메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 157, Issue 5, 2009, Pages 1383-1484

How should punitive damages work?

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 62549088089     PISSN: 00419907     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: None     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (22)

References (490)
  • 1
    • 60349087960 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Dan Markel, Retributive Damages: A Theory of Punitive Damages as Intermediate Sanction, 94 CORNELL L. REV. 239 (2009) [hereinafter Markel, Retributive Damages].
    • See Dan Markel, Retributive Damages: A Theory of Punitive Damages as Intermediate Sanction, 94 CORNELL L. REV. 239 (2009) [hereinafter Markel, Retributive Damages].
  • 2
    • 67249122825 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 549 U.S. 346 (2007). In Philip Morris, die Court held diat the Due Process Clause forbids juries from figuring in the harms to nonparties in determining die amount of punitive damages that a defendant must pay. The Court also addressed punitive damages more recendy in Exxon Shipping Co. v. Baker, 128 S. Ct. 2605 (2008). Because the Exxon case was resolved under federal maritime law, however, its significance for this project is not nearly as substantial as the Court's constitutional decision in Philip Morris.
    • 549 U.S. 346 (2007). In Philip Morris, die Court held diat the Due Process Clause forbids juries from figuring in the harms to nonparties in determining die amount of punitive damages that a defendant must pay. The Court also addressed punitive damages more recendy in Exxon Shipping Co. v. Baker, 128 S. Ct. 2605 (2008). Because the Exxon case was resolved under federal maritime law, however, its significance for this project is not nearly as substantial as the Court's constitutional decision in Philip Morris.
  • 3
    • 67249163004 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Marc Galanter & David Luban, Poetic Justice: Punitive Damages and Inegal Pluralism, 42 AM. U. L. REV. 1393, 1451 (1993) (Efficiency plays no role in the normative universe of punitive damages as we conceive of it.).
    • Cf. Marc Galanter & David Luban, Poetic Justice: Punitive Damages and Inegal Pluralism, 42 AM. U. L. REV. 1393, 1451 (1993) ("Efficiency plays no role in the normative universe of punitive damages as we conceive of it.").
  • 4
    • 67249090158 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I use the terms deterrence damages and aggravated damages in ways that might seem idiosyncratic to some readers. Deterrence damages signify those damages meant to facilitate optimal deterrence or cost internalization, not complete deterrence. Aggravated damages are meant to account for, and thereby vindicate, that part of a victim's injury, not already compensated in all jurisdictions, for insults to one's personal dignity. See infra Part II.
    • I use the terms "deterrence damages" and "aggravated damages" in ways that might seem idiosyncratic to some readers. Deterrence damages signify those damages meant to facilitate optimal deterrence or "cost internalization," not "complete deterrence." Aggravated damages are meant to account for, and thereby vindicate, that part of a victim's injury, not already compensated in all jurisdictions, for insults to one's personal dignity. See infra Part II.
  • 5
    • 67249128930 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Ciraolo v. City of N.Y., 216 F.3d 236, 244-47 (2d Cir. 2000) (Calabresi, J., concurring) (advocating nonpunitive extracompensatory damages for the sake of cost internalization);
    • See, e.g., Ciraolo v. City of N.Y., 216 F.3d 236, 244-47 (2d Cir. 2000) (Calabresi, J., concurring) (advocating nonpunitive extracompensatory damages for the sake of cost internalization);
  • 6
    • 67249124271 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bruce Chapman & Michael Trebilcock, Punitive Damages: Divergence in Search of a Rationale, 40 ALA. L. REV. 741, 805-26 (1989) (discussing cost internalization and aggravated damages for compensation of dignity harms);
    • Bruce Chapman & Michael Trebilcock, Punitive Damages: Divergence in Search of a Rationale, 40 ALA. L. REV. 741, 805-26 (1989) (discussing cost internalization and aggravated damages for compensation of dignity harms);
  • 7
    • 67249142328 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Thomas C. Galligan, Jr., Augmented Awards: The Efficient Evolution of Punitive Damages, 51 LA. L. REV. 3, 12-13 (1990) (describing cost internalization damages);
    • Thomas C. Galligan, Jr., Augmented Awards: The Efficient Evolution of Punitive Damages, 51 LA. L. REV. 3, 12-13 (1990) (describing cost internalization damages);
  • 8
    • 33745723793 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Punitive Damages: An Economic Analysis, 111
    • developing a set of principles for determining cost internalization damages
    • A. Mitchell Polinsky & Steven Shavell, Punitive Damages: An Economic Analysis, 111 HARV. L. REV. 869, 873-76 (1998) (developing a set of principles for determining cost internalization damages);
    • (1998) HARV. L. REV , vol.869 , pp. 873-876
    • Mitchell Polinsky, A.1    Shavell, S.2
  • 9
    • 22744447898 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Catherine M. Sharkey, Punitive Damages as Societal Damages, 113 YALE LJ. 347, 401-02 (2003) (discussing how a compensatory societal damages framework improves upon limitations of Polinsky and Shavell's method for ensuring cost internalization) ;
    • Catherine M. Sharkey, Punitive Damages as Societal Damages, 113 YALE LJ. 347, 401-02 (2003) (discussing how a "compensatory societal damages" framework improves upon limitations of Polinsky and Shavell's method for ensuring cost internalization) ;
  • 10
    • 41549139560 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Punitive Damages, Retribution, and Due Process, 81
    • conceiving the role of punitive damages primarily in terms of individual victim vindication and proposing methods to ensure that such vindication satisfies due process
    • Mark A. Geistfeld, Punitive Damages, Retribution, and Due Process, 81 S. CAL. L. REV. 263, 269-74, 296-309 (2008) (conceiving the role of punitive damages primarily in terms of individual victim vindication and proposing methods to ensure that such vindication satisfies due process);
    • (2008) S. CAL. L. REV , vol.263 , Issue.269-274 , pp. 296-309
    • Geistfeld, M.A.1
  • 11
    • 34250201063 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Punitive Damages: From Myth to Theory, 92
    • arguing that punitive damages should be regarded as a form of statesanctioned revenge
    • AndionyJ. Sebok, Punitive Damages: From Myth to Theory, 92 IOWA L. REV. 957, 961, 1023-29 (2007) (arguing that punitive damages should be regarded as "a form of statesanctioned revenge");
    • (2007) IOWA L. REV , vol.957 , Issue.961 , pp. 1023-1029
  • 12
    • 29744470058 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A Theory of Punitive Damages, 84
    • offering a conceptual and interpretive account of punitive damages as victim vindication
    • Benjamin C. Zipursky, A Theory of Punitive Damages, 84 TEX. L. REV. 105 (2005) (offering a conceptual and interpretive account of punitive damages as victim vindication).
    • (2005) TEX. L. REV , vol.105
    • Zipursky, B.C.1
  • 13
    • 62549151751 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • More recendy, Tom Colby has joined the group defending a victim vindication interpretation. See Thomas B. Colby, Clearing the Smoke from Philip Morris v. Williams: The Past, Present, and Future of Punitive Damages, 118 YALE LJ. 392, 434 (2008) (Punitive damages vindicate the dignity of an individual victim by allowing her to punish the defendant for committing a humiliating or insulting tort upon her.).
    • More recendy, Tom Colby has joined the group defending a victim vindication interpretation. See Thomas B. Colby, Clearing the Smoke from Philip Morris v. Williams: The Past, Present, and Future of Punitive Damages, 118 YALE LJ. 392, 434 (2008) ("Punitive damages vindicate the dignity of an individual victim by allowing her to punish the defendant for committing a humiliating or insulting tort upon her.").
  • 14
    • 0347574001 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Cass R. Sunstein et al., Assessing Punitive Damages (with Notes on Cognition and Valuation inlaw), 107 YALE LJ. 2071, 2085 (1998) (Regrettably, the legal culture lacks a full normative account of the relationship between retributive goals and punitive damages.).
    • See Cass R. Sunstein et al., Assessing Punitive Damages (with Notes on Cognition and Valuation inlaw), 107 YALE LJ. 2071, 2085 (1998) ("Regrettably, the legal culture lacks a full normative account of the relationship between retributive goals and punitive damages.").
  • 15
    • 67249164623 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • My goal in Retributive Damages, supa note 1, was primarily to address that lacuna.
    • My goal in Retributive Damages, supa note 1, was primarily to address that lacuna.
  • 16
    • 0037291734 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Thomas B. Colby, Beyond the Multiple Punishment Problem: Punitive Damages as Punishment for Individual, Private Wrongs, 87 MLNN. L. REV. 583, 643-50 (2003) (arguing that punitive damages for public purposes and without procedural safeguards would be indistinguishable from criminal punishment) ;
    • See, e.g., Thomas B. Colby, Beyond the Multiple Punishment Problem: Punitive Damages as Punishment for Individual, Private Wrongs, 87 MLNN. L. REV. 583, 643-50 (2003) (arguing that punitive damages for public purposes and without procedural safeguards would be "indistinguishable from criminal punishment") ;
  • 17
    • 67249107284 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Jeffrey W. Grass, The Penal Dimensions of Punitive Damages, 12 HASTINGS CONST. L. Q 241, 242 (1985) (By punishing defendants radier than compensating plaintiffs [the] purpose [of punitive damages] falls squarely under die ambit of criminal law. (footnote omitted))
    • Jeffrey W. Grass, The Penal Dimensions of Punitive Damages, 12 HASTINGS CONST. L. Q 241, 242 (1985) ("By punishing defendants radier than compensating plaintiffs [the] purpose [of punitive damages] falls squarely under die ambit of criminal law." (footnote omitted))
  • 18
    • 0042973001 scopus 로고
    • A Comment on the Constitutionality of Punitive Damages, 72
    • noting die lack of procedural safeguards in awarding punitive damages
    • ¡John Calvin Jeffries, Jr., A Comment on the Constitutionality of Punitive Damages, 72 VA. L. REV. 139, 139 (1986) (noting die lack of procedural safeguards in awarding punitive damages);
    • (1986) VA. L. REV , vol.139 , pp. 139
    • Jeffries Jr., J.C.1
  • 19
    • 67249131721 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Malcolm E. Wheeler, The Constitutional Case for Reforming Punitive Damages Procedures, 69 VA. L. REV. 269, 270 & n.5 (1983) (citing sources that discuss the application of criminal procedural safeguards to defendants facing the imposition of punitive damages).
    • Malcolm E. Wheeler, The Constitutional Case for Reforming Punitive Damages Procedures, 69 VA. L. REV. 269, 270 & n.5 (1983) (citing sources that discuss the application of criminal procedural safeguards to defendants facing the imposition of punitive damages).
  • 20
    • 67249097633 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See infra Section III.A.
    • See infra Section III.A.
  • 21
    • 67249111489 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dan Markel, Punitive Damages and Complex Litigation (unpublished manuscript, on file with author) [hereinafter Markel, Punitive Damages]; see also Dan Markel & Gregg Polsky, Taxing Punitive Damages (unpublished manuscript, on file with author) (addressing proper taxation policies associated with this proposed punitive damages scheme and other related tax issues).
    • Dan Markel, Punitive Damages and Complex Litigation (unpublished manuscript, on file with author) [hereinafter Markel, Punitive Damages]; see also Dan Markel & Gregg Polsky, Taxing Punitive Damages (unpublished manuscript, on file with author) (addressing proper taxation policies associated with this proposed punitive damages scheme and other related tax issues).
  • 22
    • 67249149082 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Pac. Mut. Life Ins. Co. v. Haslip, 499 U.S. 1, 25-28 (1991) (Scalia, J., concurring in the judgment) (furnishing a brief history of punitive damages).
    • See Pac. Mut. Life Ins. Co. v. Haslip, 499 U.S. 1, 25-28 (1991) (Scalia, J., concurring in the judgment) (furnishing a brief history of punitive damages).
  • 23
    • 67249129992 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This Section draws upon the discussion in Part I of Markel, Retributive Damages, supa note 1. Readers familiar with that work may skim or skip this Section
    • This Section draws upon the discussion in Part I of Markel, Retributive Damages, supa note 1. Readers familiar with that work may skim or skip this Section.
  • 24
    • 67249150710 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Those seeking a more comprehensive introduction to the topic might also consider looking at Anthony J. Sebok, Punitive Damages in the United States, in PUNITIVE DAMAGES (Helmut Koziol & Vanessa Wilcox eds., forthcoming 2009).
    • Those seeking a more comprehensive introduction to the topic might also consider looking at Anthony J. Sebok, Punitive Damages in the United States, in PUNITIVE DAMAGES (Helmut Koziol & Vanessa Wilcox eds., forthcoming 2009).
