메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 2010, Issue 2, 2010, Pages 673-718

Three conceptions of law: Towards a jurisprudence of democratic experimentalism

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 78650809455     PISSN: 0043650X     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: None     Document Type: Conference Paper
Times cited : (24)

References (214)
  • 1
    • 27744557047 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The emergence of global administrative law
    • Summer/Autumn
    • See, e.g., Benedict Kingsbury et al., The Emergence of Global Administrative Law, LAW & CONTEMP. PROBS., Summer/Autumn 2005, at 15.
    • (2005) Law & Contemp. Probs. , pp. 15
    • Kingsbury, B.1
  • 2
    • 0011525097 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • European administrative law and the global challenge
    • In the European context, see, e.g., Paul Craig & Gráinne de Burea eds.
    • In the European context, see, e.g., Carol Harlow, European Administrative Law and the Global Challenge, in THE EVOLUTION OF EU LAW 261 (Paul Craig & Gráinne de Burea eds., 1999).
    • (1999) The Evolution of EU Law , pp. 261
    • Harlow, C.1
  • 3
    • 84919552778 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • EU constitutionalism and new governance
    • 15-16 Gráinne de Búrea & Joanne Scott eds.
    • See, e.g., Neil Walker, EU Constitutionalism and New Governance, in LAW AND NEW GOVERNANCE IN THE EU AND THE US 15, 15-16 (Gráinne de Búrea & Joanne Scott eds., 2006).
    • (2006) Law and New Governance in the EU and the US , pp. 15
    • Walker, N.1
  • 4
    • 84979103695 scopus 로고
    • The effectiveness of european community law: Institutions, processes, tools and techniques
    • 31-36
    • See, e.g., Francis Snyder, The Effectiveness of European Community Law: Institutions, Processes, Tools and Techniques, 56 MOD. L. REV. 19, 31-36 (1993).
    • (1993) Mod. L. Rev. , vol.56 , pp. 19
    • Snyder, F.1
  • 5
    • 55849125766 scopus 로고
    • Substantive and reflexive elements in modem law
    • 243-44
    • See, e.g., Günther Teubner, Substantive and Reflexive Elements in Modem Law, 17 LAW & SOC'Y REV. 239, 243-44 (1983).
    • (1983) Law & Soc'y Rev. , vol.17 , pp. 239
    • Teubner, G.1
  • 6
    • 36749017514 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Global legal pluralism
    • See, e.g., Paul Berman, Global Legal Pluralism, 80 S. CAL. L. REV. 1155 (2007).
    • (2007) S. Cal. L. Rev. , vol.80 , pp. 1155
    • Berman, P.1
  • 7
    • 85017285588 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Directly-deliberative polyarchy
    • See, e.g., Joshua Cohen & Charles Sabel, Directly-Deliberative Polyarchy, 3 EUR. L.J. 313 (1997);
    • (1997) Eur. L.J. , vol.3 , pp. 313
    • Cohen, J.1    Sabel, C.2
  • 8
    • 0346155286 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A constitution of democratic experimentalism
    • and, for the U.S. perspective, Michael C. Dorf & Charles F. Sabel, A Constitution of Democratic Experimentalism, 98 COLUM. L. REV. 267(1998).
    • (1998) Colum. L. Rev. , vol.98 , pp. 267
    • Dorf, M.C.1    Sabel, C.F.2
  • 9
    • 84923037815 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The claim that conceptual enquiry is the proper methodological approach to legal theory has recently been staunchly defended by Joseph Raz.
    • The claim that conceptual enquiry is the proper methodological approach to legal theory has recently been staunchly defended by Joseph Raz. JOSEPH RAZ, BETWEEN AUTHORITY AND INTERPRETATION: ON THE THEORY OF LAW AND PRACTICAL REASON 17-46 (2009).
    • (2009) Between Authority and Interpretation: On the Theory of Law and Practical Reason , pp. 17-46
    • Raz, J.1
  • 10
    • 53949120579 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Reconceiving law and new governance
    • 519
    • See Neil Walker & Gráinne de Burea, Reconceiving Law and New Governance, 13 COLUM. J. EUR. L. 519, 519 (2007).
    • (2007) Colum. J. Eur. L. , vol.13 , pp. 519
    • Walker, N.1    De Burea, G.2
  • 11
    • 84936068266 scopus 로고
    • This accords more or less with Dworkin's distinction between concept and conception. See RONALD DWORKIN, LAW'S EMPIRE 70-72 (1986).
    • (1986) Law's Empire , pp. 70-72
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 12
    • 33748926618 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It is worth noting, however, that contra Dworkin, no assumption is made here that what he terms the "sociological concept of law" is theoretically uninteresting. See RONALD DWORKIN, JUSTICE IN ROBES 2-6 (2006).
    • (2006) Justice in Robes , pp. 2-6
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 13
    • 78650805837 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Gráinne de Burea & Joanne Scott eds.
    • The literature is, by now, huge. See LAW AND NEW GOVERNANCE IN THE EU AND THE US ix-x (Gráinne de Burea & Joanne Scott eds., 2006) (listing the numerous contributions to the work).
    • (2006) Law and New Governance in the EU and the US
  • 14
    • 33644907486 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Extra rempublicam nulla justitia?
    • See Joshua Cohen & Charles Sabel, Extra Rempublicam Nulla Justitia?, 34 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 147 (2006) (a powerful piece against Nagel's rejection of the idea of global justice).
    • (2006) Phil. & Pub. Aff. , vol.34 , pp. 147
    • Cohen, J.1    Sabel, C.2
  • 16
    • 78650830099 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., supra note 11.
    • See, e.g., supra note 11.
  • 17
    • 0013174357 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Pragmatism and democracy: Reconstructing the logic of John Dewey's faith
    • Morris Dickstein ed.
    • For a relatively recent exploration of Dewey's political philosophy see Robert B. Westbrook, Pragmatism and Democracy: Reconstructing the Logic of John Dewey's Faith, in THE REVIVAL OF PRAGMATISM: NEW ESSAYS ON SOCIAL THOUGHT, LAW, AND CULTURE 128 (Morris Dickstein ed., 1998).
    • (1998) The Revival of Pragmatism: New Essays on Social Thought, Law, and Culture , pp. 128
    • Westbrook, R.B.1
  • 19
    • 34247664182 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Security, social control, democracy and migration within the "Constitution" of the EU
    • It is interesting that "new governance" is used in Europe with its Foucaultian connotations of "governmentality." The terminology is problematic. Democratic experimentalism is far more attractive as an ideal term, not only because it avoids the connotations of "governmentality" but also because it suggests action from "the bottom-up" rather than the "top-down." The problem of what new governance actually is cannot of course be overcome by way of typological fiat. Note Rorty's quip that Foucault is traveling down a road at the end of which Dewey is waiting! See Danilo Melossi, Security, Social Control, Democracy and Migration within the "Constitution" of the EU, 11 EUR. L.J. 5, 6-7 (2005).
    • (2005) Eur. L.J. , vol.11 , pp. 5
    • Melossi, D.1
  • 22
    • 78650842717 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 3.
    • Id. at 3.
  • 23
    • 78650822055 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In the U.S. context, see Dorf & Sabel, pra note 7.
    • In the U.S. context, see Dorf & Sabel, pra note 7.
  • 24
    • 34247461629 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Civil society and the Re-imagination of European Constitutionalism
    • See Michael A. Wilkinson, Civil Society and the Re-Imagination of European Constitutionalism, 9 EUR. L.J. 451 (2003).
    • (2003) Eur. L.J. , vol.9 , pp. 451
    • Wilkinson, M.A.1
  • 26
    • 11244303709 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Renew deal: The fall of regulation and the rise of governance in contemporary legal thought
    • This inevitably provokes a further preliminary query about new governance: is all of this really that new? Are we merely mapping terrain that is actually quite old? For an examination of the historical background of new governance in the U.S., see Orly Lobel, Renew Deal: The Fall of Regulation and the Rise of Governance in Contemporary Legal Thought, 89 MINN. L. REV. 342 (2004).
