메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 96, Issue 4, 2011, Pages 749-787

Commensurability and agency: Two yet-to-be-met challenges for law and economics

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 79959387919     PISSN: 00108847     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: None     Document Type: Conference Paper
Times cited : (21)

References (271)
  • 1
    • 79959453004 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • We are aware of the distinction between commensurability and comparability. In this Essay, however, the inability to compare certain values inevitably questions their commensurability. On the distinction between the two
    • We are aware of the distinction between commensurability and comparability. In this Essay, however, the inability to compare certain values inevitably questions their commensurability. On the distinction between the two
  • 4
    • 0040582867 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Flawed Foundations: The Philosophical Critique of (a Particular Type of) Economics
    • See Martha C. Nussbaum, Flawed Foundations: The Philosophical Critique of (a Particular Type of) Economics, 64 U. CHI. L. REV. 1197, 1199 (1997) (arguing that "[a] commitment to the commensurability of all an agent's ends runs very deep in the Law and Economics movement" but that it fails to describe the real world); (Pubitemid 127445778)
    • (1997) University of Chicago Law Review , vol.64 , Issue.4 , pp. 1197
    • Nussbaum, M.C.1
  • 5
    • 0004113926 scopus 로고
    • see also, arguing for a pluralist approach to the valuation of goods, based on the idea that goods differ in kind or quality from one another and cannot always be measured by a common criterion
    • see also ELIZABETH ANDERSON, VALUE IN ETHICS AND ECONOMICS 1-16 (1993) (arguing for a pluralist approach to the valuation of goods, based on the idea that goods differ in kind or quality from one another and cannot always be measured by a common criterion);
    • (1993) Value in Ethics and Economics , pp. 1-16
    • Anderson, E.1
  • 6
    • 0011537864 scopus 로고
    • Plural utility
    • 193-210, arguing that welfare economics should understand utility "primarily as a vector with several distinct components, and only secondarily as some homogeneous magnitude"
    • Amartya Sen, Plural Utility, 81 PROC. ARISTOTELIAN SOC'Y 193, 193-210 (1981) (arguing that welfare economics should understand utility "primarily as a vector (with several distinct components), and only secondarily as some homogeneous magnitude").
    • (1981) Proc. Aristotelian Soc'y , vol.81 , pp. 193
    • Sen, A.1
  • 7
    • 77951810660 scopus 로고
    • See United States v. Carroll Towing Co., 173, 2d Cir
    • See United States v. Carroll Towing Co., 159 F.2d 169, 173 (2d Cir. 1947).
    • (1947) F.2d , vol.159 , pp. 169
  • 8
    • 0003732343 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, defining the efficient level of care as an equality between the marginal social cost and the marginal social benefit
    • See ROBERT COOTER & THOMAS ULEN, LAW AND ECONOMICS 350-51 (2008) (defining the efficient level of care as an equality between the marginal social cost and the marginal social benefit);
    • (2008) Law and Economics , pp. 350-351
    • Cooter, R.1    Ulen, T.2
  • 9
    • 79959430149 scopus 로고
    • 102, clarifying that the correct economic standard of care requires a consideration of marginal rather than total values of costs and benefits and concluding that courts also use marginal terms when applying the Hand formula
    • WILLIAM M. LANDES & RICHARD A. POSNER, THE ECONOMIC STRUCTURE OF TORT LAW 87, 99-100, 102 (1987) (clarifying that the correct economic standard of care requires a consideration of marginal rather than total values of costs and benefits and concluding that courts also use marginal terms when applying the Hand formula).
    • (1987) The Economic Structure of Tort Law , vol.87 , pp. 99-100
    • Landes, W.M.1    Posner, R.A.2
  • 10
    • 79959441059 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See COOTER & ULEN, supra note 4, at 326-28
    • See COOTER & ULEN, supra note 4, at 326-28.
  • 11
    • 79959465107 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. id. at 351 "Eventually a case will reach the adjudicators in which further precaution is not cost-justified."
    • Cf. id. at 351 ("Eventually a case will reach the adjudicators in which further precaution is not cost-justified.").
  • 12
    • 0038351724 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Thinking the unthinkable: Sacred values and taboo cognitions
    • See, 320-23, describing lay people's emotional reactions to trade-offs made between sacred values, such as life and limb, and money
    • See Philip E. Tedock, Thinking the Unthinkable: Sacred Values and Taboo Cognitions, 7 TRENDS COGNITIVE SCI. 320, 320-23 (2003) (describing lay people's emotional reactions to trade-offs made between sacred values, such as life and limb, and money).
    • (2003) Trends Cognitive Sci , vol.7 , pp. 320
    • Tedock, P.E.1
  • 13
    • 62749087737 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hand rule damages for incompensable losses
    • See, e.g., 1098, "In general, the need to buy costly precaution in daily life forces people to trade off money and risk."
    • See, e.g., Robert Cooter, Hand Rule Damages for Incompensable Losses, 40 SAN DIEGO L. REV. 1097, 1098 (2003) ("In general, the need to buy costly precaution in daily life forces people to trade off money and risk.").
    • (2003) San Diego L. Rev. , vol.40 , pp. 1097
    • Cooter, R.1
  • 14
    • 0003666422 scopus 로고
    • But see, indicating that virtually all societies refrain in some cases from explicidy balancing the monetary value of lives against monetary costs
    • But see GUIDO CALABRESI, THE COSTS OF ACCIDENTS 18-19 (1970) (indicating that virtually all societies refrain in some cases from explicidy balancing the monetary value of lives against monetary costs).
    • (1970) The Costs of Accidents , pp. 18-19
    • Calabresi, G.1
  • 15
    • 0002993989 scopus 로고
    • The decision for accidents: An approach to nonfault allocation of costs
    • See, 716, comparing society's willingness to spend much more than what a person's life is conceivably worth to save an identified individual from certain death with its refusal to bear the same costs where death is almost statistically certain, but the individual in question is unknown
    • See Guido Calabresi, The Decision For Accidents: An Approach to Nonfault Allocation of Costs, 78 HARV. L. REV. 713, 716 (1965) (comparing society's willingness to spend much more than what a person's life is conceivably worth to save an identified individual from certain death with its refusal to bear the same costs where death is almost statistically certain, but the individual in question is unknown).
    • (1965) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.78 , pp. 713
    • Calabresi, G.1
  • 16
    • 79959473520 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • We should distinguish that latter scenario from a risk to statistical life: a small risk to many individuals that will almost certainly cause the deaths of some of them in the long run
    • We should distinguish that latter scenario from a risk to statistical life: a small risk to many individuals that will almost certainly cause the deaths of some of them in the long run.
  • 17
    • 0038171291 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Risk, death and harm: The normative foundations of risk regulation
    • See generally, discussing various theories for assessing risks to life and statistical life. Sometimes public sentiment avoids creating very high risk to statistical life with almost the same intensity as creating a very high risk to a specific person's life
    • See generally Matthew D. Adler, Risk, Death and Harm: The Normative Foundations of Risk Regulation, 87 MINN. L. REV. 1293 (2003) (discussing various theories for assessing risks to life and statistical life). Sometimes public sentiment avoids creating very high risk to statistical life with almost the same intensity as creating a very high risk to a specific person's life.
    • (2003) Minn. L. Rev. , vol.87 , pp. 1293
    • Adler, M.D.1
  • 18
    • 84862610394 scopus 로고
    • A typical case that illustrates this latter point is Grimshaw v. Ford Motor Co., Ct. App, known as the "Ford Pinto case", where the court upheld large punitive damages against Ford Motor Company in part because "unlike malicious conduct directed toward a single specific individual, Ford's tortious conduct in failing to make inexpensive corrections to the Pinto design endangered the lives of thousands of Pinto purchasers."
    • A typical case that illustrates this latter point is Grimshaw v. Ford Motor Co., 174 Cal. Rptr. 348 (Ct. App. 1981), known as the "Ford Pinto case", where the court upheld large punitive damages against Ford Motor Company in part because "[u]nlike malicious conduct directed toward a single specific individual, Ford's tortious conduct [in failing to make inexpensive corrections to the Pinto design] endangered the lives of thousands of Pinto purchasers."
    • (1981) Cal. Rptr. , vol.174 , pp. 348
  • 19
    • 79959487214 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • at, Even though design alterations would result in 180 fewer deaths per year, Ford thought it would not be cost-justified because the new design would have cost an additional $11 per car
    • Grimshaw, 74 Cal. Rptr. at 388. Even though design alterations would result in 180 fewer deaths per year, Ford thought it would not be cost-justified because the new design would have cost an additional $11 per car.
    • Cal. Rptr. , vol.74 , pp. 388
    • Grimshaw1
  • 20
    • 0005226850 scopus 로고
    • The myth of the ford pinto case
    • See, 1020
    • See Gary T. Schwartz, The Myth of the Ford Pinto Case, 43 RUTGERS L. REV. 1013, 1020 (1991).
    • (1991) Rutgers L. Rev. , vol.43 , pp. 1013
    • Schwartz, G.T.1
  • 21
    • 27844566229 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf, discussing lethal dosing - a practice doctors ostensibly use to help relieve patients' pain and that also hastens death - and indicating that doctors were very rarely prosecuted for using those practices
    • Cf. SHAI J. LAVI, THE MODERN ART OF DYING: A HISTORY OF EUTHANASIA IN THE UNITED STATES 134-37 (2005) (discussing lethal dosing - a practice doctors ostensibly use to help relieve patients' pain and that also hastens death - and indicating that doctors were very rarely prosecuted for using those practices).
    • (2005) The Modern Art of Dying: A History of Euthanasia in the United States , pp. 134-137
    • Lavi, S.J.1
  • 22
    • 79959444629 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • With very high risk to property, courts tend to impose liability on the injurer regardless of whether his behavior was reasonable or not
    • With very high risk to property, courts tend to impose liability on the injurer regardless of whether his behavior was reasonable or not
  • 23
    • 33846809763 scopus 로고
    • See Vincent v. Lake Erie Transp. Co., 221-22, Minn, imposing liability on a shipowner for failing to untie his ship from the dock during a storm in order to save the ship, thereby inflicting harm on the dock
    • See Vincent v. Lake Erie Transp. Co., 124 N. W. 221, 221-22 (Minn. 1910) (imposing liability on a shipowner for failing to untie his ship from the dock during a storm in order to save the ship, thereby inflicting harm on the dock);
    • (1910) N.W. , vol.124 , pp. 221
  • 24
    • 0011538305 scopus 로고
    • A theory of strict liability
    • 168-69, demonstrating the prevalence of strict liability in those tort cases characterized as A hit B
    • Richard A. Epstein, A Theory of Strict Liability, 2 J. LEGAL STUD. 151, 168-69 (1973) (demonstrating the prevalence of strict liability in those tort cases characterized as A hit B).
    • (1973) J. Legal Stud. , vol.2 , pp. 151
    • Epstein, R.A.1
  • 25
    • 79959487949 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • There are some exceptional cases, where the risk to the patient was very high and the court was willing, in principle, to make some cost-benefit analysis
    • There are some exceptional cases, where the risk to the patient was very high and the court was willing, in principle, to make some cost-benefit analysis.
  • 26
    • 79959406030 scopus 로고
    • In Canada, in Law Estate v. Simice, Can. B. C., the Supreme Court of British Columbia found a physician negligent for denying a potentially life-saving CT scan to a patient for financial reasons. The court reasoned that "the severity of the harm mat may occur to the patient who is permitted to go undiagnosed is far greater than the financial harm that will occur to the medicare system if one more CT scan procedure only shows the patient is not suffering from a serious medical condition".
    • In Canada, in Law Estate v. Simice (1994), 21 C. C. L. T. 2d 228 (Can. B. C.), the Supreme Court of British Columbia found a physician negligent for denying a potentially life-saving CT scan to a patient for financial reasons. The court reasoned that "[t]he severity of the harm mat may occur to the patient who is permitted to go undiagnosed is far greater than the financial harm that will occur to the medicare system if one more CT scan procedure only shows the patient is not suffering from a serious medical condition".
    • (1994) C. C. L. T. 2d , vol.21 , pp. 228
  • 27
    • 79959458511 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • at para, For a similar approach in the English context
    • Simice, 21 C. C. L. T. 2d at para. 28. For a similar approach in the English context
    • C. C. L. T. 2d , vol.21 , pp. 28
    • Simice1
  • 28
    • 79959469774 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see Bali v. Wirral Health Authority, Eng.. There, the court dismissed a negligence suit against a hospital for lacking the adequate facilities to care for premature babies, which allegedly resulted in the plaintiffs brain damage. The court held: "In the field of medicine where resources are limited and the demands on those resources are many, it may be necessary to make difficult decisions as to how resources are to be allocated.... The fact that an area of medicine may be under-funded... or that a particular hospital may not have the facilities that another hospital has, may give rise to a concern among the general public and experts in the field
    • see Bali v. Wirral Health Authority, (2003) 73 B. M. L. R. 31 (Eng.). There, the court dismissed a negligence suit against a hospital for lacking the adequate facilities to care for premature babies, which allegedly resulted in the plaintiffs brain damage. The court held: "In the field of medicine where resources are limited and the demands on those resources are many, it may be necessary to make difficult decisions as to how resources are to be allocated.... The fact that an area of medicine may be under-funded... or that a particular hospital may not have the facilities that another hospital has, may give rise to a concern among the general public and experts in the field;
    • (2003) B. M. L. R. , vol.73 , pp. 31
  • 29
    • 79959460973 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • but it does not necessarily provide the basis of a claim in negligence by a patient who may suffer from the effects of the under-funding or the lack of facilities."
    • but it does not necessarily provide the basis of a claim in negligence by a patient who may suffer from the effects of the under-funding or the lack of facilities."
  • 30
    • 79959386856 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • at para, For another argument along these lines
    • Ball, 73 B. M. L. R. at para. 32. For another argument along these lines
    • B. M. L. R. , vol.73 , pp. 32
    • Ball1
  • 31
    • 79959479910 scopus 로고
    • see also, arguing that "the fact that social costs exceed expected benefits should be recognized as a defense against failure to take costly precautionary measures"
    • see also PATRICIA M. DANZON, MEDICAL MALPRACTICE: THEORY, EVIDENCE, AND PUBLIC POLICY 143 (1985) (arguing that "the fact that social costs exceed expected benefits should be recognized as a defense against failure to take costly precautionary measures").