  • 25
    • 60349093664 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Why Punitive Damages Are Unconstitutional, 53
    • discussing early English cases in which the plaintiff demonstrated a dignitary harm that would therwise remain uncompensated in the absence of exemplary damages, See
    • See Martin H. Redish & Andrew L. Mathews, Why Punitive Damages Are Unconstitutional, 53 EMORY L.J. 1, 13-16 (2004) (discussing early English cases in which the plaintiff demonstrated a dignitary harm that would therwise remain uncompensated in the absence of exemplary damages).
    • (2004) EMORY L.J , vol.1 , pp. 13-16
    • Redish, M.H.1    Mathews, A.L.2
  • 26
    • 60349118659 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Baker, 128
    • providing examples of the application of this punitive damages function, See Exxon Shipping Co. v
    • See Exxon Shipping Co. v. Baker, 128 S. Ct. 2605, 2620 (2008) (providing examples of the application of this punitive damages function).
    • (2008) S. Ct , vol.2605 , pp. 2620
  • 27
    • 67249152076 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cooper Indus., Inc. v. Leatherman Tool Group, Inc., 532 U.S. 424, 438 n.ll (2001).
    • Cooper Indus., Inc. v. Leatherman Tool Group, Inc., 532 U.S. 424, 438 n.ll (2001).
  • 28
    • 67249113639 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Andiony J. Sebok, What Did Punitive Damages Do? Why Misunderstanding the History of Punitive Damages Matters Today, 78 CHI.-KENTL. REV. 163, 205 (2003) (If punitive damages served a compensatory function [in early cases], it would have been for a category of injury that is still not considered compensable by contemporary tort law, n amely the injury of insult that wounds or dishonors.).
    • See Andiony J. Sebok, What Did Punitive Damages Do? Why Misunderstanding the History of Punitive Damages Matters Today, 78 CHI.-KENTL. REV. 163, 205 (2003) ("If punitive damages served a compensatory function [in early cases], it would have been for a category of injury that is still not considered compensable by contemporary tort law, n amely the injury of insult that wounds or dishonors.").
  • 29
    • 67249096320 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Cooper Indus., 532 U.S. at 432; Gertz v. Robert Welch, Inc., 418 U.S. 323, 350 (1974) (describing punitive damages as private fines designed to punish and deter reprehensible conduct). Nevertheless, if a state passed an enabling statute authorizing punitive damages expressly for the purposes of compensating a plaintiff or society, the Supreme Court would probably not say that such purposes are inherendy improper or unconstitutional.
    • See, e.g., Cooper Indus., 532 U.S. at 432; Gertz v. Robert Welch, Inc., 418 U.S. 323, 350 (1974) (describing punitive damages as "private fines" designed to punish and deter "reprehensible conduct"). Nevertheless, if a state passed an enabling statute authorizing punitive damages expressly for the purposes of compensating a plaintiff or society, the Supreme Court would probably not say that such purposes are inherendy improper or unconstitutional.
  • 30
    • 67249126015 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Sharkey, supra note 5, at 391-92 (elaborating a proposal for compensatory societal damages).
    • Cf. Sharkey, supra note 5, at 391-92 (elaborating a proposal for compensatory societal damages).
  • 31
    • 67249112346 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Exxon Shipping Co., 128 S. Ct. at 2621 (2008) ([T]he consensus today is that punitives are aimed not at compensation but principally at retribution and deterring harmful conduct.);
    • See, e.g., Exxon Shipping Co., 128 S. Ct. at 2621 (2008) ("[T]he consensus today is that punitives are aimed not at compensation but principally at retribution and deterring harmful conduct.");
  • 32
    • 67249156394 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Philip Morris USA v. Williams, 549 U.S. 346, 352 (2007) This Court has long made clear that '[p]unitive damages may properly be imposed to further a State's legitimate interests in punishing unlawful conduct and deterring its repetition.'
    • Philip Morris USA v. Williams, 549 U.S. 346, 352 (2007) ("This Court has long made clear that '[p]unitive damages may properly be imposed to further a State's legitimate interests in punishing unlawful conduct and deterring its repetition.'"
  • 33
    • 67249084460 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (alteration in original) (quoting BMW of N. Am., Inc. v. Gore, 517 U.S. 559, 568(1996))).
    • (alteration in original) (quoting BMW of N. Am., Inc. v. Gore, 517 U.S. 559, 568(1996))).
  • 34
    • 67249147437 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For those unfamiliar with these terms, under an optimal deterrence or cost internalization regime, a defendant who pays the costs of her tortious activity should be able to continue pursuing that activity. The decision to seek cost internalization for an activity is predicated on a determination that the gains to the defendant are socially licit. The basis for concerns about cost internalization is further described by Judge Calabresi in Ciraolo v. City of New York. See infra note 68.
    • For those unfamiliar with these terms, under an optimal deterrence or cost internalization regime, a defendant who pays the costs of her tortious activity should be able to continue pursuing that activity. The decision to seek cost internalization for an activity is predicated on a determination that the gains to the defendant are socially licit. The basis for concerns about cost internalization is further described by Judge Calabresi in Ciraolo v. City of New York. See infra note 68.
  • 35
    • 0347031888 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • By contrast, complete deterrence endeavors to remove the incentive for the defendant to undertake diat conduct altogether because the gains from such conduct are deemed illicit. See Keith N. HyIton, Punitive Damages and the Economic Theory of Penalties, 87 GEO. LJ. 421, 421 (1998). Complete deterrence is a goal that, if realized, would entail that zero instances of the particular misconduct would occur. Others have used different terms to distinguish between optimal and complete deterrence.
    • By contrast, complete deterrence endeavors to remove the incentive for the defendant to undertake diat conduct altogether because the gains from such conduct are deemed illicit. See Keith N. HyIton, Punitive Damages and the Economic Theory of Penalties, 87 GEO. LJ. 421, 421 (1998). Complete deterrence is a goal that, if realized, would entail that zero instances of the particular misconduct would occur. Others have used different terms to distinguish between optimal and complete deterrence.
  • 36
    • 67249099111 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., GUIDO CALABRESI, THE COSTS OF ACCIDENTS: A LEGAL AND ECONOMIC ANALYSIS 68-69 (1970) (distinguishing between general (permissive) deterrence and specific (prohibitory) deterrence);
    • See, e.g., GUIDO CALABRESI, THE COSTS OF ACCIDENTS: A LEGAL AND ECONOMIC ANALYSIS 68-69 (1970) (distinguishing between general (permissive) deterrence and specific (prohibitory) deterrence);
  • 37
    • 84881824864 scopus 로고
    • Prices and Sanctions, 84
    • distinguishing between the pricing and sanctioning of different types of behavior, Lasdy, it is worth noting that complete deterrence, which calls for a sentence designed to signal that the conduct is prohibited, should not be confused with complete enforcement, which would call for sufficient resources to reduce the misconduct to zero
    • Robert Cooter, Prices and Sanctions, 84 COLUM. L. REV. 1523, 1524-31 (1984) (distinguishing between the "pricing" and "sanctioning" of different types of behavior). Lasdy, it is worth noting that complete deterrence, which calls for a sentence designed to signal that the conduct is prohibited, should not be confused with complete enforcement, which would call for sufficient resources to reduce the misconduct to zero.
    • (1984) COLUM. L. REV , vol.1523 , pp. 1524-1531
    • Cooter, R.1
  • 38
    • 67249109259 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See State Farm Mut. Auto. Ins. Co. v. Campbell, 538 U.S. 408, 419 (2003) (restating the rule that punitive damages only be awarded where a defendant's conduct is so reprehensible that it justified an award in addition to compensatory damages). The Court has further specified a number of factors that contribute to a determination of reprehensibility.
    • See State Farm Mut. Auto. Ins. Co. v. Campbell, 538 U.S. 408, 419 (2003) (restating the rule that punitive damages only be awarded where a defendant's conduct is so reprehensible that it justified an award in addition to compensatory damages). The Court has further specified a number of factors that contribute to a determination of reprehensibility.
  • 39
    • 67249157228 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See BMW of N. Am., Inc. v. Gore, 517 U.S. 559, 575-77 (1996) (listing factors that indicate a greater degree of reprehensibility).
    • See BMW of N. Am., Inc. v. Gore, 517 U.S. 559, 575-77 (1996) (listing factors that indicate a greater degree of reprehensibility).
  • 40
    • 67249152493 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • S. at
    • State Farm, 538 U.S. at 418.
    • State Farm , vol.538 , Issue.U , pp. 418
  • 41
    • 67249137984 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 425
    • Id. at 425.
  • 42
    • 67249092599 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 428
    • Id. at 428
  • 43
    • 67249123834 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (quoting Gore, 517 U.S. at 575).
    • (quoting Gore, 517 U.S. at 575).
  • 45
    • 67249157229 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • S. at
    • State Farm, 538 U.S. at 421.
    • State Farm , vol.538 , Issue.U , pp. 421
  • 47
    • 67249133712 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cooper Indus., Inc. v. Leatherman Tool Group, Inc., 532 U.S. 424, 435-36 (2001).
    • Cooper Indus., Inc. v. Leatherman Tool Group, Inc., 532 U.S. 424, 435-36 (2001).
  • 48
    • 67249119631 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See State Farm, 538 U.S. at 416-17.
    • See State Farm, 538 U.S. at 416-17.
  • 50
    • 67249157647 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Michael L. Rustad, The Closing of Punitive Damages' Iron Cage, 38 LOY. L.A. L. REV. 1297 app. A (2005) (surveying punitive damages practices across states and the District of Columbia).
    • See Michael L. Rustad, The Closing of Punitive Damages' Iron Cage, 38 LOY. L.A. L. REV. 1297 app. A (2005) (surveying punitive damages practices across states and the District of Columbia).
  • 51
    • 67249111488 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note 1, at, nn.4-9 citing different approaches taken by scholars in considering extracompensatory damages
    • See Markel, Retributive Damages, supra note 1, at 242-43 nn.4-9 (citing different approaches taken by scholars in considering extracompensatory damages).
    • See Markel, Retributive Damages, supra , pp. 242-243
  • 52
    • 67249120697 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Polinsky & Shavell, supra note 5, at 897-98 (arguing that courts should use damages determinations to facilitate optimal deterrence by applying the punitive damages multiplier developed by the audiors). I recognize that by conflating deterrence with optimal deterrence (or cost internalization), I am implicidy obscuring the work of some economists who view this law through the prism of complete deterrence.
    • See Polinsky & Shavell, supra note 5, at 897-98 (arguing that courts should use damages determinations to facilitate optimal deterrence by applying the "punitive damages multiplier" developed by the audiors). I recognize that by conflating deterrence with optimal deterrence (or cost internalization), I am implicidy obscuring the work of some economists who view this law through the prism of complete deterrence.
  • 53
    • 67249103431 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g, Hylton, supra note 18, at 423 arguing diat the optimal deterrence model should be used in limited cases and that complete deterrence should be the goal in most situations
    • See, e.g., Hylton, supra note 18, at 423 (arguing diat the optimal deterrence model should be used in limited cases and that complete deterrence should be the goal in most situations).
  • 54
    • 84888467546 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note 58 for a partial explanation of the reasons for this move
    • See infra note 58 for a partial explanation of the reasons for this move.
    • See infra
  • 55
    • 67249092303 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Polinsky & Shavell, supa note 5, at 887-96 ([I] fa defendant can sometimes escape liability for the harm for which he is responsible, the proper magnitude of damages is the harm the defendant has caused, multiplied by a factor reflecting the probability of his escaping liability. (emphasis omitted)).
    • See Polinsky & Shavell, supa note 5, at 887-96 ("[I] fa defendant can sometimes escape liability for the harm for which he is responsible, the proper magnitude of damages is the harm the defendant has caused, multiplied by a factor reflecting the probability of his escaping liability." (emphasis omitted)).
  • 56
    • 25144505223 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • But see Keith N. Hylton & Thomas J. Miceli, Should Tort Damages Be Multiplied?, 21 J.L. ECON. & ORG. 388 (2005) (registering skepticism toward the use of the multiplier approach in the context of civil damages based on concerns regarding the supply of lawsuits and the cost of litigation). Professor Sharkey's proposal for compensatory societal damages was designed to address perceived shortcomings with the Polinsky-Shavell model for achieving cost internalization.
