • FISH, supra note 160, passim alterations omitted
    • FISH, supra note 160, passim (alterations omitted).


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.