    • (2004) Minn. L. Rev. , vol.89 , pp. 342
    • Lobel, O.1
  • 27
    • 11244267216 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Setting the agenda for new governance research
    • 506
    • It is not in all cases newness in terms of the existence of certain governance phenomenon, it is the newness of their recognition as playing a central role in public life that is important. Orly Lobel, Surreply: Setting the Agenda for New Governance Research, MINN. L. REV. 498, 506 (2004).
    • (2004) Minn. L. Rev. , pp. 498
    • Lobel, O.1
  • 29
    • 85191126729 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Epilogue: Accountability without sovereignty
    • Gráinne de Búrea & Joanne Scott eds.
    • See Charles F. Sabel & William H. Simon, Epilogue: Accountability Without Sovereignty, in LAW AND NEW GOVERNANCE IN THE EU AND THE US 395 (Gráinne de Búrea & Joanne Scott eds., 2006).
    • (2006) Law and New Governance in the EU and the US , pp. 395
    • Sabel, C.F.1    Simon, W.H.2
  • 30
    • 0004220262 scopus 로고
    • Unfortunately this alleged and apparent orthodoxy of legal thought is not elaborated upon. It is unfortunate because few contemporary legal positivists use the terminology of command-and-control. It was of course Hart who developed his theory in contradistinction eo the classical command theory of Austin and Bentham. See H.L.A. HART, THE CONCEPT OF LAW 16-17 (1961).
    • (1961) The Concept of Law , pp. 16-17
    • Hart, H.L.A.1
  • 31
    • 78650810977 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • de Burea & Scott, Supra note 18, at 9.
    • de Burea & Scott, Supra note 18, at 9.
  • 32
    • 78650807589 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Sabel & Simon, Supra note 25, at 395 (emphasis added).
    • See Sabel & Simon, Supra note 25, at 395 (emphasis added).
  • 33
    • 78650816771 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 396 (quotation marks omitted).
    • Id. at 396 (quotation marks omitted).
  • 34
    • 78650832479 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id.
  • 35
    • 78650809182 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id.
  • 36
    • 78650810978 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 398.
    • Id. at 398.
  • 37
    • 78650807317 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id.
  • 38
    • 78650839027 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 400.
    • Id. at 400.
  • 39
    • 0010916706 scopus 로고
    • (Bonnie Litschewski Paulson & Stanley L. Paulson trans., 1992)
    • Few in the jurisprudential tradition have actually suggested that this can be a strict distinction. Even a formalist such as Hans Kelsen conceived the distinction between lawmaking and law application to be blurred. See HANS KELSEN, INTRODUCTION TO THE PROBLEMS OF LEGAL THEORY 67-68 (Bonnie Litschewski Paulson & Stanley L. Paulson trans., 1992) (1934).
    • (1934) Introduction to the Problems of Legal Theory , pp. 67-68
    • Kelsen, H.1
  • 40
    • 78650848996 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Sabel & Simon, supra note 25, at 400.
    • See Sabel & Simon, supra note 25, at 400.
  • 41
    • 78650841583 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Another example they use is employment strategy. In the EU, European Employment Strategy (EES) reaches into areas of macro-economic policy that would anyway be outside of the scope of traditional legal control. Id.
    • Another example they use is employment strategy. In the EU, European Employment Strategy (EES) reaches into areas of macro-economic policy that would anyway be outside of the scope of traditional legal control. Id.
  • 42
    • 78650816405 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • At least in the EES it is subject to some outside discipline, in the sense that other States and non-state interests are concerned and involved as interested participants in the process of peer review. Id.
    • At least in the EES it is subject to some outside discipline, in the sense that other States and non-state interests are concerned and involved as interested participants in the process of peer review. Id.
  • 43
    • 78650810982 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 402.
    • Id. at 402.
  • 44
    • 78650819134 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id.
  • 45
    • 76749148751 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Courts as catalysts: Re-thinking the judicial role in new governance
    • The significance of using the courts to encourage and facilitate democratic experimentalism has been explored by
    • The significance of using the courts to encourage and facilitate democratic experimentalism has been explored by Joanne Scott and Susan Sturm, Courts as Catalysts: Re-Thinking the Judicial Role in New Governance, 13 COLUM. J. EUR. L. 565 (2007).
    • (2007) Colum. J. Eur. L. , vol.13 , pp. 565
    • Scott, J.1    Sturm, S.2
  • 46
    • 78650817277 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • de Burea & Scott, Supra note 18, at 10.
    • de Burea & Scott, Supra note 18, at 10.
  • 47
    • 78650803528 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 9.
    • Id. at 9.
  • 48
    • 49349111521 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Positivism, formalism, realism
    • (reviewing ANTHONY SEBOK, LEGAL POSITIVISM IN AMERICAN JURISPRUDENCE (1998)).
    • See, e.g., Brian Leiter, Positivism, Formalism, Realism, 99 COLUM. L. REV. 1138 (1999) (reviewing ANTHONY SEBOK, LEGAL POSITIVISM IN AMERICAN JURISPRUDENCE (1998)).
    • (1999) Colum. L. Rev. , vol.99 , pp. 1138
    • Leiter, B.1
  • 49
    • 78650811257 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Do philosophy and sociology mix? A non-essentialist, socio-legal positivist analysis of the concept of law
    • See, e.g., Kenneth Himma, Do Philosophy and Sociology Mix? A Non-Essentialist, Socio-Legal Positivist Analysis of the Concept of Law, 24 OXFORD J. LEGAL STUD. 717(2004).
    • (2004) Oxford J. Legal Stud. , vol.24 , pp. 717
    • Himma, K.1
  • 50
    • 78650808669 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Earlier work examining some of the implications of Weber's broader understanding of the nature of social science on his legal sociology was undertaken by David Trubek and Anthony Kronman. See, e.g., ANTHONY T. KRONMAN, MAX WEBER (1983)
    • Earlier work examining some of the implications of Weber's broader understanding of the nature of social science on his legal sociology was undertaken by David Trubek and Anthony Kronman. See, e.g., ANTHONY T. KRONMAN, MAX WEBER (1983);
  • 51
    • 84928448949 scopus 로고
    • Max Weber's tragic modernism and the study of law in society
    • (reviewing ANTHONY T. KRONMAN, MAX WEBER (1983)).
    • David M. Trubek, Max Weber's Tragic Modernism and the Study of Law in Society, 20 LAW & SOC'Y REV. 573 (1986) (reviewing ANTHONY T. KRONMAN, MAX WEBER (1983)).
    • (1986) Law & Soc'y Rev. , vol.20 , pp. 573
    • Trubek, D.M.1
  • 52
    • 78650827078 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a historical overview in the U.S. context, see Lobel, supra note 23.
    • For a historical overview in the U.S. context, see Lobel, supra note 23.
  • 53
    • 0038468408 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Administrative law in the twenty-first century
    • See also Richard Stewart, Administrative Law in the Twenty-First Century, 78 N.Y.U. L. REV. 437 (2003).
    • (2003) N.Y.U. L. Rev. , vol.78 , pp. 437
    • Stewart, R.1
  • 54
    • 78650838029 scopus 로고
    • (Frida Laski & Harold Laski trans., Howard Fertig, Inc. ed. 1970)
    • LEON DuGuIT, LAW IN THE MODERN STATE XXXV (Frida Laski & Harold Laski trans., Howard Fertig, Inc. ed. 1970) (1919). The public law theory of Duguit eschewed both analytical positivism and the idealistic holism of the natural law represented by the organic state theory of the nineteenth century. Id.
    • (1919) Law in the Modern State XXXV
    • Duguit, L.1
  • 55
    • 57349107345 scopus 로고
    • The sociology of law
    • 144
    • Eugen Ehrlich, The Sociology of Law, 36 HARV. L. REV. 129, 144 (1922) (emphasis added).