    • (1985) Danzon, Medical Malpractice: Theory, Evidence, and Public Policy , pp. 143
    • Patricia, M.1
  • 32
    • 79959445226 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is not a puzzle for corrective justice theorists who argue that negligence should be determined by the risks rather than by the precautions that, if taken, would have mitigated them
    • This is not a puzzle for corrective justice theorists who argue that negligence should be determined by the risks rather than by the precautions that, if taken, would have mitigated them.
  • 33
    • 4143106582 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Correlativity, personality, and the emerging consensus on corrective justice
    • See, 116-17, 130-31
    • See Ernest J. Weinrib, Correlativity, Personality, and the Emerging Consensus on Corrective Justice, 2 THEORETICAL INQUIRIES L. 107, 116-17, 130-31 (2001).
    • (2001) Theoretical Inquiries L. , vol.2 , pp. 107
    • Weinrib, E.J.1
  • 34
    • 79959453003 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • WTP will be limited to the individual's wealth
    • WTP will be limited to the individual's wealth.
  • 35
    • 20444469722 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dollars and death
    • See, e.g., 589, noting income constraints applicable to WTP and that, as the probability of risk nears 100%, WTP approaches 100% of income
    • See, e.g., Eric A. Posner & Cass R. Sunstein, Dollars and Death, 72 U. CHI. L. REV. 537, 589 & n. 159 (2005) (noting income constraints applicable to WTP and that, as the probability of risk nears 100%, WTP approaches 100% of income).
    • (2005) U. Chi. L. Rev. , vol.72 , Issue.159 , pp. 537
    • Posner, E.A.1    Sunstein, C.R.2
  • 36
    • 79959409730 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Notice that this conclusion seems to hold even if the victim is unidentified; as long as the victim herself knows about the risk of certain death that she is subject to, her WTA will be infinite and her WTP will be equal to her entire wealth
    • Notice that this conclusion seems to hold even if the victim is unidentified; as long as the victim herself knows about the risk of certain death that she is subject to, her WTA will be infinite and her WTP will be equal to her entire wealth.
  • 37
    • 19744376398 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Against "individual risk": A sympathetic critique of risk assessment
    • Cf, 1198, noting that WTP "to avoid certain death" will correspond to individual wealth, while WTA certain death "may well be infinite"
    • Cf. Matthew D. Adler, Against "Individual Risk": A Sympathetic Critique of Risk Assessment, 153 U. PA. L. REV. 1121, 1198 (2005) (noting that WTP "to avoid certain death" will correspond to individual wealth, while WTA certain death "may well be infinite");
    • (2005) U. Pa. L. Rev. , vol.153 , pp. 1121
    • Adler, M.D.1
  • 38
    • 79959398378 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Adler, supra note 10, at 1400 arguing that values of statistical life calculations "produce a dollar sum very different from the sum of willingness to pay/accept among those actually aware of, or afraid of, the hazard"
    • Adler, supra note 10, at 1400 (arguing that values of statistical life calculations "produce [] a dollar sum very different from the sum of willingness to pay/accept among those actually aware of, or afraid of, the hazard").
  • 39
    • 79959482331 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Posner & Sunstein, supra note 13, at 589 discussing nonlinear increases in WTP and WTA as risk probability approaches 100%
    • Cf. Posner & Sunstein, supra note 13, at 589 (discussing nonlinear increases in WTP and WTA as risk probability approaches 100%).
  • 40
    • 79959425084 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Although some would argue that this is not absurd, even they would agree that there exists a number above which trading would not make sense.
  • 41
    • 79959482909 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See ZAMIR & MEDINA, supra note 1, at 90-91, 95-96, for the argument that deontological constraints would sometimes require ascribing a higher social cost to high risks to life and limb than to low risks, more so than what the proportion between the high and low risks requires. Those authors admit, however, that at a certain point the low risks could be considered more socially costly than high risks
    • See ZAMIR & MEDINA, supra note 1, at 90-91, 95-96, for the argument that deontological constraints would sometimes require ascribing a higher social cost to high risks to life and limb than to low risks, more so than what the proportion between the high and low risks requires. Those authors admit, however, that at a certain point the low risks could be considered more socially costly than high risks.
  • 42
    • 79959478825 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 90-91, 95-96 & n. 37. Note that the authors discuss situations of deliberate killing, which could differ in many respects from the cases that we discuss in this Essay
    • Id. at 90-91, 95-96 & n. 37. Note that the authors discuss situations of deliberate killing, which could differ in many respects from the cases that we discuss in this Essay.
  • 43
    • 0001185075 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Willingness to pay and the distribution of risk and wealth
    • See, 748, 752-55
    • See John W. Pratt & Richard J. Zeckhauser, Willingness to Pay and the Distribution of Risk and Wealth, 104 J. POL. ECON. 747, 748 n. 2, 752-55 (1996).
    • (1996) J. Pol. Econ. , vol.104 , Issue.2 , pp. 747
    • Pratt, J.W.1    Zeckhauser, R.J.2
  • 44
    • 79959457360 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ariel Porat and Avraham Tabbach recently argued that a correct understanding of WTP and WTA would yield that only the magnitude of the risk reduced or increased should count for social welfare, not the pre-existing risk or the magnitude of the risk after it was reduced or increased
    • Ariel Porat and Avraham Tabbach recently argued that a correct understanding of WTP (and WTA) would yield that only the magnitude of the risk reduced (or increased) should count for social welfare, not the pre-existing risk or the magnitude of the risk after it was reduced (or increased).
  • 45
    • 79959429584 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Willingness to pay, death, wealth and damages
    • See, forthcoming, manuscript at, 20-25 on file with authors. It follows from their argument that, from a social perspective, it is better to eliminate a risk of 25% for ten individuals or, even for five individuals than a 100% risk for one individual, assuming the individuals are not identified in advance
    • See Ariel Porat & Avraham Tabbach, Willingness to Pay, Death, Wealth and Damages, 13 AM. L. & ECON. REV. (forthcoming 2011) (manuscript at 9-10, 20-25) (on file with authors). It follows from their argument that, from a social perspective, it is better to eliminate a risk of 25% for ten individuals (or, even for five individuals) than a 100% risk for one individual, assuming the individuals are not identified in advance.
    • (2011) Am. L. & Econ. Rev. , vol.13 , pp. 9-10
    • Porat, A.1    Tabbach, A.2
  • 46
    • 79959422934 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. For an earlier exposition of the discounting effect on WTP
    • See id. For an earlier exposition of the discounting effect on WTP
  • 47
    • 79959441616 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see Pratt & Zeckhauser, supra note 17. The analysis could change if victims are identified because not saving an identified person who is under risk of certain death typically creates other social costs that are not present to the same extent when risks are lower
    • see Pratt & Zeckhauser, supra note 17. The analysis could change if victims are identified because not saving an identified person who is under risk of certain death typically creates other social costs that are not present to the same extent when risks are lower.
  • 48
    • 79959401810 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 747-48
    • Id. at 747-48.
  • 49
    • 79959465554 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Porat & Tabbach, supra note 18, at 23 n. 26
    • See Porat & Tabbach, supra note 18, at 23 n. 26.
  • 50
    • 0039349225 scopus 로고
    • Efficiency, utility, and wealth maximization
    • Cf, 11, mentioning the interpersonal utility comparison problem as one basis for criticizing utilitarianism
    • Cf. Jules L. Coleman, Efficiency, Utility, and Wealth Maximization, 8 HOFSTRA L. REV. 509, 11 1980) mentioning the interpersonal utility comparison problem as one basis for criticizing utilitarianism).
    • (1980) Hofstra L. Rev. , vol.8 , pp. 509
    • Coleman, J.L.1
  • 52
    • 79959398376 scopus 로고
    • Toward an economic theory of the measurement of damages in a wrongful death action
    • 299-300, "All states give great weight to the earning capacity of the decedent in calculating damages."
    • Lloyd Cohen, Toward an Economic Theory of the Measurement of Damages in a Wrongful Death Action, 34 EMORY LJ. 295, 299-300 (1985) ("All states give great weight to the earning capacity of the decedent in calculating damages.").
    • (1985) Emory Lj , vol.34 , pp. 295
    • Cohen, L.1
  • 53
    • 0346964104 scopus 로고
    • Note, hedonic damages for wrongful death: Are tortfeasors getting away with murder?
    • See, 1695, criticizing the human capital approach, which measures the value of an individual's life based on lost future income discounted to present value but agreeing that "an individual's future income may be a proxy for the value that society placed upon that individual's productive capacity". For more criticism on the human capital approach
    • See Erin A. O'Hara, Note, Hedonic Damages for Wrongful Death: Are Tortfeasors Getting Away with Murder? 78 GEO. LJ. 1687, 1695 (1990) (criticizing the human capital approach, which measures the value of an individual's life based on lost future income discounted to present value but agreeing that "an individual's future income may be a proxy for the value that society placed upon that individual's productive capacity"). For more criticism on the human capital approach
    • (1990) Geo. Lj , vol.78 , pp. 1687
    • O'Hara, E.A.1
  • 54
    • 0346334258 scopus 로고
    • It's a wonderful life: The case for hedonic damages in wrongful death cases
    • see, 100-02, arguing that the human capital approach "undervalues life as it disregards variables such as the pleasure of living" and fails to take into account the social and cultural contribution of artists and other influential figures who do not increase the gross national product
    • see Andrew Jay McClurg, It's a Wonderful Life: The Case for Hedonic Damages in Wrongful Death Cases, 66 NOTRE DAME L. REV. 57, 100-02 (1990) (arguing that the human capital approach "undervalues life [as it disregards] variables such as the pleasure of living" and fails to take into account the social and cultural contribution of artists and other influential figures who do not increase the gross national product).
    • (1990) Notre Dame L. Rev. , vol.66 , pp. 57
    • McClurg, A.J.1
  • 55
    • 79959473519 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a distributive justice approach on the matter
    • For a distributive justice approach on the matter
  • 56
    • 18844436669 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • An inquiry into the merits of redistribution through tort law: Rejecting the claim of randomness
    • see, 95, "Of course, the courts do not explicitly admit that the rich deserve greater protection, but perhaps they do not do so consciously. However, to the extent that courts intuitively follow the Learned Hand formula, a finding of negligence is more likely to be found where potential defendants are rich, given constant prevention costs. Moreover, if it could be proven, empirically, that courts do not apply the Hand formula in a way that affords better protection to the rich, this would be a deviation from the economic model of negligence, due to distributive considerations."
    • see Tsachi Keren-Paz, An Inquiry into the Merits of Redistribution Through Tort Law: Rejecting the Claim of Randomness, 16 CAN. J. L. & JURISPRUDENCE 91, 95 n. 20 (2003) ("Of course, the courts do not explicitly admit that the rich deserve greater protection, but perhaps they do not do so consciously. However, to the extent that courts intuitively follow the Learned Hand formula, a finding of negligence is more likely to be found where potential defendants are rich, given constant prevention costs. Moreover, if it could be proven, empirically, that courts do not apply the Hand formula in a way that affords better protection to the rich, this would be a deviation from the economic model of negligence, due to distributive considerations.").
    • (2003) Can. J. L. & Jurisprudence , vol.16 , Issue.20 , pp. 91
    • Keren-Paz, T.1
  • 57
    • 79959389463 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • reluctance to compare lives led some philosophers to even more radical conclusions. For instance, John Taurek argued that we ought not to prefer the lives of the many over the lives of the few because we ought not to aggregate the value of different lives
    • The reluctance to compare lives led some philosophers to even more radical conclusions. For instance, John Taurek argued that we ought not to prefer the lives of the many over the lives of the few because we ought not to aggregate the value of different lives.
  • 58
    • 0017502091 scopus 로고
    • Should the numbers count?
    • See, 293-94, 303-09, In 2006, the Federal Constitutional Court of Germany issued a similarly motivated judgment by voiding the German Aviation Security Act, which authorized the air force to shoot down a civil aircraft if " 'in the circumstances, it can be assumed' that the aircraft was to be used against human life."
    • See John M. Taurek, Should the Numbers Count?, 6 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 293, 293-94, 303-09 (1977). In 2006, the Federal Constitutional Court of Germany issued a similarly motivated judgment by voiding the German Aviation Security Act, which authorized the air force to shoot down a civil aircraft if " 'in the circumstances, it can be assumed' that the aircraft was to be used against human life."
    • (1977) Phil. & Pub. Aff , vol.6 , pp. 293
    • Taurek, J.M.1
  • 59
    • 79959469773 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Report on the bundesverfassungsgericht's (federal constitutional court) jurisprudence in 2005/2006
    • 186, The court ruled that killing innocent people in order to save others violates basic human rights to life and human dignity
    • Felix Müller & Tobias Richter, Report on the Bundesverfassungsgericht's (Federal Constitutional Court) Jurisprudence in 2005/2006, 9 GER. L. J. 161, 186 (2008). The court ruled that killing innocent people in order to save others violates basic human rights to life and human dignity.
    • (2008) Ger. L. J. , vol.9 , pp. 161
    • Müller, F.1    Richter, T.2
  • 60
    • 79959430997 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 185-92
    • See id. at 185-92;
  • 61
    • 84922944426 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Necessity knows no law": On extreme cases and un-codifiable necessities
    • see also, forthcoming manuscript at 1-5 on file with authors
    • see also Alon Harel & Assaf Sharon, "Necessity Knows No Law": On Extreme Cases and Un-Codifiable Necessities U. TORONTO L. J. (forthcoming) (manuscript at 1-5) (on file with authors).
    • U. Toronto L. J.
    • Harel, A.1    Sharon, A.2
  • 62
    • 79959414966 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Private law redistribution, predictability, and liberty
    • Cf, 336, contrasting the restitutio in integrum principle with a redistributive rule
    • Cf. Tsachi Keren-Paz, Private Law Redistribution, Predictability, and Liberty, 50 MCGILL LJ. 327, 336 (2005) (contrasting the restitutio in integrum principle with a redistributive rule).
