메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 83, Issue 4, 2008, Pages 1035-1058

Positivism and the inseparability of law and morals

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 56049107109     PISSN: 00287881     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: None     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (113)

References (99)
  • 1
    • 0000580092 scopus 로고
    • Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals, 71
    • H.L.A. Hart, Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals, 71 HARV. L. REV. 593 (1957).
    • (1957) HARV. L. REV , vol.593
    • Hart, H.L.A.1
  • 2
    • 56049083558 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The association of this idea with Hart seems to be a confused interpretation of a thesis that he did hold, namely that the law ought not to prohibit harmless deviation from conventional moral standards. See H.L.A. HART, LAW, LIBERTY AND MORALITY 57 (1963) (Where there is no harm to be prevented and no potential victim to be protected ... it is difficult to understand the assertion that conformity ... is a value worth pursuing, notwithstanding the misery and sacrifice of freedom it involves.). That is a normative thesis about legislation and not a theory of the nature of law. If positive law necessarily enforces conventional morality, the recommendation would have been pointless.
    • The association of this idea with Hart seems to be a confused interpretation of a thesis that he did hold, namely that the law ought not to prohibit harmless deviation from conventional moral standards. See H.L.A. HART, LAW, LIBERTY AND MORALITY 57 (1963) ("Where there is no harm to be prevented and no potential victim to be protected ... it is difficult to understand the assertion that conformity ... is a value worth pursuing, notwithstanding the misery and sacrifice of freedom it involves."). That is a normative thesis about legislation and not a theory of the nature of law. If positive law necessarily enforces conventional morality, the recommendation would have been pointless.
  • 3
    • 56049120381 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hart sometimes described the thesis that he opposed as making the claim that law and morals are indissolubly fused or inseparable. Hart, supra note 1, at 594.
    • Hart sometimes described the thesis that he opposed as making the claim that law and morals are "indissolubly fused or inseparable." Hart, supra note 1, at 594.
  • 4
    • 56049122497 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I think Jules Coleman first used the term separability thesis. See Jules L. Coleman, Negative and Positive Positivism, 11 J. LEGAL STUD. 139, 140-41 (1982) (using term to refer to the denial of a necessary or constitutive relationship between law and morality).
    • I think Jules Coleman first used the term "separability thesis." See Jules L. Coleman, Negative and Positive Positivism, 11 J. LEGAL STUD. 139, 140-41 (1982) (using term to refer to "the denial of a necessary or constitutive relationship between law and morality").
  • 5
    • 56049097250 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hart, supra note 1, at 601 n.25.
    • Hart, supra note 1, at 601 n.25.
  • 6
    • 0000842517 scopus 로고
    • Positivism and Fidelity to Law - A Reply to Professor Hart, 71
    • Lon L. Fuller, Positivism and Fidelity to Law - A Reply to Professor Hart, 71 HARV. L. REV. 630, 656 (1957).
    • (1957) HARV. L. REV , vol.630 , pp. 656
    • Fuller, L.L.1
  • 7
    • 56049101434 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 631
    • Id. at 631.
  • 8
    • 56049111153 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 632
    • Id. at 632.
  • 9
    • 56049084040 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 631
    • Id. at 631.
  • 10
    • 56049112412 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 643
    • Id. at 643.
  • 11
    • 56049086917 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 646-47 (suggesting that trial judge who has the misfortune ... to live under a supreme court which he considers woefully ignorant of the ways and needs of commerce cannot achieve a satisfactory resolution of his dilemma unless he views his duty of fidelity to law in a context which also embraces his responsibility for making law what it ought to be).
    • See id. at 646-47 (suggesting that trial judge who "has the misfortune ... to live under a supreme court which he considers woefully ignorant of the ways and needs of commerce" cannot "achieve a satisfactory resolution of his dilemma unless he views his duty of fidelity to law in a context which also embraces his responsibility for making law what it ought to be").
  • 12
    • 56049113818 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 643
    • Id. at 643.
  • 13
    • 56049087363 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 634
    • Id. at 634.
  • 14
    • 56049122249 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 647
    • Id. at 647.
  • 15
    • 56049109590 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hart, supra note 1, at 593
    • Hart, supra note 1, at 593.