    • But see Keith N. Hylton & Thomas J. Miceli, Should Tort Damages Be Multiplied?, 21 J.L. ECON. & ORG. 388 (2005) (registering skepticism toward the use of the multiplier approach in the context of civil damages based on concerns regarding the supply of lawsuits and the cost of litigation). Professor Sharkey's proposal for compensatory societal damages was designed to address perceived shortcomings with the Polinsky-Shavell model for achieving cost internalization.
  • 57
    • 67249114054 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Sharkey, supra note 5, at 368-70 (identifying problems with the use of a strict punitive damages multiplier, such as the failure to include cases involving diffuse harms). The suggestions for compensating society for defendants' more diffuse harms to society, however, are not likely to survive Philip Morris for reasons similar to the argument that I make about Professor Colby's claims in Part II. That is, notwithstanding the avowedly nonpunitive rationale behind compensatory societal damages, my sense is diat the Supreme Court is unlikely to diink that such an approach satisfies due process because it allows an award of damages for harms against persons or entities that a defendant cannot litigate against specifically.
    • See Sharkey, supra note 5, at 368-70 (identifying problems with the use of a strict punitive damages multiplier, such as the failure to include cases involving "diffuse" harms). The suggestions for compensating society for defendants' more diffuse harms to society, however, are not likely to survive Philip Morris for reasons similar to the argument that I make about Professor Colby's claims in Part II. That is, notwithstanding the avowedly nonpunitive rationale behind compensatory societal damages, my sense is diat the Supreme Court is unlikely to diink that such an approach satisfies due process because it allows an award of damages for harms against persons or entities that a defendant cannot litigate against specifically.
  • 58
    • 62549084958 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Do Punitive Damages Compensate Society?, 41
    • raising concerns that Sharkey's proposal will founder on due process grounds, See
    • See Michael B. Kelly, Do Punitive Damages Compensate Society?, 41 SAN DIEGO L. REV. 1429, 1433-35 (2004) (raising concerns that Sharkey's proposal will founder on due process grounds).
    • (2004) SAN DIEGO L. REV , vol.1429 , pp. 1433-1435
    • Kelly, M.B.1
  • 59
    • 67249115820 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Sharkey, supra note 5, at 372 n.7l (collecting cases in which courts have expressed their approval of the multiplier approach).
    • See Sharkey, supra note 5, at 372 n.7l (collecting cases in which courts have expressed their approval of the multiplier approach).
  • 60
    • 67249119164 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 390-91;
    • See id. at 390-91;
  • 61
    • 67249141175 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also infra note 91.
    • see also infra note 91.
  • 62
    • 67249155921 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g, Colby, supra note 5, at 434;
    • See, e.g., Colby, supra note 5, at 434;
  • 63
    • 84972000304 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note 3, at, discussing the view that culpably wronging a person expresses that the victim is of less value than the wrongdoer
    • Galanter & Luban, supra note 3, at 1432 (discussing the view that culpably wronging a person expresses that the victim is of less value than the wrongdoer);
    • supra , pp. 1432
    • Galanter1    Luban2
  • 64
    • 67249115387 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Geistfeld, supa note 5, at 269-74 (advancing the idea of punitive damages primarily in terms of the private interest in victim vindication of tort rights);
    • Geistfeld, supa note 5, at 269-74 (advancing the idea of punitive damages primarily in terms of the private interest in victim vindication of "tort rights");
  • 65
    • 13544249890 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • John CP. Goldberg, Tori Law for Federalists (and the Rest of Us): Private Law in Disguise, 28 HARV. J.L. & PUB. POL'Y 3, 7 (2004) (What is at stake in [punitive damages] is not [a state's] interests in obtaining retribution on behalf of its citizens or in deterring sharp business practices, but the [plaintiffs'] interest in vindicating their rights not to be mistreated in the way that they were.. .. [These rights include] providing [the plaintiffs] with satisfaction-a remedy adequate to acknowledge and avenge [the defendant's] predatory conduct towards them.);
    • John CP. Goldberg, Tori Law for Federalists (and the Rest of Us): Private Law in Disguise, 28 HARV. J.L. & PUB. POL'Y 3, 7 (2004) ("What is at stake in [punitive damages] is not [a state's] interests in obtaining retribution on behalf of its citizens or in deterring sharp business practices, but the [plaintiffs'] interest in vindicating their rights not to be mistreated in the way that they were.. .. [These rights include] providing [the plaintiffs] with satisfaction-a remedy adequate to acknowledge and avenge [the defendant's] predatory conduct towards them.");
  • 66
    • 67249085773 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sebok, supa note 5, at 1007-15 ([T] he private right whose violation grounds [a punitive damages] award is the private right not to have one's dignity violated.) ;
    • Sebok, supa note 5, at 1007-15 ("[T] he private right whose violation grounds [a punitive damages] award is the private right not to have one's dignity violated.") ;
  • 67
    • 67249131308 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Zipursky, supa note 5, at 151-53 (discussing the plaintiffs right to be punitive toward a defendant liable for a willful wrong).
    • Zipursky, supa note 5, at 151-53 (discussing the plaintiffs right "to be punitive" toward a defendant liable for a willful wrong).
  • 68
    • 67249118718 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Chapman & Trebilcock, supra note 5, at 763 (Where there is already injury in place that the law recognizes as damages, this added 'insult' to injury would count more accurately as 'aggravated,' than as punitive, damages.).
    • See Chapman & Trebilcock, supra note 5, at 763 ("Where there is already injury in place that the law recognizes as damages, this added 'insult' to injury would count more accurately as 'aggravated,' than as punitive, damages.").
  • 69
    • 1842591222 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Kaimipono David Wenger & David A. Hoffman, Nullificatory Juries, 2003 WIS. L. REV. 1115, 1119 (defending the role of juries in protectfing] us from rule by legal economists through relatively unconstrained punitive awards). Galanter and Luban also endorse (at least implicitly) a jury's imposing punitive damages against a defendant, in a single case, for all the harm that the defendant's misconduct caused persons in similar situations.
    • See Kaimipono David Wenger & David A. Hoffman, Nullificatory Juries, 2003 WIS. L. REV. 1115, 1119 (defending the role of juries in "protectfing] us from rule by legal economists" through "relatively unconstrained punitive awards"). Galanter and Luban also endorse (at least implicitly) a jury's imposing punitive damages against a defendant, in a single case, for all the harm that the defendant's misconduct caused persons in similar situations.
  • 70
    • 67249127175 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Galanter & Luban, supra note 3, at 1436-38 (providing examples of expressive defeat of defendants through punitive damages). Galanter and Luban also think that judges should extend great deference to jury determinations because of juries' special competence in articulating the community's 'message' through the medium of damages.
    • See, e.g., Galanter & Luban, supra note 3, at 1436-38 (providing examples of "expressive defeat" of defendants through punitive damages). Galanter and Luban also think that judges should extend "great deference" to jury determinations because of juries' special competence in articulating "the community's 'message' through the medium of damages."
  • 72
    • 67249093017 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Rustad, supra note 29, at 1301 (characterizing tort reform of punitive damages as special legislation to help corporate America).
    • See Rustad, supra note 29, at 1301 (characterizing tort reform of punitive damages as "special legislation to help corporate America").
  • 73
    • 67249106420 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See generally THOMAS H. KOENIG & MICHAEL L. RUSTAD, IN DEFENSE OF TORT LAW (2001) (providing a paradigmatic account of the social justice theory of tort law) ;
    • See generally THOMAS H. KOENIG & MICHAEL L. RUSTAD, IN DEFENSE OF TORT LAW (2001) (providing a paradigmatic account of the social justice theory of tort law) ;
  • 74
    • 67249092598 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Richard L. Abel, Questioning the Counter-Majoritarian Thesis: The Case of Torts, 49 DEPAUL L. REV. 533 (1999) (arguing that legislatures are beholden to special interests, while courts are more likely to be focused on the common good in the tort law context);
    • Richard L. Abel, Questioning the Counter-Majoritarian Thesis: The Case of Torts, 49 DEPAUL L. REV. 533 (1999) (arguing that legislatures are beholden to special interests, while courts are more likely to be focused on the common good in the tort law context);
  • 75
    • 67249142059 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Republican Model and Punitive Damages, 41
    • defending a robust role for juries in punitive damages awards on the basis of republican theory, see also
    • see also David F. Pardett, The Republican Model and Punitive Damages, 41 SAN DIEGO L. REV. 1409 (2004) (defending a robust role for juries in punitive damages awards on the basis of republican theory).
    • (2004) SAN DIEGO L. REV , vol.1409
    • Pardett, D.F.1
  • 76
    • 67249123391 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Jean Hampton, Correcting Harms Versus Righting Wrongs: The Goal of Retribution, 39 UCLAL. REV. 1659, 1685-98 (1992) (arguing that conduct that expresses disrespect and does damage to the value of a victim warrants a punitive response to vindicate the victim's moral worth).
    • See Jean Hampton, Correcting Harms Versus Righting Wrongs: The Goal of Retribution, 39 UCLAL. REV. 1659, 1685-98 (1992) (arguing that conduct that expresses disrespect and does damage to "the value of a victim" warrants a punitive response to vindicate the victim's moral worth).
  • 77
    • 67249121584 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Galanter & Luban, supra note 3, at 1432-35. For reasons that I explained in the first article in this series, I view Galanter and Luban's account of punitive damages as primarily (though not exclusively) a victim vindication account, not a retributive justice account.
    • See Galanter & Luban, supra note 3, at 1432-35. For reasons that I explained in the first article in this series, I view Galanter and Luban's account of punitive damages as primarily (though not exclusively) a victim vindication account, not a retributive justice account.
  • 79
    • 23744477929 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I note also that a number of other punitive damages scholars, including Professors Colby, Sebok, Zipursky, and Geistfeld, have claimed to be influenced by Professor Hampton's work and, to varying degrees, have identified themselves as interested in developing the re-lationship between punitive damages and retributive justice. My own view is that their interests and values are better described as consistent with victim vindication, and less so with retributive justice, properly understood as a practice of state punishment interested in developing institutions that promote equality and rule-of-law values in the reduction of Type I and Type II punishment errors. For discussion of my view of the proper role of victims in retributive theory, see, for example, Dan Markel, State, Be Not Proud: A Retributivist Defense of the Commutation of Death Row and the Abolition of the Death Penally, 40 HARV. C.R.-C.L. L. REV. 407, 452-57 2005
    • I note also that a number of other punitive damages scholars, including Professors Colby, Sebok, Zipursky, and Geistfeld, have claimed to be influenced by Professor Hampton's work and, to varying degrees, have identified themselves as interested in developing the re-lationship between punitive damages and retributive justice. My own view is that their interests and values are better described as consistent with "victim vindication," and less so with retributive justice, properly understood as a practice of state punishment interested in developing institutions that promote equality and rule-of-law values in the reduction of Type I and Type II punishment errors. For discussion of my view of the proper role of victims in retributive theory, see, for example, Dan Markel, State, Be Not Proud: A Retributivist Defense of the Commutation of Death Row and the Abolition of the Death Penally, 40 HARV. C.R.-C.L. L. REV. 407, 452-57 (2005)
  • 81
    • 67249097212 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Sebok, supa note 5, at 1005-06 (Plaintiffs who may have a valid legal claim for punitive damages are under no obligation to pursue them. In theory, a plaintiff could request a sanction smaller than what justice might otherwise require the wrongdoer to repay. (footnote omitted));
    • See Sebok, supa note 5, at 1005-06 ("Plaintiffs who may have a valid legal claim for punitive damages are under no obligation to pursue them. In theory, a plaintiff could request a sanction smaller than what justice might otherwise require the wrongdoer to repay." (footnote omitted));
  • 82
    • 67249105966 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • id. at 1028-29 ([O]ne element of the repair of wrongful losses in tort is the active role of the victim in determining the appropriate remedy for her case of wrongful loss.);
    • id. at 1028-29 ("[O]ne element of the repair of wrongful losses in tort is the active role of the victim in determining the appropriate remedy for her case of wrongful loss.");
  • 83
    • 0142138821 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Civil Recourse, Not Corrective Justice, 91
    • Benjamin C. Zipursky, Civil Recourse, Not Corrective Justice, 91 GEO. L.J. 695, 733 (2003)
    • (2003) GEO. L.J , vol.695 , pp. 733
    • Zipursky, B.C.1
  • 84
    • 67249127174 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • T] ortcases ultimately require courts to respond to demands by plaintiffs
    • [hereinafter Zipursky, Civil Recourse] ("[T] ortcases ultimately require courts to respond to demands by plaintiffs....");
    • Civil Recourse
    • hereinafter Zipursky1
  • 85
    • 67249097213 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Zipursky,supa note 5, at 152 (The state permits the plaintiff to seek and to receive [punitive damages], but the state is not in the driver's seat.).
