메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 96, Issue 4, 2011, Pages 633-670

The reenchantment of law

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 79959446238     PISSN: 00108847     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: None     Document Type: Conference Paper
Times cited : (18)

References (328)
  • 1
    • 79959498173 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • thesis that since the 1980s the world has been experiencing a "religious revival" and a publicization of religion-a reversal of the tide of its privatization-has been crucial to religious studies as well as the study of secularization and modernization processes; it has been debated ever since
    • The thesis that since the 1980s the world has been experiencing a "religious revival" and a publicization of religion-a reversal of the tide of its privatization-has been crucial to religious studies as well as the study of secularization and modernization processes; it has been debated ever since.
  • 3
    • 84963009161 scopus 로고
    • Shrinking transcendence, expanding religion?
    • 127-28
    • Thomas Luckmann, Shrinking Transcendence, Expanding Religion?, 51 SOC. ANALYSIS 127, 127-28 (1990).
    • (1990) Soc. Analysis , vol.51 , pp. 127
    • Luckmann, T.1
  • 4
    • 79959494829 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In fact, the move toward reenchantment is, I would argue, what also underlies the religious revival. Put differendy, mystical and irrationalist trends, which were for a long period marginalized in both religion and law, are moving to the forefront, regaining prominence and influence
    • In fact, the move toward reenchantment is, I would argue, what also underlies the religious revival. Put differendy, mystical and irrationalist trends, which were for a long period marginalized in both religion and law, are moving to the forefront, regaining prominence and influence.
  • 5
    • 79959530020 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • legal realists did not only impact the realm of jurisprudence. Their voluminous writings, as well as their different careers and professional trajectories, dealt with and influenced legal institutions, substantive legal fields, legal reforms, and the entire structure of government. For recent works discussing the diverse and far-reaching impacts that legal realists had on these various aspects of the legal system, see, for example
    • The legal realists did not only impact the realm of jurisprudence. Their voluminous writings, as well as their different careers and professional trajectories, dealt with and influenced legal institutions, substantive legal fields, legal reforms, and the entire structure of government. For recent works discussing the diverse and far-reaching impacts that legal realists had on these various aspects of the legal system, see, for example, DALIA TSUK MITCHELL, ARCHITECT OF JUSTICE: FEUX S. COHEN AND THE FOUNDING OF AMERICAN LEGAL PLURALISM 2-8 (2007);
    • (2007) Architect of Justice: Feux S. Cohen and the Founding of American Legal Pluralism , pp. 2-8
    • Mitchell, D.T.1
  • 7
    • 77955794753 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Biographing realist jurisprudence
    • 765-67
    • Roy Kreitner, Biographing Realist Jurisprudence, 35 LAW & SOC. INQUIRY 765, 765-67 (2010)
    • (2010) Law & Soc. Inquiry , vol.35 , pp. 765
    • Kreitner, R.1
  • 8
    • 79959502041 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • reviewing TSUK MITCHELL, supra, and WALLER, supra
    • (reviewing TSUK MITCHELL, supra, and WALLER, supra).
  • 9
    • 79959518471 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Kreitner, supra note 3, at 784-88. For a recent articulation of the impact of the debate between realists and formalists in the U. S
    • See Kreitner, supra note 3, at 784-88. For a recent articulation of the impact of the debate between realists and formalists in the U. S.
  • 10
    • 76749088559 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Formalism and realism in ruins (mapping the logics of collapse)
    • 199-200, see, 223-43
    • see Pierre Schlag, Formalism and Realism in Ruins (Mapping the Logics of Collapse), 95 IOWA L. REV. 195, 199-200, 223-43 (2009).
    • (2009) Iowa L. Rev. , vol.95 , pp. 195
    • Schlag, P.1
  • 11
    • 79959501601 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See infra Part II
    • See infra Part II.
  • 12
    • 79959510524 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See infra Part II
    • See infra Part II.
  • 13
    • 10044294824 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The disenchantment of logically formal legal rationality, or max weber's sociology in the genealogy of the contemporary mode of western legal thought
    • 1050, For further elaboration on this point, see infra Part LB
    • Duncan Kennedy, The Disenchantment of Logically Formal Legal Rationality, or Max Weber's Sociology in the Genealogy of the Contemporary Mode of Western Legal Thought, 55 HASTINGS LJ. 1031, 1050 (2004). For further elaboration on this point, see infra Part LB.
    • (2004) Hastings Lj , vol.55 , pp. 1031
    • Kennedy, D.1
  • 14
    • 79959491574 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ironically, these disenchanting theories are the progenies of what for Weber symbolized the reenchanting and irrational moment in law: legal realism
    • Ironically, these disenchanting theories are the progenies of what for Weber symbolized the reenchanting and irrational moment in law: legal realism.
  • 15
    • 79959522566 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See infra Part LB
    • See infra Part LB.
  • 16
    • 79959505887 scopus 로고
    • The ideality of difference: Toward objectivity in legal interpretation
    • See, e.g., 1198-210, developing a formalist-inspired theory of legal interpretation that also enables interpretative objectivity
    • See, e.g., Alan Brudner, The Ideality of Difference: Toward Objectivity in Legal Interpretation, 11 CARDOZO L. REV. 1133, 1198-210 (1990) (developing a formalist-inspired theory of legal interpretation that also enables interpretative objectivity).
    • (1990) Cardozo L. Rev. , vol.11 , pp. 1133
    • Brudner, A.1
  • 17
    • 79959528210 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See infra Part II
    • See infra Part II.
  • 18
    • 79959525472 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • According to Weber, the process of disenchantment of the Occident has been going on "for millennia."
    • According to Weber, the process of disenchantment of the Occident has been going on "for millennia."
  • 19
    • 79959516202 scopus 로고
    • Science as a vocation
    • See, in, Wolf Heydebrand ed., Hans A. Gerth & C. Wright Mills trans.
    • See MAX WEBER, Science as a Vocation, in SOCIOLOGICAL WRITINGS 276, 286 (Wolf Heydebrand ed., Hans A. Gerth & C. Wright Mills trans., 1994).
    • (1994) Sociological Writings , vol.276 , pp. 286
    • Weber, M.1
  • 20
    • 79959516203 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As one commentator argues, disenchantment is "the key concept within Weber's account of the distinctiveness and significance of Western culture."
    • As one commentator argues, disenchantment is "the key concept within Weber's account of the distinctiveness and significance of Western culture."
  • 21
    • 84982684424 scopus 로고
    • Disenchantment and its discontents: Weberian perspectives on science and technology
    • Weber himself alternated between several of these concepts-rationality, instrumental rationality, rationalization, and disenchantment-and was not necessarily committed to a strict usage of one rather the other. One argues, however, that Weber distinguished between religious disenchantment and Occidental rationalization and that religious disenchantment was limited to the period that ended with Protestantism, 228
    • Ralph Schroeder, Disenchantment and Its Discontents: Weberian Perspectives on Science and Technology, 43 SOC. REV. 227, 228 (1995). Weber himself alternated between several of these concepts-rationality, instrumental rationality, rationalization, and disenchantment-and was not necessarily committed to a strict usage of one rather the other. One argues, however, that Weber distinguished between religious disenchantment and Occidental rationalization and that religious disenchantment was limited to the period that ended with Protestantism.
    • (1995) Soc. Rev. , vol.43 , pp. 227
    • Schroeder, R.1
  • 22
    • 84890591031 scopus 로고
    • The problem of thematic unity in the works of max weber
    • See, 321-23, Regardless of this position which concerns religious disenchantment, it is clear that disenchantment as a general phenomenon has not ended with the rise of Protestant ethics and is still taking place, 316
    • See Friedrich H. Tenbruck, The Problem of Thematic Unity in the Works of Max Weber, 31 BRIT. J. SOC. 316, 321-23 (1980). Regardless of this position (which concerns religious disenchantment), it is clear that disenchantment as a general phenomenon has not ended with the rise of Protestant ethics and is still taking place.
    • (1980) Brit. J. Soc. , pp. 31
    • Tenbruck, F.H.1
  • 23
    • 84937331440 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Disenchantment, enchantment and re-enchantment: Max weber at the millennium
    • See, in, 15-20
    • See Richard Jenkins, Disenchantment, Enchantment and Re-Enchantment: Max Weber at the Millennium, in 1 MIAX WEBER STUD. 11, 15-20 (2000);
    • (2000) Miax Weber Stud. , vol.1 , pp. 11
    • Jenkins, R.1
  • 24
    • 79959529798 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kennedy, supra note 7, at 1032 suggesting that "the contemporary mode of legal thought is an episode in the sequences of disenchantment and reenchantment suggested by Weber's philosophy of history"
    • Kennedy, supra note 7, at 1032 (suggesting that "the contemporary mode of legal thought [is] an episode in the sequences of disenchantment and reenchantment suggested by Weber's philosophy of history").
  • 25
    • 79959534025 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Kennedy, supra note 7, at 1057
    • See Kennedy, supra note 7, at 1057.
  • 26
    • 79959515227 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 1056-57
    • See id. at 1056-57;
  • 27
    • 79959533121 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Tenbruck, supra note 12, at 319-23
    • Tenbruck, supra note 12, at 319-23.
  • 28
    • 79959506772 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Kennedy, supra note 7, at 1056-57
    • See Kennedy, supra note 7, at 1056-57.
  • 29
    • 79959533786 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. There is no way to overemphasize the importance of calculability in Weber's depiction of the evolution of the industrialized West. The development of a calculable and rational legal system is imperative for the functioning of a sophisticated economic market
    • See id. There is no way to overemphasize the importance of calculability in Weber's depiction of the evolution of the industrialized West. The development of a calculable and rational legal system is imperative for the functioning of a sophisticated economic market.
  • 30
    • 79959518643 scopus 로고
    • See, Guendier Roth & Claus Wittich eds., Ephraim Fischoff et al. trans., Univ. of Cal. Press 1978, For a detailed discussion of diis point
    • See 1 MAX WEBER, ECONOMY AND SOCIETY 336-337 (Guendier Roth & Claus Wittich eds., Ephraim Fischoff et al. trans., Univ. of Cal. Press 1978) (1968). For a detailed discussion of diis point
    • (1968) Max Weber, Economy and Society , vol.1 , pp. 336-337
  • 31
    • 85011903108 scopus 로고
    • Max weber on law and the rise of capitalism
    • see, 732-45
    • see David M. Trubek, Max Weber on Law and the Rise of Capitalism, 1972 WIS. L. REV. 720, 732-45.
    • (1972) Wis. L. Rev. , pp. 720
    • Trubek, D.M.1
  • 32
    • 79959533120 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Tenbruck, supra note 12, at 319 quoting W. M. Sprondel's response to Weber's work: "That great religious historical process of disenchantment of the world... disavows all magical ways to salvation as a superstition and sacrilege...."
    • See Tenbruck, supra note 12, at 319 (quoting W. M. Sprondel's response to Weber's work: "That great religious historical process of disenchantment of the world... disavows all magical ways to salvation as a superstition and sacrilege....").
  • 34
    • 79959503572 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see Tenbruck, supra note 12, at 319
    • see Tenbruck, supra note 12, at 319.
  • 35
    • 79959527678 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, supra note 16, at 399-635
    • See 1 WEBER, supra note 16, at 399-635;
    • Weber , vol.1
  • 36
    • 79959523943 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kennedy, supra note 7, at 1056-57, 1061-63
    • Kennedy, supra note 7, at 1056-57, 1061-63;
  • 37
    • 79959499495 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Tenbruck, supra note 12, at 333-42
    • Tenbruck, supra note 12, at 333-42.