  • 16
    • 56049123467 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • JOSEPH RAZ, THE AUTHORITY OF LAW 38-39 (1979) [hereinafter RAZ, AUTHORITY];
    • JOSEPH RAZ, THE AUTHORITY OF LAW 38-39 (1979) [hereinafter RAZ, AUTHORITY];
  • 17
    • 56049127199 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also JOSEPH RAZ, PRACTICAL REASON AND NORMS 165-70 (2d ed. 1990) [hereinafter RAZ, PRACTICAL REASON] (discussing derivative approach and its need for a socially oriented identification of [the] law).
    • see also JOSEPH RAZ, PRACTICAL REASON AND NORMS 165-70 (2d ed. 1990) [hereinafter RAZ, PRACTICAL REASON] (discussing "derivative approach" and its "need for a socially oriented identification of [the] law").
  • 18
    • 56049103358 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • JULES COLEMAN, THE PRACTICE OF PRINCIPLE 152 (2001).
    • JULES COLEMAN, THE PRACTICE OF PRINCIPLE 152 (2001).
  • 19
    • 56049094389 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • John Gardner, Legal Positivism: 5 1/2 Myths, 46 AM. J. JURIS. 199, 223 (2001).
    • John Gardner, Legal Positivism: 5 1/2 Myths, 46 AM. J. JURIS. 199, 223 (2001).
  • 20
    • 56049110890 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Klaus Füßer, Farewell to 'Legal Positivism': The Separation Thesis Unraveling, in THE AUTONOMY OF LAW 119, 120 (Robert P. George ed., 1996).
    • Klaus Füßer, Farewell to 'Legal Positivism': The Separation Thesis Unraveling, in THE AUTONOMY OF LAW 119, 120 (Robert P. George ed., 1996).
  • 21
    • 85008214649 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It is therefore what Stephen Perry calls substantive, as opposed to methodological, positivism. See generally Stephen R. Perry, The Varieties of Legal Positivism, 9 CANADIAN J.L. & JURISPRUDENCE 361 (1996).
    • It is therefore what Stephen Perry calls "substantive," as opposed to "methodological," positivism. See generally Stephen R. Perry, The Varieties of Legal Positivism, 9 CANADIAN J.L. & JURISPRUDENCE 361 (1996).
  • 22
    • 3843098430 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For the view that the separability thesis includes at least one methodological commitment, see James Morauta, Three Separation Theses, 23 LAW & PHIL. 111, 128 (2004) (The correct analysis [of the concept of law] does not by itself entail any substantive claims about the moral value of law as such.).
    • For the view that the separability thesis includes at least one methodological commitment, see James Morauta, Three Separation Theses, 23 LAW & PHIL. 111, 128 (2004) ("The correct analysis [of the concept of law] does not by itself entail any substantive claims about the moral value of law as such.").
  • 23
    • 56049110042 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hart, supra note 1, at 615
    • Hart, supra note 1, at 615.
  • 24
    • 56049110309 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • COLEMAN, supra note 16, at 152-53
    • COLEMAN, supra note 16, at 152-53.
  • 25
    • 56049095567 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • John Finnis, The Truth in Legal Positivism, in THE AUTONOMY OF LAW, supra note 18, at 195, 205.
    • John Finnis, The Truth in Legal Positivism, in THE AUTONOMY OF LAW, supra note 18, at 195, 205.
  • 26
    • 56049112632 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • COLEMAN, supra note 16, at 152-53
    • COLEMAN, supra note 16, at 152-53.
  • 27
    • 85008238944 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For my own view, see Leslie Green, Positivism and Conventionalism, 12 CANADIAN J.L. & JURISPRUDENCE 35, 36 (1999) ([T]he rule of recognition cannot be understood as a merely conventional norm.).
    • For my own view, see Leslie Green, Positivism and Conventionalism, 12 CANADIAN J.L. & JURISPRUDENCE 35, 36 (1999) ("[T]he rule of recognition cannot be understood as a merely conventional norm.").
  • 28
    • 56049097017 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • H.L.A. HART, THE CONCEPT OF LAW 185 (2d ed. 1994).
    • H.L.A. HART, THE CONCEPT OF LAW 185 (2d ed. 1994).
  • 30
    • 56049118271 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See generally Hart, supra note 1 (exploring arguments for separability of law and morals).
    • See generally Hart, supra note 1 (exploring arguments for separability of law and morals).