    • (2005) Mcgill Lj , vol.50 , pp. 327
    • Keren-Paz, T.1
  • 63
    • 79959451884 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Imagine that courts apply a standard of care tailored to the average victim's income, regardless of the actual victim's characteristics. In the absence of any errors on the part of courts and injurers, the actual level of care that injurers take towards the highincome victims would be equal to the standard of care that courts apply (because injurers will meet the standard of care, be absolved of any liability, and therefore will not invest any more in care). Toward the low-income victims, injurers would take a lower level of care than the standard that courts would apply (because injurers will not invest in care beyond the point where the costs of precaution equal the marginal reduction in the expected harm and since they would reach that point before satisfying the standard of care). Although accounting for courts' and injurers' errors complicates the analysis, the gap between the levels of care that injurers take toward the high-income and the low-income victims still remains. For further analysis
  • 64
    • 79959474898 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Misalignments in tort law
    • see, forthcoming, manuscript at, on file with author
    • see Ariel Porat, Misalignments in Tort Law, 121 YALE LJ. (forthcoming 2011) (manuscript at Part II) (on file with author).
    • (2011) Yale Lj , vol.121 , Issue.2 PART
    • Porat, A.1
  • 65
    • 79959477720 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 23
    • See supra note 23.
  • 66
    • 79959406624 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Posner & Sunstein, supra note 13, at 594-95 arguing that the value of statistical lives, based on WTP, should be less for the poor than the rich but acknowledging the "intense controversy over valuing the lives of the rich more than the lives of the poor"
    • Cf. Posner & Sunstein, supra note 13, at 594-95 (arguing that the value of statistical lives, based on WTP, should be less for the poor than the rich but acknowledging the "intense controversy over valuing the lives of the rich more than the lives of the poor").
  • 67
    • 79959439961 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a more detailed explanation of why wealth should not be a factor in valuing people's lives
    • For a more detailed explanation of why wealth should not be a factor in valuing people's lives
  • 68
    • 79959387791 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see Porat & Tabbach, supra note 18, at 20-31
    • see Porat & Tabbach, supra note 18, at 20-31.
  • 69
    • 79959484569 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Or should employers be able to purchase the right to harass their employees by paying higher wages to those employees who agree to sell their right not to be harassed
    • Or should employers be able to purchase the right to harass their employees by paying higher wages to those employees who agree to sell their right not to be harassed?
  • 70
    • 79959425083 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra Part LA
    • See supra Part LA.
  • 71
    • 79959430999 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See DOBBS, supra note 21, at 1108 asserting that direct sexual harassment by an employer, as well as an employer's failure to deal with sexual harassment by coemployees, creates "a strong claim for tort liability based on intentional infliction of emotional distress or the like"
    • See DOBBS, supra note 21, at 1108 (asserting that direct sexual harassment by an employer, as well as an employer's failure to deal with sexual harassment by coemployees, creates "a strong claim for tort liability based on intentional infliction of emotional distress or the like").
  • 72
    • 79959470869 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A small number of states have criminalized sexual harassment
    • A small number of states have criminalized sexual harassment.
  • 73
    • 79959455447 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., tit, §, determining that a person is guilty of sexual harassment if he "threatens to engage in conduct likely to result in the commission of a sexual offense against any person" and defining sexual harassment as an "unclassified misdemeanor"
    • See, e.g., DEL. CODE ANN. tit. 11, § 763 (2007) (determining that a person is guilty of sexual harassment if he "threatens to engage in conduct likely to result in the commission of a sexual offense against any person" and defining sexual harassment as an "unclassified misdemeanor");
    • (2007) Del. Code Ann. , vol.11 , pp. 763
  • 74
    • 0041921455 scopus 로고
    • see also, §, West, imposing criminal liability on a public servant who "intentionally subjects another to sexual harassment" and defining sexual harassment as "unwelcome sexual advances, requests for sexual favors, or other verbal or physical conduct of a sexual nature". Certain forms of sexual harassment are recognized as a violation of Title VII of the Civil Rights Act of 1964, which forbids employers from discriminating against employees, inter alia, on the basis of sex
    • see also TEX. PENAL CODE ANN. § 39.03 (West 1974) (imposing criminal liability on a public servant who "intentionally subjects another to sexual harassment" and defining sexual harassment as "unwelcome sexual advances, requests for sexual favors, or other verbal or physical conduct of a sexual nature"). Certain forms of sexual harassment are recognized as a violation of Title VII of the Civil Rights Act of 1964, which forbids employers from discriminating against employees, inter alia, on the basis of sex.
    • (1974) Tex. Penal Code Ann. , vol.3903
  • 75
    • 33744755177 scopus 로고
    • See Meritor Sav. Bank v. Vinson, 65-66, ruling that sexual harassment leading to noneconomic injury can be classified as sex discrimination prohibited by Tide VII and that "a plaintiff may establish a violation of Title VII by proving that discrimination based on sex has created a hostile or abusive work environment"
    • See Meritor Sav. Bank v. Vinson, 477 U. S. 57, 65-66 (1986) (ruling that sexual harassment leading to noneconomic injury can be classified as sex discrimination prohibited by Tide VII and that "a plaintiff may establish a violation of Title VII by proving that discrimination based on sex has created a hostile or abusive work environment");
    • (1986) U. S. , vol.477 , pp. 57
  • 76
    • 84861495574 scopus 로고
    • see also Harris v. Forklift Sys., Inc., 21-22, emphasizing that sexual harassment on the basis of a hostile work environment is a violation of Title VII
    • see also Harris v. Forklift Sys., Inc., 510 U. S. 17, 21-22 (1993) (emphasizing that sexual harassment on the basis of a hostile work environment is a violation of Title VII).
    • (1993) U. S. , vol.510 , pp. 17
  • 77
    • 67649336604 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Antidiscrimination law
    • See, in, 1455, A. Mitchell Polinsky & Steven Shavell eds., noting the increase in sexual harassment claims brought by men
    • See John J. Donohue, Antidiscrimination Law, in 2 HANDBOOK OF LAW AND ECONOMICS 1387, 1455 (A. Mitchell Polinsky & Steven Shavell eds., 2007) (noting the increase in sexual harassment claims brought by men).
    • (2007) Handbook of Law and Economics , vol.2 , pp. 1387
    • Donohue, J.J.1
  • 78
    • 79959410277 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. "If hiring a woman has some chance of imposing an erroneous large monetary penalty plus the stigma of sex harassment liability, that prospect will serve as another burden associated with hiring American workers in general and women in particular."
    • See id. ("[I]f hiring a woman has some chance of imposing an erroneous large monetary penalty plus the stigma of sex harassment liability, that prospect will serve as another burden associated with hiring American workers in general and women in particular.");
  • 79
    • 1342342065 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Employment discrimination: Age discrimination and sexual harassment
    • 443, "A law forbidding sexual harassment may not on balance benefit the protected group. It may make employers more reluctant to hire women in jobs in which sexual harassment is likely...."
    • Richard A. Posner, Employment Discrimination: Age Discrimination and Sexual Harassment, 19 INT'L REV. L. & ECON. 421, 443 (1999) ("[A] law forbidding sexual harassment may not on balance benefit the protected group. It may make employers more reluctant to hire women in jobs in which sexual harassment is likely....");
    • (1999) Int'l Rev. L. & Econ , vol.19 , pp. 421
    • Posner, R.A.1
  • 80
    • 0002426678 scopus 로고
    • see also, Foreword to, at, x, "As sexual harassment litigation becomes more common, male managers may end up presupposing that every time they appoint a woman to a position that brings her into close personal contact, they hand her a loaded gun with which she can blow away their careers."
    • see also Alex Kozinski, Foreword to BARBARA LINDEMANN & DAVID D. KADUE, SEXUAL HARASSMENT IN EMPLOYMENT LAW, at v, x (1992) ("[A]s sexual harassment litigation becomes more common, male managers may end up presupposing that every time they appoint a woman to a position that brings her into close personal contact, they hand her a loaded gun with which she can blow away their careers.");
    • (1992) Sexual Harassment in Employment Law
    • Kozinski, A.1    Lindemann, B.2    Kadue, D.D.3
  • 81
    • 22844453843 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Letting the master answer employer liability for sexual harassment in the workplace after faragher and burlington industries
    • 1823, "Employers may prefer to hire those who are at less risk of harassment or who have a greater tolerance for it. The result may well be socially unacceptable employment segregation by sex - the very result that Title VII was meant to remedy."
    • Justin P. Smith, Letting the Master Answer Employer Liability For Sexual Harassment in the Workplace After Faragher and Burlington Industries, 74 N. Y. U. L. REV. 1786, 1823 (1999) ("[E]mployers may prefer to hire those who are at less risk of harassment or who have a greater tolerance for it. The result may well be socially unacceptable employment segregation by sex - the very result that Title VII was meant to remedy.");
    • (1999) N. Y. U. L. Rev. , vol.74 , pp. 1786
    • Smith, J.P.1
  • 82
    • 79959404522 scopus 로고
    • Biology and equality: Challenge for feminism in the socialist and the liberal state
    • 175, "As demonstrated by the history of American legislation on women and work, protective legislation may also diminish equality of opportunity for women. Indeed, the regulations do not sufficiently address the problems of discriminatory hiring and occupational segregation, and may actually aggravate these problems." footnote omitted
    • Margaret Y. K. Woo, Biology and Equality: Challenge for Feminism in the Socialist and the Liberal State, 42 EMORY L. J. 143, 175 (1993) ("[A]s demonstrated by the history of American legislation on women and work, protective legislation may also diminish equality of opportunity for women. Indeed, the regulations do not sufficiently address the problems of discriminatory hiring and occupational segregation, and may actually aggravate these problems." (footnote omitted)).
    • (1993) Emory L. J. , vol.42 , pp. 143
    • Woo, M.Y.K.1
  • 83
    • 44649085252 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Law, morality, and economics: Integrating moral constraints with economic analysis of law
    • Cf, 368, "The moral constraint against discrimination dictates that prohibiting discrimination can be justified even if the prohibition imposes a social cost that exceeds its benefit". For a more detailed discussion of discrimination and the conditions under which it could be justified
    • Cf. Eyal Zamir & Barak Medina, Law, Morality, and Economics: Integrating Moral Constraints with Economic Analysis of Law, 96 CALIF. L. REV. 323, 368 (2008) ("The moral constraint against discrimination dictates that prohibiting discrimination can be justified even if the prohibition imposes a social cost that exceeds its benefit"). For a more detailed discussion of discrimination and the conditions under which it could be justified
    • (2008) Calif. L. Rev. , vol.96 , pp. 323
    • Zamir, E.1    Medina, B.2
  • 84
    • 79959385775 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see ZAMIR & MEDINA, supra note 1, at 225-56
    • see ZAMIR & MEDINA, supra note 1, at 225-56.
  • 85
    • 79959445224 scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Byrd v. Richardson-Greenshields Sec., Inc., 2d, 1104, Fla, "While workplace injuries rob a person of resources, sexual harassment robs the person of dignity and self esteem. Workers' compensation addresses purely economic injury
    • See, e.g., Byrd v. Richardson-Greenshields Sec., Inc., 552 So. 2d 1099, 1104 (Fla. 1989) ("While workplace injuries rob a person of resources, sexual harassment robs the person of dignity and self esteem. Workers' compensation addresses purely economic injury;
    • (1989) So , vol.552 , pp. 1099
  • 86
    • 79959414967 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • sexual harassment laws are concerned with a much more intangible injury to personal rights."
    • sexual harassment laws are concerned with a much more intangible injury to personal rights.");
  • 87
    • 79959383391 scopus 로고
    • *1 Cal. Super. Ct. Nov. 28, "Sexual harassment strips the victim of dignity and self-respect. Such harassment is degrading and dehumanizing. It cannot be tolerated, and the law does not do so.", 1994
    • *1 (Cal. Super. Ct. Nov. 28, 1994) ("Sexual harassment strips the victim of dignity and self-respect. Such harassment is degrading and dehumanizing. It cannot be tolerated, and the law does not do so.").
    • (1994) WL 774633
  • 88
    • 79959472371 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Libertarian panics
    • Cf, 885, relating the conflict between security and liberty and stressing that "the problem from the social point of view is one of optimization: it is to choose the point along the frontier that maximizes the joint benefits of security and liberty. Neither security nor liberty is lexically prior; no claims of the type 'liberty is priceless' or 'security at all costs' will be admitted."
    • Cf Adrian Vermeule, Libertarian Panics, 36 RUTGERS LJ. 871, 885 (2005) (relating the conflict between security and liberty and stressing that "[t]he problem from the social point of view is one of optimization: it is to choose the point along the frontier that maximizes the joint benefits of security and liberty... Neither security nor liberty is lexically prior; no claims of the type 'liberty is priceless' or 'security at all costs' will be admitted.");
    • (2005) Rutgers Lj , vol.36 , pp. 871
    • Vermeule, A.1
  • 89
    • 43149097056 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Fairness, respect, and the egalitarian ethos
    • 120-22, arguing from an egalitarian perspective that when tension is created between two equally important values, society should generate a "dynamic balance" between them and refrain from treating either one with lexical priority
    • Jonathan Wolff, Fairness, Respect, and the Egalitarian Ethos, 27 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 97, 120-22 (1998) (arguing from an egalitarian perspective that when tension is created between two equally important values, society should generate a "dynamic balance" between them and refrain from treating either one with lexical priority).
    • (1998) Phil. & Pub. Aff , vol.27 , pp. 97
    • Wolff, J.1
  • 90
    • 69249142029 scopus 로고
    • An economic analysis of sex discrimination laws
    • Cf, 1335, "It is possible that the economic costs of sex discrimination law are offset by gains not measured in an economic analysis - gains in self-esteem, for example."
    • Cf. Richard A. Posner, An Economic Analysis of Sex Discrimination Laws, 56 U. CHI. L. REV. 1311, 1335 (1989) ("It is possible that the economic costs of sex discrimination law are offset by gains not measured in an economic analysis - gains in self-esteem, for example.").
    • (1989) U. Chi. L. Rev. , vol.56 , pp. 1311
    • Posner, R.A.1
  • 91
    • 79959480209 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • However, Judge Posner comments, "it is not clear that, if the canvass is broadened in this fashion, the picture brightens."
    • However, Judge Posner comments, "it is not clear that, if the canvass is broadened in this fashion, the picture brightens."
  • 92
    • 79959403958 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id.
  • 93
    • 0345783442 scopus 로고
    • Prohibiting sex discrimination in the workplace: An economic perspective
    • see also, 1349, "The societal pronouncement that women are equal to men, as well as legislated protections against harassment and other indignities, may elevate women's self-esteem and improve life on the job to such a degree that both the demand and the supply curves for female labor shift."
