메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 63, Issue 6, 2010, Pages 1619-1693

Punishment as suffering

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 78649548185     PISSN: 00422533     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: None     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (52)

References (678)
  • 1
    • 71849090367 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Happiness and punishment, 76
    • When the state punishes a criminal, it inflicts suffering
    • See John Bronsteen, Christopher Buccafusco, & Jonathan Masur, Happiness and Punishment, 76 U. Chi. L. REV. 1037, 1037 (2009) ("When the state punishes a criminal, it inflicts suffering.")
    • (2009) U. Chi. L. Rev. , vol.1037 , pp. 1037
    • Bronsteen, J.1    Buccafusco, C.2    Masur, J.3
  • 2
    • 60049101482 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The subjective experience of punishment, 109
    • [T]he subjective disutility of punishment is not some mere aftereffect of punishment. Rather, it is largely or entirely the punishment itself. Subjective disutility is a necessary component of retributive punishment and constitutes, if not the sole reason for retributive punishment, certainly a major part of it.). This Article argues the contrary. While original, it is not alone. Among others, Dan Markel and Chad Flanders have taken a firm stand against contemporary subjectivists.
    • Adam Kolber, The Subjective Experience of Punishment, 109 COLUM. L. Rev. 182, 212-13 (2009) ("[T]he subjective disutility of punishment is not some mere aftereffect of punishment. Rather, it is largely or entirely the punishment itself. Subjective disutility is a necessary component of retributive punishment and constitutes, if not the sole reason for retributive punishment, certainly a major part of it."). This Article argues the contrary. While original, it is not alone. Among others, Dan Markel and Chad Flanders have taken a firm stand against contemporary subjectivists.
    • (2009) Colum. L. Rev. , vol.182 , pp. 212-213
    • Kolber, A.1
  • 3
    • 78149435403 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bentham on stilts, 98
    • forthcoming
    • See Dan Markel & Chad Flanders, Bentham on Stilts, 98 CAL. L. Rev. (forthcoming 2010).
    • (2010) Cal. L. Rev.
    • Markel, D.1    Flanders, C.2
  • 4
    • 79952796098 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This Article uses "suffering" broadly to capture the range of subjective experiences characterized as "negative" by those who experience them. "Suffering" so defined stretches well beyond physical pain
    • This Article uses "suffering" broadly to capture the range of subjective experiences characterized as "negative" by those who experience them. "Suffering" so defined stretches well beyond physical pain.
  • 5
    • 79952806870 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • While usually credited to retributivist theories of punishment, proportionality is equally a commitment of utilitarians
    • While usually credited to retributivist theories of punishment, proportionality is equally a commitment of utilitarians.
  • 6
    • 79952813220 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., CESARE Beccaria, Of Crimes and PUNISHMENTS 73-76 (Jane Grigson trans., Marsilio Publishers 1996) (1764). Kolber expresses deep reservations about proportionality, as do Bronsteen, Buccafusco, and Masur
    • See, e.g., CESARE Beccaria, Of Crimes and PUNISHMENTS 73-76 (Jane Grigson trans., Marsilio Publishers 1996) (1764). Kolber expresses deep reservations about proportionality, as do Bronsteen, Buccafusco, and Masur.
  • 7
    • 79952809727 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Kolber, supra note 1, at 185
    • See Kolber, supra note 1, at 185
  • 8
    • 78651293232 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Retribution and the experience of punishment, 98
    • As is argued below, much of this discussion is a consequence either of a confusion between objective proportionality and comparative proportionality, or a mistake in attributing to the theorists they critique the view that comparative proportionality is an independent principle when, in fact, it is wholly derivative of objective proportionality
    • see also John Bronsteen, Christopher Buccafusco & Jonathan Masur, Retribution and the Experience of Punishment, 98 CAL. L. REV. 1463,1495-96 (2010). As is argued below, much of this discussion is a consequence either of a confusion between objective proportionality and comparative proportionality, or a mistake in attributing to the theorists they critique the view that comparative proportionality is an independent principle when, in fact, it is wholly derivative of objective proportionality.
    • (2010) Cal. L. Rev. , vol.1463 , pp. 1495-1496
    • Bronsteen, J.1    Buccafusco, C.2    Masur, J.3
  • 9
    • 79952810004 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See infra Part rV.A
    • See infra Part rV.A.
  • 10
    • 79952811201 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Griffith v. Kentucky, 479 U.S. 314, 323-28 (1987) (discussing the principle of treating similarly situated defendants the same)
    • See Griffith v. Kentucky, 479 U.S. 314, 323-28 (1987) (discussing the principle of treating similarly situated defendants the same).
  • 11
    • 79952805641 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See generally Kolber, supra note 1, at 235-36 (arguing that subjective experience matters in assessments of punishment severity)
    • See generally Kolber, supra note 1, at 235-36 (arguing that subjective experience matters in assessments of punishment severity).
  • 12
    • 74849094085 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The comparative nature of punishment, 89
    • See generally, arguing that we have to measure sentence severity by comparing offenders' baseline and punished conditions
    • See generally Adam Kolber, The Comparative Nature of Punishment, 89 B.U. L. REV. 1565, 1598 (2009) (arguing that we have to measure sentence severity by comparing offenders' baseline and punished conditions).
    • (2009) B.U. L. Rev. , vol.1565 , pp. 1598
    • Kolber, A.1
  • 13
    • 79952782432 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See generally Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1037 ("[N]ew findings about human adaptability unsettle the assumptions upon which the [penal] system rests. Specifically, people adapt well to negative changes in wealth and even to many features of prison life . ⋯")
    • See generally Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1037 ("[N]ew findings about human adaptability unsettle the assumptions upon which the [penal] system rests. Specifically, people adapt well to negative changes in wealth and even to many features of prison life . ⋯").
  • 14
    • 79952805264 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Kolber, supra note 1, at 236 (arguing that any successful justification of punishment must take subjective experience into account)
    • See Kolber, supra note 1, at 236 (arguing that any successful justification of punishment must take subjective experience into account).
  • 15
    • 79952781104 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Kolber, supra note 6, at 1566 (arguing that in order to assess punishment severity accurately we must compare an offender's life in prison relative to his life in his unpunished, baseline condition)
    • See Kolber, supra note 6, at 1566 (arguing that in order to assess punishment severity accurately we must compare an offender's life in prison relative to his life in his unpunished, baseline condition).
  • 16
    • 79952791248 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1054-55 (arguing that we would need to adjust our approach to sentencing in order to create the levels of imposed harm we intend if adjustments in the size of fines and the length of prison sentences do not affect the magnitude of the negative experience of punishment in a linear fashion)
    • See Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1054-55 (arguing that we would need to adjust our approach to sentencing in order to create the levels of imposed harm we intend if adjustments in the size of fines and the length of prison sentences do not affect the magnitude of the negative experience of punishment in a linear fashion).
  • 17
    • 79952787316 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Kolber, supra note 1, at 222-23 (noting that new technologies can be expected to help in assessing a person's distress level)
    • See Kolber, supra note 1, at 222-23 (noting that new technologies can be expected to help in assessing a person's distress level)
  • 18
    • 79952807124 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The experiential future of law, 60
    • see also, forthcoming 2011 (asserting that, in the future, we will have better technologies to measure experiences such as physical pain, pain relief, emotional distress, and anxiety)
    • see also Adam Kolber, The Experiential Future of Law, 60 EMORY L. Rev. (forthcoming 2011) (asserting that, in the future, we will have better technologies to measure experiences such as physical pain, pain relief, emotional distress, and anxiety).
    • Emory L. Rev.
    • Kolber, A.1
  • 19
    • 79952800758 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1069 (arguing that punishment theory must account for different individuals' experiences of punishment).
    • See, e.g., Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1069 (arguing that punishment theory must account for different individuals' experiences of punishment).
  • 20
    • 79952780468 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Kolber, supra note 1, at 212-13, 215-16, 218-19 (arguing that any successful justification of punishment must take the subjective experience into account)
    • See, e.g., Kolber, supra note 1, at 212-13, 215-16, 218-19 (arguing that any successful justification of punishment must take the subjective experience into account).
  • 21
    • 79952794742 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • IMMANUEL KANT, THE METAPHYSICS OF MORALS 105 (Mary Gregor trans., Cambridge Univ. Press 1996) (1785)
    • IMMANUEL KANT, THE METAPHYSICS OF MORALS 105 (Mary Gregor trans., Cambridge Univ. Press 1996) (1785).
  • 22
    • 79952801354 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1068-73 (arguing that a necessary precondition to operationalizing the retributive theory is an understanding of the manner and degree to which fines and imprisonment actually negatively affect those who receive them)
    • See Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1068-73 (arguing that a necessary precondition to operationalizing the retributive theory is an understanding of the manner and degree to which fines and imprisonment actually negatively affect those who receive them)
  • 23
    • 79952804692 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 6, at 1595-97 (arguing that we must recognize the subjective severity of an offender's punishment in order to adequately justify their punishment)
    • Kolber, supra note 6, at 1595-97 (arguing that we must recognize the subjective severity of an offender's punishment in order to adequately justify their punishment)
  • 24
    • 79952780276 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 236 (arguing that retributivists should recognize that subjective experience matters in assessments of punishment severity and should take steps toward better calibrating punishment)
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 236 (arguing that retributivists should recognize that subjective experience matters in assessments of punishment severity and should take steps toward better calibrating punishment).
  • 25
    • 79952800291 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber allows that those who view punishment solely as a tool for incapacitation may be excused since they, at least, are not so distracted by suffering
    • Kolber allows that those who view punishment solely as a tool for incapacitation may be excused since they, at least, are not so distracted by suffering.
  • 26
    • 79952805633 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Kolber, supra note 1, at 218 ("[I]nterests in incapacitating people are largely independent of the subjective experience of the incapacitated.")
    • See Kolber, supra note 1, at 218 ("[I]nterests in incapacitating people are largely independent of the subjective experience of the incapacitated.").
  • 27
    • 78649553861 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Retributivists need not and should not endorse the subjectivist account of punishment, 109
    • This Article in no way denies the fact that suffering matters
    • Kenneth W. Simons, Retributivists Need Not and Should Not Endorse the Subjectivist Account of Punishment, 109 COLUM. L. REV. SIDEBAR 1, 1 (2009), http://www.columbialawreview.org/Sidebar/volume/109/l-Simons.pdf. This Article in no way denies the fact that suffering matters.
    • (2009) Colum. L. Rev. Sidebar , vol.1 , pp. 1
    • Simons, K.W.1
  • 28
    • 79952787522 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See infra Part VI
    • See infra Part VI.
  • 29
    • 79952791560 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Retribution and reform, 71
    • arguing that retributivism does not defend contemporary conditions of excessive and harsh punishment
    • See Chad Flanders, Retribution and Reform, 71 MD. L. REV. 87 (2011) (arguing that retributivism does not defend contemporary conditions of excessive and harsh punishment)
    • (2011) Md. L. Rev. , vol.87
    • Flanders, C.1
  • 30
    • 80051479081 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Retributivism for progressives, 71
    • Arguing that objective retributivism provides persuasive reason to reject much of our current punishment practice and criminal law policy
    • David Gray & Jonathan Huber, Retributivism for Progressives, 71 MD. L. REV. 163 (2010) (arguing that objective retributivism provides persuasive reason to reject much of our current punishment practice and criminal law policy).
    • (2010) Md. L. Rev. , vol.163
    • Gray, D.1    Huber, J.2
  • 31
    • 79952782873 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • How (not) to think like a punisher, 61
    • arguing that retributivism is complicit in contemporary conditions of excessive and harsh punishment
    • But see Alice Ristroph, How (Not) to Think Like a Punisher, 61 FLA. L. REV. 727, 743 (2009) (arguing that retributivism is complicit in contemporary conditions of excessive and harsh punishment).
    • (2009) Fla. L. Rev. , vol.727 , pp. 743
    • Ristroph, A.1
  • 32
    • 79952789484 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1037 (When the state punishes a criminal, it inflicts suffering)
    • See, e.g., Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1037 ("When the state punishes a criminal, it inflicts suffering.")
  • 33
    • 79952809534 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 6, at 1595-97 (arguing that the negative experiences associated with punishment are what really matters in assessing punishment severity)
    • Kolber, supra note 6, at 1595-97 (arguing that the negative experiences associated with punishment are what really matters in assessing punishment severity)
  • 34
    • 79952793790 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 212 ([T]he subjective disutility of punishment is not some mere aftereffect of punishment. Rather, it is largely or entirely the punishment itself.)
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 212 ("[T]he subjective disutility of punishment is not some mere aftereffect of punishment. Rather, it is largely or entirely the punishment itself.").
  • 35
    • 79952795341 scopus 로고
    • arguing that punishment is a symbolic medium for expressing moral condemnation and that "[g]iven our conventions, of course, condemnation is expressed by hard treatment" but that (p]ain should match guilt only insofar as its infliction is the symbolic vehicle of public condemnation
    • See JOEL FEINBERG, DOING & DESERVING 118 (1970) (arguing that punishment is a symbolic medium for expressing moral condemnation and that "[g]iven our conventions, of course, condemnation is expressed by hard treatment" but that "(p]ain should match guilt only insofar as its infliction is the symbolic vehicle of public condemnation")
    • (1970) Doing & Deserving , vol.118
    • Feinberg, J.1
  • 36
    • 78049277364 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The moral education theory of punishment
    • A. John Simmons et al. eds., 1995) (distinguishing "punishment, " which is a "disruption of the freedom to pursue the satisfaction of one's desires," from subjective experiences of punishment, which are often, but not always, painful
    • Jean Hampton, The Moral Education Theory of Punishment, in PUNISHMENT: A PHILOSOPHY & PUBLIC AFFAIRS READER 112, 128 (A. John Simmons et al. eds., 1995) (distinguishing "punishment," which is a "disruption of the freedom to pursue the satisfaction of one's desires," from subjective experiences of punishment, which are often, but not always, painful)
    • Punishment: A Philosophy & Public Affairs Reader , vol.112 , pp. 128
    • Hampton, J.1
  • 37
    • 79952783066 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A consensual theory of punishment
    • supra, at 94 (arguing that punishment is fundamentally a normative concept). I am in debt to Amanda Pustilnik for her revelatory work on pain, in which she elaborates on the temptations of this mistake in multiple fields of law
    • Carlos Nino, A Consensual Theory of Punishment, in PUNISHMENT: A PHILOSOPHY & PUBLIC AFFAIRS READER, supra, at 94, 102-05 (arguing that punishment is fundamentally a normative concept). I am in debt to Amanda Pustilnik for her revelatory work on pain, in which she elaborates on the temptations of this mistake in multiple fields of law.
    • Punishment: A Philosophy & Public Affairs Reader , pp. 102-105
    • Nino, C.1
  • 38
    • 78049440635 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Violence on the brain: A critique of neuroscience in criminal law, 44
    • [0]verreaching claims about the applicability of neuroscience may lead to misapplications similar to those of prior episodes of the criminal law-neuroscience story
    • See, e.g., Amanda Pustilnik, Violence on the Brain: A Critique of Neuroscience in Criminal Law, 44 WAKE FOREST L. REV. 183, 187 (2009) ("[0]verreaching claims about the applicability of neuroscience may lead to misapplications similar to those of prior episodes of the criminal law-neuroscience story.").
    • (2009) Wake Forest L. Rev. , vol.183 , pp. 187
    • Pustilnik, A.1
  • 39
    • 79952806864 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1071 (arguing that punishment theory must take into account the entire array of subjective negative experiences a specific punishment will have on an offender in order to increase the prospects for achieving proportional punishments)
    • See, e.g., Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1071 (arguing that punishment theory must take into account the entire array of subjective negative experiences a specific punishment will have on an offender in order to increase the prospects for achieving proportional punishments).
  • 40
    • 79952813803 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 6, at 1587-88
    • Kolber, supra note 6, at 1587-88.
  • 41
    • 79952785907 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 188
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 188.
  • 42
    • 79952808112 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1050-55
    • Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1050-55
  • 43
    • 79952812779 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bronsteen et al., supra note 3, at 1496 (arguing that punishment severity is based on the negative experiences associated with the punishment, which should include the typical effects that incarceration has on offenders' lives after prison)
    • Bronsteen et al., supra note 3, at 1496 (arguing that punishment severity is based on the negative experiences associated with the punishment, which should include the typical effects that incarceration has on offenders' lives after prison).
  • 44
    • 79952777166 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See infra Part IV.A. There are, as Mitchell Berman points out in a recent book chapter, some punishment theorists who identify themselves as "retributivists" who endorse suffering as a goal of punishment. Mitchell Berman, Two Types of Retributivism, in, (R.A. Duff & Stuart Green eds.) (forthcoming 2010) (manuscript at 7), available at (cited with permission of author). According to Berman, these theorists hold that offenders deserve to suffer for their crimes
    • See infra Part IV.A. There are, as Mitchell Berman points out in a recent book chapter, some punishment theorists who identify themselves as "retributivists" who endorse suffering as a goal of punishment. Mitchell Berman, Two Types of Retributivism, in THE PHILOSOPHICAL FOUNDATIONS OF CRIMINAL Law (R.A. Duff & Stuart Green eds.) (forthcoming 2010) (manuscript at 7), available at http://ssrn.com/abstract=1592546 (cited with permission of author). According to Berman, these theorists hold that offenders deserve to suffer for their crimes.
    • The Philosophical Foundations of Criminal Law
  • 45
    • 79952798006 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 46
    • 79952799704 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Berman carefully teases out the serious theoretical and practical challenges faced by these theorists, who are committed to a version of instrumentalis
    • Berman carefully teases out the serious theoretical and practical challenges faced by these theorists, who are committed to a version of instrumentalism.
  • 47
    • 79952802711 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 48
    • 79952777984 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (manuscript at 8-16). For many of those reasons, and for reasons elaborated in Parts III and rV, infra, this Article uses " retributivist" to refer to and to promote objectivist theories of retributivism
    • (manuscript at 8-16). For many of those reasons, and for reasons elaborated in Parts III and rV, infra, this Article uses " retributivist" to refer to and to promote objectivist theories of retributivism.
  • 49
    • 79952784839 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See FEINBERG, supra note 20, at 116-18 (arguing that social disapproval and its appropriate expression is what should fit the crime, and not the amount of subjective suffering experienced by the offender)
    • See FEINBERG, supra note 20, at 116-18 (arguing that social disapproval and its appropriate expression is what should fit the crime, and not the amount of subjective suffering experienced by the offender).
  • 50
    • 79952783862 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Kolber, supra note 6, at 1582-83, 1600-06 (arguing that retributivism fails to adhere to one of its central features-prohibiting disproportional punishments-when it fails to calibrate punishment based on an offender's baseline subjective state)
    • See Kolber, supra note 6, at 1582-83, 1600-06 (arguing that retributivism fails to adhere to one of its central features-prohibiting disproportional punishments-when it fails to calibrate punishment based on an offender's baseline subjective state)
  • 51
    • 79952809134 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 199-216 (In order to meet the proportionality requirement, retributivists must measure punishment severity in a manner that is sensitive to individuals' experiences of punishment or else they are punishing people to an extent that exceeds justification
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 199-216 ("In order to meet the proportionality requirement, retributivists must measure punishment severity in a manner that is sensitive to individuals' experiences of punishment or else they are punishing people to an extent that exceeds justification.").
  • 52
    • 79952780096 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Kolber, supra note 1, at 183 (arguing that many retributivists would sentence different offenders to different punishments even if they commit the same crime because of the differences in the offenders' subjective experiences of punishment)
    • See Kolber, supra note 1, at 183 (arguing that many retributivists would sentence different offenders to different punishments even if they commit the same crime because of the differences in the offenders' subjective experiences of punishment).
  • 53
    • 79952790033 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1074-75
    • Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1074-75.
  • 54
    • 62749097388 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Who is the happy warrior? Philosophy poses questions to psychology, 37
    • See generally (criticizing the thin account of human agents endorsed by the psychology literature of hedonic flow)
    • See generally Martha Nussbaum, Who Is the Happy Warrior? Philosophy Poses Questions to Psychology, 37 J. LEGAL STUD. 81 (2008) (criticizing the thin account of human agents endorsed by the psychology literature of hedonic flow).
    • (2008) J. Legal Stud. , vol.81
    • Nussbaum, M.1
  • 55
    • 79952808299 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Richard Kraut and Martha Nussbaum are two of the most compelling contemporary voices of the ancients
    • Richard Kraut and Martha Nussbaum are two of the most compelling contemporary voices of the ancients.
  • 56
    • 79952799352 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See generally, e.g., RICHARD KRAUT, WHAT IS GOOD AND WHY: THE ETHICS OF WELL-BEING (2007)
    • See generally, e.g., RICHARD KRAUT, WHAT IS GOOD AND WHY: THE ETHICS OF WELL-BEING (2007)
  • 58
    • 0344453893 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Capabilities as fundamental entitlements, 9
    • hereinafter Nussbaum, Capabilities
    • Martha Nussbaum, Capabilities as Fundamental Entitlements, 9 FEMINIST ECON. 33 (2003) [hereinafter Nussbaum, Capabilities].
    • (2003) Feminist Econ. , vol.33
    • Nussbaum, M.1
  • 59
    • 79952777168 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • While perhaps not the most nuanced, Judge Richard Posner is one of the most prominent of the contemporary technical utilitarians. Nevertheless, as Adam Kolber notes, even Judge Posner resists the idea that punishment should be measured or calibrated by reference to the subjective disutility inflicted upon individual offenders
    • While perhaps not the most nuanced, Judge Richard Posner is one of the most prominent of the contemporary technical utilitarians. Nevertheless, as Adam Kolber notes, even Judge Posner resists the idea that punishment should be measured or calibrated by reference to the subjective disutility inflicted upon individual offenders.
  • 60
    • 79952789653 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Kolber, supra note 1, at 194 n.36 (citing a specific example where Judge Richard Posner declined to adjust an offender's sentence downwards despite the offender's "high sensitivity" argument)
    • See Kolber, supra note 1, at 194 n.36 (citing a specific example where Judge Richard Posner declined to adjust an offender's sentence downwards despite the offender's "high sensitivity" argument).