  • 31
    • 56049110308 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It is the last clause (and not on its merits) that distinguishes the sources thesis from the social thesis. The social thesis permits the merit-dependence of law, provided only that this dependence is itself a consequence of social facts. See Gardner, supra note 17, at 200 (discussing attempt[s] to validate certain norms by relying on merit-based tests of their sources). Others have provided statements and defenses of the sources thesis.
    • It is the last clause ("and not on its merits") that distinguishes the sources thesis from the social thesis. The social thesis permits the merit-dependence of law, provided only that this dependence is itself a consequence of social facts. See Gardner, supra note 17, at 200 (discussing "attempt[s] to validate certain norms by relying on merit-based tests of their sources"). Others have provided statements and defenses of the sources thesis.
  • 32
    • 56049123225 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See RAZ, AUTHORITY, supra note 15, at 45-52 (proposing that sources thesis reflects and systemizes several interconnected distinctions embedded in our conception of the law and provide[s] publicly ascertainable standards by which members of ... society are held to be bound);
    • See RAZ, AUTHORITY, supra note 15, at 45-52 (proposing that sources thesis "reflects and systemizes several interconnected distinctions embedded in our conception of the law" and "provide[s] publicly ascertainable standards by which members of ... society are held to be bound");
  • 33
    • 56049083074 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • JOSEPH RAZ, ETHICS IN THE PUBLIC DOMAIN 210-37 (rev. ed. 1995) (defending sources thesis and explaining its relationship to social - or incorporation - and to coherence theses);
    • JOSEPH RAZ, ETHICS IN THE PUBLIC DOMAIN 210-37 (rev. ed. 1995) (defending sources thesis and explaining its relationship to social - or "incorporation" - and to coherence theses);
  • 34
    • 42149160314 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note * reviewing several considerations supporting sources thesis
    • Green, supra note * (reviewing several considerations supporting sources thesis).
    • supra
    • Green1
  • 35
    • 46749133324 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note 15, at
    • RAZ, AUTHORITY, supra note 15, at 38-39.
    • supra , pp. 38-39
    • RAZ, A.1
  • 36
    • 56049105460 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • JOHN AUSTIN, THE PROVINCE OF JURISPRUDENCE DETERMINED 184 (Hackett Publishing Co. 1998) (1832).
    • JOHN AUSTIN, THE PROVINCE OF JURISPRUDENCE DETERMINED 184 (Hackett Publishing Co. 1998) (1832).
  • 37
    • 56049085419 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hart also remarks on Austin's point, see Hart, supra note 1, at 597, 612-13, but the only trace it leaves in the subsequent argument is his claim that not all oughts are moral oughts.
    • Hart also remarks on Austin's point, see Hart, supra note 1, at 597, 612-13, but the only trace it leaves in the subsequent argument is his claim that not all "oughts" are moral "oughts."
  • 38
    • 56049084039 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • HART, supra note 24, at 192;
    • HART, supra note 24, at 192;
  • 39
    • 56049089668 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also Hart, supra note 1, at 622 (The world in which we live ... may one day change ... and if this change were radical enough ... whole ways of thinking and talking which constitute our present conceptual apparatus ... would lapse.).
    • see also Hart, supra note 1, at 622 ("The world in which we live ... may one day change ... and if this change were radical enough ... whole ways of thinking and talking which constitute our present conceptual apparatus ... would lapse.").
  • 40
    • 56049085652 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hart, supra note 1, at 623
    • Hart, supra note 1, at 623.
  • 41
    • 56049105933 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • HART, supra note 24, at 172
    • HART, supra note 24, at 172.
  • 42
    • 56049096293 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • JEAN-JACQUES ROUSSEAU, THE SOCIAL CONTRACT 68 (Maurice Cranston trans., Penguin Books 1968) (1762).
    • JEAN-JACQUES ROUSSEAU, THE SOCIAL CONTRACT 68 (Maurice Cranston trans., Penguin Books 1968) (1762).
  • 43
    • 56049110040 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf., e.g., Joseph Raz, About Morality and the Nature of Law, 48 AM. J. JURIS. 1, 2 (2003) (discussing whether connection between law and morality should be litmus test for theories of law).
    • Cf., e.g., Joseph Raz, About Morality and the Nature of Law, 48 AM. J. JURIS. 1, 2 (2003) (discussing whether connection between law and morality should be "litmus test" for theories of law).
  • 44
    • 33846600262 scopus 로고
    • The Path of the Law, 10
    • O.W. Holmes, The Path of the Law, 10 HARV. L. REV. 457, 461 (1897).