    • (1922) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.36 , pp. 129
    • Ehrlich, E.1
  • 56
    • 78650830098 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 136. Ehrlich continues: It cannot limit itself to the Legal Provision as such. It must consider the whole of law in its social relations and must also fit the Legal Provision into this social setting. Id. at 144.
    • Id. at 136. Ehrlich continues: "It cannot limit itself to the Legal Provision as such. It must consider the whole of law in its social relations and must also fit the Legal Provision into this social setting." Id. at 144.
  • 57
    • 78650813409 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 137.
    • Id. at 137.
  • 58
    • 78650832212 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 139-40. Which, Ehrlich says, are hardly noticed by [his] contemporaries.
    • Id. at 139-40. Which, Ehrlich says, are "hardly noticed by [his] contemporaries."
  • 59
    • 78650825147 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 140.
    • Id. at 140.
  • 60
    • 78650835550 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • There is in this sense an obvious connection between the functionalism of the early legal sociologists and the later systems theory of Luhmann and Teubner. See Teubner, supra note 5, at 243-44.
    • There is in this sense an obvious connection between the functionalism of the early legal sociologists and the later systems theory of Luhmann and Teubner. See Teubner, supra note 5, at 243-44.
  • 61
    • 84972620169 scopus 로고
    • The political content of legal theory
    • 4
    • See Leslie Green, The Political Content of Legal Theory, 17 PHIL. SOC. SCI. 1, 4(1987).
    • (1987) Phil. Soc. Sci. , vol.17 , pp. 1
    • Green, L.1
  • 62
    • 78650807186 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1-4.
    • Id. at 1-4.
  • 63
    • 65149103964 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The functionalist style in public law
    • See generally Martin Loughlin, The Functionalist Style in Public Law, 55 U. TORONTO L.J. 361 (2005) (examining the functionalist style in public law, identifying it with a broadly leftist political ideology).
    • (2005) U. Toronto L.J. , vol.55 , pp. 361
    • Loughlin, M.1
  • 64
    • 0003529325 scopus 로고
    • Of course, functionalism need not necessarily eschew this kind of conceptual approach to legal theory. It might be claimed that function and essence coincide, if law's essential features are whatever best serves the purpose it represents in an Aristotelian manner of functionalism. See, e.g.
    • Of course, functionalism need not necessarily eschew this kind of conceptual approach to legal theory. It might be claimed that function and essence coincide, if law's essential features are whatever best serves the purpose it represents in an Aristotelian manner of functionalism. See, e.g., JOHN FINNIS, NATURAL LAW AND NATURAL RIGHTS (1980).
    • (1980) Natural Law and Natural Rights
    • Finnis, J.1
  • 65
    • 0039631961 scopus 로고
    • Transcendental nonsense and the functional approach
    • 812
    • See Felix Cohen, Transcendental Nonsense and the Functional Approach, 35 COLUM. L. REV. 809, 812 (1935).
    • (1935) Colum. L. Rev. , vol.35 , pp. 809
    • Cohen, F.1
  • 66
    • 78650823784 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Loughlin, supra note 54, at 363 (internal quotation marks removed).
    • See Loughlin, supra note 54, at 363 (internal quotation marks removed).
  • 67
    • 78650821479 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Roscoe Pound wrote an introduction to Ehrlich's Harvard Law Review essay. See Ehrlich, Supra note 47, at 129-30.
    • Roscoe Pound wrote an introduction to Ehrlich's Harvard Law Review essay. See Ehrlich, Supra note 47, at 129-30.
  • 69
    • 77957234344 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • St. John's U. Legal Studies Research Paper Series, Paper No. 05-011, available at (citation omitted). According to Tamanaha, the pragmatists who dominated the law teaching of the 1960s were united in favoring this kind of approach to law, sensing that this meant law was essentially a matter of balancing interests.
    • Brian Z. Tamanaha, The Perils of Pervasive Legal Instrumentalism 28 (St. John's U. Legal Studies Research Paper Series, Paper No. 05-011, 2005), available at http://ssrn.com/abstract=725582 (citation omitted). According to Tamanaha, the pragmatists who dominated the law teaching of the 1960s were united in favoring this kind of approach to law, sensing that this meant law was essentially a matter of "balancing interests."
    • (2005) The Perils of Pervasive Legal Instrumentalism , pp. 28
    • Tamanaha, B.Z.1
  • 70
    • 78650813410 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 42 (citation omitted).
    • Id. at 42 (citation omitted).
  • 71
    • 78650835852 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 28, 45-46. According to Tamanaha, by the 1970s, Legal instrumentalist views . . . had won over the legal academy. And this occurred in a context of society-wide, group-based disagreement over moral values and the public good, seemingly made worse owing to a loss of belief in the availability of objective standards by which to resolve such disputes.
    • Id. at 28, 45-46. According to Tamanaha, by the 1970s, Legal instrumentalist views . . . had won over the legal academy. And this occurred in a context of society-wide, group-based disagreement over moral values and the public good, seemingly made worse owing to a loss of belief in the availability of objective standards by which to resolve such disputes.
  • 72
    • 78650815025 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 45. The critical question is whether the functional approach teaches all manner of men to look to law as an instrument for their private or personal disposal
    • Id. at 45. The critical question is whether the functional approach teaches "all manner of men to look to law as an instrument for their private or personal disposal?"
  • 73
    • 78650847123 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id.
  • 74
    • 78650815295 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Loughlin, supra note 54, at 368.
    • See Loughlin, supra note 54, at 368.
  • 76
    • 78650808896 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Intriguingly, although Haas does refer to the earlier legal functionalists such as Duguit, he pays relatively scant attention to the function of law in the integration process. In his concern with process and with becoming, Haas's jurisprudential reflections begin, "it is understandable that the Functionalist should devote little attention to law, and indeed should minimize its role in the gradual unveiling of the immanent world community." Id. at 40.
    • Intriguingly, although Haas does refer to the earlier legal functionalists such as Duguit, he pays relatively scant attention to the function of law in the integration process. "In his concern with process and with becoming," Haas's jurisprudential reflections begin, "it is understandable that the Functionalist should devote little attention to law, and indeed should minimize its role in the gradual unveiling of the immanent world community." Id. at 40.
  • 77
    • 18444365890 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rethinking law in neo-functionalist theory
    • 310-12
    • For a more recent appraisal of law in neo-functionalism, see generally Gráinne de Burea, Rethinking Law in Neo-Functionalist Theory, 12 J. EUR. PUB. POL'Y 310, 310-12 (2005).
    • (2005) J. Eur. Pub. Pol'y , vol.12 , pp. 310
    • De Burea, G.1
  • 78
    • 85191128350 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sonft; Law, "hard law, " and EU integration
    • 69-76 Gráinne de Burea & Joanne Scott eds.
    • See, e.g., David Trubek et al., "Sonft; Law, " "Hard Law, " and EU Integration, in LAW AND NEW GOVERNANCE IN THE EU AND THE US 65, 69-76 (Gráinne de Burea & Joanne Scott eds., 2006).
    • (2006) Law and New Governance in the EU and the US , pp. 65
    • Trubek, D.1
  • 79
    • 78650812896 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It is remarkable, however, how prescient much of the pluralist analysis seems in the light of the decline of the nation-state in the latter half of the century.
    • It is remarkable, however, how prescient much of the pluralist analysis seems in the light of the decline of the nation-state in the latter half of the century.
  • 80
    • 47849120789 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New governance and legal regulation: Complementarity, rivalry, and transformation
    • David Trubek and Louise Trubek explicitly suggest their relational typology of law and new governance to be based on a functional analysis. See 544
    • David Trubek and Louise Trubek explicitly suggest their relational typology of law and new governance to be based on a functional analysis. See Dave Trubek & Louise Trubek, New Governance and Legal Regulation: Complementarity, Rivalry, and Transformation, 13 COLUM. J. EUR. L. 539, 544 n.12 (2007).