  • 61
    • 79952793600 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bronsteen, Buccafusco, and Masur note this asymmetry
    • Bronsteen, Buccafusco, and Masur note this "asymmetry."
  • 62
    • 79952777791 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1060-61 ("Deterrence ⋯ is an ex ante phenomenon: the important issue is what harm the prospective criminal believes she will suffer if she is caught and punished, not the harm that she eventually experiences."). Dan Markel and Chad Flanders discuss this asymmetry at length in an exchange with Bronsteen, Buccafusco, and Masur. Compare Markel & Flanders
    • See Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1060-61 ("Deterrence ⋯ is an ex ante phenomenon: the important issue is what harm the prospective criminal believes she will suffer if she is caught and punished, not the harm that she eventually experiences."). Dan Markel and Chad Flanders discuss this asymmetry at length in an exchange with Bronsteen, Buccafusco, and Masur. Compare Markel & Flanders
  • 63
    • 79952806865 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 1 (arguing that the variance in the experience of punishment is not critically relevant to the shape and justification of punishments), with Bronsteen et al
    • supra note 1 (arguing that the variance in the experience of punishment is not critically relevant to the shape and justification of punishments), with Bronsteen et al.
  • 64
    • 79952802912 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 3, at 1467-81 (arguing that the law should account for the differences in punishment experience when deciding how, and how much, to punish)
    • supra note 3, at 1467-81 (arguing that the law should account for the differences in punishment experience when deciding how, and how much, to punish).
  • 65
    • 79952790260 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1037
    • Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1037.
  • 66
    • 79952790666 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 6, at 1599 n.89
    • Kolber, supra note 6, at 1599 n.89.
  • 67
    • 79952780097 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 222-23
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 222-23.
  • 68
    • 0004125178 scopus 로고
    • See generally (Alan Sheridan trans., Vintage Books 2d ed. 1995) (discussing the historical impact of social normalization on criminal law)
    • See generally MICHEL FOUCAULT, DISCIPLINE AND PUNISH (Alan Sheridan trans., Vintage Books 2d ed. 1995) (1979) (discussing the historical impact of social normalization on criminal law).
    • (1979) Discipline and Punish
    • Foucault, M.1
  • 69
    • 79952776591 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Jeremy Bentham, The Panopticon Writings (Miran Bozovic ed., Verso 1995) (1787)
    • Jeremy Bentham, The Panopticon Writings (Miran Bozovic ed., Verso 1995) (1787).
  • 70
    • 79952796855 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It is worth noting that the American Law Institute is poised to abandon the commitment to utilitarian concerns as the sole justification of punishment in the Model Penal Code
    • It is worth noting that the American Law Institute is poised to abandon the commitment to utilitarian concerns as the sole justification of punishment in the Model Penal Code.
  • 71
    • 79952799163 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See infra note 199 and accompanying text
    • See infra note 199 and accompanying text.
  • 72
    • 79952793373 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Kolber, supra note 11 (arguing that the content of the law should change to pay more direct attention to experiences because more reliable technologies to measure such experiences are becoming available)
    • See Kolber, supra note 11 (arguing that the content of the law should change to pay more direct attention to experiences because more reliable technologies to measure such experiences are becoming available)
  • 73
    • 79952795908 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 222-23 (noting that emerging neuroscience technologies may allow more accurate assessments of individuals' subjective experiences in response to the argument that a system of subjectively calibrated punishments would be impossible or prohibitively expensive to fairly administer)
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 222-23 (noting that emerging neuroscience technologies may allow more accurate assessments of individuals' subjective experiences in response to the argument that a system of subjectively calibrated punishments would be impossible or prohibitively expensive to fairly administer).
  • 74
    • 79952799532 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1039-40, 1048 n.67
    • Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1039-40, 1048 n.67.
  • 75
    • 79952809542 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The psychology literature on happiness has been applied to other areas of law as well
    • The psychology literature on happiness has been applied to other areas of law as well.
  • 76
    • 56849084593 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hedonic adaptation and the settlement of civil lawsuits, 108
    • 1518 (reviewing recent research in hedonic psychology and applying it to the settlement of personal injury claims, arguing that procedural delays have a counterintuitive corrective function because injured parties' initial perceptions of harm suffered actually have little overall effect on ultimate well-being)
    • See, e.g., John Bronsteen, Christopher Buccafusco, & Jonathan Masur, Hedonic Adaptation and the Settlement of Civil Lawsuits, 108 COLUM. L. REV. 1516, 1518, 1527-35 (2008) (reviewing recent research in hedonic psychology and applying it to the settlement of personal injury claims, arguing that procedural delays have a counterintuitive corrective function because injured parties' initial perceptions of harm suffered actually have little overall effect on ultimate well-being)
    • (2008) Colum. L. Rev. , vol.1516 , pp. 1527-1535
    • Bronsteen, J.1    Buccafusco, C.2    Masur, J.3
  • 77
    • 79952809129 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Authentic happiness and meaning at law firms, 58
    • 345-50 (considering recent research applying behavioral economics and positive psychology to studies of lawyer happiness and recommending changes in law school and law firm culture and training)
    • Peter Huang & Rick Swedloff, Authentic Happiness and Meaning at Law Firms, 58 SYRACUSE L. REV. 335, 339-42, 345-50 (2008) (considering recent research applying behavioral economics and positive psychology to studies of lawyer happiness and recommending changes in law school and law firm culture and training).
    • (2008) Syracuse L. Rev. , vol.335 , pp. 339-342
    • Huang, P.1    Swedloff, R.2
  • 78
    • 79952794946 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1055-81
    • Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1055-81.
  • 79
    • 79952802523 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 11 (manuscript at 3, 13-47)
    • Kolber, supra note 11 (manuscript at 3, 13-47).
  • 80
    • 79952795915 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1041
    • Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1041.
  • 81
    • 79952779891 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 11 (manuscript at 3-4, 8, 48-50)
    • Kolber, supra note 11 (manuscript at 3-4, 8, 48-50)
  • 82
    • 79952810607 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Precis of philosophy and neuroscience: A ruthlessly reductive account, 4
    • (suggesting key neurobiological research is overlooked in the psychological literature and arguing that psychological explanations should be resigned to more heuristic roles exploring questions for which low-level cellular and molecular mechanisms of inquiry do not yet exist)
    • see, e.g., John Bickle, Precis of Philosophy and Neuroscience: A Ruthlessly Reductive Account, 4 Phenomenology & Cognitive Sci. 231, 232-37 (2005) (suggesting key neurobiological research is overlooked in the psychological literature and arguing that psychological explanations should be resigned to more heuristic roles exploring questions for which low-level cellular and molecular mechanisms of inquiry do not yet exist)
    • (2005) Phenomenology & Cognitive Sci. , vol.231 , pp. 232-237
    • Bickle, J.1
  • 83
    • 21844502417 scopus 로고
    • Psychoneural reduction of the genuinely cognitive: Some accomplished facts, 8
    • 282 (looking at empirical developments in the brain and behavioral sciences and suggesting cognitivist and psychological theories of behavior will be increasingly supplanted by neurophysiological accounts)
    • John Bickle, Psychoneural Reduction of the Genuinely Cognitive: Some Accomplished Facts, 8 PHIL. PSYCHOL. 265, 275-77, 282 (1995) (looking at empirical developments in the brain and behavioral sciences and suggesting cognitivist and psychological theories of behavior will be increasingly supplanted by neurophysiological accounts)
    • (1995) Phil. Psychol. , vol.265 , pp. 275-277
    • Bickle, J.1
  • 84
    • 24944474908 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ruthless reductionism, 18
    • (responding to Bickle and arguing for a continuing productive relationship between psychology and neuroscience)
    • Huib de Jong & Maurice Schouten, Ruthless Reductionism, 18 PHIL. PSYCHOL. 473, 478-485 (2005) (responding to Bickle and arguing for a continuing productive relationship between psychology and neuroscience)
    • (2005) Phil. Psychol. , vol.473 , pp. 478-485
    • De Jong, H.1    Schouten, M.2
  • 85
    • 79952796097 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nussbaum, supra note 30, at 86-101 (arguing that psychological literature investigating subjective well-being is replete with unquestioned normative assumptions and unacknowledged conceptual ambiguity that undermine its usefulness)
    • Nussbaum, supra note 30, at 86-101 (arguing that psychological literature investigating subjective well-being is replete with unquestioned normative assumptions and unacknowledged conceptual ambiguity that undermine its usefulness).
  • 86
    • 79952810003 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 182
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 182
  • 87
    • 79952813647 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also (J.H. Burns & H.L.A. Hart eds., Oxford Univ. Press 1996) (1807) (noting the circumstances that influence sensibility)
    • see also JEREMY BENTHAM, The PRINCIPLES OF MORALS AND OF LEGISLATION 51-73 (J.H. Burns & H.L.A. Hart eds., Oxford Univ. Press 1996) (1807) (noting the circumstances that influence sensibility)
    • The Principles of Morals and of Legislation , pp. 51-73
    • Bentham, J.1
  • 88
    • 84972348103 scopus 로고
    • Legislating the transcendental: Von hirsch's proportionality, 51
    • suggesting failure to account for subjective "sensibility" differences among those punished may undermine utilitarian theories rooted in personal deterrence
    • Nigel Walker, Legislating The Transcendental: Von Hirsch's Proportionality, 51 CAMBRIDGE L.J. 530, 533-34 (1992) (suggesting failure to account for subjective "sensibility" differences among those punished may undermine utilitarian theories rooted in personal deterrence).
    • (1992) Cambridge L.J. , vol.530 , pp. 533-534
    • Walker, N.1
  • 89
    • 79952781712 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 1,184, 231
    • Kolber, supra note 1,184, 231.
  • 90
    • 79952811596 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 189
    • Id. at 189.
  • 91
    • 79952779125 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 187 & n.5
    • Id. at 187 & n.5.
  • 92
    • 79952799705 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 190-91
    • Id. at 190-91.
  • 93
    • 79952803320 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • While not at all trivial for practical penology, as is argued below, the example holds no sway in core theoretical debates. The suffering a claustrophobe feels in the form of severe anxiety is incidental to incarceration as a punitive constraint on liberty. There is no contest that incidental suffering secondary to objectively justified punishment may raise independent moral, constitutional, legal, or institutional questions; incidental suffering may even rise to the level that amelioration or adaptation of penal technology is required. However, these practical issues need not and do not pose a challenge to traditional theories of punishment because punishment is neither justified nor measured by its ability to cause suffering.
  • 94
    • 79952805072 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1046-49 & nn.58-67 (citing research indicating improved adaptation and a decrease of emotional trauma in many prisoners over the course of their sentences)
    • See Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1046-49 & nn.58-67 (citing research indicating improved adaptation and a decrease of emotional trauma in many prisoners over the course of their sentences).
  • 95
    • 79952778363 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Kolber, supra note 1, at 187 n.5, 213 n.88, 215-16, 220. As is argued below, this choice of words suggests that something has gone wrong in subjectivist attack on retributivism
    • See Kolber, supra note 1, at 187 n.5, 213 n.88, 215-16, 220. As is argued below, this choice of words suggests that something has gone wrong in subjectivist attack on retributivism.
  • 96
    • 79952779500 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See infra Part rV
    • See infra Part rV.
  • 97
    • 79952791564 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 184
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 184.
  • 98
    • 79952782101 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 199
    • Id. at 199.
  • 99
    • 79952808488 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As Kolber points out, his critical argument is agnostic as to whether proportionality in either form must or ought to be a constraint on punishment practices. Rather, his argument proceeds from the quite accurate claim that retributivists are committed to the claim that proportionality must and ought to be a constraint on punishment practices. Kolber's critical project is to leverage that commitment using the fulcrum of subjectivism. As is argued here, retributivists need not be subjectivists and, at least in light of Kolber's arguments, ought not be subjectivists
    • As Kolber points out, his critical argument is agnostic as to whether proportionality in either form must or ought to be a constraint on punishment practices. Rather, his argument proceeds from the quite accurate claim that retributivists are committed to the claim that proportionality must and ought to be a constraint on punishment practices. Kolber's critical project is to leverage that commitment using the fulcrum of subjectivism. As is argued here, retributivists need not be subjectivists and, at least in light of Kolber's arguments, ought not be subjectivists.
  • 100
    • 79952778370 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See generally (Oct. 13, 2009), available at (describing proportionality across cases as a "cardinal precept in retributivist theory")- As is pointed out in Part IV, this commitment to comparative proportionality is not independent. Rather, it is wholly a consequence of the commitment to objective proportionality
    • See generally Talia Fisher, Comparative Sentencing 39-40 (Oct. 13, 2009), available at http://ssrn.com/abstract=1488345 (describing proportionality across cases as a "cardinal precept in retributivist theory")- As is pointed out in Part IV, this commitment to comparative proportionality is not independent. Rather, it is wholly a consequence of the commitment to objective proportionality.
    • Comparative Sentencing , pp. 39-40
    • Fisher, T.1
  • 101
    • 79952794543 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 186-87
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 186-87.
  • 102
    • 79952777798 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 103
    • 79952782877 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 104
    • 79952778967 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 187, 215-16. "Comparative proportionality" should not be confused with Kolber's critique based on the comparative nature of punishment
    • Id. at 187, 215-16. "Comparative proportionality" should not be confused with Kolber's critique based on the comparative nature of punishment.
  • 105
    • 79952809133 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • John Stuart Mill, Utilitarianism 48 (George Sher ed., Hackett Publ'g 1979) (4th ed. 1871)
    • John Stuart Mill, Utilitarianism 48 (George Sher ed., Hackett Publ'g 1979) (4th ed. 1871).
  • 106
    • 79952800757 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 7
    • Id. at 7.
  • 107
    • 79952808916 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 108
    • 79952794949 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Kolber, supra note 1, at 216-17 (discussing utilitarian theories of punishment as deterrence and the goals of optimal punishment)
    • See Kolber, supra note 1, at 216-17 (discussing utilitarian theories of punishment as deterrence and the goals of optimal punishment)
  • 109
    • 79952801770 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also Kolber, supra note 6, at 1583 (further noting utilitarian balancing of pain and happiness)
    • see also Kolber, supra note 6, at 1583 (further noting utilitarian balancing of pain and happiness).
  • 110
    • 79952789489 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 216-219
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 216-219.
  • 111
    • 79952788115 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MILL, supra note 56, at 7
    • MILL, supra note 56, at 7.
  • 112
    • 79952789652 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As in his critique of retributivism, the critical guidance Kolber offers to utilitarians is drawn from their own commitments. His critical agenda is carefully agnostic as to ultimately endorsing any positive theory of punishment
    • As in his critique of retributivism, the critical guidance Kolber offers to utilitarians is drawn from their own commitments. His critical agenda is carefully agnostic as to ultimately endorsing any positive theory of punishment.
  • 113
    • 79952810808 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 235-36
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 235-36
  • 114
    • 79952792984 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also Kolber, supra note 6, at 1608 (critiquing proportional retributivism but acknowledging there may be other reasons to prefer retributivism to consequentialism)
    • see also Kolber, supra note 6, at 1608 (critiquing proportional retributivism but acknowledging "there may be other reasons to prefer retributivism to consequentialism").
  • 115
    • 79952787714 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 186, 216-220, 230-35
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 186, 216-220, 230-35.
  • 116
    • 79952788110 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 186, 198, 216
    • Id. at 186, 198, 216.
  • 117
    • 79952800286 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 6, at 1573
    • Kolber, supra note 6, at 1573.
  • 118
    • 79952798739 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 55
    • See supra note 55.
  • 119
    • 79952796856 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 6, at 1568-69
    • Kolber, supra note 6, at 1568-69
  • 120
    • 79952799347 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 196-99
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 196-99.
  • 121
    • 79952793788 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 6, at 1571-73
    • Kolber, supra note 6, at 1571-73.
  • 122
    • 79952810407 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1571-75
    • Id. at 1571-75.
  • 123
    • 79952801166 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 124
    • 79952811390 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber grounds this argument in Joel Feinberg's influential work on measures of harm in the tort context
    • Kolber grounds this argument in Joel Feinberg's influential work on measures of harm in the tort context.
  • 125
    • 79952786930 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1571-72
    • Id. at 1571-72
  • 128
    • 79952810188 scopus 로고
    • Noncomparative justice, 83
    • In another important essay Feinberg analyzes the differences between comparative and noncomparative conceptions of justice and points out that noncomparative measures play a dominant role in the criminal field, 311-13
    • In another important essay Feinberg analyzes the differences between comparative and noncomparative conceptions of justice and points out that noncomparative measures play a dominant role in the criminal field. Joel Feinberg, Noncomparative Justice, 83 PHIL. REV. 297, 300-01, 311-13 (1974) [hereinafter Feinberg, Noncomparative Justice]. Elsewhere, Feinberg provides a muscular rejection of subjective suffering as a goal, measure, or justification of punishment. FEINBERG
    • (1974) Phil. Rev. , vol.297 , pp. 300-301
    • Feinberg, J.1
  • 129
    • 79952812585 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 20, at 116-118
    • supra note 20, at 116-118.
  • 130
    • 79952794741 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 6, at 1573-75. Bronsteen, Buccafusco, and Masur's work on hedonic adaptation may have some relevance to this account
    • Kolber, supra note 6, at 1573-75. Bronsteen, Buccafusco, and Masur's work on hedonic adaptation may have some relevance to this account.
  • 131
    • 79952789285 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1041-54
    • See Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1041-54.
  • 132
    • 79952781711 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • If the temporal arc of punishment finds the offender returning to his baseline in very short order, then it may turn out that, measured comparatively, many punishments we regard as quite severe are not so severe at all
    • If the temporal arc of punishment finds the offender returning to his baseline in very short order, then it may turn out that, measured comparatively, many punishments we regard as quite severe are not so severe at all.
  • 133
    • 79952798941 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See infra Parts II. C and V
    • See infra Parts II. C and V.
  • 134
    • 79952795157 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 6, at 1571-75
    • Kolber, supra note 6, at 1571-75.
  • 135
    • 79952795714 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra Part II.A
    • See supra Part II.A.
  • 136
    • 79952788111 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 6, at 1582-83
    • Kolber, supra note 6, at 1582-83.
  • 137
    • 79952793591 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1582
    • Id. at 1582.
  • 138
    • 79952792759 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also id. at 1582-83, 1600-07 (arguing that retributivists abandon proportionalism at great cost and should instead adopt calibration within a comparative framework)
    • see also id. at 1582-83, 1600-07 (arguing that retributivists abandon proportionalism at great cost and should instead adopt calibration within a comparative framework).
  • 139
    • 79952776592 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 140
    • 79952809541 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 141
    • 79952805640 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1567-68, 1600
    • Id. at 1567-68, 1600.
  • 142
    • 79952792542 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As Kolber recognizes, this generalization based on an assumption should not be given too much empirical weight, but is offered as a thought experiment to make his point. Work by Bronsteen, Buccafusco, and Masur show the wisdom of Kolber's caution
    • at 1567-68, 1600. As Kolber recognizes, this generalization based on an assumption should not be given too much empirical weight, but is offered as a thought experiment to make his point. Work by Bronsteen, Buccafusco, and Masur show the wisdom of Kolber's caution.
  • 143
    • 79952807123 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See infra Part II.C
    • See infra Part II.C.
  • 144
    • 79952806926 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The symbolic power of money, 20
    • The complicated role of money in generating and modifying subjective states is also explored in a recent study where researchers found that, compared to a control group, subjects who had just counted money reported less suffering in response to painful stimuli
    • The complicated role of money in generating and modifying subjective states is also explored in a recent study where researchers found that, compared to a control group, subjects who had just counted money reported less suffering in response to painful stimuli. Xinyue Zhou, Kathleen D. Vohs & Roy F. Baumeister, The Symbolic Power of Money, 20 Psychol. Sci. 700,702-04 (2009).
    • (2009) Psychol. Sci. , vol.700 , pp. 702-704
    • Zhou, X.1    Vohs, K.D.2    Baumeister, R.F.3
  • 145
    • 79952794212 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 6, at 1567-68
    • Kolber, supra note 6, at 1567-68.
  • 146
    • 79952797227 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1582-83, 1600-07
    • Id. at 1582-83, 1600-07.
  • 147
    • 79952813446 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1600-07
    • Id. at 1600-07.
  • 148
    • 79952783861 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1583-84; Kolber, supra note 1, at 236
    • Id. at 1583-84; Kolber, supra note 1, at 236.
  • 149
    • 79952781103 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 6, at 1583-85, 1594-1600
    • Kolber, supra note 6, at 1583-85, 1594-1600.
  • 150
    • 79952783662 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1583-84
    • Id. at 1583-84.
  • 151
    • 79952780098 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 1583-84, 1596
    • See id. at 1583-84, 1596.
  • 152
    • 79952786710 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 216-19
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 216-19.
  • 153
    • 79952795151 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Kolber, supra note 6, at 1583-84,1596
    • See Kolber, supra note 6, at 1583-84,1596.
  • 154
    • 79952811958 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 187, 216-19
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 187, 216-19.
  • 155
    • 79952793592 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1039 (citing Kolber, supra note 6, at 1596)
    • Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1039 (citing Kolber, supra note 6, at 1596).
  • 156
    • 79952787523 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1039
    • Id. at 1039.
  • 157
    • 79952789839 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also Bronsteen et al
    • see also Bronsteen et al.
  • 158
    • 79952789648 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 3, at 1478-81, 1482-95 (extending this argument)
    • supra note 3, at 1478-81, 1482-95 (extending this argument).
  • 159
    • 79952784625 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bronsteen et al
    • Bronsteen et al.
  • 160
    • 79952781715 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 1, at 1039-41
    • supra note 1, at 1039-41.
  • 161
    • 0348138290 scopus 로고
    • Punishment, 48
    • Calling to mind Mark Twain's quip that "reports of my death are greatly exaggerated," in 1939 J.D. Mabbott reported the common belief that the retributive view is the only moral theory except perhaps psychological hedonism which has been definitely destroyed by criticism
    • Calling to mind Mark Twain's quip that "reports of my death are greatly exaggerated," in 1939 J.D. Mabbott reported the common belief that "the retributive view is the only moral theory except perhaps psychological hedonism which has been definitely destroyed by criticism . ⋯" J.D. Mabbott, Punishment, 48 MIND 152, 152 (1939).