    • see also John J. Donohue III, Prohibiting Sex Discrimination in the Workplace: An Economic Perspective, 56 U. CHI. L. REV. 81337, 1349 (1989) ("[T]he societal pronouncement that women are equal to men, as well as legislated protections against harassment and other indignities, may elevate women's self-esteem and improve life on the job to such a degree that both the demand and the supply curves for female labor shift.").
    • (1989) U. Chi. L. Rev. , vol.56 , pp. 81337
    • Donohue III, J.J.1
  • 94
    • 79959463968 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Kozinski, supra note 35, at xi-xii discussing means other than litigation for combating sexual harassment, such as "moral suasion", employee training, and effective grievance procedures
    • See Kozinski, supra note 35, at xi-xii (discussing means other than litigation for combating sexual harassment, such as "moral suasion", employee training, and effective grievance procedures).
  • 95
    • 79959393732 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a deontological approach that strictly rejects torture regardless of the circumstances
    • For a deontological approach that strictly rejects torture regardless of the circumstances
  • 96
    • 0000976166 scopus 로고
    • War and massacre
    • see
    • see Thomas Nagel, War and Massacre, 1 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 123 (1972)
    • (1972) Phil. & Pub. Aff , vol.1 , pp. 123
    • Nagel, T.1
  • 97
    • 79959441617 scopus 로고
    • reprinted in, Marshall Cohen, Thomas Nagel & Thomas Scan-Ion eds., stating that "the most serious of the prohibited acts, like murder and torture... are supposed never to be done, because no quantity of resulting benefit is thought capable of justifying such treatment of a person"
    • reprinted in WAR AND MORAL RESPONSIBILITY 3, 22-23 (Marshall Cohen, Thomas Nagel & Thomas Scan-Ion eds., 1974) (stating that "the most serious of the prohibited acts, like murder and torture... are supposed never to be done, because no quantity of resulting benefit is thought capable of justifying such treatment of a person");
    • (1974) War and Moral Responsibility , vol.3 , pp. 22-23
  • 98
    • 27844544259 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Torture and positive law: Jurisprudence for the white house
    • 1726-39, arguing that the prohibition on torture functions as an "archetype" in the legal system, embodying a core principle of nonbrutality
    • Jeremy Waldron, Torture and Positive Law: Jurisprudence for the White House, 105 COLUM. L. REV. 1681, 1726-39 (2005) (arguing that the prohibition on torture functions as an "archetype" in the legal system, embodying a core principle of nonbrutality);
    • (2005) Colum. L. Rev. , vol.105 , pp. 1681
    • Waldron, J.1
  • 99
    • 1342310825 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The new imperialism: Violence, norms, and the "rule of law, "
    • see also, 2316-18, arguing that human rights law prohibits torture without exception because "it is trying to make a statement about the moral meaning of human action" and that "it is not in fact terribly interested in anyone's death or suffering" but is instead "mosdy. concerned with how we live our lives". A different deontological approach supports strict prohibition on torture, with an exception for "catastrophic harms" cases
    • see also Rosa Ehrenreich Brooks, The New Imperialism: Violence, Norms, and the "Rule of Law", 101 MICH. L. REV. 2275, 2316-18 (2003) (arguing that human rights law prohibits torture without exception because "[i]t is trying to make a statement about the moral meaning of human action" and that "[i]t is not in fact terribly interested in anyone's death or suffering" but is instead "[m]osdy... concerned with how we live our lives")). A different deontological approach supports strict prohibition on torture, with an exception for "catastrophic harms" cases.
    • (2003) Mich. L. Rev. , vol.101 , pp. 2275
    • Brooks, R.E.1
  • 100
    • 3042853801 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Are torture warrants warranted? Pragmatic absolutism and official disobedience
    • See, 1487, arguing that torture must be strictly prohibited but may also be morally defensible ex post in "truly exceptional cases" when public officials act extralegally in order to prevent catastrophic harms
    • See Oren Gross, Are Torture Warrants Warranted? Pragmatic Absolutism and Official Disobedience, 88 MINN. L. REV. 1481, 1487 (2004) (arguing that torture must be strictly prohibited but may also be morally defensible ex post in "truly exceptional cases" when public officials act extralegally in order to prevent catastrophic harms;
    • (2004) Minn. L. Rev. , vol.88 , pp. 1481
    • Gross, O.1
  • 101
    • 0043246478 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Precommitment" and "postcommitment": The ban on torture in the wake of september 11
    • see also, 2052, "Given the gravity of the terrorist threat, vigorous questioning short of torture - prolonged interrogation, mild sleep deprivation, perhaps the use of truth serum - might be justified in some cases."
    • see also Sanford Levinson, "Precommitment" and "Postcommitment": The Ban on Torture in The Wake of September 11, 81 EX. L. REV. 2013, 2052 (2003) ("Given the gravity of the terrorist threat, vigorous questioning short of torture - prolonged interrogation, mild sleep deprivation, perhaps the use of truth serum - might be justified in some cases.")
    • (2003) Ex. L. Rev. , vol.81 , pp. 2013
    • Levinson, S.1
  • 102
    • 0346433497 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Is torture ever justified?
    • quoting, Jan. 11, at
    • (quoting Editorial, Is Torture Ever Justified?, THE ECONOMIST, Jan. 11, 2003, at 11).
    • (2003) The Economist , pp. 11
    • Editorial1
  • 103
    • 0043276398 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., discussing different arguments in favor of and opposing the use of torture "as a last resort to prevent a ticking bomb from exploding"
    • See, e.g., ALAN M. DERSHOWITZ, WHY TERRORISM WORKS 142-63 (2002) (discussing different arguments in favor of and opposing the use of torture "as a last resort to prevent a ticking bomb from exploding");
    • (2002) Why Terrorism Works , pp. 142-163
    • Dershowitz, A.M.1
  • 104
    • 32544450170 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Should coercive interrogation be legal?
    • 681, arguing that "the legal system should authorize interrogation in some narrow range of circumstances, suitably defined and regulated ex ante"
    • Eric A. Posner & Adrian Vermeule, Should Coercive Interrogation Be Legal? 104 MICH. L. REV. 671, 681 (2006) (arguing that "the legal system should authorize interrogation in some narrow range of circumstances, suitably defined and regulated ex ante").
    • (2006) Mich. L. Rev. , vol.104 , pp. 671
    • Posner, E.A.1    Vermeule, A.2
  • 105
    • 79959481802 scopus 로고
    • See also generally Symposium on the Report of the Commission of Inquiry into the Methods of Investigation of the General Security Service Regarding Hostile Terrorist Activity, collecting comments and reviews by, among others, Alan M. Dershowitz, Sanford H. Kadish, Michael S. Moore, and Paul H. Robinson concluding torture could be permissible in a narrow, limited range of circumstances
    • See also generally Symposium on the Report of the Commission of Inquiry into the Methods of Investigation of the General Security Service Regarding Hostile Terrorist Activity, 23 ISR. L. REV. 141 (1989) (collecting comments and reviews by, among others, Alan M. Dershowitz, Sanford H. Kadish, Michael S. Moore, and Paul H. Robinson concluding torture could be permissible in a narrow, limited range of circumstances).
    • (1989) Isr. L. Rev. , vol.23 , pp. 141
  • 106
    • 0041653418 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Interrogating suspected terrorists: Should torture be an option?
    • See, 761-62, acknowledging that "under extreme 'ticking time bomb' circumstances, torture may be the least worse choice", but arguing that "legalizing torture would create administrative difficulties that would raise further moral issues"
    • See John T. Parry & Welsh S. White, Interrogating Suspected Terrorists: Should Torture Be an Option?, 63 U. PITT. L. REV. 743, 761-62 (2002) (acknowledging that "under extreme 'ticking time bomb' circumstances, torture may be the least worse choice", but arguing that "legalizing torture would create administrative difficulties that would raise further moral issues");
    • (2002) U. Pitt. L. Rev. , vol.63 , pp. 743
    • Parry, J.T.1    White, W.S.2
  • 107
    • 21244450422 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Fear and liberty
    • 989-90, "A flat prohibition on torture, one that forbids balancing in individual cases, might be justified on the basis of a kind of second-order balancing. It might be concluded not that torture is never justified in principle, but that unless torture is entirely outlawed, government will engage in torture in cases in which it is not justified, that the benefits of torture are rarely significant, and that the permission to torture in extraordinary cases will lead, on balance, to more harm than good."
    • Cass R. Sunstein, Fear and Liberty, 71 SOC. RES. 967, 989-90 (2004) ("[A] flat prohibition on torture, one that forbids balancing in individual cases, might be justified on the basis of a kind of second-order balancing. It might be concluded not that torture is never justified in principle, but that unless torture is entirely outlawed, government will engage in torture in cases in which it is not justified, that the benefits of torture are rarely significant, and that the permission to torture in extraordinary cases will lead, on balance, to more harm than good.");
    • (2004) Soc. Res. , vol.71 , pp. 967
    • Sunstein, C.R.1
  • 108
    • 33745762960 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Torture
    • see also, 271-74, "If rules are promulgated permitting torture in a 'ticking bomb scenario', torture will become the norm rather than the exception, particularly when dealing with anyone suspected of terrorist ties. Only an absolute ban on torture without exception will enable this nation to resist the impulse to ignore critical core values in favor of an elusive security.". For negating second-order considerations that support a flat ban on coercive interrogation
    • see also Marcy Strauss, Torture, 48 N. Y. L. SCH. L. REV. 201, 271-74 (2003) ("If rules are promulgated permitting torture in a 'ticking bomb scenario', torture will become the norm rather than the exception, particularly when dealing with anyone suspected of terrorist ties.... Only an absolute ban on torture without exception will enable this nation to resist the impulse to ignore critical core values in favor of an elusive security."). For negating second-order considerations that support a flat ban on coercive interrogation
    • (2003) N. Y. L. Sch. L. Rev. , vol.48 , pp. 201
    • Strauss, M.1
  • 109
    • 79959395945 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see Posner & Vermeule, supra note 42, at 683-93
    • see Posner & Vermeule, supra note 42, at 683-93.
  • 110
    • 34547574288 scopus 로고
    • Decision rules and conduct rules: On acoustic separation in criminal law
    • Cf, 630-34, discussing "acoustic separation" - having courts apply decision rules whose contents are not first communicated to the citizens - and the advantages of such a hypothetical system in minimizing conflicts between decision rules and conduct rules
    • Cf. Meir Dan-Cohen, Decision Rules and Conduct Rules: On Acoustic Separation in Criminal Law, 97 HARV. L. REV. 625, 630-34 (1984) (discussing "acoustic separation" - having courts apply decision rules whose contents are not first communicated to the citizens - and the advantages of such a hypothetical system in minimizing conflicts between decision rules and conduct rules).
    • (1984) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.97 , pp. 625
    • Dan-Cohen, M.1
  • 111
    • 79959392051 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a discussion on lexical priority of rights as opposed to utilitarian commensurability
    • For a discussion on lexical priority of rights as opposed to utilitarian commensurability
  • 112
    • 84929067399 scopus 로고
    • Rights in conflict
    • see, 509-15, The idea of "lexical order"
    • see Jeremy Waldron, Rights in Conflict, 99 ETHICS 503, 509-15 (1989). The idea of "lexical order"
    • (1989) Ethics , vol.99 , pp. 503
    • Waldron, J.1
  • 113
    • 0004048289 scopus 로고
    • is explained in, By analogy, Eyal Zamir and Barak Medina's recent book defends the idea of "threshold deontology", which grants deontological constraints priority over law and economics cost-benefit analysis but gives the latter priority over the former when the costs of not following the cost-benefit analysis reaches a certain threshold
    • is explained in JOHN RAWLS, A THEORY OF JUSTICE 42-44 (1971). By analogy, Eyal Zamir and Barak Medina's recent book defends the idea of "threshold deontology", which grants deontological constraints priority over law and economics cost-benefit analysis but gives the latter priority over the former when the costs of not following the cost-benefit analysis reaches a certain threshold.
    • (1971) A Theory of Justice , pp. 42-44
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 114
    • 79959416666 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See ZAMIR & MEDINA, supra note 1, at 1-8, 79-104. The authors apply their theory to several fields of the law
    • See ZAMIR & MEDINA, supra note 1, at 1-8, 79-104. The authors apply their theory to several fields of the law.
  • 115
    • 79959426255 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 127-311 applying threshold deontology to the fight against terrorism, freedom of speech, antidiscrimination law, and contract law
    • See id. at 127-311 (applying threshold deontology to the fight against terrorism, freedom of speech, antidiscrimination law, and contract law).
  • 116
    • 79959477721 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra Part I. A
    • See supra Part I. A.
  • 117
    • 33745620128 scopus 로고
    • See, §, & cmt. d, Nevertheless, recognition of contributory or comparative fault results in the need to estimate the injurer's fault
    • See RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS § 519 & cmt. d (1977). Nevertheless, recognition of contributory or comparative fault results in the need to estimate the injurer's fault.
    • (1977) Restatement (Second) of Torts , pp. 519
  • 118
    • 79959445665 scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Nat'l Marine Serv., Inc. v. Petroleum Serv. Corp., 276, 5th Cir, noting that in applying comparative fault in federal maritime products cases, "the plaintiffs fault must be compared with the fault of a strictly liable defendant"
    • See, e.g., Nat'l Marine Serv., Inc. v. Petroleum Serv. Corp., 736 F.2d 272, 276 (5th Cir. 1984) (noting that in applying comparative fault in federal maritime products cases, "the plaintiffs fault must be compared with the fault of a strictly liable defendant").
    • (1984) F.2d , vol.736 , pp. 272
  • 119
    • 79959445225 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • DOBBS, supra note 21, at 950
    • DOBBS, supra note 21, at 950.
  • 120
    • 79959388334 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra Part I. B
    • See supra Part I. B.
  • 121
    • 79959381199 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra notes 23-29 and accompanying text
    • See supra notes 23-29 and accompanying text.
  • 122
    • 79959410276 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra Part I. C
    • See supra Part I. C.
  • 123
    • 79959392610 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. supra note 45 discussing Zamir and Medina's threshold deontology theory
    • Cf. supra note 45 (discussing Zamir and Medina's threshold deontology theory).