  • 38
    • 79959522143 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Kennedy, supra note 7, at 1057
    • See Kennedy, supra note 7, at 1057.
  • 39
    • 79959503571 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Another way of articulating the relationship between disenchantment and reenchantment is that the latter is the "dangerous supplement" of the former: the marginal, repressed, and denied "complementary" of the main development or activity that threatens to replace and fully supplant it
    • Another way of articulating the relationship between disenchantment and reenchantment is that the latter is the "dangerous supplement" of the former: the marginal, repressed, and denied "complementary" of the main development or activity that threatens to replace and fully supplant it.
  • 40
    • 0003905795 scopus 로고
    • See, Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak trans., The Johns Hopkins Univ. Press 1976, developing and discussing the structure of "dangerous supplement" in Rousseau's philosophy. I am Uiankful to Roy Kreitner for suggesting this idea to me
    • See JACQUES DERRIDA, OF GRAMMATOLOCY 141-64 (Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak trans., The Johns Hopkins Univ. Press 1976) (1967) (developing and discussing the structure of "dangerous supplement" in Rousseau's philosophy). I am Uiankful to Roy Kreitner for suggesting this idea to me.
    • (1967) Of Grammatolocy , pp. 141-164
    • Derrida, J.1
  • 41
    • 79959501818 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Kennedy, supra note 7, at 1063
    • See Kennedy, supra note 7, at 1063.
  • 42
    • 79959517536 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id
    • See id.
  • 43
    • 79959524165 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Schroeder, supra note 12, at 232-33 describing how, in Weber's view, the inner logic of the scientific worldview led to the view's autonomy as its own intellectual sphere
    • See Schroeder, supra note 12, at 232-33 (describing how, in Weber's view, the inner logic of the scientific worldview led to the view's autonomy as its own intellectual sphere).
  • 44
    • 79959527273 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Luckmann, supra note 1, at 134-35
    • See Luckmann, supra note 1, at 134-35.
  • 45
    • 79959504036 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • idea of the evolution of distinct and autonomous intellectual and vocational spheres is developed in great detail in Weber's famous works concerning science and politics
    • The idea of the evolution of distinct and autonomous intellectual and vocational spheres is developed in great detail in Weber's famous works concerning science and politics.
  • 46
    • 0001845081 scopus 로고
    • Politics as a vocation
    • See, e.g., in, H. H. Gerth & C. Wright Mills eds. & trans., Roudedge, hereinafter WEBER, ESSAYS
    • See, e.g., MAX WEBER, Politics as a Vocation, in FROM MAX WEBER: ESSAYS IN SOCIOLOGY 77, 77-127 (H. H. Gerth & C. Wright Mills eds. & trans., Roudedge 1991) (1948) [hereinafter WEBER, ESSAYS];
    • (1948) From Max Weber: Essays in Sociology , vol.77 , pp. 77-127
    • Weber, M.1
  • 47
    • 79959520465 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Weber, supra note 11, at 276-304. For a discussion
    • Weber, supra note 11, at 276-304. For a discussion
  • 48
    • 79959513690 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see Kennedy, supra note 7, at 1060
    • see Kennedy, supra note 7, at 1060.
  • 49
    • 79959517783 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Kennedy, supra note 7, at 1058. On the legal mode of domination characterizing western modernity
    • See Kennedy, supra note 7, at 1058. On the legal mode of domination characterizing western modernity
  • 50
    • 79959526615 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see Trubek, supra note 16, at 731-39. The famous "iron cage of modernity" was extremely influential on the development of Michel Foucault's idea of "power/knowledge" and the emergence of disciplinary power
    • see Trubek, supra note 16, at 731-39. The famous "iron cage of modernity" was extremely influential on the development of Michel Foucault's idea of "power/knowledge" and the emergence of disciplinary power.
  • 52
    • 0004058566 scopus 로고
    • Colin Gordon ed., Colin Gordon et al. trans., Pantheon Books
    • MICHEL FOUCAULT, POWER/KNOWLEDGE (Colin Gordon ed., Colin Gordon et al. trans., Pantheon Books 1980) (1972).
    • (1972) Power/Knowledge
    • Foucault, M.1
  • 53
    • 79959507000 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Kennedy, supra note 7, at 1061-63
    • See Kennedy, supra note 7, at 1061-63.
  • 54
    • 79959504550 scopus 로고
    • See, Guenther Roth & Claus Wittich eds., Ephraim Fischoff et al. trans., Univ. of Cal. Press
    • See 2 MAX WEBER, ECONOMY AND SOCIETY 889 (Guenther Roth & Claus Wittich eds., Ephraim Fischoff et al. trans., Univ. of Cal. Press 1978) (1968).
    • (1968) Max Weber, Economy and Society , vol.2 , pp. 889
  • 55
    • 79959503812 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 56
    • 79959522565 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Kennedy, supra note 7, at 1057-58
    • See Kennedy, supra note 7, at 1057-58.
  • 57
    • 79959507215 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kennedy emphasizes this point. For him, the main tension within Weber's work lies in the opposition between the "iron cage of modernity" narrative, which implies that agents within each sphere are truly bound by formal rationality and cannot bona fide refuse to apply it mechanically, and the irrational/decisionist narrative, which suggests that "all bureaucrats would have the possibility of agency within their jobs, rather than being condemned to vocational formalism."
    • Kennedy emphasizes this point. For him, the main tension within Weber's work lies in the opposition between the "iron cage of modernity" narrative, which implies that agents within each sphere are truly bound by formal rationality and cannot bona fide refuse to apply it mechanically, and the irrational/decisionist narrative, which suggests that "all bureaucrats would have the possibility of agency within their jobs, rather than being condemned to vocational formalism."
  • 58
    • 79959530968 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 1055, 1061-69
    • See id. at 1055, 1061-69.
  • 59
    • 79959511435 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 29, at 880-95
    • -2 WEBER, supra note 29, at 880-95;
    • Weber , vol.2
  • 60
    • 79959499304 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also Kennedy, supra note 7, at 1039, 1059, 1064 describing Weber's notion of "lawfinding"
    • see also Kennedy, supra note 7, at 1039, 1059, 1064 (describing Weber's notion of "lawfinding");
  • 61
    • 84928219877 scopus 로고
    • Reconstructing max weber's sociology of law
    • 925-33, reviewing ANTHONY T. KRONMAN, MAX WEBER 1983
    • David M. Trubek, Reconstructing Max Weber's Sociology of Law, 37 STAN. L. REV. 919, 925-33 (1985) (reviewing ANTHONY T. KRONMAN, MAX WEBER (1983)).
    • (1985) Stan. L. Rev. , vol.37 , pp. 919
    • Trubek, D.M.1
  • 62
    • 79959515990 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In his "sociology of law", Weber describes evolutions and developments in law and legal theory, which span from antiquity until the early twentieth century
    • In his "sociology of law", Weber describes evolutions and developments in law and legal theory, which span from antiquity until the early twentieth century.
  • 63
    • 79959508791 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, supra note 29
    • See 2 WEBER, supra note 29, at 641-900.
    • Weber , vol.2 , pp. 641-900
  • 64
    • 79959522564 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Kennedy, supra note 7, at 1046 defining positivism as the "view that lawmaking is a secular process through which a state claiming the monopoly of the legitimate exercise of force enacts valid legal norms as compromises of conflicting interests"
    • See Kennedy, supra note 7, at 1046 (defining positivism as the "view that lawmaking is a secular process through which a state claiming the monopoly of the legitimate exercise of force enacts valid legal norms as compromises of conflicting interests").
  • 65
    • 79959498617 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See 2 WEBER, supra note 29, at 873-75
    • See 2 WEBER, supra note 29, at 873-75;
  • 66
    • 79959514797 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also Kennedy, supra note 7, at 1048 describing the disintegration of natural law
    • see also Kennedy, supra note 7, at 1048 (describing the disintegration of natural law).
  • 67
    • 79959524640 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, supra note 29
    • See 2 WEBER, supra note 29, at 865-76.
    • Weber , vol.2 , pp. 865-876
  • 68
    • 79959503353 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Kennedy, supra note 7, at 1048, 1064. As Weber puts it: The disappearance of the old natural law conceptions has destroyed all possibility of providing the law with a metaphysical dignity by virtue of its immanent qualities. In the great majority of its most important provisions, it has been unmasked all too visibly, indeed, as the product or the technical means of a compromise between conflicting interests
    • See Kennedy, supra note 7, at 1048, 1064. As Weber puts it: The disappearance of the old natural law conceptions has destroyed all possibility of providing the law with a metaphysical dignity by virtue of its immanent qualities. In the great majority of its most important provisions, it has been unmasked all too visibly, indeed, as the product or the technical means of a compromise between conflicting interests.
  • 69
    • 79959499702 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 29, It is important to note that in this paragraph Weber is not suggesting that lawyers who operate in a formal rational legal system are political actors; on the contrary, Weber argues that actors within a formal legal system are merely applying law, regardless of its substantive content or its "political" consequences or intentions. Law collapses into politics, therefore, in the sense that legislation is understood as a compromise between competing interests and groups that the political branch-the legislator-undertakes, not as the elaborated articulation of "reason" or as the revelation of divine law
    • WEBER, supra note 29, at 874-75. It is important to note that in this paragraph Weber is not suggesting that lawyers who operate in a formal rational legal system are political actors; on the contrary, Weber argues that actors within a formal legal system are merely applying law, regardless of its substantive content or its "political" consequences or intentions. Law collapses into politics, therefore, in the sense that legislation is understood as a compromise between competing interests and groups that the political branch-the legislator-undertakes, not as the elaborated articulation of "reason" or as the revelation of divine law.
    • Weber , vol.2 , pp. 874-875
  • 70
    • 79959531519 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id
    • See id.
  • 71
    • 79959518224 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the possibility that lawyers and judges are performing "practical wisdom" that is neither technical nor magical but instead an endeavor committed to the idea that the law is aspirational and manifesting normative ideals since it is legislated dirough political compromise and has political implications, see infra Part II. D.1
    • On the possibility that lawyers (and judges) are performing "practical wisdom" that is neither technical nor magical but instead an endeavor committed to the idea that the law is aspirational and manifesting normative ideals (since it is legislated dirough political compromise and has political implications), see infra Part II. D.1.
  • 72
    • 79959491795 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, supra note 29, On classical legal thought
    • See 2 WEBER, supra note 29, at 1057. On classical legal thought
    • Weber , vol.2 , pp. 1057
  • 73
    • 26844529985 scopus 로고
    • see, Beard Books, describing classical legal diought as a "way of thinking that amounted to a rationalistic ordering of the whole legal universe"
    • see DUNCAN KENNEDY, THE RISE AND FALL OF CLASSICAL LEGAL THOUGHT 3 (Beard Books 2006) (1975) (describing classical legal diought as a "way of thinking [that] amounted to a rationalistic ordering of the whole legal universe");
    • (1975) The Rise and Fall of Classical Legal Thought , pp. 3
    • Kennedy, D.1
  • 74
    • 0010002830 scopus 로고
    • 6, defining five major traits that legal systems possessed according to classical legal diought: comprehensiveness, completeness, formality, conceptual order, and acceptability
    • Thomas C. Grey, Langdell's Orthodoxy, 45 U. PITT. L. REV. 1, 6 (1983) (defining five major traits that legal systems possessed according to classical legal diought: comprehensiveness, completeness, formality, conceptual order, and acceptability).