    • (1939) Mind , vol.152 , pp. 152
    • Mabbott, J.D.1
  • 162
    • 79952798371 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bronsteen et al
    • Bronsteen et al.
  • 163
    • 79952783246 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 1, at 1039-46
    • supra note 1, at 1039-46.
  • 164
    • 79952785322 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1041
    • Id. at 1041.
  • 165
    • 79952780464 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1041-42
    • Id. at 1041-42.
  • 166
    • 79952785908 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1045-49
    • Id. at 1045-49.
  • 167
    • 79952783061 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 168
    • 79952799706 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1045-46
    • Id. at 1045-46.
  • 169
    • 79952779126 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also id.at 1038-39, 1058-59, 1069-70 (suggesting implications of such adaptation)
    • see also id.at 1038-39, 1058-59, 1069-70 (suggesting implications of such adaptation).
  • 170
    • 79952798008 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1053-55
    • Id. at 1053-55.
  • 171
    • 79952813219 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1055-57, 1070
    • Id. at 1055-57, 1070.
  • 172
    • 79952810807 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1053-55
    • Id. at 1053-55.
  • 173
    • 79952793380 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 84 and accompanying text
    • See supra note 84 and accompanying text.
  • 174
    • 79952777364 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • But see Zhou et al., supra note 76, at 704-05 (reporting data suggesting that threatened loss of money can enhance subjective experiences of pain)
    • But see Zhou et al., supra note 76, at 704-05 (reporting data suggesting that threatened loss of money can enhance subjective experiences of pain).
  • 175
    • 79952810002 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1043-44
    • Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1043-44.
  • 176
    • 79952808700 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 177
    • 79952798015 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1049-55
    • Id. at 1049-55.
  • 178
    • 79952795914 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1052-54
    • Id. at 1052-54
  • 179
    • 79952807319 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also infra note 103
    • see also infra note 103.
  • 180
    • 79952784428 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The authors make the quite insightful point that dramatic and sustained reductions in happiness postrelease may contribute to recidivism by reducing convicts' subjective assessments of their prospective reductions in happiness if they reoffend, are caught, convicted, and reincarcerated because, in a real sense, they have little left to lose. Bronsteen et al
    • The authors make the quite insightful point that dramatic and sustained reductions in happiness postrelease may contribute to recidivism by reducing convicts' subjective assessments of their prospective reductions in happiness if they reoffend, are caught, convicted, and reincarcerated because, in a real sense, they have little left to lose. Bronsteen et al.
  • 181
    • 79952807122 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 1, at 1066-67
    • supra note 1, at 1066-67.
  • 182
    • 33747482645 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • An integrated perspective on the collateral consequences of criminal convictions and reentry issues faced by formerly incarcerated individuals, 86
    • explaining that reentry-related services are available while noting the significant challenges formerly incarcerated individuals still face
    • See, e.g., Michael Pinard, An Integrated Perspective on the Collateral Consequences of Criminal Convictions and Reentry Issues Faced by Formerly Incarcerated Individuals, 86 B.U. L. REV. 623, 626-32 (2006) (explaining that reentry-related services are available while noting the significant challenges formerly incarcerated individuals still face)
    • (2006) B.U. L. Rev. , vol.623 , pp. 626-632
    • Pinard, M.1
  • 183
    • 79952801172 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A reentry-centered vision of criminal justice, 20
    • arguing for a criminal justice system more focused on reentry, to help the growing numbers of individuals with criminal records face the challenges of reentry
    • Michael Pinard, A Reentry-Centered Vision of Criminal Justice, 20 FED. SENTg REP. 103, 103 (2007) (arguing for a criminal justice system more focused on reentry, to help the growing numbers of individuals with criminal records face the challenges of reentry)
    • (2007) Fed. Sentg Rep. , vol.103 , pp. 103
    • Pinard, M.1
  • 184
    • 77954756012 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Collateral consequences of criminal convictions: Confronting issues of race and dignity, 85
    • explaining that scholars, attorneys, and others who have considered reentry issues generally recognize that the problem of postconviction collateral consequences is rapidly becoming more severe
    • Michael Pinard, Collateral Consequences of Criminal Convictions: Confronting Issues of Race and Dignity, 85 N.Y.U. L. REV. 457, 459-61 (2010) (explaining that scholars, attorneys, and others who have considered reentry issues "generally recognize that the problem of postconviction collateral consequences is rapidly becoming more severe")
    • (2010) N.Y.U. L. Rev. , vol.457 , pp. 459-461
    • Pinard, M.1
  • 185
    • 79952787525 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Offender reentry and the collateral consequences of criminal convictions: An introduction, 30
    • [Tjhe most pressing problems that the ex-offender encounters are the obstacles that interfere with the ability to make a smooth transition to being a productive member of the community
    • Michael Pinard & Anthony C. Thompson, Offender Reentry and the Collateral Consequences of Criminal Convictions: An Introduction, 30 N.Y.U. REV. L. & Soc. CHANGE 585, 594 (2006) ("[Tjhe most pressing problems that the ex-offender encounters are the obstacles that interfere with the ability to make a smooth transition to being a productive member of the community.").
    • (2006) N.Y.U. Rev. L. & Soc. Change , vol.585 , pp. 594
    • Pinard, M.1    Thompson, A.C.2
  • 186
    • 79952780700 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., A HARD STRAIGHT (New Day Films 2004)
    • See, e.g., A HARD STRAIGHT (New Day Films 2004).
  • 187
    • 79952785708 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1044-45, 1060-61
    • Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1044-45, 1060-61.
  • 188
    • 79952806224 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1045
    • Id. at 1045.
  • 189
    • 79952807510 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 1061
    • See id. at 1061
  • 190
    • 79952792536 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • People, as a general rule, do not remember their adaptive responses to negative stimuli
    • ("People, as a general rule, do not remember their adaptive responses to negative stimuli.").
  • 191
    • 79952778182 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id
    • See id.
  • 192
    • 79952804125 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1048-49
    • Id. at 1048-49.
  • 193
    • 79952796470 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1071-74
    • Id. at 1071-74.
  • 194
    • 79952784838 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See infra Part V.B (explaining the argument of Bronsteen, Buccafusco, and Masur that the phenomena of adaptation and of the human inability to predict personal future adaptation "are in tension with traditional theory and current practice because the deterrent 'bang' is all frontloaded," and thus, "longer sentences ⋯ serve no utilitarian purpose")
    • See infra Part V.B (explaining the argument of Bronsteen, Buccafusco, and Masur that the phenomena of adaptation and of the human inability to predict personal future adaptation "are in tension with traditional theory and current practice because the deterrent 'bang' is all frontloaded," and thus, "longer sentences ⋯ serve no utilitarian purpose").
  • 195
    • 79952806429 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1071-74
    • Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1071-74.
  • 196
    • 79952780102 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 1074-75 (If less punishment can achieve the desired end, then society gains monetarily by eschewing a more severe alternative (in particular, a longer prison sentence)
    • See id. at 1074-75 ("If less punishment can achieve the desired end, then society gains monetarily by eschewing a more severe alternative (in particular, a longer prison sentence).").
  • 197
    • 79952789845 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 1061-62
    • See id. at 1061-62
  • 198
    • 79952803923 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Explaining that failing to take adaptation into account will result in calculations of punishment that are higher than necessary, from consequentialist standpoint. This author does not contest this conclusion, but would argue for it on retributive grounds
    • at 1061-62 (explaining that failing to take adaptation into account will result in calculations of punishment that are higher than necessary, from consequentialist standpoint). This author does not contest this conclusion, but would argue for it on retributive grounds.
  • 199
    • 79952805834 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Gray & Huber, supra note 18
    • See Gray & Huber, supra note 18.
  • 200
    • 79952777985 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 215-16
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 215-16
  • 201
    • 79952809535 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also Kolber, supra note 6, at 1595 (summarizing the argument in The Subjective Experience of Punishment that "even if the disvalue of punishment consists of more than just negative subjective experiences, those experiences are at least part of what makes punishment burdensome"). Kolber makes the same claim about consequentialist theories of punishment
    • see also Kolber, supra note 6, at 1595 (summarizing the argument in The Subjective Experience of Punishment that "even if the disvalue of punishment consists of more than just negative subjective experiences, those experiences are at least part of what makes punishment burdensome"). Kolber makes the same claim about consequentialist theories of punishment.
  • 202
    • 79952791752 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 216-17. Bronsteen, Buccafusco, and Masur explicitly endorse Kolber's views on these key points. Bronsteen et al
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 216-17. Bronsteen, Buccafusco, and Masur explicitly endorse Kolber's views on these key points. Bronsteen et al.
  • 203
    • 79952795340 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 1, at 1039 n.4, 1069
    • supra note 1, at 1039 n.4, 1069.
  • 204
    • 79952779890 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As Mitch Berman has pointed out, not all theorists who identify themselves as retributivists are objectivists. Berman
    • As Mitch Berman has pointed out, not all theorists who identify themselves as retributivists are objectivists. Berman
  • 205
    • 79952800756 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 25, at 7
    • supra note 25, at 7.
  • 206
    • 79952807318 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 216
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 216.
  • 207
    • 79952808915 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 212
    • Id. at 212
  • 208
    • 79952806439 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also Kolber, supra note 6, at 1595 (summarizing the argument in The Subjective Experience of Punishment that even if the disvalue of punishment consists of more than just negative subjective experiences, those experiences are at least part of what makes punishment burdensome)
    • see also Kolber, supra note 6, at 1595 (summarizing the argument in The Subjective Experience of Punishment that "even if the disvalue of punishment consists of more than just negative subjective experiences, those experiences are at least part of what makes punishment burdensome").
  • 209
    • 79952782431 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is not to deny that other legal and non-legal institutions and persons impose penalties. Consider punitive damages awards, which raise their own theoretical and practical concerns, none of which need be addressed here. For a retributivist understanding and reconfiguration of such awards
    • This is not to deny that other legal and non-legal institutions and persons impose penalties. Consider punitive damages awards, which raise their own theoretical and practical concerns, none of which need be addressed here. For a retributivist understanding and reconfiguration of such awards
  • 210
    • 62549088089 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • How should punitive damages work? 157
    • see Dan Markel, How Should Punitive Damages Work? 157 U. Pa. L. Rev. 1383 (2009)
    • (2009) U. Pa. L. Rev. , vol.1383
    • Markel, D.1
  • 211
    • 60349087960 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Retributive damages: A theory of punitive damages as intermediate sanction, 94
    • Dan Markel, Retributive Damages: A Theory of Punitive Damages As Intermediate Sanction, 94 CORNELL L. REV. 239 (2009).
    • (2009) Cornell L. Rev. , vol.239
    • Markel, D.1
  • 212
    • 0004244925 scopus 로고
    • discussing justifications for punishment as they relate to different theories of punishment
    • See H.L.A. Hart, Punishment and Responsibility i, 4-9 (1968) (discussing justifications for punishment as they relate to different theories of punishment).
    • (1968) Punishment and Responsibility , vol.1 , pp. 4-9
    • Hart, H.L.A.1
  • 213
    • 79952796472 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Berman, supra note 25, at 7
    • See Berman, supra note 25, at 7.
  • 214
    • 79952784061 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., KANT, supra note 14, at 105 (Punishment by a court ⋯ can never be inflicted merely as a means to promote some other good for the criminal himself or for civil society. It must always be inflicted upon him only because he has committed a crime)
    • See, e.g., KANT, supra note 14, at 105 ("Punishment by a court ⋯ can never be inflicted merely as a means to promote some other good for the criminal himself or for civil society. It must always be inflicted upon him only because he has committed a crime.")
  • 215
    • 0039233110 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • defining "retributivist" as one who believes that the justification for punishing a criminal is simply that the criminal deserves to be punished
    • MICHAEL MOORE, Placing Blame: A Theory of the Criminal Law 83 (1997) (defining "retributivist" as "one who believes that the justification for punishing a criminal is simply that the criminal deserves to be punished").
    • (1997) Placing Blame: A Theory of the Criminal Law , vol.83
    • Moore, M.1
  • 216
    • 79952789488 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See KANT, supra note 14, at 105 (Punishment ⋯ can never be inflicted merely as a means to promote some other good for the criminal himself or for civil society. It must always be inflicted upon him only because he has committed a crime)
    • See KANT, supra note 14, at 105 ("Punishment ⋯ can never be inflicted merely as a means to promote some other good for the criminal himself or for civil society. It must always be inflicted upon him only because he has committed a crime.").
  • 217
    • 79952778581 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See BECCARIA, supra note 3, at 13-14 (Punishments which go beyond the need of preserving the common store or deposit of public safety are in their nature unjust)
    • See BECCARIA, supra note 3, at 13-14 ("Punishments which go beyond the need of preserving the common store or deposit of public safety are in their nature unjust.").
  • 218
    • 79952776984 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Berman, supra note 25, at 19 ("Non-instrumentalist retributivism would bar [punishment in the absence, or in excess, of an offender's desert]."). Some retributivists also argue that desert is a sufficient condition for punishment
    • See Berman, supra note 25, at 19 ("Non-instrumentalist retributivism would bar [punishment in the absence, or in excess, of an offender's desert]."). Some retributivists also argue that desert is a sufficient condition for punishment.
  • 219
    • 79952783859 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., KANT, supra note 14, at 105 (The law of punishment is a categorical imperative ⋯)
    • See, e.g., KANT, supra note 14, at 105 ("The law of punishment is a categorical imperative ⋯.")
  • 220
    • 79952799350 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MOORE, supra note 122, at 88-89, 153-54 (The distinctive aspect of retributivism is that the moral desert of an offender is a sufficient reason to punish him or her ⋯)
    • MOORE, supra note 122, at 88-89, 153-54 ('The distinctive aspect of retributivism is that the moral desert of an offender is a sufficient reason to punish him or her ⋯ .")
  • 221
    • 0033479999 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kant on wrongdoing, desert, and punishment, 18
    • [D]eep retributivists hold [that it is morally necessary that wrongdoers be made to suffer] as a fundamental moral principle, which can serve to justify retributive policies of punishment)
    • Thomas Hill, Kant on Wrongdoing, Desert, and Punishment, 18 LAW & PHIL. 407, 411-12 (1999) ("[D]eep retributivists hold [that it is morally necessary that wrongdoers be made to suffer] as a fundamental moral principle, which can serve to justify retributive policies of punishment.")
    • (1999) Law & Phil. , vol.407 , pp. 411-412
    • Hill, T.1
  • 222
    • 0002368255 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The moral worth of retributivism
    • (Ferdinand Schoeman ed., 1987) (stating that, from a retributivist standpoint, desert is "both a sufficient as well as a necessary condition of liability to punitive sanctions"). As Nigel Walker points out, however, many "modern" retributivists have shied away from the view that there is "an obligation to punish, and substituted a mere right to punish" if and only if that punishment is deserved
    • Michael S. Moore, The Moral Worth of Retributivism, in RESPONSIBILITY, CHARACTER, AND THE EMOTIONS 179, 181-182 (Ferdinand Schoeman ed., 1987) (stating that, from a retributivist standpoint, desert is "both a sufficient as well as a necessary condition of liability to punitive sanctions"). As Nigel Walker points out, however, many "modern" retributivists have shied away from the view that there is "an obligation to punish, and substituted a mere right to punish" if and only if that punishment is deserved.
    • Responsibility, Character, and the Emotions , vol.179 , pp. 181-182
    • Moore, M.S.1
  • 223
    • 79952811597 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Even more varieties of retribution, 74
    • For present purposes, this Article need not take sides in this "duty" vs. "right" debate
    • Nigel Walker, Even More Varieties of Retribution, 74 PHIL. 595, 601 (1999). For present purposes, this Article need not take sides in this "duty" vs. "right" debate.
    • (1999) Phil. , vol.595 , pp. 601
    • Walker, N.1
  • 224
    • 79952783062 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 604
    • Id. at 604.
  • 225
    • 79952787132 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This objective constraint frequently is interpreted as suggesting a hierarchy of crime and punishment such that more severe crimes lead to more severe punishments. As is elaborated below, this idea of a hierarchy of severity is somewhat misleading to the extent it suggests the existence of a fungible unit of seriousness in crime and a corresponding unit of severity in punishment. See infra Part TV.A
    • This objective constraint frequently is interpreted as suggesting a hierarchy of crime and punishment such that more severe crimes lead to more severe punishments. As is elaborated below, this idea of a hierarchy of severity is somewhat misleading to the extent it suggests the existence of a fungible unit of seriousness in crime and a corresponding unit of severity in punishment. See infra Part TV.A.
  • 226
    • 79952789649 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., KANT, supra note 14, at 106-07 (explaining how various acts and punishments have different significances to different individuals, depending on the respective individuals' sensibilities)
    • See, e.g., KANT, supra note 14, at 106-07 (explaining how various acts and punishments have different significances to different individuals, depending on the respective individuals' sensibilities)
  • 227
    • 79952804876 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also infra note 229 (providing a portion of the text of Kant's argument regarding the varying significances of acts and punishments to various criminals, and explaining its significance)
    • see also infra note 229 (providing a portion of the text of Kant's argument regarding the varying significances of acts and punishments to various criminals, and explaining its significance).
  • 228
    • 0004071138 scopus 로고
    • The punishment deserved depends on the magnitude ⋯ of the wrongness of the act, and the person's degree of responsibility ⋯ for the act
    • See ROBERT NoziCK, PHILOSOPHICAL EXPLANATIONS 363-65 (1983) ('The punishment deserved depends on the magnitude ⋯ of the wrongness of the act, and the person's degree of responsibility ⋯ for the act.").
    • (1983) Philosophical Explanations , pp. 363-365
    • Nozick, R.1
  • 229
    • 79952807514 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Why corporations are not morally responsible for anything they do
    • Larry May & Stacey Hoffman eds., 1991 (stating that the nineteenth-century common law required both an "actus reus" and "mens rea" for criminal responsibility). These same prerequisites are also important in some utilitarian systems. Herbert Wechsler's Model Penal Code, for example, maintained in different language the common law requirements for a legal prohibition sufficient to meet legality demands, a voluntary act, and a mental connection to the crime as prerequisites for criminal punishment
    • See Manuel G. Velasquez, Why Corporations Are Not Morally Responsible for Anything They Do, in COLLECTIVE RESPONSIBILITY 111, 113-14 (Larry May & Stacey Hoffman eds., 1991) (stating that the nineteenth-century common law required both an "actus reus" and "mens rea" for criminal responsibility). These same prerequisites are also important in some utilitarian systems. Herbert Wechsler's Model Penal Code, for example, maintained in different language the common law requirements for a legal prohibition sufficient to meet legality demands, a voluntary act, and a mental connection to the crime as prerequisites for criminal punishment.
    • Collective Responsibility , vol.111 , pp. 113-114
    • Velasquez, M.G.1
  • 230
    • 79952806227 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See MODEL PENAL CODE §§ 2.01-.02 (1962) (requiring for criminal liability "conduct that includes a voluntary act or the omission to perform an act of which [one] is physically capable," and purposeful, knowing, reckless, or negligent action). Inclusion of these requirements in a largely utilitarian system bespeaks the persistent influence of retributivism
    • See MODEL PENAL CODE §§ 2.01-.02 (1962) (requiring for criminal liability "conduct that includes a voluntary act or the omission to perform an act of which [one] is physically capable," and purposeful, knowing, reckless, or negligent action). Inclusion of these requirements in a largely utilitarian system bespeaks the persistent influence of retributivism.
  • 231
    • 79952781097 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Omissions and strict liability crimes may seem to constitute exceptions. For reasons outside the scope of this Article, I do not think they are
    • Omissions and strict liability crimes may seem to constitute exceptions. For reasons outside the scope of this Article, I do not think they are.
  • 232
    • 79952809721 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See David Gray, You Know You Gotta Help Me Out (Oct. 28, 2010) (unpublished manuscript, on file with author)
    • See David Gray, You Know You Gotta Help Me Out (Oct. 28, 2010) (unpublished manuscript, on file with author).
  • 233
    • 79952795912 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Taylor v. Superior Court, 477 P.2d 131, 141 (Cal. 1970) (Mosk, J., dissenting) ("Fundamental principles of criminal responsibility dictate that the defendant be subject to a greater penalty only when he has demonstrated a greater degree of culpability.")
    • See, e.g., Taylor v. Superior Court, 477 P.2d 131, 141 (Cal. 1970) (Mosk, J., dissenting) ("Fundamental principles of criminal responsibility dictate that the defendant be subject to a greater penalty only when he has demonstrated a greater degree of culpability.").
  • 234
    • 79952786927 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Feinberg, Noncomparative Justice, supra note 68, at 300-01, 311-13, 318-19
    • Feinberg, Noncomparative Justice, supra note 68, at 300-01, 311-13, 318-19
  • 235
    • 79952781906 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also MOORE, supra note 122, at 90-91 (arguing that the noncomparative proportionality principle of retributivism allows for a determination of "which cases care truly alike," and thus, allows like cases to be treated alike). As Feinberg points out, comparative disparities may reveal noncomparative injustice, and comparative disparities may underwrite moral sentiments of injustice-particularly immature moral sentiments-but where disparities do not reveal noncomparative injustice, claims that a wrong has been committed do not carry much weight
    • see also MOORE, supra note 122, at 90-91 (arguing that the noncomparative proportionality principle of retributivism allows for a determination of "which cases care truly alike," and thus, allows like cases to be treated alike). As Feinberg points out, comparative disparities may reveal noncomparative injustice, and comparative disparities may underwrite moral sentiments of injustice-particularly immature moral sentiments-but where disparities do not reveal noncomparative injustice, claims that a wrong has been committed do not carry much weight.