    • (1897) HARV. L. REV , vol.457 , pp. 461
    • Holmes, O.W.1
  • 45
    • 74049118413 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note 24, at, emphasis added
    • HART, supra note 24, at 259 (emphasis added).
    • supra , pp. 259
    • HART1
  • 46
    • 56049116290 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See infra Part III.A (explaining Hart's minimum content and germ-of-justice theses).
    • See infra Part III.A (explaining Hart's minimum content and germ-of-justice theses).
  • 47
    • 56049088326 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Fuller, supra note 5, at 656
    • Fuller, supra note 5, at 656.
  • 48
    • 56049086460 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 49
    • 56049118512 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For an assessment of the debates, see generally Leslie Green, Law and Obligations, in OXFORD HANDBOOK OF JURISPRUDENCE AND PHILOSOPHY OF LAW 514-47 (Jules Coleman & Scott Shapiro eds., 2002), exploring leading theories of political obligation and defending a version of philosophical anarchism.
    • For an assessment of the debates, see generally Leslie Green, Law and Obligations, in OXFORD HANDBOOK OF JURISPRUDENCE AND PHILOSOPHY OF LAW 514-47 (Jules Coleman & Scott Shapiro eds., 2002), exploring leading theories of political obligation and defending a version of philosophical anarchism.
  • 50
    • 56049109588 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See 2 DAVID HUME, A TREATISE OF HUMAN NATURE 219 (J.M. Dent & Sons 1966) (1739) ([A] promise would not be intelligible before human conventions had established it; and ... even if it were intelligible, it would not be attended with any moral obligation. (emphasis omitted)).
    • See 2 DAVID HUME, A TREATISE OF HUMAN NATURE 219 (J.M. Dent & Sons 1966) (1739) ("[A] promise would not be intelligible before human conventions had established it; and ... even if it were intelligible, it would not be attended with any moral obligation." (emphasis omitted)).
  • 51
    • 56049115659 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See RAZ, PRACTICAL REASON, supra note 15, at 165-70 (noting that derivative approach accepts the need for a socially oriented identification of law).
    • See RAZ, PRACTICAL REASON, supra note 15, at 165-70 (noting that derivative approach "accepts the need for a socially oriented identification of law").
  • 52
    • 56049110041 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hart, supra note 1, at 624
    • Hart, supra note 1, at 624.
  • 53
    • 56049118513 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 79-82;
    • Id. at 79-82;
  • 54
    • 56049117248 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • HART, supra note 24, at 193-200
    • HART, supra note 24, at 193-200.
  • 55
    • 56049088574 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The second thesis is subject to stringent criticism by, who asserts that formal justice is an exaggerated expression of otherwise legitimate concern for justice in the administration of the law. David Lyons, On Formal Justice, 58 CORNELL L. REV. 833, 861 (1973).
    • The second thesis is subject to stringent criticism by, who asserts that formal justice is "an exaggerated expression of otherwise legitimate concern for justice in the administration of the law." David Lyons, On Formal Justice, 58 CORNELL L. REV. 833, 861 (1973).
  • 56
    • 56049123709 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See also John Gardner, The Virtue of Justice and the Character of Law, 53 CURRENT LEGAL PROBS. 1, 9-10, 12-13 (M.D.A. Freeman ed., 2000) (arguing that idea of formal justice is myth, as principles of justice and principles of injustice do not differ in form). I try to make some sense of the thesis in Leslie Green, The Germ of Justice 11-13 (May 2005) (unpublished manuscript, on file with the New York University Law Review).
    • See also John Gardner, The Virtue of Justice and the Character of Law, 53 CURRENT LEGAL PROBS. 1, 9-10, 12-13 (M.D.A. Freeman ed., 2000) (arguing that idea of formal justice is myth, as principles of justice and principles of injustice do not differ in form). I try to make some sense of the thesis in Leslie Green, The Germ of Justice 11-13 (May 2005) (unpublished manuscript, on file with the New York University Law Review).
  • 57
    • 56049094630 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • HART, supra note 24, at 206. Hart cites the application of a law prohibiting murder as an example, explaining that such law is justly applied if it is impartially applied to all those and only those who are alike in having done what the law forbids.
    • HART, supra note 24, at 206. Hart cites the application of a law prohibiting murder as an example, explaining that such law is "justly applied" if it is "impartially applied to all those and only those who are alike in having done what the law forbids."