    • Zipursky,supa note 5, at 152 ("The state permits the plaintiff to seek and to receive [punitive damages], but the state is not in the driver's seat.").
  • 87
    • 67249150259 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • To its credit, Professor Sebok's state-sanctioned revenge account is consistent with a desire to reduce piling on (or Type I overpunishment) errors that occur through introducing evidence of harms to strangers to the litigation. See Sebok, supra note 5, at 1031-35. But Sebok doesn't address the public's interest in reducing Type II errors of either sort, or the procedural safeguards necessary to prevent Type I errors of the mistaken-punishment sort.
    • To its credit, Professor Sebok's state-sanctioned revenge account is consistent with a desire to reduce "piling on" (or Type I overpunishment) errors that occur through introducing evidence of harms to strangers to the litigation. See Sebok, supra note 5, at 1031-35. But Sebok doesn't address the public's interest in reducing Type II errors of either sort, or the procedural safeguards necessary to prevent Type I errors of the mistaken-punishment sort.
  • 88
    • 67249147030 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Similarly, for cases involving fatal risks, the methodology proposed by Professor Geistfeld, see Geistfeld, supra note 5, is helpful in ensuring some evenhandedness across cases involving certain tort victims. That said, this methodology says title about how to reduce the gamut of Type I and Type II errors outside the relatively narrow but important context of victims facing fatal risks; moreover, even in the context of fatal risks, Geistfeld's account is quiet about the need for reducing Type II errors involving nonpunishment.
    • Similarly, for cases involving fatal risks, the methodology proposed by Professor Geistfeld, see Geistfeld, supra note 5, is helpful in ensuring some evenhandedness across cases involving certain tort victims. That said, this methodology says title about how to reduce the gamut of Type I and Type II errors outside the relatively narrow but important context of victims facing fatal risks; moreover, even in the context of fatal risks, Geistfeld's account is quiet about the need for reducing Type II errors involving nonpunishment.
  • 89
    • 67249161881 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Such Type II errors leathng to underenforcement are rife. See Michael J. Saks, Do We Really Know Anything About the Behavior of the Tort Litigation System-And Why Not?, 140 U. PA. L. REV. 1147, 1183 (1992) (One of the most remarkable features of the tort system is how few plaintiffs there are. A great many potential plaintiffs are never heard from by the injurers or their insurers.);
    • Such Type II errors leathng to underenforcement are rife. See Michael J. Saks, Do We Really Know Anything About the Behavior of the Tort Litigation System-And Why Not?, 140 U. PA. L. REV. 1147, 1183 (1992) ("One of the most remarkable features of the tort system is how few plaintiffs there are. A great many potential plaintiffs are never heard from by the injurers or their insurers.");
  • 90
    • 67249115819 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also Richard L. Abel, The Real Torts Crisis- Too Few Claims, 48 OHIO ST. L.J. 443 (1987);
    • see also Richard L. Abel, The Real Torts Crisis- Too Few Claims, 48 OHIO ST. L.J. 443 (1987);
  • 91
    • 67249114497 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Marc Galanter, Real World Torts: An Antidote to Anecdote, 55 MD. L. REV. 1093, 1159 (1996) (stating that relatively few tort claims are brought to court and that, even if more claims were filed, the tort system may not have the capacity to handle them).
    • Marc Galanter, Real World Torts: An Antidote to Anecdote, 55 MD. L. REV. 1093, 1159 (1996) (stating that "relatively few" tort claims are brought to court and that, even if more claims were filed, the tort system may not have the capacity to handle them).
  • 92
    • 67249163003 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See ANDREW VON HIRSCH ET AI., CRIMINAI. DETERRENCE AND SENTENCE SEVERITY: AN ANALYSIS OF RECENT RESEARCH 45-48 (1999) (examining empirical literature and noting that there exists a correlation between increased certainty of punishment and decreased crime rates but that the evidence showing a correlation between severity of punishment and crime rates is comparatively weaker) ;
    • See ANDREW VON HIRSCH ET AI., CRIMINAI. DETERRENCE AND SENTENCE SEVERITY: AN ANALYSIS OF RECENT RESEARCH 45-48 (1999) (examining empirical literature and noting that there exists a correlation between increased certainty of punishment and decreased crime rates but that the evidence showing a correlation between severity of punishment and crime rates is comparatively weaker) ;
  • 93
    • 84977342350 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Jeffrey Grogger, Certainty vs. Severity of Punishment, 29 ECON. INQUIRY 297, 308 (1991) (The results point to large deterrent effects emanating from increased certainty of punishment, and much smaller, and generally insignificant effects, stemming from increased severity of sanction.).
    • Jeffrey Grogger, Certainty vs. Severity of Punishment, 29 ECON. INQUIRY 297, 308 (1991) ("The results point to large deterrent effects emanating from increased certainty of punishment, and much smaller, and generally insignificant effects, stemming from increased severity of sanction.").
  • 94
    • 67249092302 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Punitive damages might be thought to pursue a mixture of other goals as well. See generally Dorsey D. Ellis, Jr., Fairness and Efficiency in the Law of Punitive Damages, 56 S. CAL. L. REV. 1, 3 (1982) (At least seven purposes for imposing punitive damages can be gleaned from judicial opinions and the writings of commentators: (1) punishing the defendant; (2) deterring the defendant from repeating the offense; (3) deterringothers from committing an offense; (4) preserving the peace; (5) inducing private law enforcement; (6) compensating victims for otherwise uncompensable losses; and (7) paying the plaintiff's attorneys' fees.).
    • Punitive damages might be thought to pursue a mixture of other goals as well. See generally Dorsey D. Ellis, Jr., Fairness and Efficiency in the Law of Punitive Damages, 56 S. CAL. L. REV. 1, 3 (1982) ("At least seven purposes for imposing punitive damages can be gleaned from judicial opinions and the writings of commentators: (1) punishing the defendant; (2) deterring the defendant from repeating the offense; (3) deterringothers from committing an offense; (4) preserving the peace; (5) inducing private law enforcement; (6) compensating victims for otherwise uncompensable losses; and (7) paying the plaintiff's attorneys' fees.").
  • 95
    • 67249104291 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ellis, however, subjects these possible purposes to close scrutiny and finds some of them lacking. See id. at 76.
    • Ellis, however, subjects these possible purposes to close scrutiny and finds some of them lacking. See id. at 76.
  • 96
    • 67249123389 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • While I adopt certain scholars' views on how to conceptualize and implement what I am calling aggravated and deterrence damages, I don't necessarily present the most comprehensive or sophisticated version of those particular approaches. This caveat seems necessary in light of the fact that there are disagreements within the cost internalization school and within the victim vindication camp over various details. In designing a pluralistic structure, I have simply tried to draw on the ideas that seemed most feasible and attractive for a post-Philip Morris world of extracompensatory damages
    • While I adopt certain scholars' views on how to conceptualize and implement what I am calling aggravated and deterrence damages, I don't necessarily present the most comprehensive or sophisticated version of those particular approaches. This caveat seems necessary in light of the fact that there are disagreements within the cost internalization school and within the victim vindication camp over various details. In designing a pluralistic structure, I have simply tried to draw on the ideas that seemed most feasible and attractive for a post-Philip Morris world of extracompensatory damages.
  • 98
    • 67249114056 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Galanter and Luban, supra note 3, passim
    • See Galanter and Luban, supra note 3, passim.
  • 99
    • 34547572622 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See note 5, at, T] he desire for revenge burns bright in the human heart-too bright for the law to ignore
    • See Colby, supra note 5, at 433 ("[T] he desire for revenge burns bright in the human heart-too bright for the law to ignore.");
    • supra , pp. 433
    • Colby1
  • 100
    • 67249102137 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sebok, supra note 5, at 1031 ([S]tate-sanctioned revenge is the best interpretation of [punitive damages].).
    • Sebok, supra note 5, at 1031 ("[S]tate-sanctioned revenge is the best interpretation of [punitive damages].").
  • 101
    • 67249089709 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Wenger & Hoffman, supra note 37, at 1138-40 (explaining that jurors often reject efficiency rationales for punitive damages and instead base their awards in part on their level of moral outrage).
    • See Wenger & Hoffman, supra note 37, at 1138-40 (explaining that jurors often reject efficiency rationales for punitive damages and instead base their awards in part on their level of moral outrage).
  • 102
    • 67249161474 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • My prior works have addressed how this theory applies to other policy issues. See
    • See Markel, Retributive Damages, supra note 1, pt. II. My prior works have addressed how this theory applies to other policy issues.
    • Retributive Damages, supra note , vol.1 , Issue.PART. II
    • Markel1
  • 103
    • 3042771384 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Against Mercy, 88
    • See generally
    • See generally Dan Markel, Against Mercy, 88 MINN. L. REV. 1421 (2004)
    • (2004) MINN. L. REV , vol.1421
    • Markel, D.1
  • 105
    • 0346449873 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Are Shaming Punishments Beautifully Retributive? Retributivism and the Implications for the Alternative Sanctions Debate, 54
    • considering alternative criminal sanctions through the lens of retributive justice theory
    • Dan Markel, Are Shaming Punishments Beautifully Retributive? Retributivism and the Implications for the Alternative Sanctions Debate, 54 VAND. L. REV. 2157 (2001) (considering alternative criminal sanctions through the lens of retributive justice theory);
    • (2001) VAND. L. REV , vol.2157
    • Markel, D.1
  • 106
    • 67249154100 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Markel, State, Be Not Proud, supra note 40, at 457-77 (arguing that retributive justice is incompatible with the deadi penalty);
    • Markel, State, Be Not Proud, supra note 40, at 457-77 (arguing that retributive justice is incompatible with the deadi penalty);
  • 107
    • 67249139471 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dan Markel, The Justice of Amnesty? Towards a Theory of Retributivism in Recovering States, 49 U. TORONTO L.J. 389, 392 (1999) (arguing that the particularized amnesty utilized by some recovering states as part of a transitional justice program can be compatible with justice, even when justice is understood as retributive in nature).
    • Dan Markel, The Justice of Amnesty? Towards a Theory of Retributivism in Recovering States, 49 U. TORONTO L.J. 389, 392 (1999) (arguing that the particularized amnesty utilized by some recovering states as part of a transitional justice program can be "compatible with justice, even when justice is understood as retributive in nature").
  • 108
    • 70349423894 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • More recendy, I have extended this theory to the Supreme Court's Eighth Amendment jurisprudence, see Dan Markel, Executing Retributivism: Panetti and the Future of the Eighth Amendment, 103 NW. U. L. REV. (forthcoming Spring 2009), available at http://srn.com/abstract=1263683 (arguing that the Supreme Court's holding in Panetti v. Quarterman, 551 U.S. 930 (2007), is predicated on an understanding of retributive punishment as a communicative action directed at the offender and that this conception of punishment diminishes the constitutional justification for the death penalty). I also have extended the theory to the role that a defendant's family status should play in her criminal liability and punishment.
    • More recendy, I have extended this theory to the Supreme Court's Eighth Amendment jurisprudence, see Dan Markel, Executing Retributivism: Panetti and the Future of the Eighth Amendment, 103 NW. U. L. REV. (forthcoming Spring 2009), available at http://srn.com/abstract=1263683 (arguing that the Supreme Court's holding in Panetti v. Quarterman, 551 U.S. 930 (2007), is predicated on an understanding of retributive punishment as a communicative action directed at the offender and that this conception of punishment diminishes the constitutional justification for the death penalty). I also have extended the theory to the role that a defendant's family status should play in her criminal liability and punishment.
  • 109
    • 72649098764 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See DAN MARKEL, JENNIFER M. COLLINS & ETHAN J. LEIB, PRIVILEGE OR PUNISH: CRIMINAL JUSTICE AND THE CHALLENGE OF FAMILY TIES (2009) (examining and often challenging the current use of family status in the criminal justice system).
    • See DAN MARKEL, JENNIFER M. COLLINS & ETHAN J. LEIB, PRIVILEGE OR PUNISH: CRIMINAL JUSTICE AND THE CHALLENGE OF FAMILY TIES (2009) (examining and often challenging the current use of family status in the criminal justice system).