  • 236
    • 79952813213 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 212-13. Bronsteen, Buccafusco, and Masur are fairly straightforward in their endorsement of the proposition that punishment is suffering, stating that, "When the state punishes a criminal, it inflicts suffering," where "suffering" is a self-reported state of "unhappiness." Bronsteen et al
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 212-13. Bronsteen, Buccafusco, and Masur are fairly straightforward in their endorsement of the proposition that punishment is suffering, stating that, "When the state punishes a criminal, it inflicts suffering," where "suffering" is a self-reported state of "unhappiness." Bronsteen et al.
  • 237
    • 79952780896 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 1, at 1037-38. Kolber's critique of retributivism is also committed to the view that retributivists must define punishment as suffering, though he is less definitive on what constitutes "suffering," which is evidenced by his preference for the phrase "subjective disutility." Kolber
    • supra note 1, at 1037-38. Kolber's critique of retributivism is also committed to the view that retributivists must define punishment as suffering, though he is less definitive on what constitutes "suffering," which is evidenced by his preference for the phrase "subjective disutility." Kolber.
  • 238
    • 79952794423 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 1, at 212-213
    • supra note 1, at 212-213
  • 239
    • 79952803515 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also id. at 197-198 (explaining the relevance of prisoners' subjective experiences)
    • see also id. at 197-198 (explaining the relevance of prisoners' subjective experiences).
  • 240
    • 79952810001 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 215-16
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 215-16
  • 241
    • 79952805261 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also Kolber, supra note 6, at 1600-01 ("[T]he comparative nature of punishment makes a purely objective notion of proportionality untenable.")
    • see also Kolber, supra note 6, at 1600-01 ("[T]he comparative nature of punishment makes a purely objective notion of proportionality untenable.").
  • 242
    • 79952810000 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber makes a similar argument based on the retributivist commitment that punishment ought to be proportionate to the crime for which it is imposed. Kolber contends that an offender may experience a quantum of suffering disproportionate to his crime, a prospect that presents retributivists with a potential contradiction. Kolber
    • Kolber makes a similar argument based on the retributivist commitment that punishment ought to be proportionate to the crime for which it is imposed. Kolber contends that an offender may experience a quantum of suffering disproportionate to his crime, a prospect that presents retributivists with a potential contradiction. Kolber.
  • 243
    • 79952803516 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 1, at 199-216
    • supra note 1, at 199-216
  • 244
    • 79952792148 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1068-69 (crediting Kolber's argument that "different individuals' experiences of punishment must be taken into account"). Again, however, the claimed tension is between two claims-1) that an offender has received a punishment proportionate to his crime; and 2) that the same offender has received a quantum of suffering disproportionate to his crime-which are not in contradiction absent the added premise that punishment is suffering
    • see also Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1068-69 (crediting Kolber's argument that "different individuals' experiences of punishment must be taken into account"). Again, however, the claimed tension is between two claims-1) that an offender has received a punishment proportionate to his crime; and 2) that the same offender has received a quantum of suffering disproportionate to his crime-which are not in contradiction absent the added premise that punishment is suffering.
  • 245
    • 79952799164 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Equivocation is used here for its technical meaning, denoting a semantic shift within an argument that allows the proponent to draw an unwarranted conclusion
    • Nicholas Bunnin & Jiyuan Yu eds
    • "Equivocation" is used here for its technical meaning, denoting a semantic shift within an argument that allows the proponent to draw an unwarranted conclusion. BLACKWELL Dictionary of Western Philosophy 249 (Nicholas Bunnin & Jiyuan Yu eds., 2004).
    • (2004) Blackwell Dictionary of Western Philosophy , vol.249
  • 246
    • 79952810606 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 184-85
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 184-85.
  • 247
    • 79952793187 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 235-36
    • Id. at 235-36.
  • 248
    • 78049231450 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Welfare as happiness, 98
    • Explaining the availability of measures for gauging "the well-being that people actually feel"); Kolber, supra note 11, at 3-4 (explaining that "new technologies have already shifted the way we measure experiences and will continue to do so more dramatically over the next thirty years," and arguing that these technologies should ⋯ change the way we assess criminal blameworthiness and punishment severity
    • See John Bronsteen, Christopher Buccafusco, & Jonathan Masur, Welfare as Happiness, 98 GEO. L.J. 1583, 1596 (2010) (explaining the availability of measures for gauging "the well-being that people actually feel"); Kolber, supra note 11, at 3-4 (explaining that "new technologies have already shifted the way we measure experiences and will continue to do so more dramatically over the next thirty years," and arguing that these technologies "should ⋯ change the way we assess criminal blameworthiness and punishment severity").
    • (2010) Geo. L.J. , vol.1583 , pp. 1596
    • Bronsteen, J.1    Buccafusco, C.2    Masur, J.3
  • 249
    • 79952779132 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber recognizes the centrality of this claim to his enterprise. See Kolber, supra note 1, at 214 (noting that "[o]nly if one believes that experiential suffering should not count at all are we relieved entirely of the obligation to calibrate subjective experience," which is the logical equivalent of saying that "if one believes that experiential suffering should not count at all then we are relieved entirely of the obligation to calibrate subjective experience")
    • Kolber recognizes the centrality of this claim to his enterprise. See Kolber, supra note 1, at 214 (noting that "[o]nly if one believes that experiential suffering should not count at all are we relieved entirely of the obligation to calibrate subjective experience," which is the logical equivalent of saying that "if one believes that experiential suffering should not count at all then we are relieved entirely of the obligation to calibrate subjective experience").
  • 250
    • 79952785516 scopus 로고
    • Punishment 74
    • God and humans can punish; hurricanes cannot. Some readers may cavil, suggesting that background facts will demonstrate that these unfortunate souls "deserve" disease or physical harm because they contributed to the constellation of risks that eventually led to their suffering
    • See Kent Greenawalt, Punishment, 74 J. Crim. L. & CRIMINOLOGY 343, 344 (1983) ("God and humans can punish; hurricanes cannot."). Some readers may cavil, suggesting that background facts will demonstrate that these unfortunate souls "deserve" disease or physical harm because they contributed to the constellation of risks that eventually led to their suffering.
    • (1983) J. Crim. L. & Criminology , vol.343 , pp. 344
    • Greenawalt, K.1
  • 251
    • 79952797220 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., ARISTOTLE, NICOMACHEAN ETHICS 38-39 (Terence Irwin trans., 2d ed. 1999) ("[W]e never censure someone if nature causes his ugliness; but if his lack of training or attention causes it, we do censure him."). While perhaps true in some cases, it is not true in all cases.
    • See, e.g., ARISTOTLE, NICOMACHEAN ETHICS 38-39 (Terence Irwin trans., 2d ed. 1999) ("[W]e never censure someone if nature causes his ugliness; but if his lack of training or attention causes it, we do censure him."). While perhaps true in some cases, it is not true in all cases.
  • 252
    • 79952799528 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 253
    • 79952813644 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Regardless, the claim turns on another equivocation, neatly captured by Kant's distinction between "poena forensis" ("[pjunishment by a courf) and "poena naturalis" ("in which vice punishes itself and which the legislator does not take into account")
    • Regardless, the claim turns on another equivocation, neatly captured by Kant's distinction between "poena forensis" ("[pjunishment by a courf) and "poena naturalis" ("in which vice punishes itself and which the legislator does not take into account").
  • 254
    • 79952790671 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • KANT, supra note 1414, at 105
    • KANT, supra note 1414, at 105
  • 255
    • 79952807912 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Discussing Hart's fourth and fifth requirements for punishment, which address the qualities required of the punishing authority
    • see also GEORGE P. FLETCHER, THE GRAMMAR OF CRIMINAL LAW 231 (2007) (discussing Hart's fourth and fifth requirements for punishment, which "address the qualities required of the punishing authority")
    • (2007) The grammar of criminal law , vol.231
    • Fletcher, G.P.1
  • 256
    • 79952776599 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • HART, supra note 120, at 4-5 (defining punishment to include the following characteristics: "[i]t must be for an offence against legal rules ⋯ of an actual or supposed offender for his offence ⋯ intentionally administered by human beings other than the offender ⋯ imposed and administered by a legal system against which the offence is committed")
    • HART, supra note 120, at 4-5 (defining punishment to include the following characteristics: "[i]t must be for an offence against legal rules ⋯ of an actual or supposed offender for his offence ⋯ intentionally administered by human beings other than the offender ⋯ imposed and administered by a legal system against which the offence is committed").
  • 257
    • 78149435403 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bentham on stilts: The bare relevance of subjectivity to retributive justice
    • Disvaluable states might be defined objectively, without regard to whether a particular person experiencing that state finds it pleasant or unpleasant. That is the approach to punishment advanced in a recent article by (forthcoming 2010) (manuscript at 142), available at ("[W]hat retributivists ought to care about foremost is the imposition of the punishment as a communication directed at the offender, not the offender's idiosyncratic and variable reaction to the coercive condemnatory deprivation."). However, Kolber clearly means "disvaluable" states to refer to those states which actually cause a particular offender to experience some degree of subjective experience that is subjectively experienced as negative
    • Disvaluable states might be defined objectively, without regard to whether a particular person experiencing that state finds it pleasant or unpleasant. That is the approach to punishment advanced in a recent article by Dan Markel and Chad Flanders, Bentham on Stilts: The Bare Relevance of Subjectivity to Retributive Justice, Cal. L. REV. (forthcoming 2010) (manuscript at 142), available at http://ssrn.com/abstract=1587886 ("[W]hat retributivists ought to care about foremost is the imposition of the punishment as a communication directed at the offender, not the offender's idiosyncratic and variable reaction to the coercive condemnatory deprivation."). However, Kolber clearly means "disvaluable" states to refer to those states which actually cause a particular offender to experience some degree of subjective experience that is subjectively experienced as negative.
    • Cal. L. Rev.
    • Markel, D.1    Flanders, C.2
  • 258
    • 79952798370 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 187 n.5
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 187 n.5.
  • 259
    • 79952807313 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • FEINBERG, supra note 20, at 106. The range of such state impositions provides ready counterexamples for other attempts to refine further the claim that punishment is suffering along this general line. For example, were subjectivists to define punishment as state-imposed suffering in response to a voluntary act, they would have to distinguish income taxes, which are imposed in response to earnings, sales taxes, which are imposed in response to purchases, and registration requirements, which are imposed upon those who, for example, decide to own and drive a car. For an engaging analysis of taxes as non-punitive measures
    • FEINBERG, supra note 20, at 106. The range of such state impositions provides ready counterexamples for other attempts to refine further the claim that punishment is suffering along this general line. For example, were subjectivists to define punishment as state-imposed suffering in response to a voluntary act, they would have to distinguish income taxes, which are imposed in response to earnings, sales taxes, which are imposed in response to purchases, and registration requirements, which are imposed upon those who, for example, decide to own and drive a car. For an engaging analysis of taxes as non-punitive measures.
  • 260
    • 0347648138 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As is argued here, the flow of counterexamples only abates when one recognizes desert as a necessary and defining feature of punishment; and, further, taking this constraint on punishment seriously requires measuring punishment objectively, without regard to the idiosyncratic experiences of offenders
    • see LlAM MURPHY & Thomas Nagel, the Myth of Ownership: Taxes and justice (2002). As is argued here, the flow of counterexamples only abates when one recognizes desert as a necessary and defining feature of punishment; and, further, taking this constraint on punishment seriously requires measuring punishment objectively, without regard to the idiosyncratic experiences of offenders.
    • (2002) The Myth of Ownership: Taxes and Justice
    • Murphy, L.1    Nagel, T.2
  • 261
    • 79952801545 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 212
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 212.
  • 262
    • 79952813214 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1037 ("When the state punishes a criminal, it inflicts suffering. There are limits on the amount and type of suffering that may legitimately be imposed⋯.")
    • See Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1037 ("When the state punishes a criminal, it inflicts suffering. There are limits on the amount and type of suffering that may legitimately be imposed⋯.").
  • 263
    • 79952810806 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Flemming v. Nestor, 363 U.S. 603, 616 (1960) (asserting that administrative consequences, such as "bar[ring] from practice [of medicine] persons who commit or have committed a felony," are an exercise of "regulatory power," and do not "add to the punishment")
    • See Flemming v. Nestor, 363 U.S. 603, 616 (1960) (asserting that administrative consequences, such as "bar[ring] from practice [of medicine] persons who commit or have committed a felony," are an exercise of "regulatory power," and do not "add to the punishment").
  • 264
    • 79952803310 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As is argued below, the examples, hypotheticals, and thought experiments offered by Kolber as reductio ad absurdum against traditional theories of criminal punishment are guilty of precisely this equivocation. See infra notes 148-53 and accompanying text
    • As is argued below, the examples, hypotheticals, and thought experiments offered by Kolber as reductio ad absurdum against traditional theories of criminal punishment are guilty of precisely this equivocation. See infra notes 148-53 and accompanying text.
  • 265
    • 79952812586 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 184-85
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 184-85.
  • 266
    • 79952794737 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See infra Part VI
    • See infra Part VI.
  • 267
    • 79952796858 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 213
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 213.
  • 268
    • 79952789840 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 213-14
    • Id. at 213-14.
  • 269
    • 79952798009 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Nussbaum, supra note 30, at 86-88, 96-97 (noting that those who rely on self-reported happiness do not account for the ambiguity of incidental suffering)
    • See Nussbaum, supra note 30, at 86-88, 96-97 (noting that those who rely on self-reported happiness do not account for the ambiguity of incidental suffering).
  • 270
    • 79952790261 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Kolber, supra note 1, at 196-98
    • See Kolber, supra note 1, at 196-98
  • 271
    • 79952802346 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1069
    • Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1069.
  • 272
    • 79952799900 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1037
    • See, e.g., Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1037
  • 273
    • 79952798012 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bronsteen et al
    • Bronsteen et al.
  • 274
    • 79952810408 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 3, at 1487 n.99 (defending purpose as an element of proximate cause as a criterion for determining whether suffering is punishment)
    • supra note 3, at 1487 n.99 (defending purpose as an element of proximate cause as a criterion for determining whether suffering is punishment)
  • 275
    • 79952795715 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 196-98 (arguing that the primary burden of criminal theory is to justify "purposefully or knowingly inflict[ing] substantial pain or distress")
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 196-98 (arguing that the primary burden of criminal theory is to justify "purposefully or knowingly inflict[ing] substantial pain or distress")
  • 276
    • 79952810604 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 212-13 ("Subjective disutility is a necessary component of retributive punishment and constitutes, if not the sole reason for retributive punishment, certainly a major part of it.")
    • Id. at 212-13 ("Subjective disutility is a necessary component of retributive punishment and constitutes, if not the sole reason for retributive punishment, certainly a major part of it.").
  • 277
    • 79952796471 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Kolber, supra note 1, at 195-96. This is a significant omission
    • See Kolber, supra note 1, at 195-96. This is a significant omission.
  • 278
    • 79952794738 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See FLETCHER, supra note 141, at 228 (interpreting Hart)
    • See FLETCHER, supra note 141, at 228 (interpreting Hart)
  • 279
    • 79952813805 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • HART, supra note 120, at 4-5
    • HART, supra note 120, at 4-5.
  • 280
    • 79952789084 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 188
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 188.
  • 281
    • 79952779324 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1050
    • Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1050
  • 282
    • 79952779886 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bronsteen et al., supra note 3, at 1489
    • Bronsteen et al., supra note 3, at 1489.
  • 283
    • 79952786520 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 212-13
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 212-13.
  • 284
    • 79952801764 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 188
    • Id. at 188.
  • 285
    • 79952793598 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Knowledge or "purpose" on the part of someone may also be necessary in Kolber's view. However, neither is sufficient. As is discussed below, agents who act knowingly or purposefully to put another person at certain risk of harm may be criminally or tortiously liable for their conduct, but that knowledge or purpose does not convert the harm into punishment
    • Knowledge or "purpose" on the part of someone may also be necessary in Kolber's view. However, neither is sufficient. As is discussed below, agents who act knowingly or purposefully to put another person at certain risk of harm may be criminally or tortiously liable for their conduct, but that knowledge or purpose does not convert the harm into punishment.
  • 286
    • 79952787709 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See infra note 161 and accompanying text. The story in no way changes if the person who knowingly or purposely puts his victim in harm's way is a state official. Therefore, to maintain his claim that prison sexual assault is a component of "punishment" when it occurs, Kolber appears to be committed to the view that location is an essential criterion when distinguishing between sexual assault that is punishment and sexual assault that is not punishment
    • See infra note 161 and accompanying text. The story in no way changes if the person who knowingly or purposely puts his victim in harm's way is a state official. Therefore, to maintain his claim that prison sexual assault is a component of "punishment" when it occurs, Kolber appears to be committed to the view that location is an essential criterion when distinguishing between sexual assault that is punishment and sexual assault that is not punishment.
  • 287
    • 79952787710 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See FLETCHER, supra note 141, at 227-33.
    • See FLETCHER, supra note 141, at 227-33.
  • 288
    • 79952794541 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In recognition of this fact, some courts have held that where a prisoner escapes from custody out of fear of prisoner-on-prisoner violence he may claim a defense based on necessity
    • In recognition of this fact, some courts have held that where a prisoner escapes from custody out of fear of prisoner-on-prisoner violence he may claim a defense based on necessity.
  • 289
    • 79952776410 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., People v. Unger, 362 N.E.2d 319, 322-23 (111. 1977)
    • See, e.g., People v. Unger, 362 N.E.2d 319, 322-23 (111. 1977).
  • 290
    • 79952806430 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Respecting Hart's prohibition, I do not mean to argue by definition
    • Respecting Hart's prohibition, I do not mean to argue by definition.
  • 291
    • 79952801353 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See HART, supra note 120, at 6 (cautioning against definitional arguments)
    • See HART, supra note 120, at 6 (cautioning against definitional arguments).
  • 292
    • 79952795339 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rather, the point is that if subjectivists want to jettison three of the five commonly identified characteristics of punishment Hart cites, its advocates must provide a robust normative argument for their departure
    • Rather, the point is that if subjectivists want to jettison three of the five commonly identified characteristics of punishment Hart cites, its advocates must provide a robust normative argument for their departure.
  • 293
    • 79952798747 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Kolber, supra note 1, at 186-88 (making just this critique)
    • See Kolber, supra note 1, at 186-88 (making just this critique).
  • 294
    • 79952812155 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • This is not to say that prisoner-on-prisoner violence is of no moral or legal significance. Prison officials are charged with protecting those under their care from unlawful assault. Failures by prison officials to provide sufficient protections from prison violence may be tortious or criminal. Mercy may also recommend early release for offenders subject to criminal violence in part as a reflection of institutional failures to provide adequate security and protection. However, none of this makes prisoner-on-prisoner violence "punishment" such that failures by retributivists or utilitarians to account for it and justify it would provide reasons to abandon their theories of punishment. To the contrary, prisoner-on-prisoner violence is a crime, and suffering occasioned by crimes committed in prison is, strictly speaking, incidental to punishment. Kolber's contrary claim- that prison rape is an element of punishment-is troubling to say the least.
  • 295
    • 79952806438 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 197
    • Id. at 197.
  • 296
    • 79952801548 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 197
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 197
  • 297
    • 79952801768 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also Kolber, supra note 11
    • see also Kolber, supra note 11.
  • 298
    • 79952800503 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber extends his thought experiment to include omissions as well. That extension is addressed below
    • Kolber extends his thought experiment to include omissions as well. That extension is addressed below.
  • 299
    • 79952800504 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 197-98
    • Id. at 197-98.
  • 300
    • 79952781907 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • HART, supra note 120, at 4-5
    • HART, supra note 120, at 4-5.
  • 301
    • 79952803319 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • As is suggested in Part I and elaborated further in Part VI, objectivist theories provide powerful tools for recognizing and condemning abuse in prison and create obligations on the part of prison officials to minimize incidental suffering. To the extent Kolber and Bronsteen, Buccafusco, and Masur want to press a progressive agenda against prison sexual assault, improvements in prison conditions, vigorous reentry programs, or other efforts designed to curb abuse and limit incidental suffering, this author has no objections. To the contrary, the point here is that objective theories of criminal punishment provide more powerful tools for advancing those agendas than the subjectivist critiques pressed by Kolber and Bronsteen, Buccafusco, and Masur. For that reason, and because their critiques do not offer any reason to reject objectivist accounts of punishment, Kolber and Bronsteen, Buccafusco, and Masur should embrace objective over subjective accounts of punishment.
  • 302
    • 79952809726 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See infra Part IV
    • See infra Part IV.
  • 303
    • 79952778367 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Consider as an example the following passage: "While some theorists purport to hold objective accounts of punishment that ignore offenders' subjective experiences, such theories are doomed to fail. By ignoring subjective experience, they cannot justify the amount of distress that punishment inflicts on offenders, and so they cannot justify punishment more generally
    • Consider as an example the following passage: "While some theorists purport to hold objective accounts of punishment that ignore offenders' subjective experiences, such theories are doomed to fail. By ignoring subjective experience, they cannot justify the amount of distress that punishment inflicts on offenders, and so they cannot justify punishment more generally." Kolber, supra note 1, at 184
  • 304
    • 79952786522 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 184
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 184
  • 305
    • 79952791943 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1068, 1072 n.166
    • see also Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1068, 1072 n.166.
  • 306
    • 79952792540 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The fallacy in this argument is now evident in light of subjectivism's failure to justify the equivocation from "punishment" to suffering. If, as it now seems, the suffering these theories ignore is incidental, then punishment theory carries no obligation to justify that suffering because to do so would conflate criminal abuse with just punishment. Far from constituting a failure of theory, then, retributivists' and utilitarians' refusals to justify incidental suffering is a necessary, not a condemnatory, feature of their efforts to justify punishment more generally
    • The fallacy in this argument is now evident in light of subjectivism's failure to justify the equivocation from "punishment" to suffering. If, as it now seems, the suffering these theories ignore is incidental, then punishment theory carries no obligation to justify that suffering because to do so would conflate criminal abuse with just punishment. Far from constituting a failure of theory, then, retributivists' and utilitarians' refusals to justify incidental suffering is a necessary, not a condemnatory, feature of their efforts to justify punishment more generally.
