메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 10, Issue 1, 2004, Pages 1-17

Incorporation by law

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 57149147326     PISSN: 13523252     EISSN: 14698048     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1017/S135232520400014X     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (97)

References (13)
  • 1
    • 85022356746 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • These include concepts belonging to virtue and character-related concepts (courage, etc.), responsibility-related concepts (excuses, etc.), value concepts (admirable, etc.), normative concepts (ought, etc.), and reason concepts (rational, etc.). In previous times “descriptive” and “factual” were commonly used to designate those concepts that are not specifically practical. This, however, miscasts descriptions. (“This is John” is not a description of anything yet is supposed to be a descriptive sentence.) Designating nonevaluative propositions “factual” implies that there are no evaluative facts, which is false. I will use “evaluative” and “normative” interchangeably to refer to all of them, as well as using them more narrowly to refer to items of the subcategories indicated above.
    • We lack a general term to refer collectively to all the concepts characteristic of practical thought. These include concepts belonging to virtue and character-related concepts (courage, etc.), responsibility-related concepts (excuses, etc.), value concepts (admirable, etc.), normative concepts (ought, etc.), and reason concepts (rational, etc.). In previous times “descriptive” and “factual” were commonly used to designate those concepts that are not specifically practical. This, however, miscasts descriptions. (“This is John” is not a description of anything yet is supposed to be a descriptive sentence.) Designating nonevaluative propositions “factual” implies that there are no evaluative facts, which is false. I will use “evaluative” and “normative” interchangeably to refer to all of them, as well as using them more narrowly to refer to items of the subcategories indicated above.
    • We lack a general term to refer collectively to all the concepts characteristic of practical thought
  • 2
    • 85022407813 scopus 로고
    • That the idea is consistent with Hart's account of the law was intimated by him in his review of LON FULLER, 78 HARVARD L. REV. 1281 (1965), repr. in H.L.A. HART, ESSAYS IN JURISPRUDENCE AND PHILOSOPHY 361 (1983), and reiterated in the postscript to THE CONCEPT OF LAW 250 (1961), though neither time did Hart stop to explore the meaning and implication of the idea; see David Lyons, Principles, Positivism and Legal Theory, 87 YALE L.J. 415 (1977), at 423-424, and Philip Soper, Legal Theory and the Obligation of a Judge: The Hart/Dworkin Dispute, 75 MICHIGAN L. REV. 473 (1977). The point was embraced by Jules Coleman, Negative and Positive Positivism, 11 J. LEGAL STUD. 139, and developed and defended at length by him in JULES COLEMAN, THE PRACTICE OF PRINCIPLE (2001). See, for a general discussion of the view, Kenneth E. Himma, Inclusive Legal Positivism, in THE OXFORD HANDBOOK OF JURISPRUDENCE AND PHILOSOPHY OF LAW (J. Coleman & S. Shapiro, eds., 2002).
    • That the idea is consistent with Hart's account of the law was intimated by him in his review of LON FULLER, THE MORALITY OF LAW in Hart, 78 HARVARD L. REV. 1281 (1965), repr. in H.L.A. HART, ESSAYS IN JURISPRUDENCE AND PHILOSOPHY 361 (1983), and reiterated in the postscript to THE CONCEPT OF LAW 250 (1961), though neither time did Hart stop to explore the meaning and implication of the idea; see David Lyons, Principles, Positivism and Legal Theory, 87 YALE L.J. 415 (1977), at 423-424, and Philip Soper, Legal Theory and the Obligation of a Judge: The Hart/Dworkin Dispute, 75 MICHIGAN L. REV. 473 (1977). The point was embraced by Jules Coleman, Negative and Positive Positivism, 11 J. LEGAL STUD. 139 (1982), and developed and defended at length by him in JULES COLEMAN, THE PRACTICE OF PRINCIPLE (2001). See, for a general discussion of the view, Kenneth E. Himma, Inclusive Legal Positivism, in THE OXFORD HANDBOOK OF JURISPRUDENCE AND PHILOSOPHY OF LAW (J. Coleman & S. Shapiro, eds., 2002).
    • (1982) THE MORALITY OF LAW in Hart
  • 4
    • 85022371262 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note that the truth conditions of propositions from a point of view (so understood) are not the same as those of the corresponding material implication; for example, “if Christian doctrine is true then….” For one thing, they assert not merely that the from-a-point-of-view proposition is true but that (in this example) it is Christianity that is the ground of its truth. Besides, the falsity of Christianity, far from guaranteeing the truth of the proposition, has no bearing on the question of its truth.