    • (1983) Langdell's Orthodoxy , vol.45 , pp. 1
    • Grey, T.C.1
  • 75
    • 79959512102 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Weber calls this process the "substantive rationalization of sacred law.", supra note 29
    • Weber calls this process the "substantive rationalization of sacred law." 2 WEBER, supra note 29, at 815-31.
    • Weber , vol.2 , pp. 815-831
  • 76
    • 79959497945 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Kennedy, supra note 7, at 1057
    • See Kennedy, supra note 7, at 1057.
  • 77
    • 79959518470 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 1040-41
    • See id. at 1040-41.
  • 78
    • 37949040759 scopus 로고
    • The German free law movement as the source of American legal realism
    • 407-19, On the German "free law movement" see
    • On the German "free law movement" see James E. Herget & Stephen Wallace, The German Free Law Movement as the Source of American Legal Realism, 73 VA. L. REV. 399, 407-19 (1987).
    • (1987) Va. L. Rev. , vol.73 , pp. 399
    • Herget, J.E.1    Wallace, S.2
  • 79
    • 17544378957 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Against metaphysics in law: The historical background of American and scandinavian legal realism compared
    • See, 474-75
    • See Heikki Pihlajamǎki, Against Metaphysics in Law: The Historical Background of American and Scandinavian Legal Realism Compared, 52 AM. J. COMP. L. 469, 474-75 (2004).
    • (2004) Am. J. Comp. L. , vol.52 , pp. 469
    • Pihlajamǎki, H.1
  • 80
    • 79959532364 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • These social jurists included Rudolf von Jhering, Otto von Gierke, Eugen Ehrlich, Francois Gény, and others
    • These social jurists included Rudolf von Jhering, Otto von Gierke, Eugen Ehrlich, Francois Gény, and others.
  • 81
    • 79959500697 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 474-75. On the social jurists and Weber's critique of them
    • See id. at 474-75. On the social jurists and Weber's critique of them
  • 82
    • 79959530758 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see Kennedy, supra note 7, at 1049-50, 1052-55
    • see Kennedy, supra note 7, at 1049-50, 1052-55.
  • 83
    • 79959523017 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Kennedy, supra note 7, at 1054-55
    • See Kennedy, supra note 7, at 1054-55.
  • 84
    • 79959528849 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, supra note 29, at 815-30
    • See 2 WEBER, supra note 29, at 815-30;
    • Weber , vol.2
  • 85
    • 79959516201 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kennedy, supra note 7, at 1071-76
    • Kennedy, supra note 7, at 1071-76.
  • 86
    • 79959499303 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Kennedy, supra note 7, at 1053-54
    • See Kennedy, supra note 7, at 1053-54.
  • 87
    • 79959493143 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hence the famous, almost cliché saying, "we are all realists now."
    • Hence the famous, almost cliché saying, "we are all realists now."
  • 89
    • 77955840255 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The realist conception of law
    • see also, 610
    • see also Hanoch Dagan, The Realist Conception of Law, 57 U. TORONTO L. J. 607, 610 (2007).
    • (2007) U. Toronto L. J , vol.57 , pp. 607
    • Dagan, H.1
  • 90
    • 84926984910 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Three globalizations of law and legal thought: 1850-2000
    • See, in, 63-71 David M. Trubek & Alvaro Santos eds., describing three periods of the "globalization of legal thought" and particularly the last globalization, in which American policy analysis has disseminated throughout the globe
    • See Duncan Kennedy, Three Globalizations of Law and Legal Thought: 1850-2000, in THE NEW LAW AND ECONOMIC DEVELOPMENT 19, 21, 63-71 (David M. Trubek & Alvaro Santos eds., 2006) (describing three periods of the "globalization of legal thought" and particularly the last globalization, in which American policy analysis has disseminated throughout the globe);
    • (2006) The New Law and Economic Development , vol.19 , pp. 21
    • Kennedy, D.1
  • 91
    • 84936135622 scopus 로고
    • Legal realism now
    • 467-68
    • Joseph William Singer, Legal Realism Now, 76 CALIF. L. REV. 465, 467-68 (1988)
    • (1988) Calif. L. Rev. , vol.76 , pp. 465
    • Singer, J.W.1
  • 92
    • 0002077690 scopus 로고
    • reviewing, Alongside the triumph of legal realism and policy analysis in elite law schools, large portions of legal practitioners in the United States remained committed to a fairly formalistic mode of legal reasoning. It is indeed a question whether policy analysis-an accepted practice-is dominant or marginal outside the elite of law schools, judiciary, and the bar. And outside the United States, in continental Europe especially in Germany and France, Asia, Latin America, and other European-influenced countries, formal rationality remained a favorable mode of legal reasoning, even in elite law schools, until very recendy
    • (reviewing LAURA KALMAN, LEGAL REALISM AT YALE: 1927-1960 (1986)). Alongside the triumph of legal realism and policy analysis in elite law schools, large portions of legal practitioners in the United States remained committed to a fairly formalistic mode of legal reasoning. It is indeed a question whether policy analysis-an accepted practice-is dominant or marginal outside the elite of law schools, judiciary, and the bar. And outside the United States, in continental Europe (especially in Germany and France), Asia, Latin America, and other European-influenced countries, formal rationality remained a favorable mode of legal reasoning, even in elite law schools, until very recendy.
    • (1986) Legal Realism at Yale , pp. 1927-1960
    • Kalman, L.1
  • 93
    • 79959509543 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kennedy, supra note 7, at 1068
    • Kennedy, supra note 7, at 1068.
  • 94
    • 79959511434 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • need to create concrete, "smaller", and situation-sensitive legal categories and rules that will replace the broad and abstract concepts and categories was a major theme that legal realists developed
    • The need to create concrete, "smaller", and situation-sensitive legal categories and rules that will replace the broad and abstract concepts and categories was a major theme that legal realists developed.
  • 95
    • 0040404476 scopus 로고
    • Some realism about realism-responding to dean pound
    • See, e.g., 1237, Indeed, as Dagan points out, the fragmentation of the legal field by no means unveils its political nature. In various normative discussions, it merely indicates the need to adapt the law to needs and interests, which require case or situation sensitivity, hence breaking down overly broad categories into narrower ones
    • See, e.g., Karl N. Llewellyn, Some Realism about Realism-Responding to Dean Pound, 44 HARV. L. REV. 1222, 1237 (1931). Indeed, as Dagan points out, the fragmentation of the legal field by no means unveils its political nature. In various normative discussions, it merely indicates the need to adapt the law to needs and interests, which require case or situation sensitivity, hence breaking down overly broad categories into narrower ones.
    • (1931) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.44 , pp. 1222
    • Llewellyn, K.N.1
  • 96
    • 79959524639 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Dagan, supra note 50, at 647-51
    • See Dagan, supra note 50, at 647-51.
  • 97
    • 79959499702 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 29
    • -2 WEBER, supra note 29, at 874-75.
    • Weber , vol.2 , pp. 874-875
  • 98
    • 0039631961 scopus 로고
    • Transcendental nonsense and the functional approach
    • See, 809-21, critiquing the "transcendental" and metaphysical mode of legal reasoning, as opposed to the realist, functional mode
    • See Felix S. Cohen, Transcendental Nonsense and the Functional Approach, 35 COLUM. L. REV. 809, 809-21 (1935) (critiquing the "transcendental" and metaphysical mode of legal reasoning, as opposed to the realist, functional mode).
    • (1935) Colum. L. Rev. , vol.35 , pp. 809
    • Cohen, F.S.1
  • 99
    • 79959505189 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kennedy, supra note 7, at 1061-62
    • Kennedy, supra note 7, at 1061-62.
  • 101
    • 84935448052 scopus 로고
    • Formal justice and the spirit of capitalism: Max weber's sociology of law
    • Sally Ewing, Formal Justice and the Spirit of Capitalism: Max Weber's Sociology of Law, 21 LAW & SOC. REV. 487 (1987);
    • (1987) Law & Soc. Rev. , vol.21 , pp. 487
    • Ewing, S.1
  • 102
    • 79959492701 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Trubek, supra note 16
    • Trubek, supra note 16;
  • 103
    • 79959500919 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Trubek, supra note 33
    • Trubek, supra note 33.
  • 104
    • 79959511891 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Singer, supra note 51, at 470-503. I do not suggest that the realists did not proffer an impressive, perhaps even convincing, attempt to deal with these challenges by themselves. Nor am I suggesting that the realists' legal conception denied the possibility of all normativity; on the contrary, alongside their critique, the realists paved the way for what could be called a "disenchanted reconstruction/normativity." Indeed, they offered a wide array of reconstructive suggestions to their critique of legal formalism, most notably the social-scientific response-law's indeterminacy can be resolved through the application of social science to legal questions-and the practical reason/wisdom response-legal actors neither merely apply the law nor exert crude power but work within this tension by applying practical wisdom
    • See Singer, supra note 51, at 470-503. I do not suggest that the realists did not proffer an impressive, perhaps even convincing, attempt to deal with these challenges by themselves. Nor am I suggesting that the realists' legal conception denied the possibility of all normativity; on the contrary, alongside their critique, the realists paved the way for what could be called a "disenchanted reconstruction/normativity." Indeed, they offered a wide array of reconstructive suggestions to their critique of legal formalism, most notably the social-scientific response-law's indeterminacy can be resolved through the application of social science to legal questions-and the practical reason/wisdom response-legal actors neither merely apply the law nor exert crude power but work within this tension by applying practical wisdom.
  • 105
    • 79959499047 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Dagan, supra note 50, at 652
    • See Dagan, supra note 50, at 652.
  • 106
    • 79959497021 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Singer, supra note 51, at 469-70. Giving a comprehensive list of various critical legal theories would be impossible. The leading ones, however, are: critical legal studies, critical race theory, critical law and society, some strands of legal feminism, and critical legal history. For a comprehensive overview of the critical legal projects
    • See Singer, supra note 51, at 469-70. Giving a comprehensive list of various critical legal theories would be impossible. The leading ones, however, are: critical legal studies, critical race theory, (critical) law and society, some strands of legal feminism, and critical legal history. For a comprehensive overview of the critical legal projects
  • 108
    • 4344569622 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See also, Wendy Brown & Janet Halley eds., reviewing the state of the art of critical legal projects
    • See also LEFT LEGAUSM/LEFT CRITIQUE (Wendy Brown & Janet Halley eds., 2002) (reviewing the state of the art of critical legal projects).
    • (2002) Left Legausm/Left Critique
  • 109
    • 79959527073 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Singer, supra note 51, at 470-71. More difficult than listing all the critical theories is naming all the legal-reconstruction projects and theoreticians. Those most dominant and influential are: the legal process, law and economics, normative legal feminism also referred to as governance feminism
    • See Singer, supra note 51, at 470-71. More difficult than listing all the critical theories is naming all the legal-reconstruction projects and theoreticians. Those most dominant and influential are: the legal process, law and economics, normative legal feminism (also referred to as governance feminism
  • 111
    • 79959512516 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra Part LB
    • See supra Part LB.
  • 112
    • 79959516642 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As I elaborate in the following section, this "more" is quite different for different dieoreticians: law is immanendy rational
    • As I elaborate in the following section, this "more" is quite different for different dieoreticians: law is immanendy rational
  • 113
    • 79959497253 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see infra Part HA.; a mode for expressing and inculcating virtue
    • see infra Part HA.; a mode for expressing and inculcating virtue
  • 114
    • 79959519113 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see infra Part H. B.; a form of art, see infra Part II. C; or charismatically audioritative
    • see infra Part H. B.; a form of art, see infra Part II. C; or charismatically audioritative
  • 115
    • 79959508129 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see infra Part H. D
    • see infra Part H. D.