  • 307
    • 79952807911 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Kolber, supra note 1, at 196-98 (arguing that the primary burden of criminal theory is to justify "purposefully or knowingly inflictpng] substantial pain or distress")
    • See, e.g., Kolber, supra note 1, at 196-98 (arguing that the primary burden of criminal theory is to justify "purposefully or knowingly inflictpng] substantial pain or distress")
  • 308
    • 79952807712 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bronsteen et al., supra note 3, at 1479
    • Bronsteen et al., supra note 3, at 1479.
  • 309
    • 79952785712 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MODEL PENAL CODE § 2.02(7) (1962)
    • MODEL PENAL CODE § 2.02(7) (1962).
  • 310
    • 79952799169 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See generally Kolber, supra note 6
    • See generally Kolber, supra note 6.
  • 311
    • 79952779128 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1587-88
    • Id. at 1587-88.
  • 312
    • 79952797221 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 313
    • 79952794007 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 314
    • 79952784240 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1588
    • Id. at 1588.
  • 315
    • 79952778365 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Equally counterintuitive is the implied suggestion that the best way for an offender to reduce the objective severity of his punishment would be to go on a wildly pleasurable vacation right before submitting to custody
    • Equally counterintuitive is the implied suggestion that the best way for an offender to reduce the objective severity of his punishment would be to go on a wildly pleasurable vacation right before submitting to custody.
  • 316
    • 79952803098 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1049-53
    • Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1049-53.
  • 317
    • 79952790867 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Smith v. Doe, 538 U.S. 84, 105-06 (2003) (sex offender registration requirements are not "punishment")
    • See, e.g., Smith v. Doe, 538 U.S. 84, 105-06 (2003) (sex offender registration requirements are not "punishment")
  • 318
    • 79952795156 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kansas v. Hendricks, 521 U.S. 346, 350 (1997) (administrative incarceration of convicted sex offenders is not punishment)
    • Kansas v. Hendricks, 521 U.S. 346, 350 (1997) (administrative incarceration of convicted sex offenders is not punishment)
  • 319
    • 79952779127 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Flemming v. Nestor, 363 U.S. 603, 616 (1960) (administrative consequences, such as "bar[ring] from practice [of medicine] persons who commit or have committed a felony," are exercises of "regulatory power," and do not "add to the punishment")
    • Flemming v. Nestor, 363 U.S. 603, 616 (1960) (administrative consequences, such as "bar[ring] from practice [of medicine] persons who commit or have committed a felony," are exercises of "regulatory power," and do not "add to the punishment").
  • 320
    • 79952791042 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See MOORE, supra note 122, at 25 (arguing that to explain "punishment" one must explain a sanction's punitive purpose)
    • See MOORE, supra note 122, at 25 (arguing that to explain "punishment" one must explain a sanction's punitive purpose).
  • 321
    • 79952794425 scopus 로고
    • I refer to Tom Hanks's eponymous character in Forrest Gump (Paramount Pictures 1994), but the adage traces to a proverb of much longer history: He is handsome that handsome doth
    • I refer to Tom Hanks's eponymous character in Forrest Gump (Paramount Pictures 1994), but the adage traces to a proverb of much longer history: "He is handsome that handsome doth." WILLIAM G. BENTHAM, BOOK OF QUOTATIONS PROVERBS AND Household Words 788 (1907).
    • (1907) Book of Quotations Proverbs and Household Words , vol.788
    • Bentham, W.G.1
  • 322
    • 79952777561 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • HART, supra note 120, at 19
    • HART, supra note 120, at 19.
  • 323
    • 79952807314 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • FEINBERG, supra note 20, at 111-18
    • FEINBERG, supra note 20, at 111-18.
  • 324
    • 79952791942 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This conceptual mistake has a long history tracing back at least to Plato
    • This conceptual mistake has a long history tracing back at least to Plato.
  • 325
    • 79952788459 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See PLATO, THE REPUBLIC, 227-31 (Francis MacDonald Cornford trans., 1945). More recently, it is a mistake common in efforts by lawyers to make sense of new knowledge and technology at the cutting edge of medicine, neuroscience, and the social sciences
    • See PLATO, THE REPUBLIC, 227-31 (Francis MacDonald Cornford trans., 1945). More recently, it is a mistake common in efforts by lawyers to make sense of new knowledge and technology at the cutting edge of medicine, neuroscience, and the social sciences.
  • 326
    • 79952794214 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See generally Pustilnik, supra note 20
    • See generally Pustilnik, supra note 20.
  • 327
    • 79952795716 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1068-70
    • See, e.g., Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1068-70
  • 328
    • 79952795521 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 197, 199, 212-13, 215-16
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 197, 199, 212-13, 215-16.
  • 329
    • 79952809314 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 199 (emphasis omitted). Kolber does credit some retributivists for being objectivists. However, for reasons addressed below, he concludes that these theories either devolve into subjectivist theories or are otherwise obliged to recognize and justify differences in the subjective experiences of offenders
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 199 (emphasis omitted). Kolber does credit some retributivists for being objectivists. However, for reasons addressed below, he concludes that these theories either devolve into subjectivist theories or are otherwise obliged to recognize and justify differences in the subjective experiences of offenders.
  • 330
    • 79952811000 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 212-13, 215-16
    • Id. at 212-13, 215-16
  • 331
    • 79952794011 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 6, at 1585-86
    • Kolber, supra note 6, at 1585-86.
  • 332
    • 79952776598 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1073 n.166
    • Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1073 n.166.
  • 333
    • 79952807511 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., FEINBERG, supra note 20, at 116-18 (rejecting this view)
    • See, e.g., FEINBERG, supra note 20, at 116-18 (rejecting this view)
  • 334
    • 79952776983 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • FLETCHER, supra note 141, at 228 (same)
    • FLETCHER, supra note 141, at 228 (same)
  • 335
    • 79952778963 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hampton, supra note 20, at 128-29 (same)
    • Hampton, supra note 20, at 128-29 (same)
  • 336
    • 0042218931 scopus 로고
    • A paternalistic theory of punishment, 18
    • (same). As Mitchell Berman has pointed out, there are some contemporary retributivist theorists committed to a version of instrumentalism because they endorse a version of the subjectivist claim that the goal of punishment is to inflict suffering
    • Herbert Morris, A Paternalistic Theory of Punishment, 18 Am. PHIL. Q. 263, 270 (1981) (same). As Mitchell Berman has pointed out, there are some contemporary retributivist theorists committed to a version of instrumentalism because they endorse a version of the subjectivist claim that the goal of punishment is to inflict suffering.
    • (1981) Am. Phil. Q. , vol.263 , pp. 270
    • Morris, H.1
  • 337
    • 79952791563 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Berman, supra note 25. For these scholars, this Article should provide substantial motivation to prefer objective approaches
    • See Berman, supra note 25. For these scholars, this Article should provide substantial motivation to prefer objective approaches.
  • 338
    • 79952810410 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See FEINBERG, supra note 20, at 116
    • See FEINBERG, supra note 20, at 116.
  • 339
    • 56349137496 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Arguing that the revenge instinct has an almost universal appeal, from an evolutionary point of view, for creatures such as human beings, who live in cooperative communities
    • See Michael E. McCullough, Beyond Revenge: The Evolution of the FORGIVENESS INSTINCT 41-87 (2008) (arguing that the revenge instinct has an almost universal appeal, from an evolutionary point of view, for creatures such as human beings, who live in cooperative communities)
    • (2008) Beyond Revenge: The Evolution of the Forgiveness Instinct , pp. 41-87
    • McCullough, M.E.1
  • 340
    • 79952810409 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MILL, supra note 56, at 50-51 (noting roles of moral outrage and instincts of self-defense in punitive impulses)
    • MILL, supra note 56, at 50-51 (noting roles of moral outrage and instincts of self-defense in punitive impulses).
  • 341
    • 0003581627 scopus 로고
    • See generally One also cannot help but recall Foucault's vivid account of the elaborate execution of Damien
    • See generally SUSAN JACOBY, WILD JUSTICE: THE EVOLUTION OF REVENGE (1983). One also cannot help but recall Foucault's vivid account of the elaborate execution of Damien.
    • (1983) Wild Justice: The Evolution of Revenge
    • Jacoby, S.1
  • 342
    • 79952797225 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • FOUCAULT, supra note 35, at 3-6
    • FOUCAULT, supra note 35, at 3-6.
  • 343
    • 79952811395 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • NOZICK, supra note 128, at 366-70
    • NOZICK, supra note 128, at 366-70
  • 344
    • 79952813643 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [Retributivism] is obviously not to be identified with vengeance or revenge, any more than love is to be identified with lust
    • see also GEORGE FLETCHER, RETHINKING CRIMINAL LAW 417 (2000) ("[Retributivism] is obviously not to be identified with vengeance or revenge, any more than love is to be identified with lust.")
    • (2000) Rethinking Criminal Law , vol.417
    • Fletcher, G.1
  • 345
    • 0039154936 scopus 로고
    • ("The criminal law stands to the passion of revenge in much the same relation as marriage to the sexual appetite.")
    • J.F. STEPHENS, GENERAL VIEW OF THE CRIMINAL LAW OF ENGLAND 99 (1863) ("The criminal law stands to the passion of revenge in much the same relation as marriage to the sexual appetite.").
    • (1863) General View of the Criminal Law of England , vol.99
    • Stephens, J.F.1
  • 346
    • 79952793375 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., FLETCHER, supra note 141, at 228
    • See, e.g., FLETCHER, supra note 141, at 228
  • 347
    • 79952780467 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • HART, supra note 120, at 4-5
    • HART, supra note 120, at 4-5
  • 348
    • 79952778179 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MOORE, supra note 122, at 153
    • MOORE, supra note 122, at 153
  • 349
    • 79952783661 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hampton, supra note 20, at 128-29
    • Hampton, supra note 20, at 128-29.
  • 350
    • 79952786308 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nino, supra note 20, at 102
    • Nino, supra note 20, at 102.
  • 351
    • 79952800976 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is in contrast to most utilitarians-with the notable exception of Bentham-who maintain that suffering and happiness by their nature have a normative valence
    • This is in contrast to most utilitarians-with the notable exception of Bentham-who maintain that suffering and happiness by their nature have a normative valence.
  • 352
    • 79952787130 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Nussbaum, supra note 30, at 92-95
    • See Nussbaum, supra note 30, at 92-95.
  • 353
    • 79952787899 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • FLETCHER, supra note 190, at 396-101
    • FLETCHER, supra note 190, at 396-101.
  • 354
    • 79952780897 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., id. at 415-18, 461-62, 505-14
    • See, e.g., id. at 415-18, 461-62, 505-14
  • 355
    • 79952811600 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • FLETCHER, supra note 141, at 228
    • FLETCHER, supra note 141, at 228
  • 356
    • 79952792987 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • KANT, supra note 14, at 104-09
    • KANT, supra note 14, at 104-09
  • 357
    • 79952779889 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hampton, supra note 20, at 128-29
    • Hampton, supra note 20, at 128-29.
  • 358
    • 79952790039 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber acknowledges that some retributivists are objectivists rather than subjectivists, yet argues those theorists must account for subjective experiences of punishment in their theories. Kolber, supra note 6, at 1585-86
    • Kolber acknowledges that some retributivists are objectivists rather than subjectivists, yet argues those theorists must account for subjective experiences of punishment in their theories. Kolber, supra note 6, at 1585-86
  • 359
    • 79952797025 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 215-16
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 215-16.
  • 360
    • 79952799710 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The discussion of Kant's theory of punishment presented here is necessarily brief and as a consequence blurs over substantial debates among Kant scholars
    • The discussion of Kant's theory of punishment presented here is necessarily brief and as a consequence blurs over substantial debates among Kant scholars.
  • 361
    • 0039122975 scopus 로고
    • Kant's theory of punishment: Deterrence in its threat, retribution in its execution, 8
    • arguing that Kant envisioned threat of punishment as a deterrent and execution of punishment as objective retribution
    • See, e.g., Sharon Byrd, Kant's Theory of Punishment: Deterrence in its Threat, Retribution in its Execution, 8 LAW & PHIL. 151, 153 (1989) (arguing that Kant envisioned threat of punishment as a deterrent and execution of punishment as objective retribution)
    • (1989) Law & Phil. , vol.151 , pp. 153
    • Byrd, S.1
  • 362
    • 0040901250 scopus 로고
    • Kant's theory of punishment
    • bringing an interpretation of Kant's theory of punishment more in line with wider moral thought
    • Samuel Fleischacker, Kant's Theory of Punishment, in ESSAYS ON KANT'S POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY 191 (1992) (bringing an interpretation of Kant's theory of punishment more in line with wider moral thought)
    • (1992) Essays on Kant's Political Philosophy , vol.191
    • Fleischacker, S.1
  • 363
    • 0042081290 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kant on punishment: A coherent mix of deterrence and retribution? 1997
    • arguing that the deterrence elements in Kant's view of punishment serve an important but restricted role
    • Thomas Hill, Kant on Punishment: A Coherent Mix of Deterrence and Retribution?, 1997 ANN. Rev. L. & ETHICS 291, 293 (1997) (arguing that the deterrence elements in Kant's view of punishment serve an important but restricted role)
    • (1997) Ann. Rev. L. & Ethics , vol.291 , pp. 293
    • Hill, T.1
  • 364
    • 84899244022 scopus 로고
    • Does kant have a theory of punishment, 87
    • [hereinafter Murphy, Does Kant] (arguing, in disagreement with his past self, that Kant did not create an internally consistent theory of punishment over the course of his career)
    • Jeffrie Murphy, Does Kant Have a Theory of Punishment, 87 COLUM. L. REV. 509, 532 (1987) [hereinafter Murphy, Does Kant] (arguing, in disagreement with his past self, that Kant did not create an internally consistent theory of punishment over the course of his career)
    • (1987) Colum. L. Rev. , vol.509 , pp. 532
    • Murphy, J.1
  • 365
    • 84951388464 scopus 로고
    • Kant's theory of criminal punishment
    • [hereinafter Murphy, Kant's Theory] (defending Kant's retributivist theory of criminal punishment from utilitarian objections)
    • Jeffrie Murphy, Kant's Theory of Criminal Punishment, in RETRIBUTION, JUSTICE AND THERAPY: ESSAYS IN THE PHILOSOPHY OF LAW 82, 84-90 (1979) [hereinafter Murphy, Kant's Theory] (defending Kant's retributivist theory of criminal punishment from utilitarian objections)
    • (1979) Retribution, Justice and Therapy: Essays in the Philosophy of Law , vol.82 , pp. 84-90
    • Murphy, J.1
  • 366
    • 0039123026 scopus 로고
    • Kant's retributivism, 93
    • arguing that Kant is not a thoroughgoing retributivist but a partial retributivist
    • Don Scheid, Kant's Retributivism, 93 ETHICS 262, 265 (1983) (arguing that Kant is not a thoroughgoing retributivist but a partial retributivist).
    • (1983) Ethics , vol.262 , pp. 265
    • Scheid, D.1
  • 367
    • 79952798741 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber has not offered a positive theory of punishment and therefore has not endorsed subjectivism. Part of the purpose of this Article and the exchanges in which it participates is to persuade Kolber and others that his critique actually ought to lead him to endorse an objective theory of punishment
    • Kolber has not offered a positive theory of punishment and therefore has not endorsed subjectivism. Part of the purpose of this Article and the exchanges in which it participates is to persuade Kolber and others that his critique actually ought to lead him to endorse an objective theory of punishment.
  • 368
    • 79952806225 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Markel & Flanders, supra note 142, at 111 (explaining that because they enjoyed equal freedom in making their decisions to commit crimes, criminals should get substantially, i.e. objectively, equal punishments). Bronsteen, Buccafusco, and Masur have gone further
    • Cf. Markel & Flanders, supra note 142, at 111 (explaining that because they enjoyed equal freedom in making their decisions to commit crimes, criminals should get substantially, i.e. objectively, equal punishments). Bronsteen, Buccafusco, and Masur have gone further.
  • 369
    • 79952791940 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Bronsteen et al., supra note 3, at 104 (endorsing subjective approaches to punishment). Fletcher, supra note 190, at 416
    • See Bronsteen et al., supra note 3, at 104 (endorsing subjective approaches to punishment). Fletcher, supra note 190, at 416
  • 370
    • 79952781101 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Wayne LaFave, Criminal Law 30 (2003)
    • Wayne LaFave, Criminal Law 30 (2003).
  • 371
    • 79952797024 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • See MODEL PENAL CODE § 1.02(2) (tentative draft Apr. 9, 2007) ("Purposes: Principles of Construction. (2) The general purposes of the provisions on sentencing, applicable to all official actors in the sentencing system, are: (a) in decisions affecting the sentencing of individual offenders: (i) to render sentences in all cases within a range of severity proportionate to the gravity of offenses, the harms done to crime victims, and the blameworthiness of offenders; (ii) when reasonably feasible, to achieve offender rehabilitation, general deterrence, incapacitation of dangerous offenders, restoration of crime victims and communities, and reintegration of offenders into the law-abiding community, provided these goals are pursued within the boundaries of proportionality in subsection (a)(i); and (iii) to render sentences no more severe than necessary to achieve the applicable purposes in subsections (a)(i) and (a)(ii)."). At least one prominent author has criticized this revision.
  • 372
    • 79952808487 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Ristroph, supra note 18, at 729-745 (attacking the revision's reliance on desert in sentencing guidelines)
    • See Ristroph, supra note 18, at 729-745 (attacking the revision's reliance on desert in sentencing guidelines).
  • 373
    • 79952799530 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See 18 U.S.C. § 3553(a)(2) (2006) (stating that the law must provide just punishment for the offense)
    • See 18 U.S.C. § 3553(a)(2) (2006) (stating that the law must provide just punishment for the offense).
  • 374
    • 79952778580 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • FLETCHER, supra note 190, at 416-17
    • FLETCHER, supra note 190, at 416-17
  • 375
    • 79952799531 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also MOORE, supra note 122, at 83
    • see also MOORE, supra note 122, at 83.
  • 376
    • 79952776025 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See generally John Cottingham, Varieties of Retribution, 29 PHIL. Q. 238, 238 (1979) (distinguishing nine such relationships)
    • See generally John Cottingham, Varieties of Retribution, 29 PHIL. Q. 238, 238 (1979) (distinguishing nine such relationships).
  • 377
    • 70349141344 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Retribution's role, 84
    • noting centrality of Kant in the punishment canon). Kant's theory of punishment is a subject of hot debate among Kant scholars
    • See John Bronsteen, Retribution's Role, 84 IND. L.J. 1129, 1131 (2009) (noting centrality of Kant in the punishment canon). Kant's theory of punishment is a subject of hot debate among Kant scholars.
    • (2009) Ind. L.J. , vol.1129 , pp. 1131
    • Bronsteen, J.1
  • 378
    • 79952813218 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 196
    • See supra note 196.
  • 379
    • 79952785319 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Immanuel Kant, Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals 14 (James Ellington trans., Hackett Publ'g Co. 1983)
    • Immanuel Kant, Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals 14 (James Ellington trans., Hackett Publ'g Co. 1983).
  • 380
    • 79952808298 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • JOHNRAWLS, A THEORY OF JUSTICE 251-57 (Harvard Univ. Press 2005) (1971)
    • JOHNRAWLS, A THEORY OF JUSTICE 251-57 (Harvard Univ. Press 2005) (1971).
  • 381
    • 79952795155 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • JURGEN HABERMAS, THE THEORY OF COMMUNICATIVE ACTION 8-42 (Thomas McCarthy trans., Beacon Press 1984) (1981). Kant uses willkur
    • JURGEN HABERMAS, THE THEORY OF COMMUNICATIVE ACTION 8-42 (Thomas McCarthy trans., Beacon Press 1984) (1981). Kant uses willkur.
  • 382
    • 79952798746 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See KANT, supra note 14, at 13 (distinguishing will or choice [willkur] from a mere wish)
    • See KANT, supra note 14, at 13 (distinguishing will or choice [willkur] from a mere wish).
  • 383
    • 79952791941 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 12-14.
    • Id. at 12-14.
  • 384
    • 79952811198 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This account of freewill is not without its critics
    • This account of freewill is not without its critics.
  • 385
    • 79952793186 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Murphy, Does Kant, supra note 196, at 523-24 (arguing that Kant did not want to remove all considerations of the criminal's mental state from analysis of their desert of punishment)
    • See, e.g., Murphy, Does Kant, supra note 196, at 523-24 (arguing that Kant did not want to remove all considerations of the criminal's mental state from analysis of their desert of punishment).
  • 386
    • 79952795338 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • KANT, supra note 14, at 13
    • KANT, supra note 14, at 13.
  • 387
    • 0003335371 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Perpetual peace: A philosophical sketch
    • Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason 312-13 (Norman Smith trans., St. Martin's Press 1965) [hereinafter KANT, CRITIQUE]. Kant's conception of a Kingdom of Ends serves a similar role in his historical philosophy. While outwardly nai've in his hope for a society where everyone acts in a purely moral fashion, Kant is well aware that we are a "race of devils," and therefore need the external constraint of a state writing law in the shadow of the bloodbath of history to compel us to an approximation of the ideal, 105, (Hans Reiss ed., Cambridge University Press 1991) [hereinafter Kant, Perpetual Peace]
    • Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason 312-13 (Norman Smith trans., St. Martin's Press 1965) [hereinafter KANT, CRITIQUE]. Kant's conception of a Kingdom of Ends serves a similar role in his historical philosophy. While outwardly nai've in his hope for a society where everyone acts in a purely moral fashion, Kant is well aware that we are a "race of devils," and therefore need the external constraint of a state writing law in the shadow of the bloodbath of history to compel us to an approximation of the ideal. Immanuel Kant, Perpetual Peace: A Philosophical Sketch, in KANT: POLITICAL WRITINGS 93, 105, 112-13 (Hans Reiss ed., Cambridge University Press 1991) [hereinafter Kant, Perpetual Peace]
    • Kant: Political Writings , vol.93 , pp. 112-213
    • Kant, I.1
  • 388
    • 79952794219 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also RAWLS, supra note 205, at 246
    • see also RAWLS, supra note 205, at 246.