  • 124
    • 79959465553 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Sunstein, supra note 43, at 983 "Courts are not, to say the least, in a good position to know whether restrictions on civil liberty are defensible. They lack the factfinding competence that would enable them to make accurate assessments of the dangers.... Under the pressure of the moment, courts are likely to... favor the government, even when they should not"
    • See Sunstein, supra note 43, at 983 ("Courts are not, to say the least, in a good position to know whether restrictions on civil liberty are defensible. They lack the factfinding competence that would enable them to make accurate assessments of the dangers.... [U]nder the pressure of the moment, courts are likely to... favor[] the government, even when [they should] not").
  • 125
    • 79959407203 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 977 "In the context of threats to national security, it is predictable that governments will infringe on civil liberties without adequate justification".
    • See id. at 977 ("In the context of threats to national security, it is predictable that governments will infringe on civil liberties without adequate justification. ").
  • 126
    • 79959474354 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Adrian Vermeule discusses the view, often associated with Sunstein, that "decisionmakers who are subject to security panics ought not engage directly in balancing that attempts to strike the optimal tradeoff between liberty and security."
    • Adrian Vermeule discusses the view, often associated with Sunstein, that "decisionmakers who are subject to security panics ought not engage directly in balancing that attempts to strike the optimal tradeoff between liberty and security."
  • 127
    • 79959478298 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Vermeule, supra note 38, at 885. According to Vermeule, "the institutional solution, on this view, is to deny front-line decisionmakers the authority to engage in direct or first-order balancing of liberty and security" in favor of "'second-order balancing', under which civil liberties are overprotected through second-best rules that mitigate the risk of error in the first-order calculus."
    • Vermeule, supra note 38, at 885. According to Vermeule, "[t]he institutional solution, on this view, is to deny front-line decisionmakers the authority to engage in direct or first-order balancing of liberty and security" in favor of "'second-order balancing', under which civil liberties are overprotected through second-best rules that mitigate the risk of error in the first-order calculus."
  • 128
    • 79959443498 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. Vermeule then continues: "The argument for second-order balancing goes beyond an abstract claim that rules may correct for the errors that decisionmakers commit under first-order balancing. In this setting, the argument for second-order balancing is an argument not only for rules, but for rules with a distinctly libertarian slant - a kind of second-best libertarianism. The idea is to build into the second-order rules a skew in favor of liberty that will compensate for predictable pressures towards overweighting security - pressures such as security panics."
    • Id. Vermeule then continues: "[T]he argument for second-order balancing goes beyond an abstract claim that rules may correct for the errors that decisionmakers commit under first-order balancing. In this setting, the argument for second-order balancing is an argument not only for rules, but for rules with a distinctly libertarian slant - a kind of second-best libertarianism. The idea is to build into the second-order rules a skew in favor of liberty that will compensate for predictable pressures towards overweighting security - pressures such as security panics."
  • 129
    • 79959432689 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 886
    • Id. at 886.
  • 130
    • 84888998229 scopus 로고
    • The rule of law as a law of rules
    • See, 1179, arguing that establishing a "clear, general principle of decision" promotes uniformity injudicial decisions and advances predictability
    • See Antonin Scalia, The Rule of Law as a Law of Rules, 56 U. CHI. L. REV. 1175, 1179 (1989) (arguing that establishing a "clear, general principle of decision" promotes uniformity injudicial decisions and advances predictability);
    • (1989) U. Chi. L. Rev. , vol.56 , pp. 1175
    • Scalia, A.1
  • 131
    • 84911147294 scopus 로고
    • Formalism
    • 543, "It is clearly true that rules get in the way, but this need not always be considered a bad tiling. It may be an asset to restrict misguided, incompetent, wicked, power-hungry, or simply mistaken decisionmakers whose own sense of the good might diverge from that of the system they serve."
    • Frederick Schauer, Formalism, 97 YALE L. J. 509, 543 (1988) ("[I]t is clearly true that rules get in the way, but this need not always be considered a bad tiling.... [I]t may be an asset to restrict misguided, incompetent, wicked, power-hungry, or simply mistaken decisionmakers whose own sense of the good might diverge from that of the system they serve.").
    • (1988) Yale L. J. , vol.97 , pp. 509
    • Schauer, F.1
  • 132
    • 79959397247 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf, June 20, unpublished manuscript on file with authors discussing nontransitivity both in the Talmud and modern law and its goals
    • Cf. Barak Medina, Shlomo Naeh & Uzi Segal, Ranking Ranking Rules 6-17 (June 20, 2010) (unpublished manuscript) (on file with authors) (discussing nontransitivity both in the Talmud and modern law and its goals).
    • (2010) Ranking Ranking Rules , pp. 6-17
    • Medina, B.1    Naeh, S.2    Segal, U.3
  • 133
    • 79959403430 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 42 and accompanying text
    • See supra note 42 and accompanying text.
  • 134
    • 79959411364 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This amount is below regulatory agencies' valuations of human life, which typically range between $5 million and $6.5 million per life
    • This amount is below regulatory agencies' valuations of human life, which typically range between $5 million and $6.5 million per life.
  • 135
    • 79959477161 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Posner & Sunstein, supra note 13, at 549-51
    • See Posner & Sunstein, supra note 13, at 549-51.
  • 136
    • 79959400723 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Our argument resembles a similar argument that others use to justify inalienability rules. That argument explains that society should sometimes avoid commodifications of certain values
    • Our argument resembles a similar argument that others use to justify inalienability rules. That argument explains that society should sometimes avoid commodifications of certain values.
  • 137
    • 84936628259 scopus 로고
    • Market-inalienability
    • See, 1884-85, However, although Radin's argument is motivated by the harm done by markets
    • See Margaret Jane Radin, Market-Inalienability, 100 HARV. L. REV. 1849, 1884-85 (1987). However, although Radin's argument is motivated by the harm done by markets
    • (1987) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.100 , pp. 1849
    • Radin, M.J.1
  • 138
    • 79959463967 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see id. at 1877-87, our argument is motivated by the harm done by the law when it incorporates some types of comparisons
    • see id. at 1877-87, our argument is motivated by the harm done by the law when it incorporates some types of comparisons
  • 139
    • 79959435041 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Commodification without money
    • compare, 10-14, available at, explaining how the commodification objection, which is typically applied to markets, can be applied to regulations, as well, and clarifying that commodification by regulation could take place even without ascribing monetary values to the goods in question. For the argument that valuation of certain goods that are not commodifiable should not be conducted through market mechanisms, but instead by other criteria applied by the state that are also sensitive to the intrinsic values of such goods
    • compare Tsilly Dagan, Commodification Without Money, 11 THEORETICAL INQ. L. F. 9, 10-14 (2010), available at http://services.bepress. com/tilforum/vol11/iss1/ (explaining how the commodification objection, which is
    • (2010) Theoretical Inq. L. F , vol.11 , pp. 9
    • Dagan, T.1
  • 140
    • 79959418560 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see ANDERSON, supra note 2, at 190-216
    • see ANDERSON, supra note 2, at 190-216.
  • 141
    • 79959403431 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Tedock, supra note 7, at 322 describing experiments which show that lay people are more tolerant to trade-offs between two sacred resources - life of one patient in a hospital versus the life of another patient in the same hospital - than to trade-offs between sacred resources and money, such as the life of a patient in a hospital versus $1 million dollars
    • See Tedock, supra note 7, at 322 (describing experiments which show that lay people are more tolerant to trade-offs between two sacred resources - life of one patient in a hospital versus the life of another patient in the same hospital - than to trade-offs between sacred resources and money, such as the life of a patient in a hospital versus $1 million dollars).
  • 142
    • 79959416126 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • But notice that refraining the allocation of resources problem in the hospital could mitigate the commodification concern at the outset
    • But notice that refraining the allocation of resources problem in the hospital could mitigate the commodification concern at the outset.
  • 143
    • 79959436937 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • An alternative explanation for the nontransitivity challenge with respect to the torture example is that there is a qualitative difference between "torturing for saving life" and "torturing for saving money" - in other words, that the two "bads" have different intrinsic negative values. This alternative explanation is inconsistent with the commensurability premise
    • An alternative explanation for the nontransitivity challenge with respect to the torture example is that there is a qualitative difference between "torturing for saving life" and "torturing for saving money" - in other words, that the two "bads" have different intrinsic (negative) values. This alternative explanation is inconsistent with the commensurability premise.
  • 144
    • 79959425082 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra text accompanying note 43
    • See supra text accompanying note 43.
  • 145
    • 0010950913 scopus 로고
    • Private versus public enforcement of fines
    • See, 107-08, comparing monopolistic, competitive, and public methods of enforcement and concluding that "any of the methods of enforcement may be socially preferable, depending on the costs of each method as well as on the magnitude of the external damage"
    • See A. Mitchell Polinsky, Private Versus Public Enforcement of Fines, 9 J. LEGAL STUD. 105, 107-08 (1980) (comparing monopolistic, competitive, and public methods of enforcement and concluding that "any of the methods of enforcement may be socially preferable, depending on the costs of each method as well as on the magnitude of the external damage").
    • (1980) J. Legal Stud. , vol.9 , pp. 105
    • Polinsky, A.M.1
  • 146
    • 84934562952 scopus 로고
    • What's wrong with private prisons
    • See, 68, stressing that "soaring inmate populations and caseloads!, escalating costs", and public enforcement's inefficiency are the main problems that privatization of prisons can address
    • See John J. DiIulio, Jr., What's Wrong with Private Prisons, 92 PUB. INT. 66, 68 (1988) (stressing that "soaring inmate populations and caseloads!,] escalating costs", and public enforcement's inefficiency are the main problems that privatization of prisons can address);
    • (1988) Pub. Int , vol.92 , pp. 66
    • Diiulio Jr., J.J.1
  • 147
    • 79959481370 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Polinsky, supra note 63, at 105, 107-08
    • Polinsky, supra note 63, at 105, 107-08;
  • 148
    • 85053395780 scopus 로고
    • The optimal structure of law enforcement
    • see also Steven Shavell, The Optimal Structure of Law Enforcement, 36 J. L. & ECON. 255, 268-69 (1993) (examining criminal enforcement from an economic perspective and finding that public enforcement may be justified in cases where the identity or location of the criminal is not known to any private party and will require effort and expense to determine). (Pubitemid 24757382)
    • (1993) Journal of Law and Economics , vol.36 , Issue.1 PART 2 , pp. 255
    • Shavell, S.1
  • 149
    • 79958073507 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Humanitarian law and direct participation in hostilities by private contractors or civilian employees
    • See, 513-18, elaborating on the advantages of outsourcing military security projects to private contractors, which normally reduces costs and increases efficiency
    • See Michael N. Schmitt, Humanitarian Law and Direct Participation in Hostilities by Private Contractors or Civilian Employees, 5 CHI. J. INT'L L. 511, 513-18 (2005) (elaborating on the advantages of outsourcing military security projects to private contractors, which normally reduces costs and increases efficiency);
    • (2005) Chi. J. Int'l L. , vol.5 , pp. 511
    • Schmitt, M.N.1
  • 150
    • 79959459113 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Military privatization: Efficiency or anarchy?
    • see also, 67, "Proponents of private military contracting usually cite cost reduction and efficiency as reasons to outsource a growing number of activities to independent companies.". Calaguas, however, comments that "no definitive study has shown that the practice actually saves the military any money, "
    • see also Mark Calaguas, Military Privatization: Efficiency or Anarchy?, 6 CHI.-KENT J. INT'L & COMP. L. 58, 67 (2006) ("Proponents of private military contracting usually cite cost reduction and efficiency as reasons to outsource a growing number of activities to independent companies."). Calaguas, however, comments that "[n]o definitive study has shown that the practice actually saves the military any money, "
    • (2006) Chi.-kent J. Int'l & Comp. L. , vol.6 , pp. 58
    • Calaguas, M.1
  • 151
    • 79959446796 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • id. at 69 & n. 73 citing Interview by FRONTLINE with Steven Schooner, Law Professor, George Washington Sch. of Law and former Assoc. Adm'r for Procurement Law and Legislation, Office of Federal Procurement Pol'y May 19, 2005; air date June 21, 2005, available at, last visited March 11, 2010, but then suggests that war is about effectiveness, and that "nevertheless, the lines between economy, efficiency, and effectiveness oftentimes are blurry, "
    • id. at 69 & n. 73 (citing Interview by FRONTLINE with Steven Schooner, Law Professor, George Washington Sch. of Law and former Assoc. Adm'r for Procurement Law and Legislation, Office of Federal Procurement Pol'y (May 19, 2005; air date June 21, 2005), available at http://www.pbs.org/wgbh/pages/ frontline/shows/warriors/interviews/schooner.html) (last visited March 11, 2010), but then suggests that war is about effectiveness, and that "[n]evertheless, the lines between economy, efficiency, and effectiveness oftentimes are blurry, "
  • 152
    • 79959433244 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • id. at 69. Efficiency in this context ought to be understood broadly to include flexibility and speediness
    • id. at 69. Efficiency in this context ought to be understood broadly to include flexibility and speediness.
  • 153
    • 79959477159 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Interview with Steven Schooner, supra. "Many people think about outsourcing primarily as a tool to save money. The other way to think about it is sometimes the government pays more money for greater flexibility or greater capacity or better services or services that could be provided more quickly."
    • See Interview with Steven Schooner, supra.) ("Many people think about outsourcing primarily as a tool to save money. The other way to think about it is sometimes the government pays more money for greater flexibility or greater capacity or better services or services that could be provided more quickly.").
  • 154
    • 79959445664 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Why only the state may inflict criminal sanctions: The argument from moral burdens
    • See, e.g., 2634, "If state-inflicted sanctions are justified simply on the grounds that the state is better in calibrating the sanctions or inflicting them, it follows that when circumstances change and private individuals are shown to be able to inflict the sanction as well as the state, the agent who ought to be in charge of inflicting sanctions ought to be changed accordingly."
    • See, e.g., Alon Harel, Why Only the State May Inflict Criminal Sanctions: The Argument from Moral Burdens, 28 CARDOZO L. REV. 2629, 2634 (2007) ("If state-inflicted sanctions are justified simply on the grounds that the state is better in calibrating the sanctions or inflicting them, it follows that when circumstances change and private individuals are shown to be able to inflict the sanction as well as the state, the agent who ought to be in charge of inflicting sanctions ought to be changed accordingly.");
    • (2007) Cardozo L. Rev. , vol.28 , pp. 2629
    • Harel, A.1
  • 155
    • 79959462082 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • cf. sources cited supra notes 63-65 discussing suitability of public and private entities to carry out respective tasks
    • cf. sources cited supra notes 63-65 (discussing suitability of public and private entities to carry out respective tasks).