    • (2007) Colum. J. Eur. L. , vol.13 , Issue.12 , pp. 539
    • Trubek, D.1    Trubek, L.2
  • 81
    • 78650828400 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • However, de Burea and Scott in fact suggest that the theses they identify have a descriptive and a normative dimension, de Búrea & Scott, supra note 18, at 4.
    • However, de Burea and Scott in fact suggest that the theses they identify have a descriptive and a normative dimension, de Búrea & Scott, supra note 18, at 4.
  • 82
    • 78650831979 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Moreover, they proffer a framework for thinking not only about the actual nature and role of law in new governance, but also about its potential nature and role. Id.
    • Moreover, they proffer "a framework for thinking not only about the actual nature and role of law in new governance, but also about its potential nature and role." Id.
  • 83
    • 78650807313 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • They then go on to distinguish descriptive, explanatory and normative dimensions of the various typological components. Id. at 4-10.
    • They then go on to distinguish descriptive, explanatory and normative dimensions of the various typological components. Id. at 4-10.
  • 84
    • 53949083723 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Introduction to narrowing the gap? Law and new approaches to governance in the European Union
    • Elsewhere, de Burea and Scott suggest a focus on both functions and values. See 514
    • Elsewhere, de Burea and Scott suggest a focus on both functions and values. See Gráinne de Búrea & Joanne Scott, Introduction to Narrowing the Gap? Law and New Approaches to Governance in the European Union,13 COLUM. J. EUR. L. 513, 514 (2007).
    • (2007) Colum. J. Eur. L. , vol.13 , pp. 513
    • De Búrea, G.1    Scott, J.2
  • 85
    • 57649231034 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Learning from difference: The new architecture of experimentalist governance in the EU
    • 274
    • Charles Sabel & Jonathan Zeitlin, Learning From Difference: The New Architecture of Experimentalist Governance in the EU, 14 EUR. L.J. 271, 274 (2008).
    • (2008) Eur. L.J. , vol.14 , pp. 271
    • Sabel, C.1    Zeitlin, J.2
  • 86
    • 78650844710 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • According to Sabel and Zeitlin, the experimentalist architecture contains no one-to-one mapping of governance functions to specific institutional mechanisms or policy instruments, and vice versa. Id.
    • According to Sabel and Zeitlin, the experimentalist architecture contains "no one-to-one mapping of governance functions to specific institutional mechanisms or policy instruments, and vice versa." Id.
  • 87
    • 78650837484 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Deliberation is geared towards understanding and learning from difference rather than achieving substantive consensus. Informalism, in terms of the "mutability of institutions" and absence of formal sanctions, is more an impression than a reality. Id.
    • Deliberation is geared towards understanding and learning from difference rather than achieving substantive consensus. Informalism, in terms of the "mutability of institutions" and absence of formal sanctions, is more an impression than a reality. Id.
  • 88
    • 78650837753 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In seeking to expose and clarify difference, continuous institutional revision is in reality often highly formalized, as in the case of the procedural requirements stipulated in EU directives or the emerging body of EU administrative law, which exists to control unbridled discretion and illegitimate delegations of power. Id. at 275.
    • In seeking to expose and clarify difference, "continuous institutional revision" is in reality often highly formalized, as in the case of the procedural requirements stipulated in EU directives or the emerging body of EU administrative law, which exists to control unbridled discretion and illegitimate delegations of power. Id. at 275.
  • 89
    • 78650840879 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Finally, multi-level governance is not simply a consequence of attempts to overcome blockages due to the institutional status quo or an impasse in the conflicting array of political preferences but is a reflection of a "division of labour inherent in a recursive conception of rule making." Id.
    • Finally, multi-level governance is not simply a consequence of attempts to overcome blockages due to the institutional status quo or an impasse in the conflicting array of political preferences but is a reflection of a "division of labour inherent in a recursive conception of rule making." Id.
  • 90
    • 84855541830 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Law and new environmental governance in the European Union
    • Gráinne de Búrea & Joanne Scott eds.
    • See, e.g., Joanne Scott & Jane Holder, Law and New Environmental Governance in the European Union, in LAW AND NEW GOVERNANCE IN THE EU AND THE US 211 (Gráinne de Búrea & Joanne Scott eds., 2006).
    • (2006) Law and New Governance in the EU and the US 211
    • Scott, J.1    Holder, J.2
  • 91
    • 34548543228 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Experimental governance: The open method of coordination
    • See, e.g., Erika Szyszczak, Experimental Governance: The Open Method of Coordination, 12 EUR. L.J. 486 (2006).
    • (2006) Eur. L.J. , vol.12 , pp. 486
    • Szyszczak, E.1
  • 92
    • 33747345894 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Why there is a democratic deficit in the EU: A response to Majone and Moravcsik
    • For a powerful argument against a pure efficiency-based understanding of problems of European integration, see, e.g.
    • For a powerful argument against a pure efficiency-based understanding of problems of European integration, see, e.g., Andreas Follesdal & Simon Hix, Why There is a Democratic Deficit in the EU: A Response to Majone and Moravcsik, 44 J. COMMON MKT. STUD. 533 (2006).
    • (2006) J. Common Mkt. Stud. , vol.44 , pp. 533
    • Follesdal, A.1    Hix, S.2
  • 93
    • 78650846873 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See de Burea & Scott, supra note 18, at 4.
    • See de Burea & Scott, supra note 18, at 4.
  • 94
    • 78650830909 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • de Búrea and Scott observe descriptive, explanatory, and normative interpretation of the gap thesis. Id. at 4-6.
    • de Búrea and Scott observe descriptive, explanatory, and normative interpretation of the gap thesis. Id. at 4-6.
  • 95
    • 85015993726 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Mind the gap: Law and the new approaches to governance in the european union
    • 8
    • See Joanne Scott & David Trubek, Mind the Gap: Law and the New Approaches to Governance in the European Union, 8 EUR. L.J. 1, 8 (2002).
    • (2002) Eur. L.J. , vol.8 , pp. 1
    • Scott, J.1    Trubek, D.2
  • 96
    • 78650807870 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Community law has always had an unorthodox, or even sui generic quality about it, not least because of the unusual composition and diverse array of institutions behind the law-making process, the unorthodox inter-institutional relationships, and complex networks of political and legal power that are configured in the processes of integration. See, e.g., WEILER, Supra note 24.
    • Community law has always had an unorthodox, or even sui generic quality about it, not least because of the unusual composition and diverse array of institutions behind the law-making process, the unorthodox inter-institutional relationships, and complex networks of political and legal power that are configured in the processes of integration. See, e.g., WEILER, Supra note 24.
  • 97
    • 78650825693 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Scott & Trubek, Supra note 74, at 9.
    • See Scott & Trubek, Supra note 74, at 9.
  • 98
    • 78650819411 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Treaty on the Functioning of the European Union, art. 267.
    • Treaty on the Functioning of the European Union, art. 267.
  • 99
    • 78650849524 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Scott & Trubek, supra note 74, at 9.
    • Scott & Trubek, supra note 74, at 9.
  • 100
    • 78650824875 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id.
  • 101
    • 78650827076 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See infra Part V.
    • See infra Part V.
  • 102
    • 33745789344 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Democratic experimentalism or capitalist synchronisation? Critical reflections on directly-deliberative polyarchy
    • 103
    • See William E. Scheuerman, Democratic Experimentalism or Capitalist Synchronisation? Critical Reflections on Directly-Deliberative Polyarchy, 17 CANADIAN J.L. & JURISDICTION 101, 103 (2004) (stating a broadly sympathetic criticism of democratic experimentalism along the lines that it reflects the interests of capitalist rather than democratic development).
    • (2004) Canadian J.L. & Jurisdiction , vol.17 , pp. 101
    • Scheuerman, W.E.1
  • 103
    • 49349105630 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Law after the welfare state: Formalism, functionalism, and the ironic turn of reflexive law
    • 800
    • See Peer Zumbansen, Law After the Welfare State: Formalism, Functionalism, and the Ironic Turn of Reflexive Law, 56 AM. J. COMP. L. 769, 800 (2008).