  • 389
    • 79952809538 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • KANT, supra note 14, at 17
    • KANT, supra note 14, at 17.
  • 390
    • 79952809932 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • An agent's maxim of action is by definition available only to him, but it can be imputed to him based on his actions
    • An agent's maxim of action is by definition available only to him, but it can be imputed to him based on his actions.
  • 391
    • 79952785320 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 19
    • Id. at 19.
  • 392
    • 79952813445 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Thomas Hill has a slightly different reading, concluding that maxims incorporate "rationales" in keeping with "general principles of rational choice." As Hill admits, however, that reading sets aside "Kant's troublesome references to 'noumenal' causation." Hill, supra note 125, at 415-16
    • Thomas Hill has a slightly different reading, concluding that maxims incorporate "rationales" in keeping with "general principles of rational choice." As Hill admits, however, that reading sets aside "Kant's troublesome references to 'noumenal' causation." Hill, supra note 125, at 415-16.
  • 393
    • 79952806037 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • KANT, supra note 14, at 17
    • KANT, supra note 14, at 17.
  • 394
    • 79952785912 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In a purely communist society the maxim of theft, "I take that which is not mine," would be nonsensical because there is no conception of mine and thine. This reveals that, in all but a few cases, moral duty is derivative of background social practice. Two notable exceptions are murder and suicide, which, taken to their logical ends, would entail the destruction of humanity and the exercise of reason in general. It is therefore impossible as a moral matter for a society to condone or allow murder or suicide
    • In a purely communist society the maxim of theft, "I take that which is not mine," would be nonsensical because there is no conception of mine and thine. This reveals that, in all but a few cases, moral duty is derivative of background social practice. Two notable exceptions are murder and suicide, which, taken to their logical ends, would entail the destruction of humanity and the exercise of reason in general. It is therefore impossible as a moral matter for a society to condone or allow murder or suicide.
  • 395
    • 79952781330 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kant, Critique, supra note 211, at 312-13
    • Kant, Critique, supra note 211, at 312-13.
  • 396
    • 0003411955 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Thomas M. Greene & Hoyt H. Hudson trans., Harper & Row 1960 [hereinafter KANT, RELIGION]
    • Immanuel Kant, Religion Within the Limits of Reason Alone 87-91 (Thomas M. Greene & Hoyt H. Hudson trans., Harper & Row 1960) [hereinafter KANT, RELIGION]
    • Religion Within the Limits of Reason Alone , pp. 87-91
    • Kant, I.1
  • 397
    • 79952797614 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kant, Perpetual Peace, supra note 211, at 93, 105, 112-13
    • Kant, Perpetual Peace, supra note 211, at 93, 105, 112-13
  • 398
    • 79952791041 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also RAWLS, supra note 205, at 315
    • see also RAWLS, supra note 205, at 315
  • 399
    • 79952803102 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Murphy, Kant's Theory, supra note 196, at 87-90
    • Murphy, Kant's Theory, supra note 196, at 87-90
  • 400
    • 79952800289 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (anticipating HART, supra note 120, at 4-9, who distinguished among three questions: (1) Why have a system of punishments? (2) Who should be punished?
    • (anticipating HART, supra note 120, at 4-9, who distinguished among three questions: (1) Why have a system of punishments? (2) Who should be punished?
  • 401
    • 79952782229 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and (3) What form should punishment take?)
    • and (3) What form should punishment take?).
  • 402
    • 79952776982 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • KANT, CRITIQUE, supra note 211, at 312
    • KANT, CRITIQUE, supra note 211, at 312
  • 403
    • 79952776597 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Murphy, Does Kant, supra note 196, at 521-28
    • Murphy, Does Kant, supra note 196, at 521-28.
  • 404
    • 79952783249 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kant, Critique supra note 211, at 312
    • Kant, Critique supra note 211, at 312.
  • 405
    • 79952812376 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • KANT, supra note 14, at 105
    • KANT, supra note 14, at 105.
  • 406
    • 79952789085 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • RAWLS, supra note 205, at 241
    • RAWLS, supra note 205, at 241.
  • 407
    • 79952783858 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • KANT, supra note 14, at 105
    • KANT, supra note 14, at 105.
  • 408
    • 79952794220 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • HART, supra note 120, at 24
    • HART, supra note 120, at 24.
  • 409
    • 79952782875 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • KANT, supra note 14, at 105
    • KANT, supra note 14, at 105.
  • 410
    • 79952810189 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 411
    • 79952784239 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 106
    • Id. at 106.
  • 412
    • 79952786306 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As Thomas Hill has pointed out, moral agents may well feel "discomfort" when they realize their wrongdoing and may even accept as appropriate the condemnation of others. However, those self-directed reactive attitudes are an "inherent liability in being one moral agent among others," and "[t]here is no ground here for supposing that this suffering, or even more, should be deliberately imposed," or that wrongdoers deserve to suffer in any practical sense that entitles others to contribute to their suffering
    • As Thomas Hill has pointed out, moral agents may well feel "discomfort" when they realize their wrongdoing and may even accept as appropriate the condemnation of others. However, those self-directed reactive attitudes are an "inherent liability in being one moral agent among others," and "[t]here is no ground here for supposing that this suffering, or even more, should be deliberately imposed," or that wrongdoers deserve to suffer in any practical sense that entitles others to contribute to their suffering.
  • 413
    • 79952778964 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hill, supra note 125, at 421-22, 424
    • Hill, supra note 125, at 421-22, 424.
  • 414
    • 79952780466 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • See Kolber, supra note 1, at 184 n.l (citing Kant in a "cf." footnote for the proposition that punishment must be proportional to the subjective experiences of offenders). The passage he cites reads in full: But only the law of retribution (ius talionis)-it being understood, of course, that this is applied by a court (not by your private judgment)-can specify definitely the quality and the quantity of punishment; all other principles are fluctuating and unsuited for a sentence of pure and strict justice because extraneous considerations are mixed into them. - Now it would indeed seem that differences in social rank would not allow the principle of retribution, of like for like; but even when this is not possible in terms of the letter, the principle can always remain valid in terms of its effect if account is taken of the sensibilities of the upper classes. - A fine, for example, imposed for a verbal injury has no relation to the offense, for someone wealthy might indeed allow himself to indulge in a verbal insult on some occasion; yet the outrage he has done to someone's love or honor can still be quite similar to the hurt done to his pride if he is constrained by judgment and right not only to apologize publicly to the one he has insulted but also to kiss his hand, for instance, even though he is of a lower class.
  • 415
    • 79952801960 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Similarly, someone of high standing given to violence could be condemned not only to apologize for striking an innocent citizen socially inferior to himself but also to undergo a solitary confinement involving hardship; in addition to the discomfort he undergoes, the offender's vanity would be painfully affected, so that through his shame like would fittingly be repaid with like
    • Similarly, someone of high standing given to violence could be condemned not only to apologize for striking an innocent citizen socially inferior to himself but also to undergo a solitary confinement involving hardship; in addition to the discomfort he undergoes, the offender's vanity would be painfully affected, so that through his shame like would fittingly be repaid with like.
  • 416
    • 79952787898 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • KANT, supra note 14, at 106
    • KANT, supra note 14, at 106.
  • 417
    • 79952777360 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Read incautiously, this passage may appear to endorse a subjectivist account of punishment. It mentions "pain" and "shame" after all. To rest on this surface would be to ignore the crucial reference to retribution and its role in determining the objective necessity for shaming in certain circumstances. Here, Kant recognizes that some crimes express a maxim of status entitlement. Proper punishment in these circumstances requires bringing low the prideful. Kant is democratic in this respect. He refuses to endorse class as a claim of right to do wrong. The contemporary criminalization of hate crimes reflects a similar disposition. Jean Hampton's approach to retributivism also focuses on negating unfounded claims of entitlement.
  • 418
    • 79952792149 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See infra notes 255-59 and accompanying text. Thomas Hill reads this passage slightly differently, but ultimately also reaches the conclusion that it does not provide grounds for thinking that Kant is giving leave for judges to vary punishments according to subjective factors
    • See infra notes 255-59 and accompanying text. Thomas Hill reads this passage slightly differently, but ultimately also reaches the conclusion that it does not provide grounds for thinking that Kant is giving leave for judges to vary punishments according to subjective factors.
  • 419
    • 79952776594 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hill, supra note 125, at 434-37.
    • Hill, supra note 125, at 434-37.
  • 420
    • 79952796095 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a more expansive account of status inequality in crime and potential responses
    • For a more expansive account of status inequality in crime and potential responses.
  • 421
    • 84881146686 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A no-excuse approach to transitional justice, 87
    • hereinafter Gray, No Excuse
    • see David Gray, A No-Excuse Approach to Transitional Justice, 87 WASH. U. L. REV. 1043 (2010) [hereinafter Gray, No Excuse]
    • (2010) Wash. U. L. Rev. , vol.1043
    • Gray, D.1
  • 422
    • 84926085224 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Extraordinary justice
    • Forthcoming
    • David Gray, Extraordinary Justice, 62 ALA. L. REV. (forthcoming 2011).
    • (2011) Ala. L. Rev. , vol.62
    • Gray, D.1
  • 423
    • 79952798745 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Other punishments suggested by Kant share this same intuitive appeal. For example, the punishment for murder is death
    • Other punishments suggested by Kant share this same intuitive appeal. For example, the punishment for murder is death.
  • 424
    • 79952794218 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • KANT, supra note 14, at 106. Others are more elusive.
    • KANT, supra note 14, at 106. Others are more elusive.
  • 425
    • 79952779326 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., id. at 130 ("The punishment for rape and pederasty is castration ⋯ that for bestiality, permanent expulsion from civil society, since the criminal has made himself unworthy of human society."). Other crimes appear anachronistic
    • See, e.g., id. at 130 ("The punishment for rape and pederasty is castration ⋯ that for bestiality, permanent expulsion from civil society, since the criminal has made himself unworthy of human society."). Other crimes appear anachronistic.
  • 426
    • 79952802344 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., id. at 108-09 (providing excuses for mothers who kill illegitimate children and killings perpetrated during duels). That these punishments may seem odd, anachronistic, or culturally bound is no criticism of the theory, however, because the contradiction posed by any maxim of action is in most cases determined by reference to contingent social and legal commitments
    • See, e.g., id. at 108-09 (providing excuses for mothers who kill illegitimate children and killings perpetrated during duels). That these punishments may seem odd, anachronistic, or culturally bound is no criticism of the theory, however, because the contradiction posed by any maxim of action is in most cases determined by reference to contingent social and legal commitments.
  • 427
    • 79952777793 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 215
    • See supra note 215.
  • 428
    • 79952810805 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • This category includes many politicians, pundits, practitioners, and others who claim the mantle of retributivism. The sad fact is that many of these folks are not really retributivists at all. Rather, they mine moral outrage to justify ever more severe punishments that are hard if not impossible to justify under any traditional theory of punishment, including retributivism. This author shares in the unapologetic belief that we ought not endorse or accept individual sentences or a system of criminal punishments that cannot be justified by a coherent and persuasive theory of criminal law and punishment. Therefore, any claim that our current punitive practices do not conform, in even a rough way, to the terms and dictates of retributivism is a non sequitur in the present context. Here, the questions at issue are whether the subjectivist critique exposes a core incoherence in retributivism or whether subjectivism offers a superior theory of criminal punishment. The answer to both questions is definitively "no."
  • 431
    • 79952805451 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also MOORE, supra note 122, at 84-92, 111
    • see also MOORE, supra note 122, at 84-92, 111.
  • 432
    • 79952793597 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • HERBERT MORRIS, Persons and Punishment, in ON GUILT AND INNOCENCE 31, 34-35 (1979)
    • HERBERT MORRIS, Persons and Punishment, in ON GUILT AND INNOCENCE 31, 34-35 (1979).
  • 433
    • 0010035413 scopus 로고
    • Correcting harms versus righting wrongs: The goal of retribution 39
    • For a criticism of this view, see
    • For a criticism of this view, see Jean Hampton, Correcting Harms Versus Righting Wrongs: The Goal of Retribution 39 UCLA L. REV. 1659, 1660-61 (1992)
    • (1992) Ucla L. Rev. , vol.1659 , pp. 1660-1661
    • Hampton, J.1
  • 434
    • 79952782100 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • David Dolinko, Some Thoughts about Retributivism, 101 ETHICS 537, 545-49 (1991)
    • David Dolinko, Some Thoughts about Retributivism, 101 ETHICS 537, 545-49 (1991).
  • 435
    • 79952776773 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Morris, supra note 186
    • Morris, supra note 186.
  • 436
    • 79952811394 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 264
    • Id. at 264.
  • 437
    • 79952801767 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • RAWLS, supra note 205, at 241, 314-15, 575-76
    • RAWLS, supra note 205, at 241, 314-15, 575-76.
  • 438
    • 79952785031 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sharon Dolovich provides a more elaborate account of a Rawlsian approach to punishment than Rawls ever did in Legitimate Punishment in Liberal Democracy, 7 Markel and Flanders have a different approach that also reflects shades of Rawls
    • Sharon Dolovich provides a more elaborate account of a Rawlsian approach to punishment than Rawls ever did in Legitimate Punishment in Liberal Democracy, 7 BUFF. CRIM. L. REV. 307 (2004). Markel and Flanders have a different approach that also reflects shades of Rawls.
    • (2004) Buff. Crim. L. Rev. , vol.307
  • 439
    • 79952812782 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Markel & Flanders,supra note 1 (distinguishing between comprehensive and political conceptions of retributive justice)
    • See Markel & Flanders,supra note 1 (distinguishing between comprehensive and political conceptions of retributive justice)
  • 440
    • 79952802155 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also RAWLS, supra note 205, at 10 (arguing that punishment must be defined objectively as a restraint on liberty)
    • see also RAWLS, supra note 205, at 10 (arguing that punishment must be defined objectively as a restraint on liberty)
  • 441
    • 0002921553 scopus 로고
    • Two concepts of rules, 64
    • John Rawls, Two Concepts of Rules, 64 PHIL. Rev. 3 (1955)
    • (1955) Phil. Rev. , vol.3
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 442
    • 79952777359 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Walker, supra note 42, at 534-36 (describing a "Rawlsian" moment of reasoning from the original position)
    • Walker, supra note 42, at 534-36 (describing a "Rawlsian" moment of reasoning from the original position).
  • 443
    • 79952797224 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • FLETCHER, supra note 190, at 459-60
    • FLETCHER, supra note 190, at 459-60.
  • 444
    • 79952811195 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 461, 505-14
    • Id. at 461, 505-14.
  • 445
    • 79952811599 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • FLETCHER, supra note 141, at 227-28
    • FLETCHER, supra note 141, at 227-28.
  • 446
    • 79952797436 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As Fletcher points out, the rise of imprisonment as the main form of state-sanctioned punishment opens a space of ambiguity between criminal theory and penal practice
    • As Fletcher points out, the rise of imprisonment as the main form of state-sanctioned punishment opens a space of ambiguity between criminal theory and penal practice.
  • 447
    • 79952803315 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 226
    • Id. at 226.
  • 448
    • 79952809723 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • HART, supra note 120, at 4
    • HART, supra note 120, at 4.
  • 449
    • 79952783857 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hart's general approach relies on utilitarian considerations when justifying systems of punishment and retributive grounds when addressing questions of distribution
    • Hart's general approach relies on utilitarian considerations when justifying systems of punishment and retributive grounds when addressing questions of distribution.
  • 450
    • 79952789651 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 5-11
    • Id. at 5-11.
  • 451
    • 79952798546 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kent Greenawalt offers a similar definition of punishment as involving "designedly unpleasant consequences" which most people would wish to avoid
    • Kent Greenawalt offers a similar definition of punishment as involving "designedly unpleasant consequences" which most people would wish to
  • 452
    • 79952789486 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Greenawalt, supra note 141, at 343-44
    • Greenawalt, supra note 141, at 343-44.
  • 453
    • 79952776226 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • FLETCHER, supra note 141, at 228
    • FLETCHER, supra note 141, at 228
  • 454
    • 79952795520 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also HART, supra note 120, at 19-20, 24-25 (rejecting on various grounds subjective approaches to punishment)
    • see also HART, supra note 120, at 19-20, 24-25 (rejecting on various grounds subjective approaches to punishment)
  • 455
    • 79952794540 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 215 (recognizing that Hart defines punishment objectively)
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 215 (recognizing that Hart defines punishment objectively).
  • 456
    • 79952780705 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • But see Kolber, supra note 11, at 34 (acknowledging that "victim subjective experiences are generally relevant")
    • But see Kolber, supra note 11, at 34 (acknowledging that "victim subjective experiences are generally relevant").
  • 457
    • 79952806437 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • FLETCHER, supra note 141, at 228
    • FLETCHER, supra note 141, at 228.
  • 458
    • 79952793596 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Fletcher's discussion neatly disposes of any normative significance that can be drawn from O. Henry's famous story The Cop and the Anthem, in which the homeless protagonist goes to great lengths to get himself incarcerated, where he hopes he will be warm, fed, and relatively safe
    • Fletcher's discussion neatly disposes of any normative significance that can be drawn from O. Henry's famous story The Cop and the Anthem, in which the homeless protagonist goes to great lengths to get himself incarcerated, where he hopes he will be warm, fed, and relatively safe.
  • 459
    • 84876243854 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The cop and the anthem
    • Kolber, supra note 6, at 1580 n.42 (citing (Franklin J. Mathiews ed., 1918))
    • Kolber, supra note 6, at 1580 n.42 (citing O. HENRY, The Cop and the Anthem, in THE RANSOM OF RED CHIEF AND OTHER O. HENRY STORIES FOR BOYS 143, 143 (Franklin J. Mathiews ed., 1918))
    • The Ransom of Red Chief and Other O. Henry Stories for Boys , vol.143 , pp. 143
    • Henry, O.1
  • 460
    • 79952803926 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also Kolber, supra note 1, at 205 ("Even though his liberty will be restricted when caught, he is not retributively punished when he is subsequently imprisoned, nor are his real-life counterparts. It is simply implausible that a person can be criminally culpable and thereby deserve to receive treatment that the offender affirmatively desires.")
    • see also Kolber, supra note 1, at 205 ("Even though his liberty will be restricted when caught, he is not retributively punished when he is subsequently imprisoned, nor are his real-life counterparts. It is simply implausible that a person can be criminally culpable and thereby deserve to receive treatment that the offender affirmatively desires.").
  • 461
    • 79952789844 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • FEINBERG, supra note 20, at 97-98
    • FEINBERG, supra note 20, at 97-98.
  • 462
    • 79952809725 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 98-100
    • Id. at 98-100.
  • 463
    • 79952806657 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.; see also Markel & Flanders, supra note 1, at 107 ("[R]etributive punishment ⋯ serves as an attempt to communicate to the offender society's condemnation.")
    • Id.; see also Markel & Flanders, supra note 1, at 107 ("[R]etributive punishment ⋯ serves as an attempt to communicate to the offender society's condemnation.")
  • 464
    • 0347569386 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • What do alternative sanctions mean?, 63
    • arguing that "[pjunishment ⋯ is a special convention that signifies [society's] moral condemnation" of the offender
    • Dan Kahan, What Do Alternative Sanctions Mean?, 63 U. CHI. L. REV. 591, 593 (1996) (arguing that "[pjunishment ⋯ is a special convention that signifies [society's] moral condemnation" of the offender).
    • (1996) U. Chi. L. Rev. , vol.591 , pp. 593
    • Kahan, D.1
  • 465
    • 79952781507 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • FEINBERG, supra note 20, at 100
    • FEINBERG, supra note 20, at 100.
  • 466
    • 79952783065 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For example, Feinberg analogizes punishment as a symbolic idiom for condemnation to champagne as a symbolic idiom for celebration
    • For example, Feinberg analogizes punishment as a symbolic idiom for condemnation to champagne as a symbolic idiom for celebration.
  • 467
    • 79952808698 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. It is hard to see how the message of Ron Santo's popping the cork on a bottle of champagne after the Cubs win the World Series would be muddied for viewers if Santo actually hated the stuff
    • Id. It is hard to see how the message of Ron Santo's popping the cork on a bottle of champagne after the Cubs win the World Series would be muddied for viewers if Santo actually hated the stuff.
  • 468
    • 79952776024 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 116-18
    • Id. at 116-18.
  • 469
    • 79952804875 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • But see Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1077 (concluding that a "thoroughgoing expressivist theory that punishment involves only considerations of such disapproval would be unaffected by the phenomena we have emphasized")
    • But see Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1077 (concluding that a "thoroughgoing expressivist theory that punishment involves only considerations of such disapproval would be unaffected by the phenomena we have emphasized")
  • 470
    • 79952782659 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 208-10 (claiming that expressivists must link symbolic semantics to profane subjective experiences).These arguments are addressed infra Part IV.B
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 208-10 (claiming that expressivists must link symbolic semantics to profane subjective experiences).These arguments are addressed infra Part IV.B.
  • 471
    • 79952778178 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • FEINBERG, supra note 20, at 118
    • FEINBERG, supra note 20, at 118.
  • 472
    • 79952776413 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See generally Markel & Flanders, supra note 1
    • See generally Markel & Flanders, supra note 1.
  • 473
    • 79952786928 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See LUDWIG WITTGENSTEIN, PHILOSOPHICAL INVESTIGATIONS 89-96 (G.E.M. Anscombe trans., 1953)
    • See LUDWIG WITTGENSTEIN, PHILOSOPHICAL INVESTIGATIONS 89-96 (G.E.M. Anscombe trans., 1953).
  • 474
    • 79952811959 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nino, supra note 20, at 94
    • Nino, supra note 20, at 94.
  • 475
    • 79952803101 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 102-03
    • Id. at 102-03.
  • 476
    • 79952798940 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nino argues that punishment systems and punishment in individual cases represent a disparity in the distribution of public burdens and benefits that can only be justified by reference to consent. Culpability for a crime, in his view, entails consensual loss of immunity from punishment
    • Nino argues that punishment systems and punishment in individual cases represent a disparity in the distribution of public burdens and benefits that can only be justified by reference to consent. Culpability for a crime, in his view, entails consensual loss of immunity from punishment.