  • 110
    • 67249159391 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The victim vindication accounts say little about how to achieve consistency and predictability across cases. Furthermore, the dominant cost internalization accounts do not typically require inquiry into and judgment of the reprehensibility of the defendant's actions, so cost internalization proponents are not really interested in communicating condemnation to offenders. See, e.g., Galligan, supra note 5;
    • The victim vindication accounts say little about how to achieve consistency and predictability across cases. Furthermore, the dominant cost internalization accounts do not typically require inquiry into and judgment of the reprehensibility of the defendant's actions, so cost internalization proponents are not really interested in communicating condemnation to offenders. See, e.g., Galligan, supra note 5;
  • 111
    • 67249110552 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Polinsky & Shavell, supra note 5
    • Polinsky & Shavell, supra note 5.
  • 114
    • 34250872162 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See generally Paul H. Robinson & Robert Kurzban, Concordance and Conflict in Intuitions of Justice, 91 MLNN. L. REV. 1829 (2007) (providing research on widely shared intuitions regarding the scaling of reprehensibility);
    • See generally Paul H. Robinson & Robert Kurzban, Concordance and Conflict in Intuitions of Justice, 91 MLNN. L. REV. 1829 (2007) (providing research on widely shared intuitions regarding the scaling of reprehensibility);
  • 115
    • 67249156386 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sunstein et al, supra note 6, at 2077-78 noting consistency in moral judgments but inconsistency in translating outrage into dollars
    • Sunstein et al., supra note 6, at 2077-78 (noting consistency in moral judgments but inconsistency in translating outrage into dollars).
  • 116
    • 67249108816 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Legislatures and courts might also look to Michael Welner's research on the Depravity Scale. See Michael Welner, The Depravity Scale, http:// www.depravityscale.org (last visited Mar. 15, 2009).
    • Legislatures and courts might also look to Michael Welner's research on the "Depravity Scale." See Michael Welner, The Depravity Scale, http:// www.depravityscale.org (last visited Mar. 15, 2009).
  • 117
    • 67249087323 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This scaling approach addresses some of the concerns raised by Cass Sunstein. See, e.g, Cass R. Sunstein, On the Psychology of Punishment, 11 SUP. CT. ECON. REV. 171, 179-81 2004, recognizing the value of guidelines and benchmarks for improved cognition and fairness in punitive damages awards across cases
    • This scaling approach addresses some of the concerns raised by Cass Sunstein. See, e.g., Cass R. Sunstein, On the Psychology of Punishment, 11 SUP. CT. ECON. REV. 171, 179-81 (2004) (recognizing the value of guidelines and benchmarks for improved cognition and fairness in punitive damages awards across cases).
  • 118
    • 67249141636 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Markel, Retributive Damages, supra note 1, at 290-96 (offering rationales for scaling fines to the defendant's financial position).
    • Cf. Markel, Retributive Damages, supra note 1, at 290-96 (offering rationales for "scaling fines to the defendant's financial position").
  • 119
    • 67249123238 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The gain-stripping aspect of the retributive damages structure makes this approach broadly consistent with the complete deterrence approach advocated by economists like Keith Hylton. See Hylton, supra note 18, at 464-67 (stressing that anoptimal-penalty system would eliminate the prospect of gain by the offender) ;
    • The gain-stripping aspect of the retributive damages structure makes this approach broadly consistent with the "complete deterrence" approach advocated by economists like Keith Hylton. See Hylton, supra note 18, at 464-67 (stressing that anoptimal-penalty system would eliminate the prospect of gain by the offender) ;
  • 120
    • 67249155918 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also David D. Haddock et al., An Ordinary Economic Rationale for Extraordinary Legal Sanctions, 78 CAL. L. REV. 1, 20 (1990) (Enforcing property rules requires stripping all gain (or more) from a taking.). The retributive damages penalty also includes a wealth- and reprehensibility-informed monetary penalty that puts the defendant in a worse position than she was at the status quo ante. Complete-deterrence models permit but do not require that setback, which is part of how the retributive message of condemnation is communicated.
    • see also David D. Haddock et al., An Ordinary Economic Rationale for Extraordinary Legal Sanctions, 78 CAL. L. REV. 1, 20 (1990) ("Enforcing property rules requires stripping all gain (or more) from a taking."). The retributive damages penalty also includes a wealth- and reprehensibility-informed monetary penalty that puts the defendant in a worse position than she was at the status quo ante. Complete-deterrence models permit but do not require that setback, which is part of how the retributive message of condemnation is communicated.
  • 121
    • 67249107280 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • contrasting the messages of complete deterrence and retribution, See, at
    • See Markel, Retributive Damages, supra note 1, at 242-43 (contrasting the messages of complete deterrence and retribution).
    • Retributive Damages, supra note , vol.1 , pp. 242-243
    • Markel1
  • 122
    • 67249139875 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Such a flat fee avoids the lottery effects that a plaintiff would enjoy from having the good fortune of having a wealthy injurer
    • Such a flat fee avoids the lottery effects that a plaintiff would enjoy from having the good "fortune" of having a wealthy injurer.
  • 123
    • 67249120268 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Other valuation methodologies might also be consistent with retributive justice values. See Geistfeld, supra note 5, at 286-92, 306 (proposing for torts involving fatal risks a damages valuation that examines government data regarding the monetization of fatal risks);
    • Other valuation methodologies might also be consistent with retributive justice values. See Geistfeld, supra note 5, at 286-92, 306 (proposing for torts involving fatal risks a damages valuation that examines government data regarding the monetization of fatal risks);
  • 124
    • 67249118717 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Markel, Retributive Damages, supra note 1, at 287 n.166, 290 n.181 (explaining why a multiplier of compensatory damages for torts involving purely financial losses might also comply with retributive justice values). Despite my open-mindedness toward these alternative methods of assessing retributive damages, I should clarify that if they were to be used, the amounts imposed would also need to satisfy the retributive goals of stripping the gain and imposing an adequate, proportionate, and parsimonious setback on the defendant.
    • Markel, Retributive Damages, supra note 1, at 287 n.166, 290 n.181 (explaining why a multiplier of compensatory damages for torts involving purely financial losses might also comply with retributive justice values). Despite my open-mindedness toward these alternative methods of assessing retributive damages, I should clarify that if they were to be used, the amounts imposed would also need to satisfy the retributive goals of stripping the gain and imposing an adequate, proportionate, and parsimonious setback on the defendant.
  • 125
    • 67249144522 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Indeed, depending on the circumstances, the restructuring to evade payment could arguably be a factor used to raise one's reprehensibility score
    • Indeed, depending on the circumstances, the restructuring to evade payment could arguably be a factor used to raise one's reprehensibility score.
  • 126
    • 21144458323 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • State Sentencing Guidelines: Diversity, Consensus, and Unresolved Policy Issues, 105
    • summarizing states' use of sentencing guidelines, See generally
    • See generally Richard S. Frase, State Sentencing Guidelines: Diversity, Consensus, and Unresolved Policy Issues, 105 COLUM. L. REV. 1190, 1194-1208 (2005) (summarizing states' use of sentencing guidelines).
    • (2005) COLUM. L. REV , vol.1190 , pp. 1194-1208
    • Frase, R.S.1
  • 127
    • 67249103423 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g, supra note 3
    • See, e.g., supra note 3.
  • 128
    • 67249124265 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I am obviously not the first person to note that punitive damages serve different purposes; my hope is that the discussion here advances the ball by explaining in greater detail what a disaggregated scheme of extracompensatory damages would look like if implemented with care. Others who have contemplated disaggregation and pluralism include Professors Galligan, Sharkey, Calabresi, Polinsky & Shavell, Rustad, and Salbu. See, e.g, Ciraolo v. City of N.Y, 216 F.3d 236, 2446 2d Cir. 2000, Calabresi, J, concurring, Indeed, it would not be inappropriate to disaggregate the retributive and deterrent functions of extracompensatory damages altogether and allow separate awards to further the two separate goals
    • I am obviously not the first person to note that punitive damages serve different purposes; my hope is that the discussion here advances the ball by explaining in greater detail what a disaggregated scheme of extracompensatory damages would look like if implemented with care. Others who have contemplated disaggregation and pluralism include Professors Galligan, Sharkey, Calabresi, Polinsky & Shavell, Rustad, and Salbu. See, e.g., Ciraolo v. City of N.Y., 216 F.3d 236, 2446 (2d Cir. 2000) (Calabresi, J., concurring) ("Indeed, it would not be inappropriate to disaggregate the retributive and deterrent functions of extracompensatory damages altogether and allow separate awards to further the two separate goals.");
  • 129
    • 67249084875 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Thomas C. Galligan, Jr., Disaggregating MoreThan-Wliole Damages in Personal Injury Law: Deterrence and Punishment, 71 TENN. L. REV. 117 (2003);
    • Thomas C. Galligan, Jr., Disaggregating MoreThan-Wliole Damages in Personal Injury Law: Deterrence and Punishment, 71 TENN. L. REV. 117 (2003);
  • 130
    • 67249136253 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Polinsky & Shavell, supra note 5;
    • Polinsky & Shavell, supra note 5;
  • 131
    • 67249106848 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Happy No Morep: Federalism Derailed by the Court that Would Be King of Punitive Damages, 64
    • adumbrating the plural goals that punitive damages serve
    • Michael L. Rustad, Happy No Morep: Federalism Derailed by the Court that Would Be King of Punitive Damages, 64 MD. L. REV. 461, 46893 (2005) (adumbrating the plural goals that punitive damages serve);
    • (2005) MD. L. REV , vol.461 , pp. 46893
    • Rustad, M.L.1
  • 132
    • 67249114943 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Steven R. Salbu, Developing Rational Punitive Damages Policies: Beyond the Constitution, 49 FLA. L. REV. 247 (1997, recognizing different rationales for punitive damages and noting that diose rationales can be used separately or jointly to calculate damages, Sharkey, supra note 5, at 363 Notwithstanding the fact that the retributive-based and deterrence-based components of punitive damages are not fully separable, and indeed have potentially synergistic or overlapping effects, there are significant gains to be achieved from treating them as conceptually distinct, In various respects, my account builds on and departs from these earlier efforts, most significantly in terms of distinguishing between the public interest in retributive justice and the private interest in victim vindication, and also in explaining how cost internalization intersects with these goals, especially after Philip Morris
    • Steven R. Salbu, Developing Rational Punitive Damages Policies: Beyond the Constitution, 49 FLA. L. REV. 247 (1997) (recognizing different rationales for punitive damages and noting that diose rationales can be used separately or jointly to calculate damages); Sharkey, supra note 5, at 363 ("Notwithstanding the fact that the retributive-based and deterrence-based components of punitive damages are not fully separable, and indeed have potentially synergistic or overlapping effects, there are significant gains to be achieved from treating them as conceptually distinct."). In various respects, my account builds on and departs from these earlier efforts, most significantly in terms of distinguishing between the public interest in retributive justice and the private interest in victim vindication, and also in explaining how cost internalization intersects with these goals, especially after Philip Morris.
  • 133
    • 67249146589 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Galanter & Luban, supra note 3, at 1439-40 (urging jurisdictions to require jury explanations). The jury-explanation device undermines the confidentiality of jury deliberations, but it is hard to
    • See, e.g., Galanter & Luban, supra note 3, at 1439-40 (urging jurisdictions to require jury explanations). The jury-explanation device undermines the confidentiality of jury deliberations, but it is hard to understand why that confidentiality should be a higher priority than the achievement of the public's interest in the fair and accurate imposition of justice. The concern of judicial interference with the jury's role is especially exaggerated given thatjudges perform various gatekeeping roles.
  • 134
    • 67249160833 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 216 F.3d 236, 244-46 (2d Cir. 2000) (Calabresi, J., concurring). Calabresi drew on the work of other scholars in endorsing cost internalization and urging the separation of cost internalization from punishment. See, e.g., Polinsky Sc Shavell, supra note 5, at 906 ([T] he imposition of damages equal to harm, appropriately multiplied to reflect the probability of escaping liability, achieves proper deterrence.);
    • 216 F.3d 236, 244-46 (2d Cir. 2000) (Calabresi, J., concurring). Calabresi drew on the work of other scholars in endorsing cost internalization and urging the separation of cost internalization from punishment. See, e.g., Polinsky Sc Shavell, supra note 5, at 906 ("[T] he imposition of damages equal to harm, appropriately multiplied to reflect the probability of escaping liability, achieves proper deterrence.");
  • 135
    • 67249152488 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also Galligan, supra note 5. Galligan's account is very instructive regarding the deterrence function, but it does not work through the details of implementing the public's interest in retributive justice. It also fails to separate the public interest in retributive justice from the victim's private interest in vindicating the injury to her dignity. Nonetheless, the points that Galligan makes about the proper way to determine optimal deterrence are useful in a context where total cost internalization damages would be permissible.