    • (2008) Am. J. Comp. L. , vol.56 , pp. 769
    • Zumbansen, P.1
  • 104
    • 0035586519 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Reflexive law and the challenges of globalisation
    • 95
    • William E. Scheuerman, Reflexive Law and the Challenges of Globalisation, 9 J. POL. PHIL. 81, 95 (2001).
    • (2001) J. Pol. Phil. , vol.9 , pp. 81
    • Scheuerman, W.E.1
  • 105
    • 78650835548 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Scheuerman was quite sanguine about banking self-regulation although he also noted the democratic deficiencies of G-10 attempts at regulating self-regulation of the banking sectors. Id. at 94-95.
    • Scheuerman was quite sanguine about banking self-regulation although he also noted the democratic deficiencies of G-10 attempts at regulating self-regulation of the banking sectors. Id. at 94-95.
  • 106
    • 78650827889 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 95.
    • Id. at 95.
  • 107
    • 78650846875 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 90-91.
    • Id. at 90-91.
  • 108
    • 0342872989 scopus 로고
    • The postmodern transition: Law and politics
    • Id. at 92 quoting 115 Austin Sarat & Thomas Kearas eds.
    • Id. at 92 (quoting Boaventura de Sousa Santos, The Postmodern Transition: Law and Politics, in THE FATE OF LAW 79, 115 (Austin Sarat & Thomas Kearas eds., 1991)).
    • (1991) The Fate of Law , pp. 79
    • De Sousa Santos, B.1
  • 109
    • 78650808413 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Scheuerman also notes, referring to Jerome Frank, that these types of dilemma are not exactly that new. Id.
    • Scheuerman also notes, referring to Jerome Frank, that these types of dilemma are not exactly that new. Id.
  • 110
    • 78650832475 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As of course is the question of whether any particular ends are served by them, contravening the supposed neutrality of the rule of law.
    • As of course is the question of whether any particular ends are served by them, contravening the supposed neutrality of the rule of law.
  • 111
    • 78650810399 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See de Búrea & Scott, supra note 18. They suggest another possibility, that law is able to resist the new governance phenomenon. Id. at 4-5.
    • See de Búrea & Scott, supra note 18. They suggest another possibility, that law is able to resist the new governance phenomenon. Id. at 4-5.
  • 112
    • 78650818592 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Scott & Trubek, Supra note 74, at 8-12.
    • See, e.g., Scott & Trubek, Supra note 74, at 8-12.
  • 113
    • 78650822609 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Much of this differentiation of veneer, need not, and is not, of course denied by the proponents of new governance modes. Id.
    • Much of this differentiation of veneer, need not, and is not, of course denied by the proponents of new governance modes. Id.
  • 114
    • 79551676797 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 8 Robert Schuman Centre for Advanced Stud., European U. Inst. Working Papers, No. RSCAS 2009/24, available at
    • Mark Dawson, Son Law and the Rule of Law in the European Union: Revision or Redundancy? 1, 8 (Robert Schuman Centre for Advanced Stud., European U. Inst. Working Papers, No. RSCAS 2009/24, 2009), available at http://ssrn.com/ abstract= 1415003.
    • (2009) Son Law and the Rule of Law in the European Union: Revision or Redundancy? , pp. 1
    • Dawson, M.1
  • 115
    • 78650810400 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id.
  • 116
    • 33845705383 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • European governance: Meaning and value of a concept
    • Id. quoting 316-7
    • Id. (quoting Christoph Möllers, European Governance: Meaning and Value of a Concept, 43 COMMON MKT. L. REV., 313, 316-7 (2006)) (internal quotation marks omitted).
    • (2006) Common Mkt. L. Rev. , vol.43 , pp. 313
    • Möllers, C.1
  • 117
    • 78650822607 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Zumbansen, supra note 82, at 801.
    • Zumbansen, supra note 82, at 801.
  • 119
    • 78650843764 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • We should not assume, therefore, that new governance is simply "a covert form of deregulation, designed to mask reduction of environmental standards and social protection" and consider that it is this alone which establishes a gap with traditional law, see Trubek & Trubek, Supra, note 65, 547 n.29. In other words the question of a gap between law and new governance should not be preempted by a simplistic association of new governance and neo-liberalism.
    • We should not assume, therefore, that new governance is simply "a covert form of deregulation, designed to mask reduction of environmental standards and social protection" and consider that it is this alone which establishes a gap with traditional law, see Trubek & Trubek, Supra, note 65, 547 n.29. In other words the question of a gap between law and new governance should not be preempted by a simplistic association of new governance and neo-liberalism.
  • 120
    • 12444341803 scopus 로고
    • This recalls the Habermasian critique of Weberian cognitive-instrumental rationality. See 1 (Thomas McCarthy trans., Beacon Press 1984)
    • This recalls the Habermasian critique of Weberian cognitive-instrumental rationality. See 1 JÜRGEN HABERMAS, THE THEORY OF COMMUNICATIVE ACTION: REASON AND THE RATIONALIZATION OF SOCIETY 189 (Thomas McCarthy trans., Beacon Press 1984) (1981).
    • (1981) The Theory of Communicative Action: Reason and the Rationalization of Society , pp. 189
    • Habermas, J.1
  • 121
    • 62649114528 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Defending the possibility of a neutral functional theory of law
    • 97
    • For example, Kenneth Ehrenberg argues that functionalism helps explain law rather than define it or provide membership criteria for law. Just because law is not a "functional kind" does not mean one cannot use a functional methodology for its explanation. Kenneth M. Ehrenberg, Defending the Possibility of a Neutral Functional Theory of Law, 29 OXFORD J. LEGAL STUD. 91, 97 (2009).
    • (2009) Oxford J. Legal Stud. , vol.29 , pp. 91
    • Ehrenberg, K.M.1
  • 122
    • 53949103254 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Law, governance, or new governance? The changing open method of coordination
    • 659
    • Neglect of this question has been much a complaint against new governance scholarship as it is its critics. As Kilpatrick and Armstrong note in the treatment of soft law and hard law as dichotomous, there is "a tendency towards definition by default-that which is evidently not hard law must by default be soft law . .. rather than clearer theorization of what it means to be law in order to identify harder and softer variants.'' Kenneth Armstrong & Claire Kilpatrick, Law, Governance, or New Governance? The Changing Open Method of Coordination, 13 COLUM. J. EUR. L. 649, 659 (2007) (internal citation omitted).
    • (2007) Colum. J. Eur. L. , vol.13 , pp. 649
    • Armstrong, K.1    Kilpatrick, C.2
  • 123
    • 78650836647 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Scott & Trubek, supra note 74, at 8 (emphasis added). But which are premises and which are values? Is hierarchy, for example, really a value? Or is it simply an inevitable condition? Or contrary to both assumptions, is it merely a historically contingent aspect of social and political life
    • See Scott & Trubek, supra note 74, at 8 (emphasis added). But which are premises and which are values? Is hierarchy, for example, really a value? Or is it simply an inevitable condition? Or contrary to both assumptions, is it merely a historically contingent aspect of social and political life?
  • 124
    • 78650804479 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dawson, supra note 91, at 5.
    • Dawson, supra note 91, at 5.
  • 125
    • 78650852343 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 8.
    • Id. at 8.
  • 126
    • 78650826248 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id.
  • 127
    • 78650813629 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Scheuerman, supra note 81, at 102.
    • Scheuerman, supra note 81, at 102.
  • 128
    • 78650822050 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • There is, for example, according to Scheuerman, a lack of engagement with the normative arguments in favor of centralized elected representative legislatures over the course of the last few centuries.
    • There is, for example, according to Scheuerman, a lack of engagement with the normative arguments "in favor of centralized elected representative legislatures over the course of the last few centuries."