  • 477
    • 79952806658 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 478
    • 79952804500 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 96-97, 102-03, 107-08
    • Id. at 96-97, 102-03, 107-08.
  • 479
    • 79952811197 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See generally Hampton, supra note 20
    • See generally Hampton, supra note 20.
  • 480
    • 80054351562 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • But see Deirdre Golash, The Retributive Paradox, 54 ANALYSIS 72, 73-78 (1994) (providing a pithy, if not entirely persuasive, critique of Hampton's theory)
    • But see Deirdre Golash, The Retributive Paradox, 54 ANALYSIS 72, 73-78 (1994) (providing a pithy, if not entirely persuasive, critique of Hampton's theory).
  • 481
    • 79952813808 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Hampton, supra note 20, at 117-19 (describing the moral education theory as concerned less with punishment for societal purposes and more with benefiting the offender with moral knowledge and freedom to autonomously correct her future behavior)
    • See Hampton, supra note 20, at 117-19 (describing the moral education theory as concerned less with punishment for societal purposes and more with benefiting the offender with moral knowledge and freedom to autonomously correct her future behavior).
  • 482
    • 79952801766 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hampton, supra note 233, at 1665-85
    • Hampton, supra note 233, at 1665-85
  • 483
    • 79952799168 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also Bronsteen, supra note 203, at 1151 (citing unpublished data gathered by Kenworthey Bilz supporting Hampton's view)
    • see also Bronsteen, supra note 203, at 1151 (citing unpublished data gathered by Kenworthey Bilz supporting Hampton's view).
  • 484
    • 79952811598 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • But see Walker, supra note 42, at 531-32
    • But see Walker, supra note 42, at 531-32.
  • 485
    • 79952798548 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hampton, supra note 20, at 128-29
    • Hampton, supra note 20, at 128-29.
  • 486
    • 79952785711 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hampton offers the example of a physician convicted of Medicare fraud who is sentenced to community service in a state clinic
    • Hampton offers the example of a physician convicted of Medicare fraud who is sentenced to community service in a state clinic.
  • 487
    • 79952784837 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 128
    • Id. at 128.
  • 488
    • 79952805837 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As she points out, attending to the sick need neither be painful nor unpleasant for the physician for his sentence to constitute " punishment" so long as his freedom is constrained and that constraint entails a moral lesson
    • As she points out, attending to the sick need neither be painful nor unpleasant for the physician for his sentence to constitute " punishment" so long as his freedom is constrained and that constraint entails a moral lesson.
  • 489
    • 79952789287 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 490
    • 79952812961 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • NOZICK, supra note 128, at 363-80
    • NOZICK, supra note 128, at 363-80.
  • 491
    • 79952790263 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 374-80
    • Id. at 374-80.
  • 492
    • 23744477929 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Dan Markel, State Be Not Proud, 40 HARV. C.R.-C.L. L. Rev. 407, 411-13 (2005) (critiquing courts and commentators who make this conflation between retributive justice and vengeance)
    • See, e.g., Dan Markel, State Be Not Proud, 40 HARV. C.R.-C.L. L. Rev. 407, 411-13 (2005) (critiquing courts and commentators who make this conflation between retributive justice and vengeance).
  • 493
    • 79952778579 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., FLETCHER, supra note 190, at 417 (proposing that " 'retribution' is not in itself an argument for making criminals suffer," but rather a means for offenders to correct the societal imbalance caused by criminal behavior)
    • See, e.g., FLETCHER, supra note 190, at 417 (proposing that " 'retribution' is not in itself an argument for making criminals suffer," but rather a means for offenders to correct the societal imbalance caused by criminal behavior)
  • 494
    • 79952803318 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Markel, supra note 262, at 411-13, 437-38 (arguing that the purpose of punishment is not revenge)
    • Markel, supra note 262, at 411-13, 437-38 (arguing that the purpose of punishment is not revenge)
  • 495
    • 79952802522 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Morris, supra note 186, at 270 (positing that retributivists reject "like for like" punishment on moral grounds)
    • Morris, supra note 186, at 270 (positing that retributivists reject "like for like" punishment on moral grounds).
  • 496
    • 79952794539 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Berman, supra note 25, at 8-9, 27-28 (categorizing the retributivist view as recognizing the "intrinsic value in the suffering of wrongdoers" rather than focusing on the value attributed to punishment by the plurality)
    • See Berman, supra note 25, at 8-9, 27-28 (categorizing the retributivist view as recognizing the "intrinsic value in the suffering of wrongdoers" rather than focusing on the value attributed to punishment by the plurality).
  • 497
    • 79952793595 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As Thomas Hill points out, in the ideal case an offender would experience guilt and moral suffering
    • As Thomas Hill points out, in the ideal case an offender would experience guilt and moral suffering.
  • 498
    • 79952807119 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hill, supra note 125, at 414-23
    • Hill, supra note 125, at 414-23.
  • 499
    • 79952792150 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As a solution for a race of devils, however, punishment under law is not defined or justified by the goal of inflicting guilt or moral suffering
    • As a solution for a race of devils, however, punishment under law is not defined or justified by the goal of inflicting guilt or moral suffering.
  • 500
    • 79952794424 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Gray, NoExcuse, supra note 228, at 1081
    • Gray, NoExcuse, supra note 228, at 1081.
  • 501
    • 79952780704 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • First, organizing a public response to crime around the project of inspiring spontaneous subjective states would raise serious conceptional and practical concerns
    • First, organizing a public response to crime around the project of inspiring spontaneous subjective states would raise serious conceptional and practical concerns.
  • 502
    • 79952813642 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1048-51, 1054-55, 1062-64
    • Id. at 1048-51, 1054-55, 1062-64.
  • 503
    • 79952779131 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Second, guilt and moral suffering are subjective and matters of private conscience
    • Second, guilt and moral suffering are subjective and matters of private conscience.
  • 504
    • 79952785911 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • KANT, supra note 14, at 106. By contrast, punishment under law is a public matter, which as a practice maintains that only the law of retribution (ius talionis)-it being understood, of course, that this is applied by a court (not by your private judgment)-can specify definitely the quality and the quantity of punishment
    • KANT, supra note 14, at 106. By contrast, punishment under law is a public matter, which as a practice maintains that only "the law of retribution (ius talionis)-it being understood, of course, that this is applied by a court (not by your private judgment)-can specify definitely the quality and the quantity of punishment."
  • 505
    • 79952809537 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. To lump this sort of suffering in with suffering of concern for subjectivist critics would repeat the core equivocation exposed in this Article
    • Id. To lump this sort of suffering in with suffering of concern for subjectivist critics would repeat the core equivocation exposed in this Article.
  • 506
    • 79952791939 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See 4 WILLIAM BLACKSTONE, COMMENTARIES *ll-20 (requiring proportionality of punishment)
    • See 4 WILLIAM BLACKSTONE, COMMENTARIES *ll-20 (requiring proportionality of punishment)
  • 507
    • 79952798547 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • NOZICK, supra note 128, at 363-65 (providing an objective formula for calculating the amount of punishment deserved by the degree of wrongness and the offender's responsibility)
    • NOZICK, supra note 128, at 363-65 (providing an objective formula for calculating the amount of punishment deserved by the degree of wrongness and the offender's responsibility).
  • 508
    • 79952808699 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • FEINBERG, supra note 20, at 116-18
    • FEINBERG, supra note 20, at 116-18.
  • 509
    • 79952795154 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Bronsteen et al., supra note 3, at 1465-67, 1481 (arguing the importance of proportionality in punishment and the need to reform the criminal justice system to reflect that importance)
    • See Bronsteen et al., supra note 3, at 1465-67, 1481 (arguing the importance of proportionality in punishment and the need to reform the criminal justice system to reflect that importance).
  • 510
    • 79952806867 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See MOORE, supra note 122, at 90-91 (proposing that while retributivism prefers that "Q]ike cases ⋯ be treated alike," it requires that punishment match desert)
    • See MOORE, supra note 122, at 90-91 (proposing that while retributivism prefers that "Q]ike cases ⋯ be treated alike," it requires that punishment match desert).
  • 511
    • 79952812154 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Feinberg, Noncomparative Justice, supra note 68, at 300-01, 311-13, 318-19
    • Feinberg, Noncomparative Justice, supra note 68, at 300-01, 311-13, 318-19.
  • 512
    • 79952789843 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 311-13, 318-19
    • Id. at 311-13, 318-19.
  • 513
    • 79952806929 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See generally DEBORAH HELLMAN, WHEN IS DISCRIMINATION WRONG? (2008)
    • See generally DEBORAH HELLMAN, WHEN IS DISCRIMINATION WRONG? (2008).
  • 514
    • 79952790262 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Feinberg, Noncomparative Justice, supra note 68, at 311 (arguing that this analogy proves that "criminal desert is in part noncomparative," because it is possible to have a system where all punishments are unjust due to unreasonable severity)
    • See Feinberg, Noncomparative Justice, supra note 68, at 311 (arguing that this analogy proves that "criminal desert is in part noncomparative," because it is possible to have a system where all punishments are unjust due to unreasonable severity).
  • 515
    • 79952808697 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • While far from determinative in the present discussion, it is worth noting that the Supreme Court's death penalty jurisprudence appears to endorse an objective rather than subjective account of "punishment." In In re Kemmler, 136 U.S. 436, 447 (1890)
    • While far from determinative in the present discussion, it is worth noting that the Supreme Court's death penalty jurisprudence appears to endorse an objective rather than subjective account of "punishment." In In re Kemmler, 136 U.S. 436, 447 (1890)
  • 516
    • 79952792986 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • the Court confirmed that particularly barbaric punishments, such as disembowelment, are prohibited by the Eighth Amendment because "they involve torture or a lingering death" and are therefore "inhuman and barbarous, something more than the mere extinguishment of life." While it is not unreasonable to think that this "something more" is pain, the Court "has never invalidated a State's chosen procedure for carrying out a sentence of death as the infliction of cruel and unusual punishment," Baze v. Rees, 553 U.S. 35, 48 (2008)
    • the Court confirmed that particularly barbaric punishments, such as disembowelment, are prohibited by the Eighth Amendment because "they involve torture or a lingering death" and are therefore "inhuman and barbarous, something more than the mere extinguishment of life." While it is not unreasonable to think that this "something more" is pain, the Court "has never invalidated a State's chosen procedure for carrying out a sentence of death as the infliction of cruel and unusual punishment," Baze v. Rees, 553 U.S. 35, 48 (2008)
  • 517
    • 79952813217 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • When asked to rule on the constitutionality of electrocution on particularly gruesome facts, the Court held that "[t]he cruelty against which the Constitution protects a convicted man is cruelty inherent in the method of punishment, not the necessary suffering involved in any method employed to extinguish life humanely," Louisiana ex rel. Francis v. Resweber, 329 U.S. 459, 464 (1947)
    • When asked to rule on the constitutionality of electrocution on particularly gruesome facts, the Court held that "[t]he cruelty against which the Constitution protects a convicted man is cruelty inherent in the method of punishment, not the necessary suffering involved in any method employed to extinguish life humanely," Louisiana ex rel. Francis v. Resweber, 329 U.S. 459, 464 (1947).
  • 518
    • 79952806928 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • When asked to determine the constitutionality of imposing death on mentally impaired and juvenile offenders in Roper v. Simmons, 543 U.S. 551, 568-74 (2005)
    • When asked to determine the constitutionality of imposing death on mentally impaired and juvenile offenders in Roper v. Simmons, 543 U.S. 551, 568-74 (2005)
  • 519
    • 79952778966 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Again in Atkins v. Virginia, 536 U.S. 304, 317-21 (2002)
    • Again in Atkins v. Virginia, 536 U.S. 304, 317-21 (2002)
  • 520
    • 79952800096 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Court again adopted an objective view, focusing its attention on the moral culpability of these agents and our "evolving standards of decency," rather than the unique suffering members of these classes of offender might experience
    • The Court again adopted an objective view, focusing its attention on the moral culpability of these agents and our "evolving standards of decency," rather than the unique suffering members of these classes of offender might experience.
  • 521
    • 79952778578 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See also Graham v. Florida, 130 S. Ct. 2011 (2010) (adopting the same approach in holding that the Eighth Amendment prohibits sentencing juvenile offenders to life in prison without the possibility of release). However, one should not make too much of the Court's record in these matters. The Court has never squarely addressed the question whether punishment is suffering, and as a consequence is often less than clear on where it stands
    • See also Graham v. Florida, 130 S. Ct. 2011 (2010) (adopting the same approach in holding that the Eighth Amendment prohibits sentencing juvenile offenders to life in prison without the possibility of release). However, one should not make too much of the Court's record in these matters. The Court has never squarely addressed the question whether punishment is suffering, and as a consequence is often less than clear on where it stands.
  • 522
    • 79952784238 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 6, at 1591
    • Kolber, supra note 6, at 1591.
  • 523
    • 79952797023 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1068-74 (describing retributivist approaches to punishment as consistently objective)
    • See, e.g., Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1068-74 (describing retributivist approaches to punishment as consistently objective)
  • 524
    • 79952812588 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 6, at 1585-94 (stating that "the currency of punishment is understood in objective terms.")
    • Kolber, supra note 6, at 1585-94 (stating that "the currency of punishment is understood in objective terms.").
  • 525
    • 79952806433 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • But see Kolber, supra note 1, at 203-08 (acknowledging that while valuing objectivity, for punishment to be successful, the offender must have some subjective awareness)
    • But see Kolber, supra note 1, at 203-08 (acknowledging that while valuing objectivity, for punishment to be successful, the offender must have some subjective awareness).
  • 526
    • 79952794216 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 203 (quoting RAWLS, supra note 205, at 10)
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 203 (quoting RAWLS, supra note 205, at 10).
  • 527
    • 79952798209 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1068-69, 1072 n.166, for a discussion of accounting for subjectivity when analyzing punishment from a retributivist perspective
    • See Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1068-69, 1072 n.166, for a discussion of accounting for subjectivity when analyzing punishment from a retributivist perspective.
  • 528
    • 79952796096 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 196-98
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 196-98.
  • 529
    • 79952783660 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 203
    • Id. at 203
  • 530
    • 79952804690 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1069 (endorsing Kolber's five arguments as their own)
    • see also Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1069 (endorsing Kolber's five arguments as their own).
  • 531
    • 79952808486 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 203; see also Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1068, 1072 n.166 (agreeing with Kolber's assertion)
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 203; see also Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1068, 1072 n.166 (agreeing with Kolber's assertion).
  • 532
    • 79952803317 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 203
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 203.
  • 533
    • 79952810191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Golash, supra note 256, at 73 (pointing out that appeals to intuition are "unsatisfactory" in part "because some have this intuition while others don't")
    • See Golash, supra note 256, at 73 (pointing out that appeals to intuition are "unsatisfactory" in part "because some have this intuition while others don't").
  • 534
    • 79952776595 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Dolinko, supra note 233, at 557-58
    • See Dolinko, supra note 233, at 557-58.
  • 535
    • 79952785318 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 536
    • 79952807513 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 203
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 203.
  • 537
    • 79952804126 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Hampton, supra note 20, at 115-18 (clarifying the border between utilitarian and retributive theories of punishment by reference to the role of punishment in producing pain, which provides a "nonmoral" reason for compliance with law)
    • See Hampton, supra note 20, at 115-18 (clarifying the border between utilitarian and retributive theories of punishment by reference to the role of punishment in producing pain, which provides a "nonmoral" reason for compliance with law).
  • 538
    • 79952784425 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As an example, consider Kolber's discussion of "libertiles."
    • As an example, consider Kolber's discussion of "libertiles."
  • 539
    • 79952805070 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 6, at 1567-69
    • Kolber, supra note 6, at 1567-69.
  • 540
    • 79952784836 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • To conceive of liberty as quantified according to the comparative value of that liberty to an agent or the fruits accrued through exploitation of that liberty collapses deontological accounts of justice and liberty into utilitarianism without argument or justification
    • To conceive of liberty as quantified according to the comparative value of that liberty to an agent or the fruits accrued through exploitation of that liberty collapses deontological accounts of justice and liberty into utilitarianism without argument or justification.
  • 541
    • 79952780274 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • KANT, supra note 14, at 105
    • KANT, supra note 14, at 105
  • 542
    • 79952794740 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also Berman, supra note 25 (exploring the theoretical difficulties that befall suffering-focused retributivists)
    • see also Berman, supra note 25 (exploring the theoretical difficulties that befall suffering-focused retributivists).
  • 543
    • 79952792539 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • KANT, supra note 14, at 105
    • KANT, supra note 14, at 105.
  • 544
    • 79952790038 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 203-04
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 203-04
  • 545
    • 79952801169 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1069 (adopting this argument)
    • see also Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1069 (adopting this argument).
  • 546
    • 79952813216 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 204
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 204.
  • 547
    • 79952806226 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 548
    • 79952801959 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 209 n.72
    • Id. at 209 n.72.
  • 549
    • 79952794217 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra notes 255-259 and accompanying text
    • See supra notes 255-259 and accompanying text.
  • 550
    • 79952811196 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • NOZICK, supra note 128, at 368
    • NOZICK, supra note 128, at 368
  • 551
    • 79952793377 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Morris, supra note 186, at 264
    • Morris, supra note 186, at 264.
  • 552
    • 79952779130 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Panetti v. Quarterman, 551 U.S. 930, 954-60 (2007); Ford v. Wainwright, 477 U.S. 399, 401 (1986)
    • Panetti v. Quarterman, 551 U.S. 930, 954-60 (2007); Ford v. Wainwright, 477 U.S. 399, 401 (1986)
  • 554
    • 79952805638 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., FLETCHER, supra note 141, at 228
    • See, e.g., FLETCHER, supra note 141, at 228
  • 555
    • 79952798369 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hampton, supra note 20, at 128-29
    • Hampton, supra note 20, at 128-29.
  • 556
    • 79952790866 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • KANT, supra note 14, at 107
    • KANT, supra note 14, at 107
  • 557
    • 79952790454 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also MORRIS, supra note 232, at 48-49
    • see also MORRIS, supra note 232, at 48-49
  • 558
    • 79952780899 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • NOZICK, supra note 128, at 370-80
    • NOZICK, supra note 128, at 370-80
  • 559
    • 79952778778 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hill, supra note 125, at 439
    • Hill, supra note 125, at 439.
  • 560
    • 79952807910 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 212
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 212
  • 561
    • 79952783248 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1037-38, 1068-70
    • see also Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1037-38, 1068-70.
  • 562
    • 79952808696 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It is the logical implication from Bronsteen, Buccafusco, and Masur's discussion that the same would be true of an offender who
    • It is the logical implication from Bronsteen, Buccafusco, and Masur's discussion that the same would be true of an offender who "views incarceration as a badge of honor."
    • Views incarceration as a badge of honor
  • 563
    • 79952790670 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1077 (discussing offender perception within the context of expressive theories)
    • See Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1077 (discussing offender perception within the context of expressive theories).
  • 564
    • 79952783064 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • FOUCAULT, supra note 35, at 3-6
    • FOUCAULT, supra note 35, at 3-6.
  • 565
    • 79952784237 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 204 (emphasis added)
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 204 (emphasis added).
  • 566
    • 79952803100 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Again, Bronsteen, Buccafusco, and Masur fully endorse Kolber's views on this point
    • Again, Bronsteen, Buccafusco, and Masur fully endorse Kolber's views on this point.
  • 567
    • 79952800754 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1068-69
    • Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1068-69.
  • 568
    • 79952781506 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 204, 215
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 204, 215.
  • 569
    • 79952804499 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See FLETCHER, supra note 141, at 228 (noting that substance of punishment is "always whether the sanction is typically or characteristically onerous, not whether the sanction is experienced as punishment in the particular case")
    • See FLETCHER, supra note 141, at 228 (noting that substance of punishment is "always whether the sanction is typically or characteristically onerous, not whether the sanction is experienced as punishment in the particular case").
  • 570
    • 79952793378 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 205
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 205
  • 571
    • 79952794947 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1070-73 (arguing that adaptive capacities undermine the balancing of desert and punishment in pure retributivism)
    • see also Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1070-73 (arguing that adaptive capacities undermine the balancing of desert and punishment in pure retributivism).
  • 572
    • 79952784060 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 205
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 205
  • 573
    • 79952809724 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see HART, supra note 120, at 11 (discussing the "distribution" of punishment as who may be punished and by how much)
    • see HART, supra note 120, at 11 (discussing the "distribution" of punishment as who may be punished and by how much)
  • 574
    • 79952805453 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Murphy, Does Kant, supra note 196, at 530 (discussing Kant's views on proportionality as balancing punishment "against the offense for which [it] is administered")
    • Murphy, Does Kant, supra note 196, at 530 (discussing Kant's views on proportionality as balancing punishment "against the offense for which [it] is administered")
  • 575
    • 79952789487 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also Feinberg, Noncomparative Justice, supra note 68, at 311 (arguing that criminal desert is necessarily in part noncomparative)
    • see also Feinberg, Noncomparative Justice, supra note 68, at 311 (arguing that criminal desert is necessarily in part noncomparative).
  • 576
    • 79952806434 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Feinberg considers the vivid example of a system where beheading and disembowelment became the standard punishment for overtime parking
    • Feinberg considers the vivid example of a system where beheading and disembowelment became the standard punishment for overtime parking
  • 577
    • 79952805639 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 578
    • 79952777794 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As he points out, such a punishment is objectively unjust, and [m]oreover, it would be unjust even if it were the mildest penalty in the whole system of criminal law, with more serious offenses punished with proportionately greater severity still
    • As he points out, such a punishment is objectively unjust, and [m]oreover, it would be unjust even if it were the mildest penalty in the whole system of criminal law, with more serious offenses punished with proportionately greater severity still.
  • 579
    • 79952786713 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 580
    • 79952788877 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 235
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 235.
  • 581
    • 79952810192 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 207
    • Id. at 207
  • 582
    • 79952801170 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1069 (adopting this argument)
    • see also Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1069 (adopting this argument).