    • see also Galligan, supra note 5. Galligan's account is very instructive regarding the deterrence function, but it does not work through the details of implementing the public's interest in retributive justice. It also fails to separate the public interest in retributive justice from the victim's private interest in vindicating the injury to her dignity. Nonetheless, the points that Galligan makes about the proper way to determine optimal deterrence are useful in a context where "total cost internalization" damages would be permissible.
  • 137
    • 67249126014 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • However, because of the way at Philip Morris makes total cost internalization constitutionally problematic, see infra subsection II.A.2.1 do not think that there is a constitutionally permissible basis for structuring deterrence damages in the way that Professor Galligan suggests.
    • However, because of the way at Philip Morris makes "total cost internalization" constitutionally problematic, see infra subsection II.A.2.1 do not think that there is a constitutionally permissible basis for structuring deterrence damages in the way that Professor Galligan suggests.
  • 138
    • 67249154104 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See City of Newport v. Fact Concerts, Inc., 453 U.S. 247, 259-66 (1981) (affirming the common law absolute immunity of municipalities against punitive damages actions for the bad-faith misdeeds of their officials).
    • See City of Newport v. Fact Concerts, Inc., 453 U.S. 247, 259-66 (1981) (affirming the common law absolute immunity of municipalities against punitive damages actions for the bad-faith misdeeds of their officials).
  • 139
    • 67249133710 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Judge Calabresi wrote that [c]osts may not be sufficiendy reflected in compensatory damages for several reasons, most of which go to the fact that not all injured parties are in fact compensated by the responsible injurer. For example, a victim may not realize that she has been harmed by a particular actor's conduct, or may not be able to identify the person or entity who has injured her. Where the injurer makes active efforts to conceal the harm, this problem is of course exacerbated. Moreover, even if a victim is aware of her injury and is able to identify its cause, she may not bring suit. A person will be unlikely to sue if the costs of doing so-including the time, effort, and stress associated with bringing a lawsuit-outweigh the compensation she can expect to receive. A victim is especially unlikely to sue, therefore, in cases where the probable compensatory damages are relatively low. As a result, a harm that affects many people, but each only to a limited degree, will generally
    • Judge Calabresi wrote that [c]osts may not be sufficiendy reflected in compensatory damages for several reasons, most of which go to the fact that not all injured parties are in fact compensated by the responsible injurer. For example, a victim may not realize that she has been harmed by a particular actor's conduct, or may not be able to identify the person or entity who has injured her. Where the injurer makes active efforts to conceal the harm, this problem is of course exacerbated. Moreover, even if a victim is aware of her injury and is able to identify its cause, she may not bring suit. A person will be unlikely to sue if the costs of doing so-including the time, effort, and stress associated with bringing a lawsuit-outweigh the compensation she can expect to receive. A victim is especially unlikely to sue, therefore, in cases where the probable compensatory damages are relatively low. As a result, a harm that affects many people, but each only to a limited degree, will generally be given inadequate weight if only compensatory damages are assessed. In addition, some victims will not sue even if the damages they could expect to receive would exceed the costs of suing. Victims will differ gready in their knowledge of and access to the legal process, and those who are relatively poor and unsophisticated, as a practical matter, are frequently unable to bring suit to redress their injuries even if those injuries are grave. A harm that disproportionately affects such victims, therefore, is also particularly likely not to be accurately reflected in compensatory damages. Ciraolo, 216 F.3d at 243-44 (Calabresi, J., concurring) (citations omitted).
  • 140
    • 67249112345 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • According to their supporters, optimal deterrence damages should be set at a level such that the expected damages of defendants equal the harm they have caused, for then their damage payments will, in an average sense, equal the harm. This implies a simple formula for calculating punitive damages, according to which harm is multiplied by a factor reflecting the likelihood of escaping liability. Polinsky & Shavell, supra note 5, at 954
    • According to their supporters, optimal deterrence damages should be set at a level such that the expected damages of defendants equal the harm they have caused, for then their damage payments will, in an average sense, equal the harm. This implies a simple formula for calculating punitive damages, according to which harm is multiplied by a factor reflecting the likelihood of escaping liability. Polinsky & Shavell, supra note 5, at 954.
  • 141
    • 0009905372 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Some law and economics scholars have registered skepticism with the multiplier principle. See, e.g., Richard Craswell, Deterrence and Damages: The Multiplier Principle and Its Alternatives, 97 MICH. L. REV. 2185, 2191-98 (1999) (contending that the use of a static multiplier misapprehends the variable probabilities of punishment, which generally correlate with the seriousness of a crime);
    • Some law and economics scholars have registered skepticism with the multiplier principle. See, e.g., Richard Craswell, Deterrence and Damages: The Multiplier Principle and Its Alternatives, 97 MICH. L. REV. 2185, 2191-98 (1999) (contending that the use of a static multiplier misapprehends the variable probabilities of punishment, which generally correlate with the seriousness of a crime);
  • 142
    • 67249084009 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also Sharkey, supra note 5, at 368-69 (raising concern that the Polinsky-Shavell approach doesn't achieve adequate cost internalization). I should note that my proposal largely brackets the skepticism towards the deterrence damages multiplier, but if economists converge on a different metfiod of achieving cost internalization in a way that is compatible with Philip Morris, I am certainly open to it.
    • see also Sharkey, supra note 5, at 368-69 (raising concern that the Polinsky-Shavell approach doesn't achieve adequate cost internalization). I should note that my proposal largely brackets the skepticism towards the deterrence damages multiplier, but if economists converge on a different metfiod of achieving cost internalization in a way that is compatible with Philip Morris, I am certainly open to it.
  • 143
    • 67249111073 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Thomas C. Galligan, Jr., The Risks of and Reactions to Underdeterrence in Torts, 70 MO. L. REV. 691, 692 2005 arguing that rules developed for individual actions do not deter effectively in the mass tort context.
    • See Thomas C. Galligan, Jr., The Risks of and Reactions to Underdeterrence in Torts, 70 MO. L. REV. 691, 692 2005 arguing that rules developed for individual actions do not deter effectively in the mass tort context.
  • 144
    • 67249159396 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Again, I note that my use of deterrence damages may seem idiosyncratic to those who think of deterrence in terms of complete deterrence. Here I simply mean to describe damages meant to realize cost internalization to the extent that I view permissible in a post-Philip Morris world.
    • Again, I note that my use of "deterrence" damages may seem idiosyncratic to those who think of deterrence in terms of complete deterrence. Here I simply mean to describe damages meant to realize cost internalization to the extent that I view permissible in a post-Philip Morris world.
  • 145
    • 67249117418 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Polinsky & Shavell, supra note 5, at 905-10 (arguing that deterrence damages should be calculated as the amount of the plaintiff's harm multiplied by the reciprocal of the probability that the defendant will escape liability, and maintaining that the reprehensibility of the defendant's conduct is irrelevant for deterrence damage purposes);
    • See Polinsky & Shavell, supra note 5, at 905-10 (arguing that deterrence damages should be calculated as the amount of the plaintiff's harm multiplied by the reciprocal of the probability that the defendant will escape liability, and maintaining that the reprehensibility of the defendant's conduct is irrelevant for deterrence damage purposes);
  • 146
    • 0041875905 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kenneth W. Simons, Deontology, Negligence, Tort, and Grime, 76 B.U. L. REV. 273, 273 (1996) (explaining that, under an optimal deterrence regime, one is entitied to harm the victim so long as he pays for the harm (with the expectation that this entidement will induce him to take optimal care)).
    • Kenneth W. Simons, Deontology, Negligence, Tort, and Grime, 76 B.U. L. REV. 273, 273 (1996) (explaining that, under an optimal deterrence regime, one is "entitied to harm the victim so long as he pays for the harm (with the expectation that this entidement will induce him to take optimal care)").
  • 147
    • 67249115818 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • But see Sharkey, supra note 5, at 405 (requiring a threshold finding of at least recklessness before such nonpunitive extracompensatorydamages can be imposed). For reasons explained elsewhere, Sharkey's threshold requirement of recklessness stands in tension with a better understanding of cost internalization.
    • But see Sharkey, supra note 5, at 405 (requiring a threshold finding of at least recklessness before such nonpunitive extracompensatorydamages can be imposed). For reasons explained elsewhere, Sharkey's threshold requirement of recklessness stands in tension with a better understanding of cost internalization.
  • 148
    • 67249129575 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Galligan, supra note 5, at 62-63 (arguing that augmented awards are intended to deter and not to punish-therefore making focus on the defendant's state of mind irrelevant to calculating these awards);
    • See Galligan, supra note 5, at 62-63 (arguing that augmented awards are intended to deter and not to punish-therefore making focus on the defendant's state of mind irrelevant to calculating these awards);
  • 149
    • 67249125598 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kelly, supra note 32, at 1440 n.36 (explaining that Sharkey's proposal of limiting societal damages to instances where defendants engage in conduct that is at least reckless seems to move the justification back toward retribution, letting state of mind, not undercompensation, differentiate the cases where additional deterrence is needed);
    • Kelly, supra note 32, at 1440 n.36 (explaining that Sharkey's proposal of limiting "societal" damages to instances where defendants engage in conduct that is at least reckless "seems to move the justification back toward retribution, letting state of mind, not undercompensation, differentiate the cases where additional deterrence is needed");
  • 150
    • 67249124744 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • & n.9, 244 explaining that the issue of reprehensibility is separate from the issue of whether a defendant has been forced to bear the costs of her actions, at
    • Markel, Retributive Damages, supra note 1, at 243 & n.9, 244 (explaining that the issue of reprehensibility is separate from the issue of whether a defendant has been forced to bear the costs of her actions).
    • Retributive Damages, supra note , vol.1 , pp. 243
    • Markel1
  • 151
    • 67249151206 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Polinsky & Shavell, supra note 5, at 905-10. To be sure, one might still have residual anxieties about whether deterrence damages would perform an adequate compensatory and norm-projection function-especially in cases where the payment of deterrence damages will not readily be commensurable with the harm suffered. In other words, there is a legitimate concern that compensation never compensates in the tort context because the plaintiff never wanted to earn that compensation.
    • See Polinsky & Shavell, supra note 5, at 905-10. To be sure, one might still have residual anxieties about whether deterrence damages would perform an adequate compensatory and norm-projection function-especially in cases where the payment of deterrence damages will not readily be commensurable with the harm suffered. In other words, there is a legitimate concern that "compensation never compensates" in the tort context because the plaintiff never wanted to "earn" that compensation.
  • 152
    • 67249111072 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See JOSEPH WILLIAM SINGER, ENTITLEMENTS: THE PARADOX OF PROPERTY 282 (2000). But that concern indicates only why deterrence damages should not be the exclusive purpose of extracompensatory damages.
    • See JOSEPH WILLIAM SINGER, ENTITLEMENTS: THE PARADOX OF PROPERTY 282 (2000). But that concern indicates only why deterrence damages should not be the exclusive purpose of extracompensatory damages.
  • 153
    • 67249117868 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • TXO Prod. Corp. v. Alliance Res. Corp., 509 U.S. 443 (1993). For a discussion of the Supreme Court's infidelity to precedent in this context, see Posting of Dan Markel to PrawfsBlawg, Philip Morris: Up in Smoke?, http://prawfsblawg.blogs.com/ prawfsblawg/2007/02/philip-morris-u.html Feb. 20, 2007.
    • TXO Prod. Corp. v. Alliance Res. Corp., 509 U.S. 443 (1993). For a discussion of the Supreme Court's infidelity to precedent in this context, see Posting of Dan Markel to PrawfsBlawg, Philip Morris: Up in Smoke?, http://prawfsblawg.blogs.com/ prawfsblawg/2007/02/philip-morris-u.html Feb. 20, 2007.
  • 154
    • 67249122407 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See TXO Prod. Corp., 509 U.S. at 460-62;
    • See TXO Prod. Corp., 509 U.S. at 460-62;
  • 155
    • 67249132158 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also BMW of N. Am., Inc. v. Gore, 517 U.S. 559, 582 n.35 (1996) (indicating, implicidy, that punitive damages awards might be permitted to reflect the harm caused to all in-state purchasers of BMWs and not just the harm caused to the individual plaintiff bringing suit);
    • see also BMW of N. Am., Inc. v. Gore, 517 U.S. 559, 582 n.35 (1996) (indicating, implicidy, that punitive damages awards might be permitted to reflect the harm caused to all in-state purchasers of BMWs and not just the harm caused to the individual plaintiff bringing suit);
  • 156
    • 67249105118 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kirkland v. Midland Mortgage Co., 243 F.3d 1277, 1280 (11th Cir. 2001) ([P]unitive damages... [are] measured to reflect, not the wrong done to a single individual, but the wrongfulness of the conduct as a whole.).