  • 58
    • 56049085653 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 160
    • Id. at 160.
  • 59
    • 56049093505 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hart also notes that rules of procedural justice are designed to ensure that rules are applied only to what are genuinely cases of the rule or at least to minimize the risks of inequalities in this sense. Hart, supra note 1, at 624.
    • Hart also notes that rules of procedural justice "are designed to ensure that rules are applied only to what are genuinely cases of the rule or at least to minimize the risks of inequalities in this sense." Hart, supra note 1, at 624.
  • 60
    • 56049091088 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hart, supra note 1, at 624
    • Hart, supra note 1, at 624.
  • 61
    • 56049106181 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • HANS KELSEN, The Idea of Natural Law, in ESSAYS IN LEGAL AND MORAL PHILOSOPHY 34 (Ota Weinberger ed., Peter Heath trans., 1973).
    • HANS KELSEN, The Idea of Natural Law, in ESSAYS IN LEGAL AND MORAL PHILOSOPHY 34 (Ota Weinberger ed., Peter Heath trans., 1973).
  • 62
    • 56049102896 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., JOHN FINNIS, NATURAL LAW AND NATURAL RIGHTS 82 (1980) ([Hart's] list of universally recognized or 'indisputable' ends contains only one entry: survival.). Finnis's list includes at least: life, knowledge, play, aesthetic experience, friendship, practical reasonableness, and religion.
    • See, e.g., JOHN FINNIS, NATURAL LAW AND NATURAL RIGHTS 82 (1980) ("[Hart's] list of universally recognized or 'indisputable' ends contains only one entry: survival."). Finnis's list includes at least: life, knowledge, play, aesthetic experience, friendship, practical reasonableness, and religion.
  • 63
    • 56049117015 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 85-92
    • Id. at 85-92.
  • 64
    • 46749133324 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The argument that follows is abridged; for elaboration, see, note 15, at
    • The argument that follows is abridged; for elaboration, see RAZ, AUTHORITY, supra note 15, at 28-33, 122-45.
    • supra
    • RAZ, A.1
  • 65
    • 56049094160 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See also LESLIE GREEN, THE AUTHORITY OF THE STATE 21-88 (1988) (exploring nature of authority and state's self image as legitimate authority);
    • See also LESLIE GREEN, THE AUTHORITY OF THE STATE 21-88 (1988) (exploring nature of authority and state's "self image" as legitimate authority);
  • 66
    • 0041532436 scopus 로고
    • Hart on Moral Rights and Legal Duties, 4
    • Joseph Raz, Hart on Moral Rights and Legal Duties, 4 OXFORD J. LEGAL STUD. 123, 129-31 (1984)
    • (1984) OXFORD J. LEGAL STUD , vol.123 , pp. 129-131
    • Raz, J.1
  • 67
    • 56049101924 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (arguing that, if having duty entails having reason to act, then judges who accept rule of recognition must either accept or pretend to accept that legal duties are morally binding). Note that I am not following Kelsen, see supra note 47, at 31-33, in his assumption that all laws impose obligations. I am assuming only that all legal systems contain obligation-imposing norms, and that these purport to be morally binding on their subjects.
    • (arguing that, if having duty entails having reason to act, then judges who accept rule of recognition must either accept or pretend to accept that legal duties are morally binding). Note that I am not following Kelsen, see supra note 47, at 31-33, in his assumption that all laws impose obligations. I am assuming only that all legal systems contain obligation-imposing norms, and that these purport to be morally binding on their subjects.
  • 68
    • 56049118951 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • But see MATTHEW H. KRAMER, IN DEFENSE OF LEGAL POSITIVISM: LAW WITHOUT TRIMMINGS 84-89 (1999) ([T]he requirements of legal norms can be stark imperatives that do not in themselves . . . constitute such reasons-for-action.).
    • But see MATTHEW H. KRAMER, IN DEFENSE OF LEGAL POSITIVISM: LAW WITHOUT TRIMMINGS 84-89 (1999) ("[T]he requirements of legal norms can be stark imperatives that do not in themselves . . . constitute such reasons-for-action.").