    • Though of course one is committed to it being truly so from that point of view. Note that the truth conditions of propositions from a point of view (so understood) are not the same as those of the corresponding material implication; for example, “if Christian doctrine is true then….” For one thing, they assert not merely that the from-a-point-of-view proposition is true but that (in this example) it is Christianity that is the ground of its truth. Besides, the falsity of Christianity, far from guaranteeing the truth of the proposition, has no bearing on the question of its truth.
    • Though of course one is committed to it being truly so from that point of view
  • 5
    • 85022452096 scopus 로고
    • in THE COMPLETE PLAYS OF BERNARD SHAW
    • G.B. SHAW, PYGMALION, in THE COMPLETE PLAYS OF BERNARD SHAW 729 (1934).
    • (1934) PYGMALION , pp. 729
    • SHAW, G.B.1
  • 6
    • 0004294163 scopus 로고
    • This may have been Hart's view in his later work; see H.L.A. HART
    • This may have been Hart's view in his later work; see H.L.A. HART, ESSAYS ON BENTHAM (1983).
    • (1983) ESSAYS ON BENTHAM
  • 10
    • 85022356342 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (drawn to my attention by T. Endicott) is in practice direction 25.13 of the Civil Procedure Rules (in the U.K.) which says: “The court may make an order for security for costs under rule 25.12 if (a) it is satisfied, having regard to all the circumstances of the case, that it is just to make such an order.” Clearly it might just as well have said “the court may, in its discretion, make an order for security for costs….” In that case, too, the court would have had to do what is just. The language of the rule merely reminds courts that their discretion was not curtailed. It does not “incorporate” anything.
    • A very simple illustration (drawn to my attention by T. Endicott) is in practice direction 25.13 of the Civil Procedure Rules (in the U.K.) which says: “The court may make an order for security for costs under rule 25.12 if (a) it is satisfied, having regard to all the circumstances of the case, that it is just to make such an order.” Clearly it might just as well have said “the court may, in its discretion, make an order for security for costs….” In that case, too, the court would have had to do what is just. The language of the rule merely reminds courts that their discretion was not curtailed. It does not “incorporate” anything.
    • A very simple illustration
  • 11
    • 85022426602 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Such a society may even be subject to law. The existence of a legal system in any country does not depend on the possession of the concept of law by the population of that country. But it does not follow, of course, that in that country there is no boundary demarcating the limits of law, distinguishing between what is part of it and what is not. The argument in the text applies to it as well.
    • Of course, a society or a culture that does not have the concepts of morality and of law does not have a view about their demarcation. Such a society may even be subject to law. The existence of a legal system in any country does not depend on the possession of the concept of law by the population of that country. But it does not follow, of course, that in that country there is no boundary demarcating the limits of law, distinguishing between what is part of it and what is not. The argument in the text applies to it as well.
    • Of course, a society or a culture that does not have the concepts of morality and of law does not have a view about their demarcation
  • 12
    • 85022418641 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I rely on the view that the law exists, where it does, as a normative system; that is, that there are no single, stand-alone laws that are not part of a normative system., note 3, calls the sufficiency condition of inclusive legal positivism, that is, to the view that so-called “incorporation” can turn morality into law. I do not, in this article, consider in any way the case for or against the view that the validity of legal norms may depend, whether because some other law so determines or for other reasons, on them being consistent with some nonlegal norms, moral or other.
    • These remarks apply only to what Himma, I rely on the view that the law exists, where it does, as a normative system; that is, that there are no single, stand-alone laws that are not part of a normative system., note 3, calls the sufficiency condition of inclusive legal positivism, that is, to the view that so-called “incorporation” can turn morality into law. I do not, in this article, consider in any way the case for or against the view that the validity of legal norms may depend, whether because some other law so determines or for other reasons, on them being consistent with some nonlegal norms, moral or other.
    • These remarks apply only to what Himma


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.