  • 116
    • 84936068266 scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., charismatization of legal authorities
    • See, e.g., RONALD DWORKIN, LAW'S EMPIRE 225-75 (1986) (charismatization of legal authorities);
    • (1986) Law's Empire , pp. 225-275
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 119
    • 0346960516 scopus 로고
    • In praise of collides
    • hereinafter Nonet, In Praise of Collicles law as art
    • Philippe Nonet, In Praise of Collides, 74 IOWA L. REV. 807 (1989) [hereinafter Nonet, In Praise of Collicles] (law as art);
    • (1989) Iowa L. Rev. , vol.74 , pp. 807
    • Nonet, P.1
  • 120
    • 84928460118 scopus 로고
    • In the Matter of Green v. Recht, hereinafter Nonet, Green v. Recht law as a form of art
    • Philippe Nonet, In the Matter of Green v. Recht, 75 CALIF. L. REV. 363 (1987) [hereinafter Nonet, Green v. Recht] (law as a form of art);
    • (1987) Calif. L. Rev. , vol.75 , pp. 363
    • Nonet, P.1
  • 121
    • 84935464287 scopus 로고
    • Legal formalism: On the immanent rationality of law
    • Legal Formalism
    • Ernest J. Weinrib, Legal Formalism: On the Immanent Rationality of Law, 97 YALE LJ. 949 (1988) (legal formalism).
    • (1988) Yale Lj , vol.97 , pp. 949
    • Weinrib, E.J.1
  • 122
    • 79959500695 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In this sense, my argument is hermeneutic rather than empirical or positive, as I offer a new interpretative framework for a significant volume of scholarly works. I do not claim to have discovered any new data or facts, but merely suggest that the set of works that I discuss are best read in light of the conceptual framework that I offer
    • In this sense, my argument is hermeneutic rather than empirical or positive, as I offer a new interpretative framework for a significant volume of scholarly works. I do not claim to have discovered any new data or facts, but merely suggest that the set of works that I discuss are best read in light of the conceptual framework that I offer.
  • 123
    • 79959515782 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • One such major strand of legal thought includes scholars influenced by the writings of political theologians such as Carl Schmitt, Walter Benjamin, Jacques Derrida, and Giorgio Agamben. These philosophers, in distinct ways, advance the idea that modernity still carries remnants of the theological and of theological modes of reasoning. For legal scholars working in that vein, there is a formidable task to uncover, as Lavi points out, "the sacred past or a transcendent future that lurk beneath the surface of rational-secularized law."
    • One such major strand of legal thought includes scholars influenced by the writings of political theologians such as Carl Schmitt, Walter Benjamin, Jacques Derrida, and Giorgio Agamben. These philosophers, in distinct ways, advance the idea that modernity still carries remnants of the theological and of theological modes of reasoning. For legal scholars working in that vein, there is a formidable task to uncover, as Lavi points out, "the sacred past or a transcendent future that lurk beneath the surface of rational-secularized law."
  • 124
    • 79959518469 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Enchanting a disenchanted law: On the jewish ritual and secular history in nineteenth century Germany
    • See, forthcoming, Some such legal writers unveil law's profound theological structure and content in order to reenchant it and find in it the metaphysical, the divine, and the ideal
    • See Shai Lavi, Enchanting a Disenchanted Law: On the Jewish Ritual and Secular History in Nineteenth Century Germany, 1 U. IRVINE L. REV. (forthcoming 2011). Some such legal writers unveil law's profound theological structure and content in order to reenchant it and find in it the metaphysical, the divine, and the ideal.
    • (2011) U. Irvine L. Rev. , vol.1
    • Lavi, S.1
  • 125
    • 79955092809 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Constituent power as body: Outline of a constitutional theology
    • See, e.g.
    • See, e.g., Lior Barshack, Constituent Power as Body: Outline of a Constitutional Theology, 56 U. TORONTO L. J. 185 (2006);
    • (2006) U. Toronto L. J. , vol.56 , pp. 185
    • Barshack, L.1
  • 128
    • 0004106103 scopus 로고
    • See generally, hereinafter WEINRIB, PRIVATE LAW, discussing formalism as a means of understanding private law
    • See generally ERNEST J. WEINRIB, THE IDEA OF PRIVATE LAW (1995) [hereinafter WEINRIB, PRIVATE LAW] (discussing formalism as a means of understanding private law);
    • (1995) The Idea of Private Law
    • Weinrib, E.J.1
  • 129
    • 79959518011 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Weinrib, supra note 63 defending legal formalism
    • Weinrib, supra note 63 (defending legal formalism);
  • 130
    • 85050413989 scopus 로고
    • The jurisprudence of legal formalism
    • Annual Institute for Humane Studies Law and Philosophy Issue: Symposium on Legal Formalism American Association of Law Schools Section on Law and Interpretation
    • Ernest J. Weinrib, The Jurisprudence of Legal Formalism, 16 HARV. J. L. & PUB. POL'Y 583 (1993) [hereinafter Weinrib, Jurisprudence] (refuting the notion that formalism is dead). (Pubitemid 24817558)
    • (1993) Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy , vol.16 , Issue.3 , pp. 583
    • Weinrib, E.J.1
  • 131
    • 79954552996 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., arguing that, despite its limits, formalism is a necessary framework for interpreting and developing a liberal theory of penal justice
    • See, e.g., ALAN BRUDNER, PUNISHMENT AND FREEDOM: A LIBERAL THEORY OF PENAL JUSTICE 28-58 (2009) (arguing that, despite its limits, formalism is a necessary framework for interpreting and developing a liberal theory of penal justice);
    • (2009) Punishment and Freedom: A Liberal Theory of Penal Justice , pp. 28-58
    • Brudner, A.1
  • 132
    • 0004132521 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • developing a formalist-inspired conception of property law
    • J. E. PENNER, THE IDEA OF PROPERTY IN LAW (1997) (developing a formalist-inspired conception of property law);
    • (1997) The Idea of Property in Law
    • Penner, J.E.1
  • 135
    • 79959494605 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Weinrib, supra note 63, at 950
    • Weinrib, supra note 63, at 950.
  • 136
    • 79959509792 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • list is lengthy and includes BRUDNER, supra note 67, at 28-48 criminal law, constitutional law
    • The list is lengthy and includes BRUDNER, supra note 67, at 28-48 (criminal law, constitutional law);
  • 137
    • 79959508556 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • PENNER, supra note 67, at 103-04 property
    • PENNER, supra note 67, at 103-04 (property);
  • 138
    • 79959516199 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • RIPSTEIN, supra note 67, at 30-56 contracts, property, constitutional law, criminal law
    • RIPSTEIN, supra note 67, at 30-56 (contracts, property, constitutional law, criminal law);
  • 139
    • 79959502040 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 66, torts
    • WEINRIB, PRIVATE LAW, supra note 66, at 23-55 (torts);
    • Weinrib, Private Law , pp. 23-55
  • 140
    • 0037795498 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Poverty and property in Kant's system of rights
    • hereinafter Weinrib, Kant's System of Rights property, 800-01
    • Ernest J. Weinrib, Poverty and Property in Kant's System of Rights, 78 NOTRE DAME L. REV. 795, 800-01 (2003) [hereinafter Weinrib, Kant's System of Rights] (property);
    • (2003) Notre Dame L. Rev. , vol.78 , pp. 795
    • Weinrib, E.J.1
  • 141
    • 79959513443 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Restoring restitution
    • hereinafter Weinrib, Restoring Restitution, 862-63
    • Ernest J. Weinrib, Restoring Restitution, 91 VA. L. REV. 861, 862-63 (2005) [hereinafter Weinrib, Restoring Restitution]
    • (2005) Va. L. Rev. , vol.91 , pp. 861
    • Weinrib, E.J.1
  • 143
    • 79959517310 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Weinrib, Jurisprudence, supra note 66, at 583
    • Weinrib, Jurisprudence, supra note 66, at 583.
  • 144
    • 79959526134 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Weinrib, supra note 63, at 966
    • Weinrib, supra note 63, at 966.
  • 145
    • 79959500468 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 973, 985-99
    • See id. at 973, 985-99.
  • 146
    • 79959495535 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra Part LB
    • See supra Part LB.
  • 147
    • 79959532361 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Weinrib, supra note 63, at 952-55
    • See Weinrib, supra note 63, at 952-55.
  • 148
    • 79959510966 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 962-63, 966-84
    • See id. at 962-63, 966-84.
  • 149
    • 79959532169 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See. id. at 966
    • See. id. at 966.
  • 150
    • 79959515783 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Weinrib, Kant's System of Rights, supra note 69, at 795-828
    • See, e.g., Weinrib, Kant's System of Rights, supra note 69, at 795-828.
  • 151
    • 79959532614 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See RIPSTEIN, supra note 67, at 1-30
    • See RIPSTEIN, supra note 67, at 1-30.
  • 152
    • 79959510755 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See BRUDNER, supra note 67, at 34-35, 45-48, 231-32
    • See BRUDNER, supra note 67, at 34-35, 45-48, 231-32;
  • 153
    • 79959529795 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Brudner, supra note 9, at 1183-98
    • Brudner, supra note 9, at 1183-98.
  • 154
    • 79959503351 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Weinrib, supra note 63, at 954 n. 14 citing Aquinas as the "classic account" of formalism
    • See Weinrib, supra note 63, at 954 n. 14 (citing Aquinas as the "classic account" of formalism).
  • 155
    • 79959504968 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 977-81 noting that Aristotle was the first to describe juridical abstractions in his discussion of justice
    • See id. at 977-81 (noting that Aristotle was the first to describe juridical abstractions in his discussion of justice).
  • 156
    • 79959491573 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • profound historicity of legal formalism is obvious in Weber's sociology of law because all modes of legal thought are historical and change over time
    • The profound historicity of legal formalism is obvious in Weber's sociology of law because all modes of legal thought are historical and change over time.
  • 157
    • 79959521130 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Weber claimed that legal positivism was an essential part of the evoludon of legal disenchantment because it meant that no matter what the legislator determined, the legal system would be able to work it into an elaborate system of rules, bureaucratically applied, supra note 29
    • Weber claimed that legal positivism was an essential part of the evoludon of legal disenchantment because it meant that no matter what the legislator determined, the legal system would be able to work it into an elaborate system of rules, bureaucratically applied. 2 WEBER, supra note 29, at 875-76.
    • Weber , vol.2 , pp. 875-876
  • 158
    • 79959497693 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See BRUDNER, supra note 67, at 21-55. Although Brudner claims that formalism has limits and that a full normative account requires considerations of morality and policy, he generally accepts formalism as a necessary framework for legal theory
    • See BRUDNER, supra note 67, at 21-55. Although Brudner claims that formalism has limits and that a full normative account requires considerations of morality and policy, he generally accepts formalism as a necessary framework for legal theory.
  • 159
    • 79959534023 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id
    • See id.
  • 161
    • 79959502973 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See PENNER, supra note 67
    • See PENNER, supra note 67.
  • 162
    • 79959533119 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See BRUDNER, supra note 67
    • See BRUDNER, supra note 67.