  • 156
    • 79959385774 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, art. I, §§
    • See U. S. CONST, art. I, §§ 1, 8.
    • U. S. Const , vol.1 , pp. 8
  • 157
    • 46749087076 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nomos without narrative
    • But see, 474-86, 501-02, presenting arguments in favor of privatization of the law, including the "law production power", and comparing privatization of the law and multiculturalism as two decentralization paradigms that challenge the monopolist concentration of law production power in the hands of the state
    • But see Talia Fisher, Nomos Without Narrative, 9 THEORETICAL INQ. L. 473, 474-86, 501-02 (2008) (presenting arguments in favor of privatization of the law, including the "law production power", and comparing privatization of the law and multiculturalism as two decentralization paradigms that challenge the monopolist concentration of law production power in the hands of the state).
    • (2008) Theoretical Inq. L. , vol.9 , pp. 473
    • Fisher, T.1
  • 158
    • 79959439960 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf, art. III, §§, vesting judicial power of the United States in the courts
    • Cf. U. S. CONST, art. III, §§ 1, 2 (vesting judicial power of the United States in the courts);
    • U. S. Const , vol.1 , pp. 2
  • 159
    • 77951893454 scopus 로고
    • Mistretta v. United States, 396, noting that the "substantive judgment in the field of sentencing has been and remains appropriate to the Judicial Branch"
    • Mistretta v. United States, 488 U. S. 361, 396 (1989) (noting that the "substantive judgment in the field of sentencing has been and remains appropriate to the Judicial Branch").
    • (1989) U. S. , vol.488 , pp. 361
  • 160
    • 79959447912 scopus 로고
    • See, Michael Oakeshott ed., Collier Books, 1651 "Public ministers are also all those, that have authority from the sovereign, to procure the execution of judgments given; to publish the sovereign's commands; to suppress tumults; to apprehend, and imprison malefactors; and other acts tending to the conservation of the peace. For every act they do by such authority, is the act of the commonwealth; and their service, answerable to that of the hands, in a body natural."
    • See THOMAS HOBBES, LEVIATHAN 183 (Michael Oakeshott ed., Collier Books 1962) (1651) ("Public ministers are also all those, that have authority from the sovereign, to procure the execution of judgments given; to publish the sovereign's commands; to suppress tumults; to apprehend, and imprison malefactors; and other acts tending to the conservation of the peace. For every act they do by such authority, is the act of the commonwealth; and their service, answerable to that of the hands, in a body natural.").
    • (1962) Leviathan , pp. 183
    • Hobbes, T.1
  • 161
    • 0348103898 scopus 로고
    • The duty to govern: A critical perspective on the private management of prisons and jails
    • For a more recent perspective, see, in, Douglas C. McDonald ed., "At a minimum, it can be said that, both in theory and in practice, the formulation and administration of criminal laws by recognized public authorities is one of the liberal state's most central and historic functions; indeed, in some formulations it is the liberal state's reason for being."
    • For a more recent perspective, see John J. DiIulio, Jr., The Duty to Govern: A Critical Perspective on the Private Management of Prisons and Jails, in PRIVATE PRISONS AND THE PUBLIC INTEREST 155, 175 (Douglas C. McDonald ed., 1990) ("At a minimum, it can be said that, both in theory and in practice, the formulation and administration of criminal laws by recognized public authorities is one of the liberal state's most central and historic functions; indeed, in some formulations it is the liberal state's reason for being.").
    • (1990) Private Prisons and the Public Interest , vol.155 , pp. 175
    • DiIulio Jr., J.J.1
  • 162
    • 79959396700 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra notes 67-68 and infra Part II. B
    • See supra notes 67-68 and infra Part II. B.
  • 163
    • 53849103055 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., discussing outsourcing of traditional military functions to private contractors
    • See, e.g., PAUL R. VERKUIL, OUTSOURCING SOVEREIGNTY 26-30 (2007) (discussing outsourcing of traditional military functions to private contractors).
    • (2007) Outsourcing Sovereignty , pp. 26-30
    • Verkuil, P.R.1
  • 164
    • 79959416127 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • There are two evident manifestations of the privatization of punishment: the rise in the use of shaming penalties which are ultimately private sanctions because they are in effect inflicted by individuals and the rise of private prisons. With respect to the first
    • There are two evident manifestations of the privatization of punishment: the rise in the use of shaming penalties (which are ultimately private sanctions because they are in effect inflicted by individuals) and the rise of private prisons. With respect to the first
  • 165
    • 0039444199 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Shaming white-collar criminals: A proposal for reform of the federal sentencing guidelines
    • see, 368-80
    • see Dan M. Kahan & Eric A. Posner, Shaming White-Collar Criminals: A Proposal for Reform of the Federal Sentencing Guidelines, 42 J. L. & ECON. 365, 368-80 (1999)
    • (1999) J. L. & Econ. , vol.42 , pp. 365
    • Kahan, D.M.1    Posner, E.A.2
  • 166
    • 0347569386 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • What do alternative sanctions mean?
    • and Dan M. Kahan, What Do Alternative Sanctions Mean?, 63 U. CHI. L. REV. 591, 631-49 (1996). For a discussion of private prisons (Pubitemid 126408719)
    • (1996) University of Chicago Law Review , vol.63 , Issue.2 , pp. 591
    • Kahan, D.M.1
  • 168
    • 79959430436 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a discussion of the rise in private militarized firms and their greater role in wars
    • For a discussion of the rise in private militarized firms and their greater role in wars
  • 169
    • 0035782869 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Corporate warriors: The rise of the privatized military industry and its ramifications for international security
    • see generally, discussing the rise and implications of privatized military firms
    • see generally P. W. Singer, Corporate Warriors: The Rise of the Privatized Military Industry and Its Ramifications for International Security, 26 INT'L SECURITY 186 (2001) (discussing the rise and implications of privatized military firms);
    • (2001) Int'l Security , vol.26 , pp. 186
    • Singer, P.W.1
  • 170
    • 1642357616 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Wars, profits, and the vacuum of lam: Privatized military firms and international law
    • discussing the limited applicability of international law to privatized military firms
    • P. W. Singer, Wars, Profits, and the Vacuum of Lam: Privatized Military Firms and International Law, 42 COLUM. J. TRANSNAT'L L. 521 (2004) (discussing the limited applicability of international law to privatized military firms).
    • (2004) Colum. J. Transnat'l L. , vol.42 , pp. 521
    • Singer, P.W.1
  • 171
    • 70449662173 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Public law values in a privatized world
    • See, 384, "While advocates of privatization have generally argued for the practice on efficiency grounds, critics have worried that, even if privatization may cut financial costs, it can threaten important public law values." footnote omitted
    • See Laura A. Dickinson, Public Law Values in a Privatized World, 31 YALE J. INT'L L. 383, 384 (2006) ("While advocates of privatization have generally argued for the practice on efficiency grounds, critics have worried that, even if privatization may cut financial costs, it can threaten important public law values." (footnote omitted)).
    • (2006) Yale J. Int'l L. , vol.31 , pp. 383
    • Dickinson, L.A.1
  • 172
    • 84955501534 scopus 로고
    • §, at, Peter Laslett ed., Cambridge Univ. Press, 1690
    • JOHN LOCKE, TWO TREATISES OF GOVERNMENT § 13, at 293-94 (Peter Laslett ed., Cambridge Univ. Press 1960) (1690).
    • (1960) Two Treatises of Government , vol.13 , pp. 293-294
    • Locke, J.1
  • 173
    • 79959463425 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, June 2, unpublished manuscript on file with author
    • See Alon Harel, Outsourcing Violence 8-9 (June 2, 2010) unpublished manuscript) (on file with author);
    • (2010) Outsourcing Violence , pp. 8-9
    • Harel, A.1
  • 174
    • 79959477160 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • cf. DiIulio, supra note 64, at 71-75 recounting history of private corrections facilities in the United States and objections to privatization based on historical experience
    • cf. DiIulio, supra note 64, at 71-75 (recounting history of private corrections facilities in the United States and objections to privatization based on historical experience).
  • 175
    • 84923444323 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Isr. Nov. 19, available at, There, the court declared unconstitutional the law authorizing the establishment of a private prison because the establishment of such a prison would be incompatible with human dignity, 2009
    • The Israeli Supreme Court adopted these concerns in Academic Center of Law & Business v. Minister of Finance [2009] (Isr.) (Nov. 19, 2009), available at http://elyonl.court.gov. il/files-eng/05/050/026/n39/05026050.n39. htm. There, the court declared unconstitutional the law authorizing the establishment of a private prison because the establishment of such a prison would be incompatible with human dignity.
    • (2009) Academic Center of Law & Business V. Minister of Finance
  • 176
    • 79959395944 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • para, Isr., available at
    • HCJ 2605/05 Academic Ctr. of Law & Bus. v. Minister of Fin. para. 34-39 [2009] (Isr.), available at http://elyonl.court.gov. il/files-eng/05/050/ 026/n39/05026050.n39.htm.
    • (2009) Academic Ctr. of Law & Bus. V. Minister of Fin , pp. 34-39
  • 177
    • 79959428449 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See sources cited supra note 76
    • See sources cited supra note 76.
  • 178
    • 79959400147 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Harel, supra note 76, at 8
    • See Harel, supra note 76, at 8;
  • 179
    • 79959410275 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also supra note 74
    • see also supra note 74.
  • 180
    • 79959413686 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Harel, supra note 76, at 8
    • Harel, supra note 76, at 8;
  • 181
    • 79959456791 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See VERKUIL, supra note 71, at 1, 40-41 "A government appointment creates a public servant who, whether through the oath, the security clearance, the desire to achieve public goals, or the psychic income of service, is different from those in the private sector."
    • See VERKUIL, supra note 71, at 1, 40-41 ("A government appointment creates a public servant who, whether through the oath, the security clearance, the desire to achieve public goals, or the psychic income of service, is different from those in the private sector.").
  • 182
    • 84921847322 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, surveying the norm against the use of mercenaries and the privatization of wars. In the contemporary legal context, Paul Verkuil voices such noninstrumental concerns to privatization
    • See SARAH PERCY, MERCENARIES: THE HISTORY OF A NORM IN INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS 1-2 (2007) (surveying the norm against the use of mercenaries and the privatization of wars). In the contemporary legal context, Paul Verkuil voices such noninstrumental concerns to privatization.
    • (2007) Mercenaries: The History of a Norm in International Relations , pp. 1-2
    • Percy, S.1
  • 183
    • 38849136319 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Public law limitations on privatization of government functions
    • See generally, discussing limitations and concerns regarding privatization
    • See generally Paul R. Verkuil, Public Law Limitations on Privatization of Government Functions, 84 N. C. L. REV. 397 (2006) (discussing limitations and concerns regarding privatization).
    • (2006) N. C. L. Rev. , vol.84 , pp. 397
    • Verkuil, P.R.1
  • 184
    • 79959390903 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • We leave for another occasion the task of establishing that sometimes there are nonconsequentialist considerations supporting the selection of a private agent over a public one
    • We leave for another occasion the task of establishing that sometimes there are nonconsequentialist considerations supporting the selection of a private agent over a public one.
  • 185
    • 0041018635 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • art I, §§, 8
    • U. S. CONST, art I, §§ 1, 8.
    • U. S. Const , pp. 1
  • 186
    • 79959422384 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. art II, §§ 1, 2
    • Id. art II, §§ 1, 2.
  • 187
    • 79959456002 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. LOCKE, supra note 75, at § 141, 380-81 asserting that the legislative power is a delegated power from the people and cannot be transferred
    • Cf. LOCKE, supra note 75, at § 141, 380-81 (asserting that the legislative power is a delegated power from the people and cannot be transferred).
  • 188
    • 79959428448 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Federal Activities Inventory Reform Act of, §, note
    • Federal Activities Inventory Reform Act of 1998, 31 U. S. C. § 501 note (2006).
    • (1998) U. S. C. , vol.31 , pp. 501
  • 189
    • 79959449456 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Office of mgmt. & Budget, circular no. A-76 revised
    • Id. Somewhat different wording can be found in the Office of Management and Budget OMB Circular No. A-76, which defines an inherently governmental activity as opposed to function as "an activity that is so intimately related to the public interest as to mandate performance by government personnel.", at, a May 29, Although the FAIR Act provides that the term encompasses activities requiring "the exercise of discretion in applying Federal Government authority, "
    • Id. Somewhat different wording can be found in the Office of Management and Budget (OMB) Circular No. A-76, which defines an inherently governmental activity (as opposed to function) as "an activity that is so intimately related to the public interest as to mandate performance by government personnel." OFFICE OF MGMT. & BUDGET, CIRCULAR NO. A-76 REVISED, PERFORMANCE OF COMMERCIAL ACTIVITIES, at B-1 (a) (May 29, 2003). Although the FAIR Act provides that the term encompasses activities requiring "the exercise of discretion in applying Federal Government authority, "
    • (2003) Performance of Commercial Activities
  • 190
    • 79959455446 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • §, note, sec. 5, B, OMB Circular A-76's formulation of the term only includes requiring "the exercise of substantial discretion, "
    • U. S. C. § 501 note, sec. 5 (2) (B), OMB Circular A-76's formulation of the term only includes requiring "the exercise of substantial discretion, "
    • U. S. C. , vol.31 , Issue.2 , pp. 501
  • 191
    • 84928301658 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra ax. B-1 b emphasis added. Noting this divergence, in 2010 the OMB's Office of Federal Procurement Policy proposed a policy letter that would adopt the FAIR Act formulation "as the single, government-wide definition" of an inherently governmental function
    • OMB CIRCULAR A-76, supra ax. B-1 (b) (emphasis added). Noting this divergence, in 2010 the OMB's Office of Federal Procurement Policy proposed a policy letter that would adopt the FAIR Act formulation "as the single, government-wide definition" of an inherently governmental function.
    • Omb Circular
  • 192
    • 77956822392 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Work Reserved for Performance by Federal Government Employees, 188, 16, 190 Mar. 31
    • Work Reserved for Performance by Federal Government Employees, 75 Fed. Reg. 16, 188, 16, 190 (Mar. 31, 2010).