  • 69
    • 56049109589 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • H.L.A. HART, Legal Duty and Obligation, in ESSAYS ON BENTHAM: JURISPRUDENCE AND POLITICAL THEORY 127, 157-60 (1982) [hereinafter HART, Legal Duty and Obligation];
    • H.L.A. HART, Legal Duty and Obligation, in ESSAYS ON BENTHAM: JURISPRUDENCE AND POLITICAL THEORY 127, 157-60 (1982) [hereinafter HART, Legal Duty and Obligation];
  • 70
    • 56049099096 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • cf. H.L.A. HART, ESSAYS IN JURISPRUDENCE AND PHILOSOPHY 10 (1983) ([I]t seems to me to be unrealistic to suppose that judges ... must always either believe or pretend to believe in the false theory that there is always a moral obligation to conform to the law.).
    • cf. H.L.A. HART, ESSAYS IN JURISPRUDENCE AND PHILOSOPHY 10 (1983) ("[I]t seems to me to be unrealistic to suppose that judges ... must always either believe or pretend to believe in the false theory that there is always a moral obligation to conform to the law.").
  • 71
    • 56049111942 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • T]o say that an individual has a legal obligation to act in a certain way is to say that such action may be properly demanded or extracted from him according to legal rules or principles regulating such demands for action, See, at
    • See HART, Legal Duty and Obligation, supra note 51, at 160 ("[T]o say that an individual has a legal obligation to act in a certain way is to say that such action may be properly demanded or extracted from him according to legal rules or principles regulating such demands for action.").
    • Legal Duty and Obligation, supra note , vol.51 , pp. 160
    • HART1
  • 72
    • 56049118270 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Gardner, supra note 44, at 2;
    • See Gardner, supra note 44, at 2;
  • 73
    • 42149160314 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note 44, at, explaining allocative role of adjudication
    • Green, supra note 44, at 29 (explaining allocative role of adjudication).
    • supra , pp. 29
    • Green1
  • 74
    • 56049124146 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Fuller, supra note 5, at 644-48
    • Fuller, supra note 5, at 644-48.
  • 75
    • 56049118723 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Necessary Connection Between Law and Morality, 22
    • Tony Honoré, The Necessary Connection Between Law and Morality, 22 OXFORD J. LEGAL STUD. 489, 491 (2002).
    • (2002) OXFORD J. LEGAL STUD , vol.489 , pp. 491
    • Honoré, T.1
  • 76
    • 56049092093 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This point is not unique to moral considerations. Something that binds a court only as far as it rationally persuades it is not a source because it lacks authority. There are, however, permissive sources of law which have a very weak form of authority and apply only in limited circumstances. In Scotland, for example, the institutional writers were traditionally a permissive source of law: Customary practice of the courts gave their views weight independent of their merits. In some jurisdictions, foreign law functions as a permissive source. I cannot explore the special features of permissive sources here. For some brief remarks on the issue, see HART, supra note 24, at 294 n.101
    • This point is not unique to moral considerations. Something that binds a court only as far as it rationally persuades it is not a source because it lacks authority. There are, however, permissive sources of law which have a very weak form of authority and apply only in limited circumstances. In Scotland, for example, the institutional writers were traditionally a permissive source of law: Customary practice of the courts gave their views weight independent of their merits. In some jurisdictions, foreign law functions as a permissive source. I cannot explore the special features of permissive sources here. For some brief remarks on the issue, see HART, supra note 24, at 294 n.101.
  • 77
    • 56049100543 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 54 and accompanying text (describing Fuller's analysis of internal morality of law).
    • See supra note 54 and accompanying text (describing Fuller's analysis of "internal" morality of law).
  • 78
    • 56049121998 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Füßer notes this possibility, though he associates it with anarchism. Füßer, supra note 18, at 122.
    • Füßer notes this possibility, though he associates it with anarchism. Füßer, supra note 18, at 122.
  • 79
    • 56049122496 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • GRANT GILMORE, THE AGES OF AMERICAN LAW 110-11 (1977).
    • GRANT GILMORE, THE AGES OF AMERICAN LAW 110-11 (1977).
  • 80
    • 56049101433 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • E.P. THOMPSON, WHIGS AND HUNTERS: THE ORIGIN OF THE BLACK ACT 266 (1975).
    • E.P. THOMPSON, WHIGS AND HUNTERS: THE ORIGIN OF THE BLACK ACT 266 (1975).
  • 81
    • 56049114266 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • HART, supra note 24, at 91-97
    • HART, supra note 24, at 91-97.