  • 164
    • 79959516420 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I refer here especially to Ripstein and Brudner, who are explicit about their commitment to freedom as the tides of their books suggest for Ripstein it is Force and Freedom and for Brudner Punishment and Freedom
    • I refer here especially to Ripstein and Brudner, who are explicit about their commitment to freedom as the tides of their books suggest for Ripstein it is Force and Freedom and for Brudner Punishment and Freedom.
  • 165
    • 79959526364 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Kennedy, supra note 7, at 1064
    • See Kennedy, supra note 7, at 1064.
  • 166
    • 79959526614 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., RIPSTEIN, supra note 67, at 255 "Kant is certainly committed to the idea that 'right must never be accommodated to politics, but politics must always be accommodated to right.'"
    • See, e.g., RIPSTEIN, supra note 67, at 255 ("Kant is certainly committed to the idea that 'right must never be accommodated to politics, but politics must always be accommodated to right.'").
  • 167
    • 79959506293 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • problem of law's special relation to morality is obviously one of the themes that twentieth-century jurisprudence deals with most extensively even more so over the past thirty years and is not unique to contemporary formalism. Indeed I argue that the renewed interest in natural law and in law's morality is another marker of the reenchantment of law
    • The problem of law's special relation to morality is obviously one of the themes that twentieth-century jurisprudence deals with most extensively (even more so over the past thirty years) and is not unique to contemporary formalism. Indeed I argue that the renewed interest in natural law and in law's morality is another marker of the reenchantment of law.
  • 168
    • 79959505429 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See infra Part H. B
    • See infra Part H. B.
  • 169
    • 79959499302 scopus 로고
    • Formalism, positivism, and natural law in ernest weinrib's tort theory: Will the real ernest weinrib please come forward?
    • Some have therefore argued that Weinrib's formalism is reminiscent of natural law. See, 350
    • Some have therefore argued that Weinrib's formalism is reminiscent of natural law. See George Brencher IV, Formalism, Positivism, and Natural Law in Ernest Weinrib's Tort Theory: Will the Real Ernest Weinrib Please Come Forward?, 642 U. TORONTO L. J. 318, 350 (1992).
    • (1992) U. Toronto L. J , vol.642 , pp. 318
    • Brencher IV, G.1
  • 170
    • 79959511220 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Kennedy, supra note 7, at 1064 "Weber's theory of the disenchantment of lawmaking ended with its fusion into politics-specifically legislative politics."
    • See Kennedy, supra note 7, at 1064 ("Weber's theory of the disenchantment of lawmaking ended with its fusion into politics-specifically legislative politics.").
  • 171
    • 79959514147 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Weinrib, supra note 63, at 985-99
    • See, e.g., Weinrib, supra note 63, at 985-99.
  • 172
    • 79959499702 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 29
    • -2 WEBER, supra note 29, at 874-75.
    • Weber , vol.2 , pp. 874-875
  • 173
    • 79959502040 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, supra note 66
    • See WEINRIB, PRIVATE LAW, supra note 66, at 6.
    • Weinrib, Private Law , pp. 6
  • 174
    • 79959510754 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "It is not accidental that our greatest art is intimate and not monumental, nor is it accidental that today only within the smallest and intimate circles, in personal human situations, in pianissimo, that something is pulsating that corresponds to the prophetic pneuma, which in former times swept through the great communities like a firebrand, welding them together."
    • "It is not accidental that our greatest art is intimate and not monumental, nor is it accidental that today only within the smallest and intimate circles, in personal human situations, in pianissimo, that something is pulsating that corresponds to the prophetic pneuma, which in former times swept through the great communities like a firebrand, welding them together."
  • 175
    • 79959526851 scopus 로고
    • The origins of modern capitalism
    • Wolf Heydebrand ed., Frank H. Knight trans.
    • MAX WEBER, The Origins of Modern Capitalism, in SOCIOLOGICAL WRITINGS 151, 155 (Wolf Heydebrand ed., Frank H. Knight trans., 1994).
    • (1994) Sociological Writings , vol.151 , pp. 155
    • Weber, M.1
  • 176
    • 79959493848 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, In a book review, Kennedy identifies four different meanings of the phrase enchantment of reason in Schlag's theorization: first, an immoderate confidence, an excessive belief in one's own reason; second, the rule of reason; third, denying reason's vulnerability; and fourth, "'an odd conjunction of the magical and the technological' in thinking about law."
    • See PIERRE SCHLAG, THE ENCHANTMENT OF REASON 1 (1998). In a book review, Kennedy identifies four different meanings of the phrase enchantment of reason in Schlag's theorization: first, an immoderate confidence, an excessive belief in one's own reason; second, the rule of reason; third, denying reason's vulnerability; and fourth, "'an odd conjunction of the magical and the technological' in thinking about law."
    • (1998) The Enchantment of Reason , vol.1
    • Schlag, P.1
  • 177
    • 79959503568 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Pierre schlag's the enchantment of reason
    • See, 516-39
    • See Duncan Kennedy, Pierre Schlag's The Enchantment of Reason, 57 U. MIAMI L. REV. 513, 516-39 (2003).
    • (2003) U. Miami L. Rev. , vol.57 , pp. 513
    • Kennedy, D.1
  • 178
    • 79959499702 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 29
    • -2 WEBER, supra note 29, at 874-75.
    • Weber , vol.2 , pp. 874-875
  • 179
    • 0003535796 scopus 로고
    • Classical works advocating the need to reinsert virtue into our political and legal systems include
    • Classical works advocating the need to reinsert virtue into our political and legal systems include PHILIPPA FOOT, VIRTUES AND VICES AND OTHER ESSAYS IN MORAL PHILOSOPHY 1-19 (1978);
    • (1978) Virtues and Vices and Other Essays in Moral Philosophy , pp. 1-19
    • Foot, P.1
  • 180
    • 79959517782 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • GLENDON, supra note 63, at 1-17
    • GLENDON, supra note 63, at 1-17;
  • 182
    • 79959498394 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SANDEL, supra note 63, at 104-09
    • SANDEL, supra note 63, at 104-09;
  • 183
    • 84985348224 scopus 로고
    • Non-relative virtues: An aristotelian approach
    • 32-34, Peter A. French et al. eds, Bonnie Honig argues that contemporary-virtue theorists such as John Rawls and Michael Sandel use the concept of "virtue" to quench real politics, which is about irresolvable contests and disagreements
    • Martha C. Nussbaum, Non-Relative Virtues: An Aristotelian Approach, in 13 MIDWEST STUDIES IN PHILOSOPHY: ETHICAL THEORY 32, 32-34 (Peter A. French et al. eds, 1988). Bonnie Honig argues that contemporary-virtue theorists (such as John Rawls and Michael Sandel) use the concept of "virtue" to quench real politics, which is about irresolvable contests and disagreements.
    • (1988) Midwest Studies in Philosophy: Ethical Theory , vol.13 , pp. 32
    • Nussbaum, M.C.1
  • 185
    • 68949134356 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Land virtues
    • See, e.g., 860-87
    • See, e.g., Eduardo M. Penalver, Land Virtues, 94 CORNELL L. REV. 821, 860-87 (2009).
    • (2009) Cornell L. Rev. , vol.94 , pp. 821
    • Penalver, E.M.1
  • 186
    • 61049304166 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Virtue jurisprudence: A virtue-centered theory of judging
    • See, 179, arguing for a "virtue-centered theory of judging", which looks to encourage certain desirable characteristics of judges and which can account for the role that judges play in the legal system. It is important to distinguish the interest that virtue theorists find in "character" and the attention that legal realists' interest gave to the concrete character of legal actors, especially judges. While for virtue theorists character is an object of interest due to the importance of intentions to the evaluation of the actions and therefore it is important that judges, for example, would have an ideal character
    • See Lawrence B. Solum, Virtue Jurisprudence: A Virtue-Centered Theory of Judging, 34 METAPHILOSOPHY 178, 179 (2003) (arguing for a "virtue-centered theory of judging", which looks to encourage certain desirable characteristics of judges and which can account for the role that judges play in the legal system). It is important to distinguish the interest that virtue theorists find in "character" and the attention that legal realists' interest gave to the concrete character of legal actors, especially judges. While for virtue theorists character is an object of interest due to the importance of intentions to the evaluation of the actions (and therefore it is important that judges, for example, would have an ideal character)
    • (2003) Metaphilosophy , vol.34 , pp. 178
    • Solum, L.B.1
  • 187
    • 79959530755 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see id., for realists the investigation of the character of judges was necessary to predict what they might do in a specific dispute
    • see id., for realists the investigation of the character of judges was necessary to predict what they might do in a specific dispute.
  • 188
    • 79959503569 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Penalver, supra note 102, at 864
    • See Penalver, supra note 102, at 864.
  • 189
    • 79959490894 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Solum, supra note 103, at 181 "Virtue ethics has implications for an account of the proper ends of legislation. If the aim of law is to make citizens virtuous..., what are the implications for the content of the laws?"
    • See Solum, supra note 103, at 181 ("Virtue ethics has implications for an account of the proper ends of legislation. If the aim of law is to make citizens virtuous..., what are the implications for the content of the laws?").
  • 190
    • 79959507213 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Penalver, supra note 102, at 863-64 reintroducing the Aristotelian ethical tradition into the study of property and land use
    • See, e.g., Penalver, supra note 102, at 863-64 (reintroducing the Aristotelian ethical tradition into the study of property and land use).
  • 191
    • 0039283440 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Virtue ethics: A misleading category?
    • See, 164-67
    • See Martha C. Nussbaum, Virtue Ethics: A Misleading Category?, 3 J. ETHICS 163, 164-67 (1999).
    • (1999) J. Ethics , vol.3 , pp. 163
    • Nussbaum, M.C.1
  • 192
    • 79959522142 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Weinrib, supra note 63, at 977 n. 8
    • See, e.g., Weinrib, supra note 63, at 977 n. 8.
  • 193
    • 79959503350 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., BRUDNER, supra note 67, at 26
    • See, e.g., BRUDNER, supra note 67, at 26.
  • 194
    • 79959520024 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., id. at 1-30
    • See, e.g., id. at 1-30.
  • 195
    • 0347971722 scopus 로고
    • Be just to one another: Preliminary thoughts on civility, moral character, and professionalism
    • See, e.g., 113, "The practice of law as a profession presupposes a commitment to civility in rational discourse."