    • (2010) Fed. Reg. , vol.75 , pp. 16
  • 193
    • 79959468648 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Presidential Memorandum of March 4, 2009: Government Contracting, Memorandum for the Heads of Executive Department and Agencies
    • Presidential Memorandum of March 4, 2009: Government Contracting, Memorandum for the Heads of Executive Department and Agencies
  • 194
    • 84941041191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 755, 9, 755-56 Mar. 6
    • Fed. Reg. 9, 755, 9, 755-56 (Mar. 6, 2009).
    • (2009) Fed. Reg. , vol.74 , pp. 9
  • 195
    • 79959471836 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • §, B
    • FAIR Act § 5 (2) (B)
    • Fair Act , vol.5 , Issue.2
  • 196
    • 79959455446 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • §, note. Furthermore, the next paragraph - section C - describes the "functions excluded" from the definition of inherently governmental functions
    • U. S. C. § 501 note. Furthermore, the next paragraph - section (C) - describes the "functions excluded" from the definition of inherently governmental functions.
    • U. S. C. , vol.31 , pp. 501
  • 198
    • 77956775444 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • z.ast;, N. D. Ohio Dec. 11, noting that "in 2005, this court held that 'Level IATC air traffic control is not an inherently governmental function'"
    • z.ast; 5 (N. D. Ohio Dec. 11, 2009) (noting that "[i]n 2005, this court held that 'Level IATC [air traffic control] is not an inherently governmental function'");
    • (2009) U. S. Dist. Lexis 115449 , pp. 5
  • 200
    • 79959398377 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • z.ast;;, 6th Cir. Mar. 7, holding that air traffic controllers had standing to challenge FAA's privatization of services because the controllers' interest in ensuring that the FAA did not privatize inherently governmental functions was in zone of interests protected by the Office of Federal Procurement Policy Act Amendments of 1979 and reflected in OMB Circular A-76
    • z.ast;; 12-15 (6th Cir. Mar. 7, 1996) (holding that air traffic controllers had standing to challenge FAA's privatization of services because the controllers' interest in ensuring that the FAA did not privatize inherently governmental functions was in zone of interests protected by the Office of Federal Procurement Policy Act Amendments of 1979 and reflected in OMB Circular A-76);
    • (1996) U. S. App. Lexis , vol.8258 , pp. 12-15
  • 202
    • 79959474353 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • z.ast;, N. D. Ohio Feb. 23, concluding that the FAA failed to comply with OMB Circular A-76 because the record lacked any explanation for its determination that all ATC work was not inherently governmental, but noting that "it is not the place of the court to make that determination of inherently governmental or not in the first instance"
    • z.ast; 8-12 (N. D. Ohio Feb. 23, 2006) (concluding that the FAA failed to comply with OMB Circular A-76 because the record lacked any explanation for its determination that all ATC work was not inherently governmental, but noting that "it is not the place of the court to make that determination [of inherently governmental or not] in the first instance").
    • (2006) U. S. Dist. Lexis , vol.6869 , pp. 8-12
  • 203
    • 79959488517 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In a different context, the courts frequently make determinations as to whether something is or is not a governmental function when deciding whether a defendant is entitled to some sort of official immunity
    • In a different context, the courts frequently make determinations as to whether something is or is not a governmental function when deciding whether a defendant is entitled to some sort of official immunity.
  • 204
    • 79959449457 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Martin v. Halliburton, 484, 5th Cir, concluding that the court lacked jurisdiction to review the trial court's denial of defendant's official immunity defense because the immunity defense is applicable only in the performance of official duties that are discretionary, and the relevant regulations barred the defendants, private contractors, from performing inherently governmental functions, which are by their nature discretionary
    • See Martin v. Halliburton, 618 F.3d 476, 484 (5th Cir. 2010) (concluding that the court lacked jurisdiction to review the trial court's denial of defendant's official immunity defense because the immunity defense is applicable only in the performance of official duties that are discretionary, and the relevant regulations barred the defendants, private contractors, from performing inherently governmental functions, which are by their nature discretionary);
    • (2010) F.3d , vol.618 , pp. 476
  • 205
    • 77950465703 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Takle v. Univ. of Wis. Hosp. & Clinics Auth., 770-72, 7th Cir, determining that "there is nothing inherently governmental about a hospital" and thus that the hospital was not entitled to sovereign immunity
    • Takle v. Univ. of Wis. Hosp. & Clinics Auth., 402 F.3d 768, 770-72 (7th Cir. 2005) (determining that "[t]here is nothing inherently governmental about a hospital" and thus that the hospital was not entitled to sovereign immunity).
    • (2005) F.3d , vol.402 , pp. 768
  • 206
    • 79959419721 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • FAIR Act and OMB Circular A-76, however, only provide limited bases for judicial review of agency decisions as to whether to privatize certain activities and whether such activities are inherendy governmental or commercial
    • The FAIR Act and OMB Circular A-76, however, only provide limited bases for judicial review of agency decisions as to whether to privatize certain activities and whether such activities are inherendy governmental or commercial.
  • 207
    • 79959433916 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Verkuil, supra note 80, at 452-54. Of course, "generalized judicial review provisions of the APA Administrative Procedure Act are available."
    • See Verkuil, supra note 80, at 452-54. Of course, "[g]eneralized judicial review provisions of the APA [Administrative Procedure Act] are available."
  • 208
    • 79959438065 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 452 footnote omitted
    • Id. at 452 (footnote omitted).
  • 209
    • 79959429023 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 455 "Whether to privatize inherently governmental functions is a political question that implicates the doctrine of separation of powers."
    • See id. at 455 ("[Whether to privatize inherently governmental functions] is a political question that implicates the doctrine of separation of powers.").
  • 210
    • 79959383390 scopus 로고
    • 706
    • CI. Ct. 703, 706 (1985).
    • (1985) Ci. Ct. , vol.8 , pp. 703
  • 211
    • 79959467564 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Arrowhead metals
    • See, at, "Article 1, Section 8, clause 5 of the United States Constitution confers on Congress the power 'To coin money.' Thus, it is not unreasonable to view broadly the coining of money to be a government function".
    • See Arrowhead Metals, 8 CI. Ct. at 706 ("Article 1, Section 8, clause 5 of the United States Constitution confers on Congress the power 'To coin money.' Thus, it is not unreasonable to view broadly the coining of money to be a government function. ").
    • Ci. Ct. , vol.8 , pp. 706
  • 212
    • 79959459803 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 714 holding that "it was rational and within the Mint's discretion to determine that the issue of whether blanking was an inherently governmental function deserved further study"
    • See id. at 714 (holding that "it was rational and within the Mint's discretion to determine that [the] issue [of whether blanking was an inherently governmental function] deserved further study").
  • 213
    • 79959482908 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. deferring to the Mint's classification
    • See id. (deferring to the Mint's classification).
  • 214
    • 79959384679 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Verkuil, supra note 80, at 421 "The constitutional theories that might be employed to secure against this threat, such as the nondelegation doctrine, have been around for a long time. In addition, statutory provisions, such as the Subdelegation Act and judicial review provisions of the APA, can also play a role in controlling delegations to private hands."
    • See Verkuil, supra note 80, at 421 ("[T]he constitutional theories that might be employed to secure against this threat, such as the nondelegation doctrine, have been around for a long time. In addition, statutory provisions, such as the Subdelegation Act and judicial review provisions of the APA, can also play a role in controlling delegations to private hands.").
  • 215
    • 79959465106 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra notes 67, 82 and accompanying text
    • See supra notes 67, 82 and accompanying text
  • 216
    • 79959472933 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • But see Fisher, supra note 67, at 474-83, describing three theoretical law models opposing a state monopoly on law production
    • But see Fisher, supra note 67, at 474-83 (describing three theoretical law models opposing a state monopoly on law production);
  • 217
    • 79959448883 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Verkuil, supra note 80, at 433 n. 194 "The nondelegation doctrine has been concerned with the transfer of legislative power to the executive branch, more than with the transfer of legislative power to private hands." internal citation omitted
    • Verkuil, supra note 80, at 433 n. 194 ("The nondelegation doctrine has been concerned with the transfer of legislative power to the executive branch, more than with the transfer of legislative power to private hands." (internal citation omitted)).
  • 218
    • 79959447362 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For the roots of this approach
    • For the roots of this approach
  • 219
    • 79959460972 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see LOCKE, supra note 75, § 141, at 380-81 asserting that "the Legislative cannot transfer the Power of Making Laws to any other hands. For it being but a delegated Power from the People, they, who have it, cannot pass it over to others.... And when the People have said, We will submit to rules, and be govern'd by Laws made by such Men, and in such Forms, no Body else can say other Men shall make Laws for them; nor can the people be bound by any Laws but such as are Enacted by those, whom they have Chosen, and Authorised to make Laws for them". For a more recent treatment
    • see LOCKE, supra note 75, § 141, at 380-81 (asserting that "[t]he Legislative cannot transfer the Power of Making Laws to any other hands. For it being but a delegated Power from the People, they, who have it, cannot pass it over to others.... And when the People have said, We will submit to rules, and be govern'd by Laws made by such Men, and in such Forms, no Body else can say other Men shall make Laws for them; nor can the people be bound by any Laws but such as are Enacted by those, whom they have Chosen, and Authorised to make Laws for them"). For a more recent treatment
  • 220
    • 79959392050 scopus 로고
    • Delegation of governmental power to private parties
    • see, 52, "One aspect of the rule against delegation is that a rule-making power may not be delegated.". Several Supreme Court decisions in the 1930s endorsed the nondelegation doctrine in the context of private bothes
    • see David Lanham, Delegation of Governmental Power to Private Parties, 6 OTAGO L. REV. 50, 52 (1985) ("One aspect of the rule against delegation is that a rule-making power may not be delegated."). Several Supreme Court decisions in the 1930s endorsed the nondelegation doctrine in the context of private bothes.
    • (1985) Otago L. Rev. , vol.6 , pp. 50
    • Lanham, D.1
  • 221
    • 84858239105 scopus 로고
    • In Carter v. Carter Coal Co., 311, the Supreme Court struck down the Bituminous Coal Conservation Act also known as the Guffey-Snyder Coal Act. The Act established a commission composed of miners, coal producers, and the public to regulate fair competition, production standards, minimum wages, work hours, and labor relations in the coal industry
    • In Carter v. Carter Coal Co., 298 U. S. 238, 311 (1936), the Supreme Court struck down the Bituminous Coal Conservation Act (also known as the Guffey-Snyder Coal Act). The Act established a commission composed of miners, coal producers, and the public to regulate fair competition, production standards, minimum wages, work hours, and labor relations in the coal industry.
    • (1936) U. S. , vol.298 , pp. 238
  • 222
    • 79959407202 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 281-83, 310. In finding the act unconstitutional, the Court held that "the power conferred upon the majority is, in effect, the power to regulate the affairs of an unwilling minority. This is legislative delegation in its most obnoxious form; for it is not even delegation to an official or an official body, presumptively disinterested, but to private persons whose interests may be and often are adverse to the interests of others in the same business.... And a statute which attempts to confer such power undertakes an intolerable and unconstitutional interference with personal liberty and private property."
    • Id. at 281-83, 310. In finding the act unconstitutional, the Court held that "[t]he power conferred upon the majority is, in effect, the power to regulate the affairs of an unwilling minority. This is legislative delegation in its most obnoxious form; for it is not even delegation to an official or an official body, presumptively disinterested, but to private persons whose interests may be and often are adverse to the interests of others in the same business.... And a statute which attempts to confer such power undertakes an intolerable and unconstitutional interference with personal liberty and private property."
  • 223
    • 79959468649 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 311
    • Id. at 311.
  • 224
    • 33645943220 scopus 로고
    • In A. L. A. Schechter Poultry Corp. v. United States, 295 U. S. 495, 537-42 (1935), the Court unanimously held that the National Industrial Recovery Act, a main component of President Roosevelt's New Deal, which allowed private trade and industrial groups to write local codes for trade, was unconstitutional. In delivering the Court's opinion, Chief Justice Hughes wrote: "The Government urges that the codes will 'consist of rules of competition deemed fair for each industry by representative members of that industry - by the persons most vitally concerned and most familiar with its problems.'... But would it be seriously contended that Congress could delegate its legislative authority to trade or industrial associations or groups so as to empower them to enact the laws they deem to be wise and beneficent for the rehabilitation and expansion of their trade or industries?... The answer is obvious. Such a delegation of legislative power is unknown to our law and is utterly inconsistent with the constitutional prerogatives and duties of Congress."
    • (1935) U. S. , vol.295 , pp. 495
  • 225
    • 79959432688 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 537
    • Id. at 537;
  • 226
    • 0041425562 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Schechter poultry at the millennium: A delegation doctrine for the administrative state
    • see also, 1427-28, "The new delegation doctrine. prevents private parties from effectively assuming lawmaking authority.... Private lawmaking has a tendency to produce regulation that both interferes with individual liberty for suspect public purposes and inadequately reflects a broad public purpose to justify such interference. In this regard, private lawmaking is undemocratic even if it can be said to be efficient or rational on some other grounds."
    • see also Lisa Schultz Bressman, Schechter Poultry at the Millennium: A Delegation Doctrine for the Administrative State, 109 YALE L. J. 1399, 1427-28 (2000) ("[T]he new delegation doctrine... prevents private parties from effectively assuming lawmaking authority.... [P]rivate lawmaking has a tendency to produce regulation that both interferes with individual liberty for suspect public purposes and inadequately reflects a broad public purpose to justify such interference. In this regard, private lawmaking is undemocratic even if it can be said to be efficient or rational on some other grounds.").
    • (2000) Yale L. J. , vol.109 , pp. 1399
    • Bressman, L.S.1
  • 227
    • 79959430998 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See generally Verkuil, supra note 80, at 425-26 & n. 52 discussing nondelegable duties, including the legislature's duty to vote on bills
    • See generally Verkuil, supra note 80, at 425-26 & n. 52 (discussing nondelegable duties, including the legislature's duty to vote on bills).
  • 228
    • 79959393731 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 425-26, 449
    • See id. at 425-26, 449;
  • 229
    • 79959487948 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also, art. I, §
    • see also U. S. CONST, art. I, § 8;
    • U. S. Const , Issue.8
  • 230
    • 79959426815 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • art. II, § 2
    • art. II, § 2.