  • 583
    • 79952781329 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra Part II.B
    • See supra Part II.B.
  • 584
    • 79952795519 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 6, at 1585-86
    • Kolber, supra note 6, at 1585-86.
  • 585
    • 79952794538 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1586
    • Id. at 1586.
  • 586
    • 79952803316 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Retributivists must accept some portion of the responsibility here for choosing the word "deprivation," when "constraint" is probably more accurate
    • Retributivists must accept some portion of the responsibility here for choosing the word "deprivation," when "constraint" is probably more accurate.
  • 587
    • 79952795153 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 207
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 207
  • 588
    • 79952798743 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also Kolber, supra note 6, at 1587 (describing the variety of baseline states through the analogy of the abducted drug dealer)
    • see also Kolber, supra note 6, at 1587 (describing the variety of baseline states through the analogy of the abducted drug dealer).
  • 589
    • 79952790037 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 6, at 1587-89, 1593-94
    • Kolber, supra note 6, at 1587-89, 1593-94.
  • 590
    • 79952782874 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1590
    • Id. at 1590.
  • 591
    • 79952806436 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 592
    • 79952800502 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1590 n.65
    • Id. at 1590 n.65.
  • 593
    • 79952787524 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., 1 BLACKSTONE, supra note 266, at *40 (arguing that laws, discoverable by application of reason, and by which "freewill is in some degree regulated and restrained," are necessary conditions of justice)
    • See, e.g., 1 BLACKSTONE, supra note 266, at *40 (arguing that laws, discoverable by application of reason, and by which "freewill is in some degree regulated and restrained," are necessary conditions of justice)
  • 594
    • 79952807316 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • THOMAS HOBBES, LEVIATHAN 78 (Edwin Curley ed., 1994) 316. (determining that reason pushes individuals toward societal obligations or "peace" in order to protect individual liberty from all others in society who are also driven by "passions")
    • THOMAS HOBBES, LEVIATHAN 78 (Edwin Curley ed., 1994) 316.(determining that reason pushes individuals toward societal obligations or "peace" in order to protect individual liberty from all others in society who are also driven by "passions")
  • 595
    • 0003020378 scopus 로고
    • Idea for A universal history with a cosmopolitan intent
    • (Hans Reiss ed 1991) (positing that freewill "unconsciously promote[s] an end," whereby being forced to relinquish freewill ensures lasting freewill for all)
    • Immanuel Kant, Idea for A Universal History with a Cosmopolitan Intent (1784), reprinted in KANT: POLITICAL WRITINGS 41, 46-48 (Hans Reiss ed 1991) (positing that freewill "unconsciously promote[s] an end," whereby being forced to relinquish freewill ensures lasting freewill for all)
    • (1784) Reprinted in Kant: Political Writings , vol.41 , pp. 46-48
    • Kant, I.1
  • 596
    • 79952776596 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • KANT, supra note 14, at 89-90 (proposing that without law, "individual human beings, peoples, and states can never be secure against violence from one another," thereby requiring prohibitions on behavior ultimately to protect individual freedom)
    • KANT, supra note 14, at 89-90 (proposing that without law, "individual human beings, peoples, and states can never be secure against violence from one another," thereby requiring prohibitions on behavior ultimately to protect individual freedom)
  • 597
    • 79952796860 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • KANT, RELIGION, supra note 217, at 104-05 (stating that law is required to contain the private feelings of individuals)
    • KANT, RELIGION, supra note 217, at 104-05 (stating that law is required to contain the private feelings of individuals).
  • 598
    • 79952801171 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., RAWLS, supra note 205, at 201-05 (clarifying "the meaning of the priority of liberty" and the loss thereof)
    • See, e.g., RAWLS, supra note 205, at 201-05 (clarifying "the meaning of the priority of liberty" and the loss thereof).
  • 599
    • 79952811393 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 6, at 1587-89, 1593-94
    • Kolber, supra note 6, at 1587-89, 1593-94.
  • 600
    • 79952799167 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dan Markel and Chad Flanders make a similar point
    • Dan Markel and Chad Flanders make a similar point.
  • 601
    • 79952794537 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Markel & Flanders, supra note 1, at 170-78
    • See Markel & Flanders, supra note 1, at 170-78.
  • 602
    • 79952786101 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 232
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 232.
  • 603
    • 79952791938 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Bronsteen et al., supra note 3, at 1463-67 (arguing that evidence of prisoners' adaptability should inform the theory and practice of punishment)
    • See Bronsteen et al., supra note 3, at 1463-67 (arguing that evidence of prisoners' adaptability should inform the theory and practice of punishment)
  • 604
    • 79952796859 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bronsteen et al., supra note 139, at 1641 ("[Governments and policymakers should adopt a decision procedure based upon subjective well-being ⋯ .")
    • Bronsteen et al., supra note 139, at 1641 ("[Governments and policymakers should adopt a decision procedure based upon subjective well-being ⋯ .")
  • 605
    • 79952806435 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 11, at 4 ("If we seek to have justified criminal justice practices, then we need to consider subjective experience more than we do now.")
    • Kolber, supra note 11, at 4 ("If we seek to have justified criminal justice practices, then we need to consider subjective experience more than we do now.").
  • 606
    • 0000842517 scopus 로고
    • Positivism and fidelity to law-A reply to professor hart, 71
    • Lon L. Fuller, Positivism and Fidelity to Law-A Reply to Professor Hart, 71 HARV. L. REV. 630, 631 (1958).
    • (1958) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.630 , pp. 631
    • Fuller, L.L.1
  • 607
    • 79952809132 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 6, at 1569-70
    • Kolber, supra note 6, at 1569-70
  • 608
    • 79952808485 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 186-87
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 186-87.
  • 609
    • 79952786711 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 6, at 1569-70
    • Kolber, supra note 6, at 1569-70.
  • 610
    • 79952799899 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a useful discussion of the relationship between criminal justice and distributive justice
    • For a useful discussion of the relationship between criminal justice and distributive justice
  • 611
    • 79952803314 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see Stuart P. Green, Hard Times, Hard Time: Retributive Justice for Unjustly Disadvantaged Offenders, 2010 U. CHI. LEGAL F. (forthcoming 2010), available at http://ssrn.com/abstract=1511732
    • see Stuart P. Green, Hard Times, Hard Time: Retributive Justice for Unjustly Disadvantaged Offenders, 2010 U. CHI. LEGAL F. (forthcoming 2010), available at http://ssrn.com/abstract=1511732
  • 612
    • 79952788876 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Feinberg, Noncomparative Justice, supra note 68, at 300-01, 311-13
    • Feinberg, Noncomparative Justice, supra note 68, at 300-01, 311-13.
  • 613
    • 79952780703 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 212
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 212.
  • 614
    • 79952789485 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Green, supra note 327 (manuscript at 2-5) (explaining that the poor account for a disproportionately high percentage of crime victims and criminal offenders)
    • See, e.g., Green, supra note 327 (manuscript at 2-5) (explaining that the poor account for a disproportionately high percentage of crime victims and criminal offenders)
  • 615
    • 79952781713 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • OFFICE OF THE Surgeon Gen., U.S. Dep't of Health and Human Servs., Youth Violence: A Report of the SURGEON GENERAL ch. 4, (last visited Sept. 10, 2010) ("Race is a proxy for other known risk factors-living in poor, single parent families, doing poorly at school, and being exposed to neighborhood disadvantage, gangs, violence, and crime.").
    • OFFICE OF THE Surgeon Gen., U.S. Dep't of Health and Human Servs., Youth Violence: A Report of the SURGEON GENERAL ch. 4, http://www.surgeongeneral.gov/ library/youthviolence/toc.html (last visited Sept. 10, 2010) ("Race is a proxy for other known risk factors-living in poor, single parent families, doing poorly at school, and being exposed to neighborhood disadvantage, gangs, violence, and crime.").
  • 616
    • 79952806866 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Feb. 1995) [hereinafter Special Report] (recommending that Congress reduce the 100:1 ratio of sentences imposed for crack and powder cocaine offenses)
    • See U.S. Sentencing Commission, Special Report to Congress: Cocaine and Federal Sentencing Policy (Feb. 1995) [hereinafter Special Report] (recommending that Congress reduce the 100:1 ratio of sentences imposed for crack and powder cocaine offenses).
    • U.S. Sentencing Commission, Special Report to Congress: Cocaine and Federal Sentencing Policy
  • 617
    • 79952782228 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Green, supra note 327; Special Report, supra, note 331
    • See Green, supra note 327; Special Report, supra, note 331.
  • 618
    • 79952779498 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Feinberg, Noncomparative Justice, supra note 68, at 301
    • Feinberg, Noncomparative Justice, supra note 68, at 301.
  • 619
    • 79952799709 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Kolber, supra note 6, at 1567-69 (discussing how, for example, "[r]ich people have rights to use particular property that poor people lack," which suggests that rich people have higher baseline conditions)
    • See Kolber, supra note 6, at 1567-69 (discussing how, for example, "[r]ich people have rights to use particular property that poor people lack," which suggests that rich people have higher baseline conditions).
  • 620
    • 79952790453 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Kolber, supra note 1, at 230-31 ("All else being equal, as an empirical matter, wealthy people are likely to suffer more intensely in prison than those with less wealth who are placed in the same prison conditions.")
    • See Kolber, supra note 1, at 230-31 ("All else being equal, as an empirical matter, wealthy people are likely to suffer more intensely in prison than those with less wealth who are placed in the same prison conditions.").
  • 621
    • 79952790669 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 219
    • Id. at 219
  • 622
    • 79952805836 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ("[T]he only way to avoid the obligation to take the subjective experience of punishment into account is to abolish punishment entirely.")
    • ("[T]he only way to avoid the obligation to take the subjective experience of punishment into account is to abolish punishment entirely.").
  • 623
    • 79952809315 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1055-68 (discussing the applications of subjectivist findings on hedonic adaptation, forecasting, and post-prison effects to utilitarian theories of punishment)
    • See Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1055-68 (discussing the applications of subjectivist findings on hedonic adaptation, forecasting, and post-prison effects to utilitarian theories of punishment)
  • 624
    • 79952782658 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 236 (maintaining that consequentialists are already "quite receptive to the claim that they are prima facie obligated to take account of actual or anticipated subjective experiences")
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 236 (maintaining that consequentialists are already "quite receptive to the claim that they are prima facie obligated to take account of actual or anticipated subjective experiences").
  • 625
    • 79952789842 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See infra Part VI
    • See infra Part VI.
  • 626
    • 79952779325 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 219
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 219.
  • 627
    • 0042220176 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Principles of penal law, reprinted
    • (John Bowring ed., Russell & Russell 1962) (1843). There is good reason to doubt the model of agency implied by this model
    • Jeremy Bentham, Principles of Penal Law, reprinted in The Works of Jeremy BENTHAM 365, 395-96 (John Bowring ed., Russell & Russell 1962) (1843). There is good reason to doubt the model of agency implied by this model.
    • The Works of Jeremy BENTHAM , vol.365 , pp. 395-396
    • Bentham, J.1
  • 628
    • 79952801765 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., David J. Pyle, The Economic Approach to Crime and Punishment, 6 J. INTERDISC. ECON. 1, 4-8 (1995)
    • See, e.g., David J. Pyle, The Economic Approach to Crime and Punishment, 6 J. INTERDISC. ECON. 1, 4-8 (1995)
  • 629
    • 55549118277 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The role of deterrence in the formulation of criminal law rules: At its worst when doing its best, 91
    • Present purposes do not require taking a position in this debate
    • Paul Robinson & John Darley, The Role of Deterrence in the Formulation of Criminal Law Rules: At Its Worst When Doing Its Best, 91 GEO. L.J. 949, 951-53 (2003). Present purposes do not require taking a position in this debate.
    • (2003) GEO. L.J. , vol.949 , pp. 951-953
    • Robinson, P.1    Darley, J.2
  • 630
    • 79952800287 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For an extensive discussion of these timing issues
    • For an extensive discussion of these timing issues
  • 631
    • 79952780702 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see Markel & Flanders, supra note 1, and Bronsteen et al., supra note 3. Kolber argues that we should nevertheless factor in the subjective differences among defenders because offenders sensitive to imprisonment will be more sensitive to threats of imprisonment while offenders less sensitive to imprisonment will be less sensitive to threats of imprisonment
    • see Markel & Flanders, supra note 1, and Bronsteen et al., supra note 3. Kolber argues that we should nevertheless factor in the subjective differences among defenders because offenders sensitive to imprisonment will be more sensitive to threats of imprisonment while offenders less sensitive to imprisonment will be less sensitive to threats of imprisonment.
  • 632
    • 79952811194 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 217. This is a dubious claim, particularly in light of studies cited by Bronsteen, Buccafusco, and Masur
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 217. This is a dubious claim, particularly in light of studies cited by Bronsteen, Buccafusco, and Masur
  • 633
    • 79952791936 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 1, at 1041-45, suggesting that most of us are quite bad at forecasting our actual sensitivities to stimuli
    • supra note 1, at 1041-45, suggesting that most of us are quite bad at forecasting our actual sensitivities to stimuli.
  • 634
    • 79952807512 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See also Kolber, supra note 1 at 211 & n.79, 217 (conceding that individuals may not be good predictors of their future responses to punishment). Setting those issues aside, this response is, strictly speaking, a non sequitur, both because it addresses specific rather than general deterrence and because it fails to respect the important line between ex post and ex ante that is central to deterrence policy and analysis
    • See also Kolber, supra note 1 at 211 & n.79, 217 (conceding that individuals may not be good predictors of their future responses to punishment). Setting those issues aside, this response is, strictly speaking, a non sequitur, both because it addresses specific rather than general deterrence and because it fails to respect the important line between ex post and ex ante that is central to deterrence policy and analysis.
  • 635
    • 79952795518 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It is worth pointing out that the most effective contributors to these perceptions are likely not the actual, real-time, subjective experiences of prisoners, but a constellation of actual and purported reports of those experiences. Television shows, movies, media reports, etc., are probably far more influential contributors to the general deterrence effects of punishment than the actual experiences of real offenders
    • It is worth pointing out that the most effective contributors to these perceptions are likely not the actual, real-time, subjective experiences of prisoners, but a constellation of actual and purported reports of those experiences. Television shows, movies, media reports, etc., are probably far more influential contributors to the general deterrence effects of punishment than the actual experiences of real offenders.
  • 636
    • 79952780701 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1060
    • Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1060.
  • 637
    • 79952793593 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 24
    • Id. at 24
  • 638
    • 79952776772 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 216-18, 218 n.101
    • Kolber, supra note 1, at 216-18, 218 n.101.
  • 639
    • 79952809931 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • HART, supra note 120, at 19
    • HART, supra note 120, at 19.
  • 640
    • 79952807711 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 641
    • 79952803099 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1058-62
    • Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1058-62.
  • 642
    • 79952781099 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1044
    • Id. at 1044.
  • 643
    • 79952795152 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dan Markel and Chad Flanders make this point powerfully in Bentham on Stilts
    • Dan Markel and Chad Flanders make this point powerfully in Bentham on Stilts
  • 644
    • 79952778777 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 1
    • supra note 1.
  • 645
    • 79952798011 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See also, RAWLS, supra note 205, at 9
    • See also, RAWLS, supra note 205, at 9.
  • 646
    • 79952791750 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ("[I[f some kind of very cruel crime becomes common, and none of the criminals can be caught, it might be highly expedient, as an example, to hang an innocent man, if a charge against him could be so framed that he were universally thought guilty; indeed this would only fail to be an ideal instance of utilitarian 'punishment' because the victim himself would not have been so likely as a real felon to commit such a crime in the future; in all other respects it would be perfectly deterrent and therefore felicific") (internal citation omitted)
    • ("[I[f some kind of very cruel crime becomes common, and none of the criminals can be caught, it might be highly expedient, as an example, to hang an innocent man, if a charge against him could be so framed that he were universally thought guilty; indeed this would only fail to be an ideal instance of utilitarian 'punishment' because the victim himself would not have been so likely as a real felon to commit such a crime in the future; in all other respects it would be perfectly deterrent and therefore felicific") (internal citation omitted).
  • 647
    • 79952787131 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra Parts I, III.C.3
    • See supra Parts I, III.C.3.
  • 648
    • 79952787711 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1046-49
    • Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1046-49.
  • 649
    • 79952811391 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1058-61
    • Id. at 1058-61.
  • 650
    • 79952791246 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MILL, supra note 56, at 7
    • MILL, supra note 56, at 7.
  • 651
    • 79952801958 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 8
    • Id. at 8.
  • 652
    • 79952779129 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 10
    • Id. at 10.
  • 653
    • 79952783469 scopus 로고
    • (John Bryant ed., Penguin Books 1996)
    • But see HERMAN MELVILLE, TYPEE: A PEEP AT POLYNESIAN LIFE 178-83 (John Bryant ed., Penguin Books 1996) (1846).
    • (1846) Typee: A Peep at Polynesian Life , pp. 178-183
    • Melville, H.1
  • 654
    • 79952803701 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., KRAUT, supra note 31
    • See, e.g., KRAUT, supra note 31
  • 655
    • 70449118614 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Harvard Univ. Press 2009)
    • AMARTYA Sen, THE IDEA OF JUSTICE 225-317 (Harvard Univ. Press 2009)
    • The Idea of Justice , pp. 225-317
    • Sen, A.1
  • 656
    • 79952796666 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nussbaum, Capabilities, supra note 31
    • Nussbaum, Capabilities, supra note 31
  • 657
    • 79952804308 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nussbaum, supra note 30
    • Nussbaum, supra note 30.
  • 658
    • 79952813806 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Nussbaum, Capabilities, supra note 31
    • See, e.g., Nussbaum, Capabilities, supra note 31.
  • 659
    • 79952784834 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See NUSSBAUM, FRONTIERS supra note 31
    • See NUSSBAUM, FRONTIERS supra note 31.
  • 660
    • 79952812587 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • KRAUT, supra note 31, at 131
    • KRAUT, supra note 31, at 131.
  • 661
    • 79952802713 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., MILL, supra note 56, at 8-10 (discussing an example of a criticism)
    • See, e.g., MILL, supra note 56, at 8-10 (discussing an example of a criticism).
  • 662
    • 79952789841 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • E.g., Nussbaum, supra note 30, at 99-103
    • E.g., Nussbaum, supra note 30, at 99-103.
  • 663
    • 79952784835 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Academics, for example
    • Academics, for example.
  • 664
    • 79952803313 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., THE STATLER BROTHERS, Flowers on the Wall, on FLOWERS ON THE WALL (Columbia Records 1965) ("Countin' flowers on the wall/That don't bother me at all/Playin' solitaire till dawn with a deck of fifty-one/Smokin' cigarettes and watchin' Captain Kangaroo/Now don't tell me I've nothin' to do.")
    • See, e.g., THE STATLER BROTHERS, Flowers on the Wall, on FLOWERS ON THE WALL (Columbia Records 1965) ("Countin' flowers on the wall/That don't bother me at all/Playin' solitaire till dawn with a deck of fifty-one/Smokin' cigarettes and watchin' Captain Kangaroo/Now don't tell me I've nothin' to do.").
  • 665
    • 79952776023 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nussbaum, supra note 30, at 86-88
    • Nussbaum, supra note 30, at 86-88.
  • 666
    • 79952805635 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The literature is rife with more profound questions ranging from Robert Nozick's ethical turn on brain-in-a-vat problems to challenges posed by cultural relativists, which are topics for late-night dorm conversations at universities and colleges the world over. It is beyond the scope of this Article to take up those discussions, but the fact that they can be had comes close to proving that the point apparently is lost on Bronsteen, Buccafusco, and Masur, who attempt to draw normative conclusions from the literature on hedonic adaptation
    • The literature is rife with more profound questions ranging from Robert Nozick's ethical turn on brain-in-a-vat problems to challenges posed by cultural relativists, which are topics for late-night dorm conversations at universities and colleges the world over. It is beyond the scope of this Article to take up those discussions, but the fact that they can be had comes close to proving that the point apparently is lost on Bronsteen, Buccafusco, and Masur, who attempt to draw normative conclusions from the literature on hedonic adaptation.
  • 667
    • 79952788875 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1049-55
    • Bronsteen et al., supra note 1, at 1049-55.
  • 668
    • 79952783247 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 669
    • 79952787315 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 102
    • See supra note 102.
  • 670
    • 79952782430 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Fuller, supra note 324, at 643
    • Fuller, supra note 324, at 643.
  • 671
    • 79952798545 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sentencing Memorandum at 14-15, Simon v. United States, No. CR-90-216 (E.D.N.Y. March 17, 2005), available at
    • Sentencing Memorandum at 14-15, Simon v. United States, No. CR-90-216 (E.D.N.Y. March 17, 2005), available at http://www.nyed.uscourts.gov/pub/ rulings/cr/2005/90cr216sm31705.pdf.
  • 672
    • 79952788112 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • KANT, supra note 14, at 107-08
    • KANT, supra note 14, at 107-08.
  • 673
    • 79952807118 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Cooey v. Strickland, 589 F.3d 210, 215 (6th Cir. 2009)
    • See, e.g., Cooey v. Strickland, 589 F.3d 210, 215 (6th Cir. 2009)
  • 674
    • 79952784235 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Emmett v. Johnson, 532 F.3d 291, 292-93 (4th Cir. 2008)
    • Emmett v. Johnson, 532 F.3d 291, 292-93 (4th Cir. 2008)
  • 675
    • 79952789286 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hamilton v. Jones, 472 F.3d 814, 816-17 (10th Cir. 2007)
    • Hamilton v. Jones, 472 F.3d 814, 816-17 (10th Cir. 2007).
  • 676
    • 79952799165 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 274
    • See supra note 274.
  • 677
    • 79952792985 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Gray & Huber, supra note 18 (arguing on retributivist grounds for progressive changes to American criminal law and punishment policy)
    • See Gray & Huber, supra note 18 (arguing on retributivist grounds for progressive changes to American criminal law and punishment policy).
  • 678
    • 79952785909 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • KANT, supra note 14, at 105
    • KANT, supra note 14, at 105.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.