    • See, e.g., Mark Neal Aaronson, Be Just to One Another: Preliminary Thoughts on Civility, Moral Character, and Professionalism, 8 ST. THOMAS L. REV. 113, 113 (1995) ("The practice of law as a profession presupposes a commitment to civility in rational discourse.");
    • (1995) St. Thomas L. Rev. , vol.8 , pp. 113
    • Aaronson, M.N.1
  • 196
    • 79954227835 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Justice as right relationship: A philosophical and theological reflection on affirmative action
    • using theories of virtue in assessing the role of justice in legal, political, and human history, 378-79
    • Robert John Araujo, Justice as Right Relationship: A Philosophical and Theological Reflection on Affirmative Action, 27 PEPP. L. REV. 377, 378-79 (2002) (using theories of virtue in assessing the role of justice in legal, political, and human history);
    • (2002) Pepp. L. Rev. , vol.27 , pp. 377
    • Araujo, R.J.1
  • 197
    • 84937310288 scopus 로고
    • Taking aristotle seriously: Republican-oriented legal theory and the moral foundation of deliberative democracy
    • Miriam Galston, Taking Aristotle Seriously: Republican-Oriented Legal Theory and the Moral Foundation of Deliberative Democracy, 82 CALIF. L. REV. 329, 378-86 (1994) (using Aristode's theory of virtue to defend the argument that communities must morally educate citizens to make politics more deliberative); (Pubitemid 24780892)
    • (1994) California Law Review , vol.82 , Issue.2 , pp. 329
    • Galston, M.1
  • 198
    • 79954223385 scopus 로고
    • The virtue of liberality in American communal life
    • 987, 1012, arguing that America's problem of a "permanent underclass" reflects a failure of virtue
    • Linda R. Hirshman, The Virtue of Liberality in American Communal Life, 88 MICH. L. REV. 983, 987, 1012 (1990) (arguing that America's problem of a "permanent underclass" reflects a failure of virtue);
    • (1990) Mich. L. Rev. , vol.88 , pp. 983
    • Hirshman, L.R.1
  • 199
    • 11944273212 scopus 로고
    • Virtue and inculpation
    • 1425, premising his view of the criminal-justice system on Aristotle's dieory that criminal law serves the greater good of humanity by promoting virtue
    • Kyron Huigens, Virtue and Inculpation, 108 HARV. L. REV. 1423, 1425 (1995) (premising his view of the criminal-justice system on Aristotle's dieory that criminal law serves the greater good of humanity by promoting virtue);
    • (1995) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.108 , pp. 1423
    • Huigens, K.1
  • 200
    • 79959492699 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The concept of property: Relations through objects of social wealth
    • 340, describing Western property regimes as exhibiting "some teleology of virtue"
    • David Lametti, The Concept of Property: Relations Through Objects of Social Wealth, 53 U. TORONTO L. J. 325, 340 (2003) (describing Western property regimes as exhibiting "some teleology of virtue");
    • (2003) U. Toronto L. J , vol.53 , pp. 325
    • Lametti, D.1
  • 201
    • 79959496455 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Eduardo M. Pefialver, supra note 102, at 862-87 introducing virtue as an alternative to economic land-use dieory
    • Eduardo M. Pefialver, supra note 102, at 862-87 (introducing virtue as an alternative to economic land-use dieory);
  • 202
    • 79959534022 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Solum, supra note 103, at 178-79 introducing a virtue-centered theory of judging
    • Solum, supra note 103, at 178-79 (introducing a virtue-centered theory of judging).
  • 203
    • 79959519775 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Pefialver, supra note 102, at 865
    • See Pefialver, supra note 102, at 865.
  • 204
    • 79959527467 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Pefialver includes most liberal values and virtues within a "fully developed conception of human flourishing" thus leaving the enormous task to balance between them at the hands of the judge as well as the administrator and even the landowner
    • Pefialver includes most liberal values and virtues within a "fully developed conception of human flourishing" thus leaving the enormous task to balance between them at the hands of the judge (as well as the administrator and even the landowner).
  • 205
    • 79959506998 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Peñalver, supra note 102, at 867-74, 869 n. 197
    • See Peñalver, supra note 102, at 867-74, 869 n. 197;
  • 206
    • 79959493424 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Restoring the right constitution?
    • see also, 748, "Drawing the appropriate limits around permissible state action in the private sphere ultimately depends upon the consideration of the effectiveness of legal norms in particular contexts as well as the development of an adequate account of human flourishing and the role of human freedom within that account."
    • see also Eduardo M. Peüalver, Restoring the Right Constitution?, 116 YALE LJ. 732, 748 (2007) ("Drawing the appropriate limits around permissible state action in the private sphere ultimately depends upon the consideration of the effectiveness of legal norms in particular contexts as well as the development of an adequate account of human flourishing and the role of human freedom within that account.").
    • (2007) Yale Lj , vol.116 , pp. 732
    • Peüalver, E.M.1
  • 207
    • 33747061045 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The rise of managerial judging in international criminal law
    • See, e.g.
    • See, e.g., Máximo Langer, The Rise of Managerial Judging in International Criminal Law, 53 AM. J. COMP. L. 835 (2005);
    • (2005) Am. J. Comp. L. , vol.53 , pp. 835
    • Langer, M.1
  • 208
    • 0039688261 scopus 로고
    • Managerial judges
    • describing the rise of "managerial judges" in U. S. civil procedures
    • Judith Resnik, Managerial Judges, 96 HARV. L. REV. 374 (1982) (describing the rise of "managerial judges" in U. S. civil procedures).
    • (1982) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.96 , pp. 374
    • Resnik, J.1
  • 209
    • 79959522363 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Peiialver, supra note 102, at 865
    • See Peiialver, supra note 102, at 865.
  • 210
    • 79959527468 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is, to my mind, the crucial difference between virtue theory of adjudication and an institutional dieory such as the one developed by Owen Fiss
    • This is, to my mind, the crucial difference between virtue theory of adjudication and an institutional dieory such as the one developed by Owen Fiss.
  • 211
    • 79959527270 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See also infra Part II. D discussing the reenchantment of legal audiorities
    • See also infra Part II. D (discussing the reenchantment of legal audiorities).
  • 212
    • 79959513190 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Peñalver, supra note 102, at 876
    • See Peñalver, supra note 102, at 876.
  • 213
    • 79959518882 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id
    • See id.
  • 214
    • 79959507698 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 887. !
    • See id. at 887. !
  • 215
    • 79959524807 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dagan advocates this position, according to which the realist conception of law is based on judges applying practical wisdom in order to deal with the tensions inherent in any legal system
    • Dagan advocates this position, according to which the realist conception of law is based on judges applying practical wisdom in order to deal with the tensions inherent in any legal system.
  • 216
    • 79959517309 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Dagan, supra note 50, at 644-45, 648, 652
    • See Dagan, supra note 50, at 644-45, 648, 652.
  • 217
    • 79959512951 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Nonet, Green v. Recht, supra note 63
    • See, e.g., Nonet, Green v. Recht, supra note 63;
  • 219
    • 84930557504 scopus 로고
    • What is positive law?
    • hereinafter Nonet, Positive Law
    • Philippe Nonet, What Is Positive Law?, 100 YALE LJ. 667 (1990) [hereinafter Nonet, Positive Law];
    • (1990) Yale Lj , vol.100 , pp. 667
    • Nonet, P.1
  • 220
    • 79959527675 scopus 로고
    • Sanction
    • Philippe Nonet, Sanction, 25 CUMB. L. REV. 489 (1995);
    • (1995) Cumb. L. Rev. , vol.25 , pp. 489
    • Nonet, P.1
  • 222
    • 79959532360 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Nonet, Green v. Recht, supra note 63, at 375-77
    • See Nonet, Green v. Recht, supra note 63, at 375-77.
  • 223
    • 79959521347 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Lavi eloquently explains this resistance in his contribution to this issue. Theory, he argues, suggests a perspective that is therefore already limited by the position of the observer. It is, he claims, part of the move to epistemology, which has given up on truly knowing the object
    • Lavi eloquently explains this resistance in his contribution to this issue. Theory, he argues, suggests a perspective that is therefore already limited by the position of the observer. It is, he claims, part of the move to epistemology, which has given up on truly knowing the object.
  • 224
    • 79959400302 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Turning the tables on "law and... ": A jurisprudential inquiry into contemporary legal theory
    • See
    • See Shai Lavi, Turning the Tables on "Law and... ": A Jurisprudential Inquiry into Contemporary Legal Theory, 96 CORNELL L. REV. 811 (2011).
    • (2011) Cornell L. Rev. , vol.96 , pp. 811
    • Lavi, S.1
  • 228
    • 84985305578 scopus 로고
    • Genealogy and jurisprudence: Nietzsche, nihilism, and the social scientification of law
    • Marianne Constable, Genealogy and Jurisprudence: Nietzsche, Nihilism, and the Social Scientification of Law, 19 LAW & SOC. INQUIRY 551, 554-55 (1994). (Pubitemid 24835290)
    • (1994) Law and Social Inquiry , vol.19 , Issue.3 , pp. 551
    • Constable, M.1
  • 230
    • 79959525244 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Friedrich nietzsche, the code of manu, and the art of legislation
    • 1134-35
    • Roger Berkowitz, Friedrich Nietzsche, the Code of Manu, and the Art of Legislation, 24 CARDOZO L. REV. 1131, 1134-35 (2003).
    • (2003) Cardozo L. Rev. , vol.24 , pp. 1131
    • Berkowitz, R.1
  • 231
    • 33645911599 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Herbert morris and punishment
    • See, 109
    • See Linda Ross Meyer, Herbert Morris and Punishment, 22 QUINNIPIAC L. REV. 109, 109 (2003);
    • (2003) Quinnipiac L. Rev. , vol.22 , pp. 109
    • Meyer, L.R.1
  • 232
    • 0346934919 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Is practical reason mindless?
    • Linda Ross Meyer, Is Practical Reason Mindless?, 86 GEO. LJ. 647, 648-52 (1998). (Pubitemid 128429257)
    • (1998) Georgetown Law Journal , vol.86 , Issue.3 , pp. 647
    • Meyer, L.R.1
  • 233
    • 33845407512 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The critical modernism of hanna arendt
    • See
    • See Mark Antaki, The Critical Modernism of Hanna Arendt, 8 THEORETICAL INQUIRIES L. 251 (2007);
    • (2007) Theoretical Inquiries L. , vol.8 , pp. 251
    • Antaki, M.1
  • 234
    • 70350205301 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The world (lessness) of human rights
    • 205-06
    • Mark Antaki, The World (lessness) of Human Rights, 49 MCGILL L. J. 203, 205-06 (2004).
    • (2004) Mcgill L. J , vol.49 , pp. 203
    • Antaki, M.1
  • 236
    • 79959498829 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Lavi argues that the needed move is not to bring metaphysics back into the law but actually to engage in an ontological investigation of it, which will enable us to see "the law as it is" rather than as it is perceived by various perspecdves or disciplines
    • Lavi argues that the needed move is not to bring metaphysics back into the law but actually to engage in an ontological investigation of it, which will enable us to see "the law as it is" rather than as it is perceived by various perspecdves or disciplines.
  • 237
    • 79959506771 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Lavi, supra note 123, at 816-17
    • See Lavi, supra note 123, at 816-17.
  • 238
    • 79959492462 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Nonet, Green v. Recht, supra note 63, at 377 "A dark age has come. Welcome it. Be grateful that your fate was to live in a time when the absence of spirit would demand so much thought.... Perhaps the light will shine more brighdy when it rises in darkness."
    • See Nonet, Green v. Recht, supra note 63, at 377 ("A dark age has
  • 239
    • 79959530754 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See CONSTABLE, supra note 124
    • See CONSTABLE, supra note 124;
  • 240
    • 79959502732 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 121
    • Nonet, Positive Law, supra note 121, at 669-72.
    • Positive Law , pp. 669-672
    • Nonet1
  • 241
    • 79959527271 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Kennedy, supra note 7, at 1055-61
    • See Kennedy, supra note 7, at 1055-61.
  • 242
    • 79959507697 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nonet describes "law and." as follows: The odors of law and... are among the foulest.... Look at the people with whom law and... has populated the earth. Look at that swarming mass of busy, hurried, restless, racing, radike humanity.... See what and how these beings are: wanting and needing, being deficient, crippled, hence dependent, eager recipients, sufferers, motivated, acted upon... never responsible, never punishable, never deserving, only able to have their future predicted, therefore also superstitiously crawling at the feet of fortunetellers in abject fear of pain and deam.... In law and..., though not by it, humanity is defiled
    • Nonet describes "law and..." as follows: [T]he odors of law and... are among the foulest.... Look at the people with whom law and... has populated the earth. Look at that swarming mass of busy, hurried, restless, racing, radike humanity.... See what and how these beings are: wanting and needing, being deficient, crippled, hence dependent, eager recipients, sufferers, motivated, acted upon... never responsible, never punishable, never deserving, only able to have their future predicted, therefore also superstitiously crawling at the feet of fortunetellers in abject fear of pain and deam.... In law and..., though not by it, humanity is defiled.