    • Kirkland v. Midland Mortgage Co., 243 F.3d 1277, 1280 (11th Cir. 2001) ("[P]unitive damages... [are] measured to reflect, not the wrong done to a single individual, but the wrongfulness of the conduct as a whole.").
  • 157
    • 84868973841 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Philip Morris USA v. Williams, 549 U.S. 346, 353-54 (2007). The jury had awarded the decedent's wife $21,000 in economic compensatory damages, $800,000 in noneconomic compensatory damages, and $79.5 million in punitive damages.
    • Philip Morris USA v. Williams, 549 U.S. 346, 353-54 (2007). The jury had awarded the decedent's wife $21,000 in economic compensatory damages, $800,000 in noneconomic compensatory damages, and $79.5 million in punitive damages.
  • 158
    • 67249139063 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 350. Recendy, on remand from the U.S. Supreme Court, the Supreme Court of Oregon upheld the jury verdict, claiming that there was an adequate and independent state ground for the decision.
    • Id. at 350. Recendy, on remand from the U.S. Supreme Court, the Supreme Court of Oregon upheld the jury verdict, claiming that there was an adequate and independent state ground for the decision.
  • 159
    • 67249112777 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Williams v. Philip Morris Inc., 176 P.3d 1255, 1260-61 (Or. 2008). Subsequendy, the United States Supreme Court agreed, once again, to rehear an appeal brought by Philip Morris-but only on the issue of whether the Oregon Supreme Court failed to abide by the instructions of the remand, not whether the punitive damages in the case were constitutionally excessive. Philip Morris USA Inc. v. Williams, 128 S. Ct. 2904 (2008). The Supreme Court, however, recendy announced that its grant of certiorari on this issue was improvidendy granted, leaving the decision by the Oregon courts to stand. Philip Morris USA Inc. v. Williams, No. 07-1216, slip op. U.S. Mar. 31, 2009.
    • See Williams v. Philip Morris Inc., 176 P.3d 1255, 1260-61 (Or. 2008). Subsequendy, the United States Supreme Court agreed, once again, to rehear an appeal brought by Philip Morris-but only on the issue of whether the Oregon Supreme Court failed to abide by the instructions of the remand, not whether the punitive damages in the case were constitutionally excessive. Philip Morris USA Inc. v. Williams, 128 S. Ct. 2904 (2008). The Supreme Court, however, recendy announced that its grant of certiorari on this issue was improvidendy granted, leaving the decision by the Oregon courts to stand. Philip Morris USA Inc. v. Williams, No. 07-1216, slip op. U.S. Mar. 31, 2009.
  • 160
    • 67249100457 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • By total cost internalization, I mean the full scope of harm caused by a defendant's wrongdoing, and not just the harm caused to the plaintiff in the instant litigation.
    • By "total cost internalization," I mean the full scope of harm caused by a defendant's wrongdoing, and not just the harm caused to the plaintiff in the instant litigation.
  • 161
    • 67249130442 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Colby, supra note 5, passim
    • See Colby, supra note 5, passim.
  • 162
    • 67249134143 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 467-79. Because cost internalization refers to a different kind of deterrence (optimal) than the one probably intended under the Court's pronouncements (complete deterrence), Colby's conclusion is plausible as a matter of theory and logic. But because I think that this conclusion is realistically at odds with the gravamen of the Philip Morris decision, I doubt that the Philip Morris Court meant that one could pursue statewide cost internalization with little to no constitutional oversight, for reasons I explain shortiy.
    • Id. at 467-79. Because cost internalization refers to a different kind of deterrence (optimal) than the one probably intended under the Court's pronouncements (complete deterrence), Colby's conclusion is plausible as a matter of theory and logic. But because I think that this conclusion is realistically at odds with the gravamen of the Philip Morris decision, I doubt that the Philip Morris Court meant that one could pursue statewide cost internalization with little to no constitutional oversight, for reasons I explain shortiy.
  • 163
    • 67249114947 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 476 (Williams does not stand in the way of implementing an extracompensatory remedy that seeks optimal deterrence.). My sense is that Professor Sharkey's social-damages proposal would similarly seek to restrain the reach of Philip Morris so that it would not apply to nonpunitive extracompensatory damages.
    • See id. at 476 ("Williams does not stand in the way of implementing an extracompensatory remedy that seeks optimal deterrence."). My sense is that Professor Sharkey's social-damages proposal would similarly seek to restrain the reach of Philip Morris so that it would not apply to nonpunitive extracompensatory damages.
  • 164
    • 67249109695 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Professor Colby posits that a public interest in retributive justice cannot constitutionally be pursued outside the criminal law because of the absence of constitutional criminal procedural safeguards in civil suits. Id. at 440-57. For reasons I will explain in Part III, I find this view to be mistaken
    • Professor Colby posits that a public interest in retributive justice cannot constitutionally be pursued outside the criminal law because of the absence of constitutional criminal procedural safeguards in civil suits. Id. at 440-57. For reasons I will explain in Part III, I find this view to be mistaken.
  • 165
    • 67249104290 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Unsurprisingly, other scholars supportive of cost internalization damages have also suggested that the Supreme Court's Due Process jurisprudence may not apply in its entirety to nonpunitive damages designed simply to compensate society for various harms to nonparties within state lines. See, e.g., Sharkey, supra note 5, at 428-33 (rejecting the argument that due process extraterritoriality and multiple-punishment concerns would prevent the implementation of a societal-damages scheme);
    • Unsurprisingly, other scholars supportive of cost internalization damages have also suggested that the Supreme Court's Due Process jurisprudence may not apply in its entirety to nonpunitive damages designed simply to compensate society for various harms to nonparties within state lines. See, e.g., Sharkey, supra note 5, at 428-33 (rejecting the argument that due process extraterritoriality and multiple-punishment concerns would prevent the implementation of a societal-damages scheme);
  • 166
    • 67249160839 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ciraolo v. City of N.Y., 216 F.3d 236, 246 n.8 (2d Cir. 2000) (Calabresi, J., concurring) (suggesting by implication that, in contrast to truly punitive damages, socially compensatory damages do not require additional procedural protections).
    • Ciraolo v. City of N.Y., 216 F.3d 236, 246 n.8 (2d Cir. 2000) (Calabresi, J., concurring) (suggesting by implication that, in contrast to truly punitive damages, socially compensatory damages do not require additional procedural protections).
  • 167
    • 67249122414 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 543 U.S. 220 2005
    • 543 U.S. 220 (2005).
  • 168
    • 33646700246 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Michael W. McConnell, The Booker Mess, 83 DENV. U. L. REV. 665 (2006) (discussing the doctrinal chaos embedded in Booker's two separate opinions).
    • See Michael W. McConnell, The Booker Mess, 83 DENV. U. L. REV. 665 (2006) (discussing the doctrinal chaos embedded in Booker's two separate opinions).
  • 169
    • 67249133245 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. BMW of N. Am., Inc. v. Gore, 517 U.S. 559, 592-94 (1996) (Breyer, J., concurring) (discussing the use of a multiplier as a potentially constitutionally plausible limit on punitive damages).
    • Cf. BMW of N. Am., Inc. v. Gore, 517 U.S. 559, 592-94 (1996) (Breyer, J., concurring) (discussing the use of a multiplier as a potentially constitutionally plausible limit on punitive damages).
  • 170
    • 67249144116 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., State Farm Mut. Auto. Ins. Co. v. Campbell, 538 U.S. 408, 422 (2003) (A basic principle of federalism is that each State may make its own reasoned judgment about what conduct is permitted or proscribed within its borders, and each State alone can determine what measure of punishment, if any, to impose on a defendant who acts within its jurisdiction.).
    • See, e.g., State Farm Mut. Auto. Ins. Co. v. Campbell, 538 U.S. 408, 422 (2003) ("A basic principle of federalism is that each State may make its own reasoned judgment about what conduct is permitted or proscribed within its borders, and each State alone can determine what measure of punishment, if any, to impose on a defendant who acts within its jurisdiction.").
  • 171
    • 67249122413 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I reiterate that I don't have a dog in this particular fight; if it turns out that Professor Colby's reading of cost internalization after Philip Morris is correct, a view which seems similar to Professor Sharkey's view articulated pre-Philip Morris, then I would be happy to have the jury instructions and potentially the procedural safeguards dealing with cost internalization adjusted accordingly.
    • I reiterate that I don't have a dog in this particular fight; if it turns out that Professor Colby's reading of cost internalization after Philip Morris is correct, a view which seems similar to Professor Sharkey's view articulated pre-Philip Morris, then I would be happy to have the jury instructions and potentially the procedural safeguards dealing with cost internalization adjusted accordingly.
  • 172
    • 67249147861 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cooper Indus., Inc. v. Leatherman Tool Group, Inc., 532 U.S. 424, 432-36 (2001).
    • Cooper Indus., Inc. v. Leatherman Tool Group, Inc., 532 U.S. 424, 432-36 (2001).
  • 173
    • 67249110092 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Gore, 517 U.S. at 592-94 (Breyer, J., concurring) (alluding to the possibility of more deferential review of damages designed to perform a constraining role of cost internalization);
    • Cf. Gore, 517 U.S. at 592-94 (Breyer, J., concurring) (alluding to the possibility of "more deferential review" of damages designed to perform a "constraining" role of cost internalization);
  • 174
    • 67249089047 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sharkey, supra note 5, at 446 (suggesting deferential review for compensatory societal damages but stringent de novo review for 'morally'-based retributive 'punitive' damages, I agree with Sharkey's endorsement of deferential review for cost internalization, but I think that it is important to further decouple review of victim vindication from review of the public retributive function. I say more about that infra subsection III.B.2. Also, since Sharkey's proposal is for total cost internalization, whereas mine permits only what I might call Philip Moms-compatible cost internalization, I think that deferring to the jury for these damages is a bit easier to justify because there are fewer challenges to jury competence when juries are limited to the inquiry of the likelihood that the defendant would have evaded compensation to the plaintiff (s) /victim (s) only
    • Sharkey, supra note 5, at 446 (suggesting deferential review for compensatory societal damages but stringent de novo review for "'morally'-based retributive 'punitive' damages"). I agree with Sharkey's endorsement of deferential review for cost internalization, but I think that it is important to further decouple review of victim vindication from review of the public retributive function. I say more about that infra subsection III.B.2. Also, since Sharkey's proposal is for "total cost internalization," whereas mine permits only what I might call Philip Moms-compatible cost internalization, I think that deferring to the jury for these damages is a bit easier to justify because there are fewer challenges to jury competence when juries are limited to the inquiry of the likelihood that the defendant would have evaded compensation to the plaintiff (s) /victim (s) only.
  • 176
    • 67249108817 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Galligan, supra note 5, at 140-41 (discussing die potential use of placing societal compensatory damages in a public fund) ;
    • See Galligan, supra note 5, at 140-41 (discussing die potential use of placing "societal compensatory damages" in a public fund) ;
  • 177
    • 67249120261 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also Sharkey, supra note 5, at 402 (suggesting the possibility of using augmented damages to establish a fund, for the benefit of nonparties to the case, to offset the type of harm at issue in the case);
    • see also Sharkey, supra note 5, at 402 (suggesting the possibility of using "augmented damages" to establish a fund, for the benefit of nonparties to the case, "to offset the type of harm at issue in the case");
  • 178
    • 67249146186 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • id. at 392 (Societal damages, as envisioned in this Article, would redress the harms inflicted by the defendant upon parties not before the court. (emphasis added)).
    • id. at 392 ("Societal damages, as envisioned in this Article, would redress the harms inflicted by the defendant upon parties not before the court." (emphasis added)).