  • 83
    • 56049085420 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Stephen Guest, Two Strands in Hart's Theory of Law, in POSITIVISM TODAY 29, 30 (Stephen Guest ed., 1996).
    • Stephen Guest, Two Strands in Hart's Theory of Law, in POSITIVISM TODAY 29, 30 (Stephen Guest ed., 1996).
  • 84
    • 56049121747 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • HART, supra note 24, at 202
    • HART, supra note 24, at 202.
  • 85
    • 56049085199 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 117
    • Id. at 117.
  • 86
    • 85008163184 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For an important discussion of this passage, from which we draw somewhat different lessons, see Jeremy Waldron, All We Like Sheep, 12 CANADIAN J.L. & JURISPRUDENCE 169, 186 (1999).
    • For an important discussion of this passage, from which we draw somewhat different lessons, see Jeremy Waldron, All We Like Sheep, 12 CANADIAN J.L. & JURISPRUDENCE 169, 186 (1999).
  • 87
    • 56049095803 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • H.L.A. HART, 1776-1976: Law in the Perspective of Philosophy, in ESSAYS IN JURISPRUDENCE AND PHILOSOPHY, supra note 51, at 145, 146-47.
    • H.L.A. HART, 1776-1976: Law in the Perspective of Philosophy, in ESSAYS IN JURISPRUDENCE AND PHILOSOPHY, supra note 51, at 145, 146-47.
  • 88
    • 56049099095 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • HART, supra note 24, at 250-54
    • HART, supra note 24, at 250-54.
  • 89
    • 56049083820 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 185-86
    • Id. at 185-86.
  • 90
    • 56049091561 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 207
    • Id. at 207.
  • 92
    • 56049117706 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • DAVID LYONS, ETHICS AND THE RULE OF LAW 63 (1984) (citing positivist view that law is not necessarily good, right, and just).
    • DAVID LYONS, ETHICS AND THE RULE OF LAW 63 (1984) (citing positivist view that "law is not necessarily good, right, and just").
  • 93
    • 56049122495 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note that this is not Füßer's weaker Fallibility Thesis, according to which under certain counterfactual circumstances the law would not be morally valuable. Füßer, supra note 18, at 128. It is instead the claim that under actual conditions, there is no guarantee that law satisfies the moral standards by which it is properly appraised.
    • Note that this is not Füßer's weaker "Fallibility Thesis," according to which "under certain counterfactual circumstances the law would not be morally valuable." Füßer, supra note 18, at 128. It is instead the claim that under actual conditions, there is no guarantee that law satisfies the moral standards by which it is properly appraised.
  • 94
    • 56049086459 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Lyons calls it a regulating principle, by which he means that it imposes a presumptive justificatory burden on those who deny it. LYONS, supra note 70, at 67 (The doctrine that law is morally fallible is not a finding of legal theory but a regulating principle.... Any theory implying the law is inherently good, right, and just will bear a heavy burden of implausibility.). My claim is stronger: No acceptable legal theory may deny it; explaining the moral fallibility of law is an adequacy condition of any successful theory of law.
    • Lyons calls it a "regulating principle," by which he means that it imposes a presumptive justificatory burden on those who deny it. LYONS, supra note 70, at 67 ("The doctrine that law is morally fallible is not a finding of legal theory but a regulating principle.... Any theory implying the law is inherently good, right, and just will bear a heavy burden of implausibility."). My claim is stronger: No acceptable legal theory may deny it; explaining the moral fallibility of law is an adequacy condition of any successful theory of law.
  • 95
    • 56049123465 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • HART, supra note 24, at 207
    • HART, supra note 24, at 207.
  • 96
    • 56049107355 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Fuller, supra note 5, at 636
    • Fuller, supra note 5, at 636.
  • 97
    • 56049107115 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hart, supra note 1, at 624
    • Hart, supra note 1, at 624.
  • 98
    • 56049100986 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ARISTOTLE, POLITICS 113-16 (Ernest Barker trans., Oxford Univ. Press 1962).
    • ARISTOTLE, POLITICS 113-16 (Ernest Barker trans., Oxford Univ. Press 1962).
  • 99
    • 56049084502 scopus 로고
    • For a classic study, with a somewhat different emphasis from mine, see generally
    • For a classic study, with a somewhat different emphasis from mine, see generally JUDITH N. SHKLAR, LEGALISM (1964).
    • (1964)
    • JUDITH, N.1    SHKLAR, L.2


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.