  • 243
    • 79959491793 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nonet, Green v. Recht, supra note 63, at 376-77
    • Nonet, Green v. Recht, supra note 63, at 376-77.
  • 244
    • 79959492242 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • BERKOWITZ, supra note 125
    • BERKOWITZ, supra note 125.
  • 245
    • 79959509542 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • LAVI, supra note 128
    • LAVI, supra note 128.
  • 247
    • 79959508344 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Indeed, the main of legal history could be labeled as another disenchanted theory of law, which strips it off its metaphysical dignity, unity, and coherence by exposing law as the outcome of mundane and profane processes and interests. For a critique of this disenchanted mode of historicizing
    • Indeed, the main of legal history could be labeled as another disenchanted theory of law, which strips it off its metaphysical dignity, unity, and coherence by exposing law as the outcome of mundane and profane processes and interests. For a critique of this disenchanted mode of historicizing
  • 248
    • 79959493425 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see Tomlins, supra note 65
    • see Tomlins, supra note 65.
  • 249
    • 79959518222 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • BERKOWITZ, supra note 125, at xiii
    • BERKOWITZ, supra note 125, at xiii.
  • 250
    • 79959529582 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Berkowitz, supra note 125, at 1134 finding exemplary, "good" legislation in ancient codes such as the Code of Manu
    • See Berkowitz, supra note 125, at 1134 (finding exemplary, "good" legislation in ancient codes such as the Code of Manu);
  • 251
    • 79959521129 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nonet, Green v. Recht, supra note 63, at 376
    • Nonet, Green v. Recht, supra note 63, at 376.
  • 252
    • 79959493939 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nonet, Green v. Recht, supra note 63, at 376
    • Nonet, Green v. Recht, supra note 63, at 376.
  • 253
    • 79959509541 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • BERKOWITZ, supra note 125, at ix
    • BERKOWITZ, supra note 125, at ix.
  • 254
    • 79959533557 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Berkowitz, for instance, claims that "we know that there is more to being a neighbor than paying for the damage one does. Only one who understands that he is enmeshed in a moral world keeps his promise even when it is convenient, efficient, and legal to break it."
    • Berkowitz, for instance, claims that "we know that there is more to being a neighbor than paying for the damage one does. Only one who understands that he is enmeshed in a moral world keeps his promise even when it is convenient, efficient, and legal to break it."
  • 255
    • 79959492700 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at xii
    • Id. at xii.
  • 256
    • 79959496923 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • LAVI, supra note 128, at 75-98, 126-71
    • LAVI, supra note 128, at 75-98, 126-71.
  • 257
    • 79959518468 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Constable, supra note 124, at 572-80
    • Constable, supra note 124, at 572-80.
  • 258
    • 79959496690 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • BERKOWITZ, supra note 125, at xii
    • BERKOWITZ, supra note 125, at xii.
  • 259
    • 79959518639 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nonet, Green v. Recht, supra note 63, at 376
    • Nonet, Green v. Recht, supra note 63, at 376.
  • 260
    • 79959523709 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra Part I. B
    • See supra Part I. B.
  • 261
    • 79959520023 scopus 로고
    • See Kennedy, supra note 7, at 1065 quoting, Guenther Roth & Claus Wittich eds., Univ. of Cal. Press 1978
    • See Kennedy, supra note 7, at 1065 (quoting 2 MAX WEBER, ECONOMY AND SOCIETY: AN OUTLINE OF INTERPRETIVE SOCIOLOGY 875 (Guenther Roth & Claus Wittich eds., Univ. of Cal. Press 1978) (1921-1922)).
    • (1921) Max Weber, Economy and Society: An Outline of Interpretive Sociology , vol.2 , pp. 875
  • 262
    • 79959506522 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Langer, supra note 114 describing a global movement towards managerial judging
    • See Langer, supra note 114 (describing a global movement towards managerial judging).
  • 264
    • 79959515781 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cohen, supra note 55, at 846 the need to study the psychology of judges
    • Cohen, supra note 55, at 846 (the need to study the psychology of judges);
  • 265
    • 0039039964 scopus 로고
    • The judgment intuitive: The function of the "hunch" in judicial decision
    • on judicial "hunch" as the determining factor in judgment
    • Joseph C. Hutcheson, Jr., The Judgment Intuitive: The Function of the "Hunch" in Judicial Decision, 14 CORNELL L. Q. 274 (1929) (on judicial "hunch" as the determining factor in judgment).
    • (1929) Cornell L. Q. , vol.14 , pp. 274
    • Hutcheson Jr., J.C.1
  • 267
    • 0002055435 scopus 로고
    • William N. Eskridge, Jr., & Philip P. Frickey eds., defining procedures and processes that would legitimate the legal process and adjudication
    • HENRY M. HART, Jr., & ALBERT M. SACKS, THE LEGAL PROCESS: BASIC PROBLEMS IN THE MAKING AND APPLICATION OF LAW (William N. Eskridge, Jr., & Philip P. Frickey eds., 1994) (defining procedures and processes that would legitimate the legal process and adjudication).
    • (1994) The Legal Process: Basic Problems in the Making and Application of Law
    • Hart Jr., H.M.1    Sacks, A.M.2
  • 269
    • 79959525243 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • xhe various law and social-science schools of thought are too many to name, yet most dominant are "law and economics" and "law and society" usually meaning sociology and anthropology. For the purposes of this discussion, normative law and economics is the best example of a theory that legitimates the judge by subjecting her to the methodology of economics
    • xhe various law and social-science schools of thought are too many to name, yet most dominant are "law and economics" and "law and society" (usually meaning sociology and anthropology. For the purposes of this discussion, normative law and economics is the best example of a theory that legitimates the judge by subjecting her to the methodology of economics.
  • 270
    • 0001630127 scopus 로고
    • The ethical and political basis of the efficiency norm in common law adjudication
    • See, e.g.
    • See, e.g., Richard A. Posner, The Ethical and Political Basis of the Efficiency Norm in Common Law Adjudication, 8 HOFSTRA L. REV. 487 (1980).
    • (1980) Hofstra L. Rev. , vol.8 , pp. 487
    • Posner, R.A.1
  • 271
    • 79959430591 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The character of legal theory
    • See Hanoch Dagan
    • See Hanoch Dagan & Roy Kreitner, The Character of Legal Theory, 96 CORNELL L. REV. 671 (2011);
    • (2011) Cornell L. Rev. , vol.96 , pp. 671
    • Kreitner, R.1
  • 272
    • 0347710456 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Law as craft
    • see also, 2274-322, exploring the similarities between the law and other craft traditions
    • see also Brett G. Scharffs, Law as Craft, 54 VAND. L. REV. 2245, 2274-322 (2001) (exploring the similarities between the law and other craft traditions).
    • (2001) Vand. L. Rev. , vol.54 , pp. 2245
    • Scharffs, B.G.1
  • 273
    • 79959520463 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dagan & Kreitner, supra note 154
    • Dagan & Kreitner, supra note 154.
  • 275
    • 79959492698 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Solum, supra note 103, at 192-93
    • See Solum, supra note 103, at 192-93.
  • 276
    • 0039632008 scopus 로고
    • A return to stare decisis
    • 73-75, emphasis added. This characterization might seem somewhat unfair, given Oliphant's attempt to bind the judge through institutional arrangements much like Fiss. Yet, I think that there is enough in Oliphant to render him a reenchanter of the judges' charisma or traditional authority
    • Herman Oliphant, A Return to Stare Decisis, 14 A. B. A. J. 71, 73-75 (1928) (emphasis added). This characterization might seem somewhat unfair, given Oliphant's attempt to bind the judge through institutional arrangements much like Fiss. Yet, I think that there is enough in Oliphant to render him a reenchanter of the judges' charisma or traditional authority.
    • (1928) A. B. A. J. , vol.14 , pp. 71
    • Oliphant, H.1
  • 278
    • 84936068266 scopus 로고
    • See, hereinafter DWORKIN, LAW'S EMPIRE
    • See RONALD DWORKIN, LAW'S EMPIRE 239-50 (1986) [hereinafter DWORKIN, LAW'S EMPIRE];
    • (1986) Law's Empire , pp. 239-250
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 280
    • 79959502277 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, supra note 160, at 6-10, 96-98, 219-24, 254-70
    • See DWORKIN, LAW'S EMPIRE, supra note 160, at 6-10, 96-98, 219-24, 254-70.
    • Dworkin, Law's Empire
  • 282
    • 0003903243 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • James Bohman & William Rehg eds.
    • DELIBERATIVE DEMOCRACY (James Bohman & William Rehg eds., 1997);
    • (1997) Deliberative Democracy
  • 284
    • 0002247753 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Introduction: The democratic moment and the problem of difference
    • 16 Seyla Benhabib ed., introducing a collection of essays aimed at convincing "intellectuals... that democracy can be defended with rigorous argument... not only with good faith and pious wishes"
    • Seyla Benhabib, Introduction: The Democratic Moment and the Problem of Difference, in DEMOCRACY AND DIFFERENCE: CONTESTING THE BOUNDARIES OF THE POLITICAL 1, 16 (Seyla Benhabib ed., 1996) (introducing a collection of essays aimed at convincing "intellectuals... that democracy can be defended with rigorous argument... not only with good faith and pious wishes");
    • (1996) Democracy and Difference: Contesting the Boundaries of the Political , pp. 1
    • Benhabib, S.1
  • 285
    • 0002247751 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Toward a deliberative model of democratic legitimacy
    • supra, at 67 hereinafter Benhabib, Deliberative Model
    • Seyla Benhabib, Toward a Deliberative Model of Democratic Legitimacy, in DEMOCRACY AND DIFFERENCE, supra, at 67 [hereinafter Benhabib, Deliberative Model];
    • Democracy and Difference
    • Benhabib, S.1
  • 286
    • 79959519112 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Three normative models for democracy
    • supra, at 21. For a discussion and critique of Habermas's theory of discursive democracy
    • Jürgen Habermas, Three Normative Models for Democracy, in DEMOCRACY AND DIFFERENCE, supra, at 21. For a discussion and critique of Habermas's theory of discursive democracy
    • Democracy and Difference
    • Habermas, J.1
  • 287
    • 0002048136 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Reflections on habermas on democracy
    • see
    • see Joshua Cohen, Reflections on Habermas on Democracy, 12 RATIO JURIS 385 (1999).
    • (1999) Ratio Juris , vol.12 , pp. 385
    • Cohen, J.1
  • 288
    • 79959502516 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 162 and accompanying text
    • See supra note 162 and accompanying text.
  • 289
    • 0003868677 scopus 로고
    • For the classic work on the crisis of parliamentary democracy in the early twentieth century, see, Ellen Kennedy trans., For a more recent account of the severe deficiencies of contemporary parliamentary democracies
    • For the classic work on the crisis of parliamentary democracy in the early twentieth century, see CARL SCHMITT, THE CRISIS OF PARLIAMENTARY DEMOCRACY (Ellen Kennedy trans., 1985). For a more recent account of the severe deficiencies of contemporary parliamentary democracies
    • (1985) The Crisis of Parliamentary Democracy
    • Schmitt, C.1
  • 291
    • 11944263707 scopus 로고
    • A civic republican fustification for the bureaucratic state
    • Mark Seidenfeld, A Civic Republican fustification for the Bureaucratic State, 105 HARV. L. REV. 1511 (1992).