  • 129
    • 78650831425 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 119
    • Id. at 119;
  • 131
    • 78650840345 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Scheuerman, supra note 81, at 122.
    • Scheuerman, supra note 81, at 122.
  • 132
    • 0004056569 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (internal citation marks omitted)
    • What this suggests, for Scheuerman, is that the law is following the pattern of capitalist development which has moved from "top-heavy bureaucratic forms of uniform state regulation" to the "organizational logic of flexible specialization." Id. at 123. Sabel et al. seem to celebrate the "organizational accomplishments of flexible specialization vis-à-vis earlier forms of capitalism," id. at 125, ignoring the "new forms of unequal, arbitrary power within the organization," id. (quoting RICHARD SENNETT, THE CORROSION OF CHARACTER: THE PERSONAL CONSEQUENCES OF WORK IN THE NEW CAPITALISM 55 (1998)) (internal citation marks omitted).
    • (1998) The Corrosion of Character: The Personal Consequences of Work In The New Capitalism , pp. 55
    • Sennett, R.1
  • 133
    • 77952378245 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • European Governance Papers, No. N-07-03, Iain F. Fraser trans., available at
    • See, e.g., Christian Joerges, Integration Through Delegislation? An Irritated Heckler 21 (European Governance Papers, No. N-07-03, Iain F. Fraser trans., 2007), available at http://www.connex-network.org/eurogov/pdf/egp- newgov-N-07>-03.pdf.
    • (2007) Integration Through Delegislation? An Irritated Heckler , pp. 21
    • Joerges, C.1
  • 134
    • 78650852596 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Governance legalism: Hayek and sabel on reason and rules, organization and law, 2010
    • For a different assessment of the influence of Hayek in the early new governance literature, see Amy Cohen, Governance Legalism: Hayek and Sabel On Reason and Rules, Organization and Law, 2010 Wis. L. REV. 357, 362-63.
    • Wis. L. Rev. , vol.357 , pp. 362-363
    • Cohen, A.1
  • 136
    • 78650830911 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In more explanatory mode, the liberal legalist might argue that the practical significance of new governance is exaggerated, that the state still remains the predominant institutional actor and that our theoretical presuppositions about the law need to be structured accordingly. This position might be labeled one of denial
    • In more explanatory mode, the liberal legalist might argue that the practical significance of new governance is exaggerated, that the state still remains the predominant institutional actor and that our theoretical presuppositions about the law need to be structured accordingly. This position might be labeled one of "denial."
  • 137
    • 0003996038 scopus 로고
    • This understanding of the modern rule of law is found in, for example, FRIEDRICH A. HAYEK, THE ROAD TO SERFDOM 72-73 (1944).
    • (1944) The Road To Serfdom , pp. 72-73
    • Hayek, F.A.1
  • 138
    • 78650803244 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Max Weber's own account takes this analysis deeper, relating the spirit of capitalism to religious calling and a protestant ethics. Weber perceives modern formal law to be deeply implicated in the rise of the Protestant ethic and the spirit of capitalism but in a complex and ambiguous manner. As Habermas notes, Weber fails to develop the connections or disconnections between capitalism and law's perceived value rationality. See HABERMAS, supra note 97, at 228-29
    • Max Weber's own account takes this analysis deeper, relating the spirit of capitalism to religious calling and a protestant ethics. Weber perceives modern formal law to be deeply implicated in the rise of the Protestant ethic and the spirit of capitalism but in a complex and ambiguous manner. As Habermas notes, Weber fails to develop the connections or disconnections between capitalism and law's perceived value rationality. See HABERMAS, supra note 97, at 228-29.
  • 139
    • 52449133827 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Simmonds argues that the rule of law is not only instrumentally valuable (appropriating Fuller's eight desiderata). Id. at 66. According to Simmonds, Laws are invoked as a justification for force, and an adequate legal theory must render this practice intelligible. Id. at 140
    • N.E. SIMMONDS, LAW AS A MORAL IDEA 138 (2007). Simmonds argues that the rule of law is not only instrumentally valuable (appropriating Fuller's eight desiderata). Id. at 66. According to Simmonds, "Laws are invoked as a justification for force, and an adequate legal theory must render this practice intelligible." Id. at 140.
    • (2007) Law As A Moral Idea , pp. 138
    • Simmonds, N.E.1
  • 140
    • 36148972904 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The fate of public international law: Between technique and politics
    • 19 (emphasis added) although Koskenniemi goes on to note that the constitution of the international realm would be imperial in nature, not least because of the absence of a global pouvoir constituant. Constitutionalism was also perceived by many in the European Union to be an appropriate framework for securing the transnational rule of law and responding to the aim of democratizing the Union and bringing it closer to the citizen. Evidence of a certain constitutionalist mindset in the EU is easy to find, one notable scholar famously referring to constitutionalism as the "DOS" of European integration. See WEILER, supra note 24, at 221. Weiler himself was notably skeptical about the idea of European Constitution
    • See Marti Koskenniemi, The Fate of Public International Law: Between Technique and Politics, 70 MOD. L. REV. 1, 19 (2007) (emphasis added) although Koskenniemi goes on to note that the constitution of the international realm would be imperial in nature, not least because of the absence of a global pouvoir constituant. Constitutionalism was also perceived by many in the European Union to be an appropriate framework for securing the transnational rule of law and responding to the aim of democratizing the Union and bringing it closer to the citizen. Evidence of a certain "constitutionalist" mindset in the EU is easy to find, one notable scholar famously referring to constitutionalism as the "DOS" of European integration. See WEILER, supra note 24, at 221. Weiler himself was notably skeptical about the idea of European Constitution.
    • (2007) Mod. L. Rev. , vol.70 , pp. 1
    • Koskenniemi, M.1
  • 141
    • 78650840344 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • That is not to say the adherents to some form of liberal legalism are always sanguine about the ability of state-like mechanisms of accountability to be reproduced at the non-state level without some significant loss of legitimacy
    • That is not to say the adherents to some form of liberal legalism are always sanguine about the ability of state-like mechanisms of accountability to be reproduced at the non-state level without some significant loss of legitimacy.
  • 142
    • 78650802677 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Dawson, supra note 91, at 6
    • See Dawson, supra note 91, at 6.
  • 143
    • 78650845227 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 6-7
    • Id. at 6-7.
  • 144
    • 78650815293 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1
    • Id. at 1.
  • 145
    • 78650840070 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Kingsbury et al., supra note 1, at 37, 39-42
    • See Kingsbury et al., supra note 1, at 37, 39-42.
  • 146
    • 78650828906 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Inst. Int'l. Law & Just. Working Papers, No. 2008/7, available at Although Dyzenhaus addresses his jurisprudential enquiry towards the concept of global administrative law, rather than new governance, many similar issues arise
    • David Dyzenhaus, Accountability and the Concept of (Global) Administrative Law A (Inst. Int'l. Law & Just. Working Papers, No. 2008/7, 2008), available at http://www.iilj.org/publications/2008-7Dyzenhaus.asp. Although Dyzenhaus addresses his jurisprudential enquiry towards the concept of global administrative law, rather than new governance, many similar issues arise.
    • (2008) Accountability and the Concept of (Global) Administrative Law A
    • Dyzenhaus, D.1
  • 147
    • 78650845509 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 4
    • Id. at 4.
  • 148
    • 78650846287 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 4 (emphasis added)
    • Id. at 4 (emphasis added).
  • 149
    • 78650840071 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id.
  • 150
    • 78650844318 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id.
  • 151
    • 78650838026 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 13
    • Id. at 13.
  • 152
    • 78650845756 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 15 (internal quotation marks omitted)
    • Id. at 15 (internal quotation marks omitted).
  • 153
    • 78650810981 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 23
    • Id. at 23.
  • 154
    • 78650843000 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Walker & de Búrea, supra note 9, at 522
    • See Walker & de Búrea, supra note 9, at 522.
  • 155
    • 78650815024 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Green, supra note 52, at 4
    • See, e.g., Green, supra note 52, at 4.