  • 231
    • 79959439175 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Of course, this decision is made in conjunction with the legislature, which has sole authority to define criminal offenses and prescribe punishment
    • Of course, this decision is made in conjunction with the legislature, which has sole authority to define criminal offenses and prescribe punishment
  • 232
    • 79959481801 scopus 로고
    • See Whalen v. United States, 689
    • See Whalen v. United States, 445 U. S. 684, 689 (1980).
    • (1980) U. S. , vol.445 , pp. 684
  • 233
    • 79959382884 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • We do not deny that legitimacy-based considerations are sometimes parasitic on the efficacy of the institution to make the right decisions. Yet we think that at least some legitimacy-based considerations are not parasitic. In particular, we establish the existence of nonparasitic legitimacy-based considerations in the context of the infliction of criminal sanctions
    • We do not deny that legitimacy-based considerations are sometimes parasitic on the efficacy of the institution to make the right decisions. Yet we think that at least some legitimacy-based considerations are not parasitic. In particular, we establish the existence of nonparasitic legitimacy-based considerations in the context of the infliction of criminal sanctions.
  • 234
    • 84884924239 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • What is wrong with inflicting shame sanctions?
    • See, 1087-92
    • See James Q. Whitman, What is Wrong with Inflicting Shame Sanctions?, 107 YALE L. J. 1055, 1087-92 (1998).
    • (1998) Yale L. J. , vol.107 , pp. 1055
    • Whitman, J.Q.1
  • 235
    • 79959435616 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra notes 74-80, 96-99
    • See supra notes 74-80, 96-99;
  • 236
    • 79959395944 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also, Isr., available at, "When the power to deny the liberty of the individual is given to a private corporation, the legitimacy of the sanction of imprisonment is undermined, since the sanction is enforced by a party that is motivated first and foremost by economic considerations - considerations that are irrelevant to the realization of the purposes of the sentence, which are public purposes."
    • see also HCJ 2605/05 Academic Ctr. of Law & Bus. v. Minister of Fin. [2009] (Isr.), available at http://elyonl.court.gov. il/files-eng/05/050/026/ n39/05026050.n39.htm ("[W]hen the power to deny the liberty of the individual is given to a private corporation, the legitimacy of the sanction of imprisonment is undermined, since the sanction is enforced by a party that is motivated first and foremost by economic considerations - considerations that are irrelevant to the realization of the purposes of the sentence, which are public purposes.");
    • (2009) Academic Ctr. of Law & Bus. V. Minister of Fin
  • 237
    • 79959414206 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • DiIulio, Jr., supra note 64, at 79 "In my judgment, to remain legitimate and morally significant, the authority to govern behind bars, to deprive citizens of their liberty, to coerce and even kill them, must remain in the hands of government authorities.... The message that 'those who abuse liberty shall live without it' is the philosophical brick and mortar of every correctional facility. That message ought to be conveyed by the offended community of law-abiding citizens, through its public agents, to the incarcerated individual."
    • DiIulio, Jr., supra note 64, at 79 ("In my judgment, to remain legitimate and morally significant, the authority to govern behind bars, to deprive citizens of their liberty, to coerce (and even kill) them, must remain in the hands of government authorities.... [T]he message that 'those who abuse liberty shall live without it' is the philosophical brick and mortar of every correctional facility. That message ought to be conveyed by the offended community of law-abiding citizens, through its public agents, to the incarcerated individual.").
  • 238
    • 15944427158 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Implementing the law by impartial agents: An exercise in tort law and international law
    • See, 4-8, discussing the characteristics of an instrumentally good agent
    • See Eyal Benvenisti & Ariel Porat, Implementing the Law by Impartial Agents: An Exercise in Tort Law and International Law, 6 THEORETICAL INQ. L. 1, 4-8 (2005) (discussing the characteristics of an instrumentally good agent).
    • (2005) Theoretical Inq. L. , vol.6 , pp. 1
    • Benvenisti, E.1    Porat, A.2
  • 239
    • 84961138181 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Why only the state may inflict criminal sanctions: The case against privately inflicted sanctions
    • We borrow this example from, 121, hereinafter Harel, Privately Inflicted Sanctions
    • We borrow this example from Alon Harel, Why Only the State May Inflict Criminal Sanctions: The Case Against Privately Inflicted Sanctions, 14 LEGAL THEORY 113, 121 (2008) [hereinafter Harel, Privately Inflicted Sanctions].
    • (2008) Legal Theory , vol.14 , pp. 113
    • Harel, A.1
  • 242
    • 62949225166 scopus 로고
    • Choosing the avenger: Some aspects of the bloodfeud in metheval Iceland and England
    • see, 162-68, stressing that in medieval England and Iceland, "the duty to take up the feud or the liability to suffer its consequences was largely a function of kinship", and elaborating on the kinship conditions which constitute a right to perform the killing
    • see William Ian Miller,. Choosing the Avenger: Some Aspects of the Bloodfeud in Metheval Iceland and England, 1 LAW and HIST. REV. 159, 162-68 (1983) (stressing that in medieval England and Iceland, "[t]he duty to take up the feud or the liability to suffer its consequences was largely a function of kinship", and elaborating on the kinship conditions which constitute a right to perform the killing).
    • (1983) Law and Hist. Rev. , vol.1 , pp. 159
    • Miller, W.I.1
  • 244
    • 0141885865 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'He'll learn it on his body': Disciplining childhood in Canadian law
    • 202, For a short description of the common law rules concerning physical disciplining of children
    • Anne McGillivray, 'He'll Learn It on His Body': Disciplining Childhood in Canadian Law, 5 INT'L J. CHILD. RTS. 193, 202 (1997). For a short description of the common law rules concerning physical disciplining of children
    • (1997) Int'l J. Child. Rts , vol.5 , pp. 193
    • McGillivray, A.1
  • 245
    • 79959457358 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see id. at 201-06
    • see id. at 201-06.
  • 246
    • 79959450052 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Justice Wilson stressed a similar point in her concurring opinion in the leading Canadian case on necessity
    • Justice Wilson stressed a similar point in her concurring opinion in the leading Canadian case on necessity.
  • 247
    • 84889820047 scopus 로고
    • See Perka v. The Queen, 276, Can. Wilson, J., concurring. Justice Wilson argued that justified necessity can apply in cases in which "it is necessary to rescue someone to whom one owes a positive duty of rescue."
    • See Perka v. The Queen, [1984] 2 S. C. R. 232, 276 (Can.) (Wilson, J., concurring). Justice Wilson argued that justified necessity can apply in cases in which "it is necessary to rescue someone to whom one owes a positive duty of rescue."
    • (1984) S. C. R. , vol.2 , pp. 232
  • 248
    • 79959442202 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. Wilson, J., concurring. In Justice Wilson's view, such a justification would not apply to strangers to whom one does not owe such a duty
    • Id. (Wilson, J., concurring). In Justice Wilson's view, such a justification would not apply to strangers to whom one does not owe such a duty.
  • 249
    • 79959471302 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. Wilson, J., concurring. It is unclear from the decision, however, whether the reason for not allowing strangers to invoke the defense of necessity is grounded, according to the Justice's view, in instrumental or noninstrumental grounds
    • Id. (Wilson, J., concurring). It is unclear from the decision, however, whether the reason for not allowing strangers to invoke the defense of necessity is grounded, according to the Justice's view, in instrumental or noninstrumental grounds.
  • 250
    • 77954025913 scopus 로고
    • Cf. Ingraham v. Wright, 662, "Although the early cases viewed the authority of the teacher as deriving from the parents, the concept of parental delegation has been replaced by the view - more consonant with compulsory education laws - that the State itself may impose such corporal punishment as is reasonably necessary for the proper education of the child and for the maintenance of group discipline." footnote and internal quotation marks omitted
    • Cf. Ingraham v. Wright, 430 U. S. 651, 662 (1977) ("Although the early cases viewed the authority of the teacher as deriving from the parents, the concept of parental delegation has been replaced by the view - more consonant with compulsory education laws - that the State itself may impose such corporal punishment as is reasonably necessary for the proper education of the child and for the maintenance of group discipline." (footnote and internal quotation marks omitted));
    • (1977) U. S. , vol.430 , pp. 651
  • 251
    • 79959482330 scopus 로고
    • Johnson v. Dep't of Soc. Servs., 53, Ct. App, acknowledging the right of parents to discipline children but distinguishing it from "the delegation by the parents to third parties... of the rights of discipline by corporal punishment" in upholding a regulation prohibiting corporal punishment by daycare centers
    • Johnson v. Dep't of Soc. Servs., 177 Cal. Rptr. 49, 53 (Ct. App. 1981) (acknowledging the right of parents to discipline children but distinguishing it from "the delegation by the parents to third parties... of the rights of discipline by corporal punishment" in upholding a regulation prohibiting corporal punishment by daycare centers).
    • (1981) Cal. Rptr. , vol.177 , pp. 49
  • 252
    • 0037975258 scopus 로고
    • The expressive function of punishment
    • 74, R. A. Duff &: David Garland eds.
    • Joel Feinberg, The Expressive Function of Punishment, in A READER ON PUNISHMENT 73, 74 (R. A. Duff &: David Garland eds., 1994).
    • (1994) A Reader on Punishment , pp. 73
    • Feinberg, J.1
  • 253
    • 79959436204 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 76
    • See id. at 76.
  • 255
    • 79959395944 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, Isr., available at
    • See HCJ 2605/05 Academic Ctr. of Law & Bus. v. Minister of Fin. [2009] (Isr.), available at http://elyonl.courtgov. il/files-eng/05/050/026/n39/ 05026050.n39.htm.
    • (2009) Academic Ctr. of Law & Bus. V. Minister of Fin
  • 257
    • 33748668213 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The last executioner
    • Cf, Jan. 18, noting that although he was an employee of New York State, "it had become common practice for Sing Sing's executioner to freelance elsewhere" and to oversee executions in other states requesting his services
    • Cf. Jennifer Gonnerman, The Last Executioner, VILLAGE VOICE (Jan. 18, 2005), http://www.villagevoice.com/content/printVersion/188926/ (noting that although he was an employee of New York State, "[i]t had become common practice for Sing Sing's executioner to freelance elsewhere" and to oversee executions in other states requesting his services);
    • (2005) Village Voice
    • Gonnerman, J.1
  • 258
    • 76649105920 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Lethal injection and the problem of constitutional remethes
    • see also, 304-05, discussing Missouri's former lethal injection protocol, whereby neither politicians nor Department of Corrections officials designed the lethal injection procedure and instead delegated the responsibility to "an independent contractor. who had complete discretion to change the procedure at a moment's notice" internal quotation marks omitted
    • see also Eric Berger, Lethal Injection and the Problem of Constitutional Remethes, 27 YALE L. & POL'Y REV. 259, 304-05 (2009) (discussing Missouri's former lethal injection protocol, whereby neither politicians nor Department of Corrections officials designed the lethal injection procedure and instead delegated the responsibility to "an independent contractor... [who] had complete discretion to change the procedure at a moment's notice" (internal quotation marks omitted)).
    • (2009) Yale L. & Pol'y Rev. , vol.27 , pp. 259
    • Berger, E.1
  • 259
    • 79959390902 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the methods of payment of executioners in England
    • On the methods of payment of executioners in England
  • 260
    • 85050788320 scopus 로고
    • The executioner: His place in english society
    • see, 238-40
    • see Gerald D. Robin, The Executioner: His Place in English Society, 15 BRIT. J. SOC. 234, 238-40 (1964).
    • (1964) Brit. J. Soc. , vol.15 , pp. 234
    • Robin, G.D.1
  • 262
    • 0002921553 scopus 로고
    • Two concepts of rules
    • 3, footnote omitted
    • John Rawls, Two Concepts of Rules, 64 PHIL. REV. 3, 3 (1955) (footnote omitted).
    • (1955) Phil. Rev. , vol.64 , pp. 3
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 263
    • 79959457930 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 6-7, 10-13
    • See id. at 6-7, 10-13.
  • 264
    • 79959393730 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • APPLBAUM, supra note 118, at 39-41
    • APPLBAUM, supra note 118, at 39-41.
  • 265
    • 79959407723 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 41
    • Id. at 41.
  • 266
    • 0001901842 scopus 로고
    • See, Christopher Betts trans., Oxford Univ. Press, 1762 "The purpose of the social treaty is the preservation of the contracting parties. He who wills an end wills the means to that end: and the means in this case necessarily involves some risk, and even some loss. He who wills that his life may be preserved at the expense of others must also, when necessary, give his life for their sake.... And when the ruler has said: 'It is in the state's interest that you should die', he must the, because it is only on this condition that he has hitherto lived in safety, his life being no longer only a benefit due to nature, but a conditional gift of the state."
    • See JEAN-JACQUES ROUSSEAU, DISCOURSE ON POLITICAL ECONOMY AND THE SOCIAL CONTRACT 71 (Christopher Betts trans., Oxford Univ. Press 1994) (1762) ("The purpose of the social treaty is the preservation of the contracting parties. He who wills an end wills the means to that end: and the means in this case necessarily involves some risk, and even some loss. He who wills that his life may be preserved at the expense of others must also, when necessary, give his life for their sake.... [A]nd when the ruler has said: 'It is in the state's interest that you should die', he must the, because it is only on this condition that he has hitherto lived in safety, his life being no longer only a benefit due to nature, but a conditional gift of the state.").
    • (1994) Discourse on Political Economy and the Social Contract , pp. 71
    • Jean-Jacques, R.1
  • 267
    • 0003956640 scopus 로고
    • Cf, "A person who forces another to act in a certain way, and therefore one who coerces another, makes him act against his will. He subjects the will of another to his own and thereby invades that person's autonomy."
    • Cf. JOSEPH RAZ, THE MORALITY OF FREEDOM 154 (1986) ("A person who forces another to act in a certain way, and therefore one who coerces another, makes him act against his will. He subjects the will of another to his own and thereby invades that person's autonomy.").
    • (1986) The Morality of Freedom , pp. 154
    • Raz, J.1
  • 268
    • 79959390303 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is the general rule in international law
    • This is the general rule in international law.
  • 270
    • 79959383389 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Among the doctrinal implications of this view is the hostile attitude towards mercenaries
    • Among the doctrinal implications of this view is the hostile attitude towards mercenaries.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.