    • (1992) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.105 , pp. 1511
    • Seidenfeld, M.1
  • 292
    • 79959498171 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Although it would be impossible for me to discuss it in length, I would like to note that the surge of constitutional theory and of constitutionalization-in the United States and abroad-is another mark of the legitimacy crisis of the parliamentary administrative state and of positive law. Although a constitution is clearly a positive legal document, enacted (and amended) according to legal procedures, therefore obtaining its legitimacy from its being posited, it enjoys a unique status, either because it is often understood to be a direct articulation of moral principles or because it embothes a more authentic will of the population (due to requirements of supermajorities, plebiscites, and so forth). Once adopted, a constitution, especially if accompanied by judicial review of legislation-a practice adopted in more and more jurisdictions throughout the world-gives the entire legal field a moral and democratic legitimacy. Furthermore, it gives the legal system an image of a practice dedicated to the protection of an ancient, sacred, coherent, and authoritative text.
  • 295
    • 79959521703 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cohen, supra note 162, at 387-90
    • Cohen, supra note 162, at 387-90;
  • 296
    • 79959530544 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Habermas, supra note 162, at 21
    • Habermas, supra note 162, at 21.
  • 297
    • 79959501600 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Wealth maximization or efficiency can be seen as such a principle or idea because, at least for some law and economics scholars, it should serve as the principle according to which all norms and decisions should be shaped, interpreted, and received
    • Wealth maximization or efficiency can be seen as such a principle or idea because, at least for some law and economics scholars, it should serve as the principle according to which all norms and decisions should be shaped, interpreted, and received.
  • 299
    • 79959521586 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Posner, supra note 153
    • Posner, supra note 153;
  • 300
    • 79959387919 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Commensurability and agency: Two yet-to-be-met challenges for law and economics
    • see also, defending a more eclectic law and economics perspective
    • see also Alon Harel & Ariel Porat, Commensurability and Agency: Two Yet-to-Be-Met Challenges for Law and Economics, 96 CORNELL L. REV. 749 (2011) (defending a more eclectic law and economics perspective).
    • (2011) Cornell L. Rev. , vol.96 , pp. 749
    • Harel, A.1    Porat, A.2
  • 301
    • 79959521346 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is the case of the rise of "dignity" as a foundational value or right in various jurisdictions throughout the world. In South Africa, Germany, Israel, Canada, and the United States, as well as in numerous international documents, dignity has become, over the past twenty years, an explicitly enshrined or implicit fundamental value or right Submitting the entire legal system to one core value or right-even if understood as serving functional goals and as rational procedure-is a highly reenchanting maneuver since it gives the legal system coherence, unity, and moral legitimation. On the rise of dignity
    • This is the case of the rise of "dignity" as a foundational value or right in various jurisdictions throughout the world. In South Africa, Germany, Israel, Canada, and the United States, as well as in numerous international documents, dignity has become, over the past twenty years, an explicitly enshrined or implicit fundamental value or right Submitting the entire legal system to one core value or right-even if understood as serving functional goals and as rational procedure-is a highly reenchanting maneuver since it gives the legal system coherence, unity, and moral legitimation. On the rise of dignity
  • 304
    • 79959511648 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Indeed, even those who see law as an effective expression or vehicle for the achievement of "ideology", be it socialist, Marxist, free marketer, feminist, or nationalist, in fact reenchant law to a certain degree. For example, some feminist legal scholarship, highly committed to structuralist conceptions regarding the relationship between men and women what Halley calls the "men over women" conception, belongs to this type of legal reenchantment
    • Indeed, even those who see law as an effective expression or vehicle for the achievement of "ideology", be it socialist, Marxist, free marketer, feminist, or nationalist, in fact reenchant law to a certain degree. For example, some feminist legal scholarship, highly committed to structuralist conceptions regarding the relationship between men and women (what Halley calls the "men over women" conception), belongs to this type of legal reenchantment.
  • 305
    • 79959506521 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, HAMEY, supra note 60
    • See HAMEY, supra note 60.
  • 306
    • 79959514796 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • When I talk about "ideality" I do not mean "normativity. " Although normative endeavors might often include what I call "marginal" or "supplementary" reenchantment, ideality refers to an antirealist and antifunctionalist view of the law
    • When I talk about "ideality" I do not mean "normativity. " Although normative endeavors might often include what I call "marginal" or "supplementary" reenchantment, ideality refers to an antirealist and antifunctionalist view of the law.
  • 307
    • 79959492241 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See discussion infra Part III. B
    • See discussion infra Part III. B.
  • 308
    • 79959517097 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • In April 2010, the conference "'Law As... ': Theory and Method in Legal History" was held at the University of California, Irvine Law School. The public invitation to the conference reads as follows: The "law and" problematic has been highly productive. The question nevertheless arises whether we have arrived at an intellectual moment in which, a century after its invention, "law and" has run its course. If so, what might be the implications for legal history? "Law and" relies on empirical context to situate law as a determinate domain of activity. The result is a causally functional and empirical account of law.... Suppose we dispense with the conjunctive metaphors of "law and", and instead reach for different metaphors. What might they be? One possibility is optical metaphors-that is, metaphors of appearance, or image, or resemblance. Instead of parsing relations between distinct domains of activity, between law and what lies "outside" it, the objective of legal historical research might be to imagine them as the same domain: what do we get if we imagine law and economy as the same phenomenon-that is, law as economy (or economy as law)? What of law as art, as science, as war, as peace? What new method or theory might be the result?
  • 309
    • 79959525471 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Law as... "at UC Irvine
    • Feb. 3, 2010, 2:23 AM, hereinafter UC Irvine Invitation
    • Dan Ernst, "Law As... "at UC Irvine, LEGAL HIST. BLOG (Feb. 3, 2010, 2:23 AM) http://legalhistoryblog.blogspot.com/2010/02/law-as-at-uc-irvine. html [hereinafter UC Irvine Invitation].
    • Legal Hist. Blog
    • Ernst, D.1
  • 310
    • 79959495298 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Indeed, "law as culture" often entails some antirealist impetus. This is the case because cultural analysis of law often involves hermeneutic arguments about meaning and signification rather than empirical, consequentialist, or instrumentalist assertions. As Robert Cover asserts, "the capacity of law to imbue action with significance is not limited to resistance or disobedience. Law is a resource in signification that enables us to submit, rejoice, struggle, pervert, mock, disgrace, humiliate or dignify."
    • Indeed, "law as culture" often entails some antirealist impetus. This is the case because cultural analysis of law often involves hermeneutic arguments about meaning and signification rather than empirical, consequentialist, or instrumentalist assertions. As Robert Cover asserts, "the capacity of law to imbue action with significance is not limited to resistance or disobedience. Law is a resource in signification that enables us to submit, rejoice, struggle, pervert, mock, disgrace, humiliate or dignify."
  • 311
    • 0003323192 scopus 로고
    • Foreword: Nomos and narrative
    • See, 8, Likewise, "law as art" might be a critical and disenchanting project focused on the power dimension in law-if we see art as a locus of power struggles as in a Nietzschean "will to power", contestation, and politics
    • See Robert M. Cover, Foreword: Nomos and Narrative, 97 HARV. L. REV. 4, 8 (1983). Likewise, "law as art" might be a critical and disenchanting project focused on the power dimension in law-if we see art as a locus of power struggles (as in a Nietzschean "will to power"), contestation, and politics.
    • (1983) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.97 , pp. 4
    • Cover, R.M.1
  • 312
    • 79959534021 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See UC Irvine Invitation, supra note 172
    • See UC Irvine Invitation, supra note 172.
  • 313
    • 79959531944 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This ideal world of Kant and Hegel is the object of Marx's critique
    • This ideal world (of Kant and Hegel) is the object of Marx's critique.
  • 314
    • 0002342717 scopus 로고
    • See, CJ. Arthur ed.
    • See Karl Marx & Frederick Engels, THE GERMAN IDEOLOGY 39-41, 68-72 (CJ. Arthur ed., 1970).
    • (1970) The German Ideology , vol.39-41 , pp. 68-72
    • Marx, K.1    Engels, F.2
  • 315
    • 79959526133 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As Lavi argues, the ontological investigation aims at discovering what the law really is and not what we can know about it from one perspective or another
    • As Lavi argues, the ontological investigation aims at discovering what the law really is and not what we can know about it from one perspective or another.
  • 316
    • 79959504967 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Lavi, supra note 123
    • Lavi, supra note 123.
  • 317
    • 79959521585 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Cover, supra note 173, at 8
    • See Cover, supra note 173, at 8.
  • 319
    • 79959532921 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Indeed, while the legal realists were predominantly progressive, their contemporary progenies and legal instrumentalists are not The realist cry that law should reflect current social reality was the basis for politically progressive reforms a hundred years ago, but it is no longer the case now
    • Indeed, while the legal realists were predominantly progressive, their contemporary progenies and legal instrumentalists are not The realist cry that law should reflect current social reality was the basis for politically progressive reforms a hundred years ago, but it is no longer the case now.
  • 320
    • 84935146771 scopus 로고
    • Roll over beethoven
    • See, discussing the irrationalist position within critical legal studies
    • See Peter Gabel & Duncan Kennedy, Roll over Beethoven, 36 STAN. L. REV. 1 (1984) (discussing the irrationalist position within critical legal studies).
    • (1984) Stan. L. Rev. , vol.36 , pp. 1
    • Gabel, P.1    Kennedy, D.2
  • 321
    • 79959516860 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 29
    • -2 WEBER, supra note 29, at 875.
    • Weber , vol.2 , pp. 875
  • 322
    • 79959505886 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra text accompanying note 38
    • See supra text accompanying note 38.
  • 323
    • 79959499702 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, supra note 29, 1031-32
    • See 2 WEBER, supra note 29, at 874-75, 1031-32.
    • Weber , vol.2 , pp. 874-875
  • 324
    • 79959505428 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 889
    • Id. at 889.
  • 325
    • 79959527674 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Kennedy, supra note 7, at 1030-52
    • See Kennedy, supra note 7, at 1030-52.
  • 326
    • 79959492697 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I am aware of the great difference that can be made between Nietzschean and Heideggerian hope. For Heideggerian reenchanters, there is an obvious mourning for a lost world, and we must try to find our way back into it; Nietzschean reenchantment, however, basically-and perhaps desperately-calls upon us to reenchant the world not by finding our way back to the lost world, but by creating a new world through our will and joy. I thank Pierre Schlag for this point
    • I am aware of the great difference that can be made between Nietzschean and Heideggerian hope. For Heideggerian reenchanters, there is an obvious mourning for a lost world, and we must try to find our way back into it; Nietzschean reenchantment, however, basically-and perhaps desperately-calls upon us to reenchant the world not by finding our way back to the lost world, but by creating a new world through our will and joy. I thank Pierre Schlag for this point.
  • 327
    • 79959502039 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Kennedy, supra note 7, at 875
    • See Kennedy, supra note 7, at 875.
  • 328
    • 79959496454 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 26
    • WEBER, ESSAYS, supra note 26, at 155.
    • Essays , pp. 155
    • Weber1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.