  • 156
    • 78650808131 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As is the case, perhaps, in some natural law theorizing in the Aristotelian tradition. This is not the occasion to examine that possibility, which is quite different in approach to the functionalism examined above. See, e.g., FINNIS, supra note 55
    • As is the case, perhaps, in some natural law theorizing in the Aristotelian tradition. This is not the occasion to examine that possibility, which is quite different in approach to the functionalism examined above. See, e.g., FINNIS, supra note 55.
  • 157
    • 78650808126 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Leslie Green helpfully notes that we can distinguish between its latent" and "manifest functions, the Marxist view that "law supports the dominant means of production" or reifies class power being an obvious example of the latter claim. See Green, Supra note 52, at 4
    • Leslie Green helpfully notes that we can distinguish between its "latent" and "manifest" functions, the Marxist view that "law supports the dominant means of production" or reifies class power being an obvious example of the latter claim. See Green, Supra note 52, at 4.
  • 158
    • 78650827618 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Contra, e.g., KELSEN, supra note 35
    • Contra, e.g., KELSEN, supra note 35.
  • 159
    • 76249123071 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Understanding legal pluralism: Past to present, local to global
    • 393
    • A denial of which has led to legal pluralism coming unstuck in its failure to elaborate a concept of law, such that everything becomes law or legal, or as Tamanaha recently put it, we end up "swimming, or drowning, in [it]." See Brian Tamanaha, Understanding Legal Pluralism: Past to Present, Local to Global, 30 SYDNEY L. REV. 375, 393 (2008).
    • (2008) Sydney L. Rev. , vol.30 , pp. 375
    • Tamanaha, B.1
  • 161
    • 78650833581 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 159-60
    • Id. at 159-60.
  • 162
    • 78650841876 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See HART, Supra note 26, at 79
    • See HART, Supra note 26, at 79.
  • 163
    • 78650816113 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Tamanaha, Supra note 134, at 393
    • See, e.g., Tamanaha, Supra note 134, at 393.
  • 164
    • 0003842108 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 2d ed. (noting that law's claim to legitimate authority is a moral claim)
    • See, e.g., JOSEPH RAZ, THE AUTHORITY OF LAW: ESSAYS ON LAW AND MORALITY 31 (2d ed. 2009) (noting that law's claim to legitimate authority is a moral claim).
    • (2009) The Authority of Law: Essays on Law And Morality , pp. 31
    • Joseph, R.A.Z.1
  • 165
    • 84935470880 scopus 로고
    • Law as a social system
    • 140
    • See Niklas Luhmann, Law as a Social System, 83 Nw. U. L. REV. 136, 140 (1989).
    • (1989) Nw. U. L. Rev. , vol.83 , pp. 136
    • Luhmann, N.1
  • 166
    • 46749087077 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Corporate social responsibility: Towards a new market embedded morality?
    • 374, 394
    • See Ronen Shamir, Corporate Social Responsibility: Towards a New Market Embedded Morality?, 9 THEORETICAL INQUIRIES L. 371, 374, 394 (2008).
    • (2008) Theoretical Inquiries L. , vol.9 , pp. 371
    • Shamir, R.1
  • 167
    • 78650804771 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See HART, supra note 26, at 201-04. Raz too argues that the rule of law essentially mediates wrongs the possibility of which are anyway created by law in the first place. See RAZ, supranote 139, at 210-11
    • See HART, supra note 26, at 201-04. Raz too argues that the rule of law essentially mediates wrongs the possibility of which are anyway created by law in the first place. See RAZ, supranote 139, at 210-11.
  • 168
    • 56049107109 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Positivism and the inseparability of law and morals
    • 1052-54
    • See, e.g., Leslie Green, Positivism and the Inseparability of Law and Morals, 83 N.Y.U. L. REV. 1035, 1052-54 (2008).
    • (2008) N.Y.U. L. Rev. , vol.83 , pp. 1035
    • Green, L.1
  • 170
    • 78650803788 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Green, Supra note 143, at 1057-58
    • See Green, Supra note 143, at 1057-58.
  • 171
    • 77956148041 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Is law Morally Risky? Alienation, acceptance and hart's concept of law
    • forthcoming (on file with author)
    • See Mike Wilkinson, Is Law Morally Risky? Alienation, Acceptance and Hart's Concept of Law, 30 OXFORD J. LEGAL STUD, (forthcoming 2010) (on file with author).
    • (2010) Oxford J. Legal Stud , vol.30
    • Wilkinson, M.1
  • 172
    • 78650844962 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Law is in danger of becoming official-dominated. If Hart's account is correct, only officials need to adopt the internal point of view towards the rule of recognition in order for the society to have a legal order. See Green, supra note 143, at 1058
    • Law is in danger of becoming official-dominated. If Hart's account is correct, only officials need to adopt the internal point of view towards the rule of recognition in order for the society to have a legal order. See Green, supra note 143, at 1058;
  • 174
    • 84909215767 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Reflexive constitution-making and transitional governance
    • This insight has recently been revived in the context of globalizing democracy. See Erik Oddvar Eriksen ed.
    • This insight has recently been revived in the context of globalizing democracy. See James Bohman, Reflexive Constitution-Making and Transitional Governance, in MAKING THE EUROPEAN POLITY: REFLEXIVE INTEGRATION IN THE EU (Erik Oddvar Eriksen ed., 2005).
    • (2005) Making The European Polity: Reflexive Integration In The EU
    • Bohman, J.1
  • 175
    • 78650849523 scopus 로고
    • (Frida Laski & Harold Laski trans., Howard Fertig, Inc. ed. 1970) (discussing the socialization of law)
    • Harold Laski, Introduction to LAW IN THE MODERN STATE (Frida Laski & Harold Laski trans., Howard Fertig, Inc. ed. 1970) (1919) (discussing the socialization of law).
    • (1919) Introduction to Law in the Modern State
    • Laski, H.1
  • 176
    • 78650848431 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This builds on the mutual penetration thesis. See Walker & de Búrea, Supra note 9, at 522
    • This builds on the "mutual penetration" thesis. See Walker & de Búrea, Supra note 9, at 522.
  • 178
    • 78650820918 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 210
    • Id. at 210.
  • 179
    • 78650852609 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Univ. of Iowa Legal Studies Research Paper No. 0904, 2009), available at (building on the idea that legality must ultimately be conceptualized as a relationship)
    • See also Alexander Somek, Administration Without Sovereignty 18 (Univ. of Iowa Legal Studies Research Paper No. 09-04, 2009), available at http://ssrn.com/abstract=1333282 (building on the idea that legality must ultimately be conceptualized as a relationship).
    • Administration Without Sovereignty , pp. 18
    • Somek, A.1
  • 180
    • 78650832476 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This, perhaps, is characteristic of the liberal social contract tradition to which Fuller ascribes. See generally FULLER, Supra note 150, at 43-47. A full account of this tradition is beyond the scope of this Article
    • This, perhaps, is characteristic of the liberal social contract tradition to which Fuller ascribes. See generally FULLER, Supra note 150, at 43-47. A full account of this tradition is beyond the scope of this Article.
  • 181
    • 79952480438 scopus 로고
    • Law and legislation in the administrative state
    • 399 In the context of the administrative state, it is far from clear that Fuller's desiderata are clearly desirable when we consider legislation as "directives to implementation mechanisms . . . ." Id. at 399-400. Law is not so much about rules addressed to citizens but policy directed to officials and agencies. Id.
    • Id. at 46 n.3. It is also worth noting that "the [alleged] limited applicability of Fuller's principles to modern legislation." See Edward Rubin, Law and Legislation in the Administrative State, 89 COLUM. L. REV. 369, 399 (1989). In the context of the administrative state, it is far from clear that Fuller's desiderata are clearly desirable when we consider legislation as "directives to implementation mechanisms . . . ." Id. at 399-400. Law is not so much about rules addressed to citizens but policy directed to officials and agencies. Id.
    • (1989) Colum. L. Rev. , vol.89 , pp. 369
    • Rubin, E.1
  • 183
    • 78650836392 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 127
    • Id. at 127.
  • 184
    • 78650805575 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id.
  • 185
    • 78650802154 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 133
    • Id. at 133.
  • 186
    • 78650842713 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 133-35
    • Id. at 133-35.
  • 187
    • 78650816398 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 127
    • Id. at 127.
  • 188
    • 78650832750 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Walker & de Búrea, supra note 9, at 522
    • Walker & de Búrea, supra note 9, at 522.
  • 189
    • 78650813632 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 533 (emphasis added)
    • Id. at 533 (emphasis added).
  • 190
    • 78650809738 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • They reach this conclusion after discussing and discarding the formal pair of pedigree conceptions, institutional conceptions, and the "sociological pair" of symbolic conceptions and functional conceptions as aspects of law's "conceptual hegemony," suggesting in both cases either absorption or separation of law and new governance. Id. 532-34
    • They reach this conclusion after discussing and discarding the "formal pair" of pedigree conceptions, institutional conceptions, and the "sociological pair" of symbolic conceptions and functional conceptions as aspects of law's "conceptual hegemony," suggesting in both cases either absorption or separation of law and new governance. Id. 532-34.
  • 191
    • 78650839024 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 533
    • Id. at 533.
  • 192
    • 78650815855 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 533-34
    • Id. at 533-34.
  • 193
    • 78650822052 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See HART, Supra note 26, at 95-96
    • See HART, Supra note 26, at 95-96.
  • 194
    • 78650840598 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Walker & de Búrea, supra note 9, at 534
    • Walker & de Búrea, supra note 9, at 534.
  • 195
    • 78650815856 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id.
  • 196
    • 78650821189 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 534-35
    • Id. at 534-35.
  • 197
    • 78650843763 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See de Búrea & Scott, Supra note 18, at 6-9 (identifying "fundamental/baseline hybridity," "instrumental/developmental hybridity," and "default hybridity")
    • See de Búrea & Scott, Supra note 18, at 6-9 (identifying "fundamental/baseline hybridity," "instrumental/developmental hybridity," and "default hybridity").
  • 198
    • 78650839283 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 6
    • Id. at 6.
  • 199
    • 58949087930 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The JCMS annual lecture: National welfare states and european integration: In search of a virtuous nesting
    • Maurizio Ferrara, The JCMS Annual Lecture: National Welfare States and European Integration: In Search of a "Virtuous Nesting," 47 J. COMMON MKT. STUD. 219 (2009).
    • (2009) J. Common Mkt. Stud. , vol.47 , pp. 219
    • Ferrara, M.1
  • 200
    • 61349178025 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Governing without law or governing without government? New-ish governance and the legitimacy of the EU
    • 173
    • New governance has the tendency to be output oriented. See Colin Scott, Governing Without Law or Governing Without Government? New-ish Governance and the Legitimacy of the EU, 15 EUR. L.J. 160, 173 (2009).
    • (2009) Eur. L.J. , vol.15 , pp. 160
    • Scott, C.1
  • 201
    • 0003576528 scopus 로고
    • (William Rehg trans., 1996) The way Habermas attempts to redeem this claim through discourse theory brings the question of law's normativity, its legitimate authority, in direct contact with a theory of democracy and democratic political will-formation in the public sphere. Id.
    • This reflects Habermas's argument that the addressees of law must be able to see themselves as its authors. See JÜRGEN HABERMAS, BETWEEN FACTS AND NORMS: CONTRIBUTIONS TO A DISCOURSE THEORY OF LAW AND DEMOCRACY 449 (William Rehg trans., 1996) (1992). The way Habermas attempts to redeem this claim through discourse theory brings the question of law's "normativity," its legitimate authority, in direct contact with a theory of democracy and democratic political will-formation in the public sphere. Id.
    • (1992) Between Facts And Norms: Contributions To A Discourse Theory of Law And Democracy , pp. 449
    • Habermas, J.1
  • 202
    • 85191112147 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Toyota jurisprudence: Legal theory and rolling rule regimes
    • Gráinne de Búrea & Joanne Scott eds.
    • William H. Simon, Toyota Jurisprudence: Legal Theory and Rolling Rule Regimes, in LAW AND NEW GOVERNANCE IN THE EU AND THE US 37 (Gráinne de Búrea & Joanne Scott eds., 2006).
    • (2006) Law And New Governance in the EU and the US , pp. 37
    • Simon, W.H.1
  • 203
    • 78650835850 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 38-41. Simon rejects five propositions of traditional mainstream legal thought: that the dominant function of the legal system is dispute resolution or the optimization of socially accepted values; that the legal system engages in a dialect of formal rules and informal standards; that legal reasoning in hard cases is interstitial; that the core of legal decision-making is differentiated from other societal activities; and that legal decision-making is paradigmatically retrospective and individualist. Id.
    • Id. at 38-41. Simon rejects five propositions of traditional mainstream legal thought: that the dominant function of the legal system is dispute resolution or the optimization of socially accepted values; that the legal system engages in a dialect of formal rules and informal standards; that legal reasoning in hard cases is interstitial; that the core of legal decision-making is differentiated from other societal activities; and that legal decision-making is paradigmatically retrospective and individualist. Id.
  • 204
    • 78650809472 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 40-41
    • Id. at 40-41.
  • 205
    • 78650807315 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 43
    • Id. at 43.
  • 206
    • 78650808415 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id.
  • 207
    • 78650813631 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In this celebration of experience and experimentation and the learning process that ensues the debt to John Dewey is evident. Id. at 64
    • In this celebration of experience and experimentation and the learning process that ensues the debt to John Dewey is evident. Id. at 64.
  • 208
    • 78650837206 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., HABERMAS, Supra note 174, at 449-50
    • See, e.g., HABERMAS, Supra note 174, at 449-50.
  • 209
    • 78650810318 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • HART, supra note 26, at 179
    • HART, supra note 26, at 179.
  • 210
    • 78650825694 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 113-14
    • Id. at 113-14.
  • 211
    • 78650804770 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • KRONMAN, Supra note 44
    • KRONMAN, Supra note 44.
  • 212
    • 78650806377 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 175 (internal quotation marks omitted)
    • Id. at 175 (internal quotation marks omitted).
  • 213
    • 78650820387 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. (discussing Weber's application of the iron cage metaphor to the field of law)
    • See id. (discussing Weber's application of the iron cage metaphor to the field of law).
  • 214
    • 78650828137 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For Habermas, like Hart, the modern legal order is Janus-faced. HABERMAS, Supra note 174, at 448. But the parallel is not striking in this instance, since for Habermas, the Janus represents not the official on the one hand and the citizen on the other, but the citizen in both its glances, looking towards the subject who takes only a strategic approach to rule violation, and towards the citizen who adopts a normative approach: Modern law presents itself as Janus-faced to its addressees: it leaves it up to them which of two possible approaches they want to take to law. Either they can consider legal norms merely as commands, in the sense of factual constraints on their personal scope for action, and take a strategic approach to the calculable consequences of possible rule violations; or they can take a pedformative attitude in which they view norms as valid precepts and comply "out of respect for the law." Id. at 448
    • For Habermas, like Hart, the modern legal order is "Janus-faced. " HABERMAS, Supra note 174, at 448. But the parallel is not striking in this instance, since for Habermas, the Janus represents not the official on the one hand and the citizen on the other, but the citizen in both its glances, looking towards the subject who takes only a strategic approach to rule violation, and towards the citizen who adopts a normative approach: Modern law presents itself as Janus-faced to its addressees: it leaves it up to them which of two possible approaches they want to take to law. Either they can consider legal norms merely as commands, in the sense of factual constraints on their personal scope for action, and take a strategic approach to the calculable consequences of possible rule violations; or they can take a pedformative attitude in which they view norms as valid precepts and comply "out of respect for the law." Id. at 448.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.