  • 179
    • 67249106850 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Theoretically, cost internalization advocates might encourage a cost internalization strategy that avoids conferring upon a plaintiff a monopoly to seek recourse or settle. In other words, where underdeterrence is a concern because of victims who fail to bring sufficient cases, one might want to permit a private attorney general (or a public agency) to ensure that the defendant fully internalizes the costs of tortious conduct that a victim decides not to pursue (to the full extent, The same desire to decouple deterrence from compensation might be true where one is concerned about overcompensation to plaintiffs or insufficient precautions taken by victim-plaintiffs. For examples of arguments in favor of decoupling compensatory damages awarded to plaintiffs from deterrence damages paid by defendants, see A. Mitchell Polinsky & Yeon-Koo Che, Decoupling Liability: Optimal Incentives for Care and Litigation, 22 RANDJ. ECON. 562 1991
    • Theoretically, cost internalization advocates might encourage a cost internalization strategy that avoids conferring upon a plaintiff a monopoly to seek recourse or settle. In other words, where underdeterrence is a concern because of victims who fail to bring sufficient cases, one might want to permit a private attorney general (or a public agency) to ensure that the defendant fully internalizes the costs of tortious conduct that a victim decides not to pursue (to the full extent). The same desire to decouple deterrence from compensation might be true where one is concerned about overcompensation to plaintiffs or insufficient precautions taken by victim-plaintiffs. For examples of arguments in favor of decoupling compensatory damages awarded to plaintiffs from deterrence damages paid by defendants, see A. Mitchell Polinsky & Yeon-Koo Che, Decoupling Liability: Optimal Incentives for Care and Litigation, 22 RANDJ. ECON. 562 (1991),
  • 180
    • 0036993917 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Decoupling Deterrence and Compensation Functions in Mass Tort Class Actions for Future Loss, 88
    • and David Rosenberg, Decoupling Deterrence and Compensation Functions in Mass Tort Class Actions for Future Loss, 88 VA. L. REV. 1871, 1873-74 (2002).
    • (2002) VA. L. REV. 1871 , pp. 1873-1874
    • Rosenberg, D.1
  • 181
    • 67249145728 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Polinsky & Shavell, supra note 5, app. (detailing model jury instructions that contend that the amount of cost internalization damages should offset the amount of damages for the purposes of retribution).
    • See Polinsky & Shavell, supra note 5, app. (detailing model jury instructions that contend that the amount of cost internalization damages should offset the amount of damages for the purposes of retribution).
  • 182
    • 67249127172 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 906 (That a defendant's conduct can be described as reprehensible is in itself irrelevant. Rather, the focus in determining punitive damages should be on the injurer's chance of escaping liability.).
    • See id. at 906 ("That a defendant's conduct can be described as reprehensible is in itself irrelevant. Rather, the focus in determining punitive damages should be on the injurer's chance of escaping liability.").
  • 183
    • 67249144526 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Ciraolo v. City of N.Y, 216 F.3d 236, 246 (2d Cir. 2000) (Calabresi, J., concurring) (But a separate award of punitive damages would be allowed only in cases where the defendant's conduct was sufficiendy reprehensible to deserve punishmentapart from whatever assessment was required to compensate the individual victim or society as a whole. (emphasis omitted)).
    • Cf. Ciraolo v. City of N.Y, 216 F.3d 236, 246 (2d Cir. 2000) (Calabresi, J., concurring) ("But a separate award of punitive damages would be allowed only in cases where the defendant's conduct was sufficiendy reprehensible to deserve punishmentapart from whatever assessment was required to compensate the individual victim or society as a whole." (emphasis omitted)).
  • 184
    • 67249165486 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • By respecting the distinctive values associated with retributive justice and cost internalization, the proposal here departs from those of both Galanter & Luban and Polinsky & Shavell. See Galanter & Luban, supra note 3, at 1451 (arguing that decoupling punitive awards and moral judgments simply misses the point);
    • By respecting the distinctive values associated with retributive justice and cost internalization, the proposal here departs from those of both Galanter & Luban and Polinsky & Shavell. See Galanter & Luban, supra note 3, at 1451 (arguing that decoupling punitive awards and moral judgments "simply misses the point");
  • 185
    • 67249092596 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Polinsky & Shavell, supra note 5, app. (presenting model jury instructions that advocate the subtraction of cost internalization damages from the amount of damages meant to achieve retributive punishment).
    • Polinsky & Shavell, supra note 5, app. (presenting model jury instructions that advocate the subtraction of cost internalization damages from the amount of damages meant to achieve retributive punishment).
  • 186
    • 34548243816 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Section II, B for further discussion on the intersection of deterrence damages and aggravated damages
    • See infra Section II, B for further discussion on the intersection of deterrence damages and aggravated damages.
    • See infra
  • 187
    • 67249098677 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Economists disagree about the precise architecture for punitive damages. Compare Robert D. Cooter, Economic Analysis of Punitive Damages, 56 S. CAL. L. REV. 79 (1982) (arguing that punitive damages should be used only in cases of gross, inten-tional fault and should be determined based on the costs of compliance or benefits of noncompliance that motivated the violation), with Polinsky and Shavell, supra note 5 (advocating the multiplier approach).
    • Economists disagree about the precise architecture for punitive damages. Compare Robert D. Cooter, Economic Analysis of Punitive Damages, 56 S. CAL. L. REV. 79 (1982) (arguing that punitive damages should be used only in cases of gross, inten-tional fault and should be determined based on the costs of compliance or benefits of noncompliance that motivated the violation), with Polinsky and Shavell, supra note 5 (advocating the multiplier approach).
  • 189
    • 67249086433 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • My inspiration for this term came from two commonwealth scholars. See Chapman & Trebilcock, supra note 5, at 746-47 (discussing an English case, Rookes v. Barnard, [1964] All E.R. 367, 407 (Eng.), that distinguished aggravated from punitive damages).
    • My inspiration for this term came from two commonwealth scholars. See Chapman & Trebilcock, supra note 5, at 746-47 (discussing an English case, Rookes v. Barnard, [1964] All E.R. 367, 407 (Eng.), that distinguished aggravated from punitive damages).
  • 190
    • 67249161473 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I am not claiming that my proposed use of the term aggravated damages captures historical, extant, or emerging practices in Canadian and English cases. However, for illuminating descriptions of aggravated damages in comparative perspective, see Anthony J. Sebok & Vanessa Wilcox, Aggravated Damages, in PUNITIVE DAMAGES (Helmut Koziol & Vanessa Wilcox eds., forthcoming 2009).
    • I am not claiming that my proposed use of the term "aggravated damages" captures historical, extant, or emerging practices in Canadian and English cases. However, for illuminating descriptions of aggravated damages in comparative perspective, see Anthony J. Sebok & Vanessa Wilcox, Aggravated Damages, in PUNITIVE DAMAGES (Helmut Koziol & Vanessa Wilcox eds., forthcoming 2009).
  • 191
    • 67249142327 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sebok, supra note 15, at 204-05 (emphasis added).
    • Sebok, supra note 15, at 204-05 (emphasis added).
  • 192
    • 67249147029 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra subsection I.A.2.
    • See supra subsection I.A.2.
  • 193
    • 67249150258 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sebok, supra note 5, at 1023-29
    • Sebok, supra note 5, at 1023-29.
  • 194
    • 67249129573 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Colby, supra note 5, at 423-40 (arguing that punitive damages are best understood as a form of punishment for private wrongs).
    • See Colby, supra note 5, at 423-40 (arguing that punitive damages are best understood as a form of punishment for "private wrongs").
  • 195
    • 67249123832 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For example, as a descriptive matter, Sebok's account acknowledges the difficulty of incorporating the State Farm Court's presumptive single-digit ratio into his theory.
    • For example, as a descriptive matter, Sebok's account acknowledges the difficulty of incorporating the State Farm Court's presumptive single-digit ratio into his theory.
  • 196
    • 67249152490 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Sebok, supra note 5, at 1029-36 (criticizing Justice Kennedy's opinion that [s] ingle-digit multipliers are more likely to comport with due process, State Farm Mut. Auto. Ins. Co. v. Campbell, 538 U.S. 408, 425 (2003), as lacking a principled foundation, as justified merely by a desire for simplicity, and as impossible to square with a post-Lochner theory of due process).
    • See Sebok, supra note 5, at 1029-36 (criticizing Justice Kennedy's opinion that "[s] ingle-digit multipliers are more likely to comport with due process," State Farm Mut. Auto. Ins. Co. v. Campbell, 538 U.S. 408, 425 (2003), as lacking a "principled foundation," as justified merely by a desire for simplicity, and as "impossible to square with a post-Lochner theory of due process").
  • 197
    • 67249144528 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Of course, to the extent that victim vindication models do supplement insufficient compensatory damages, punitive damages are not the appropriate way to remedy these problems; instead, we should address the problematic rules of lawyer compensation. See Kelly, supra note 32, at 1441 arguing that punitive damages merely dodge problems with class actions and other difficulties of litigation, while also undermin[ing] efforts to correct these problems
    • Of course, to the extent that victim vindication models do supplement insufficient compensatory damages, punitive damages are not the appropriate way to remedy these problems; instead, we should address the problematic rules of lawyer compensation. See Kelly, supra note 32, at 1441 (arguing that punitive damages merely "dodge" problems with class actions and other difficulties of litigation, while also "undermin[ing] efforts to correct these problems").
  • 198
    • 67249148259 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Indeed, scholars like Arthur Ripstein, Sebok, and now Colby specifically reject the equation between vindicating the plaintiff's interest in dignity repair and compensating the plaintiff for the injury to her dignity, claiming that dignity is not something that is compensable. See, e.g., Colby, supra note 5, at 435-36, 436 n.187 (citing Ripstein and Sebok with approval).
    • Indeed, scholars like Arthur Ripstein, Sebok, and now Colby specifically reject the equation between "vindicating" the plaintiff's interest in dignity repair and "compensating" the plaintiff for the injury to her dignity, claiming that dignity is not something that is "compensable." See, e.g., Colby, supra note 5, at 435-36, 436 n.187 (citing Ripstein and Sebok with approval).
  • 199
    • 67249110558 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • But see Ernest J. Weinrib, Punishment and Disgorgement as Contract Remedies, 78 CHI.-KENT L. REV. 55, 91 (2003) (The courts properly regard such [aggravated] damages as compensatory rather than punitive, since they repair a loss, albeit an intangible one.).
    • But see Ernest J. Weinrib, Punishment and Disgorgement as Contract Remedies, 78 CHI.-KENT L. REV. 55, 91 (2003) ("The courts properly regard such [aggravated] damages as compensatory rather than punitive, since they repair a loss, albeit an intangible one.").
  • 200
    • 67249092300 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • explaining the differences between retributive justice and revenge, See, at
    • See Markel, Retributive Damages, supra note 1, at 270-71 (explaining the differences between retributive justice and revenge).
    • Retributive Damages, supra note , vol.1 , pp. 270-271
    • Markel1
  • 201
    • 67249119163 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Circles-Restorative Justice, http://www. restorativejustice.org/intro/ tutorial/processes/circles (last visited Mar. 15, 2009) (explaining the use of healing circles as a way to address harm to a victim caused by an offender);
    • See, e.g., Circles-Restorative Justice, http://www. restorativejustice.org/intro/ tutorial/processes/circles (last visited Mar. 15, 2009) (explaining the use of "healing circles" as a way to address harm to a victim caused by an offender);
  • 202
    • 34547795153 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Wrong Turns on the Road to Alternative Sanctions: Reflections on the Future of Shaming Punishments and Restorative Justice, 85
    • see also
    • see also Dan Markel, Wrong Turns on the Road to Alternative Sanctions: Reflections on the Future of Shaming Punishments and Restorative Justice, 85 TEX. L. REV. 1385 (2007).
    • (2007) TEX. L. REV , vol.1385
    • Markel, D.1
  • 203
    • 67249148676 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In the successor article to this one, Punitive Damages and Complex Litigation, supra note 9, I discuss the intelligibility of punishing a corporation for its misconduct. As a result, it might seem inconsistent to deny corporations access to dignity-based aggravated damages while at the same time thinking that they have sufficient independent identity to warrant retributive condemnation. I think that one can reduce this inconsistency by looking at the nature of the misconduct: for example, it might be that the insult to dignity is defamation of the corporate plaintiff e.g, the managers of X Corporation intentionally sell spoiled food, There, the misconduct injures the dignity of the entity as a team, in which case the team arguably should be able to collect aggravated damages on top of other losses
    • In the successor article to this one, Punitive Damages and Complex Litigation, supra note 9, I discuss the intelligibility of punishing a corporation for its misconduct. As a result, it might seem inconsistent to deny corporations access to dignity-based aggravated damages while at the same time thinking that they have sufficient independent identity to warrant retributive condemnation. I think that one can reduce this inconsistency by looking at the nature of the misconduct: for example, it might be that the insult to dignity is defamation of the corporate plaintiff (e.g., "the managers of X Corporation intentionally sell spoiled food"). There, the misconduct injures the dignity of the entity as a team, in which case the team arguably should be able to collect aggravated damages on top of other losses.
  • 204
    • 67249107953 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I therefore find myself likely to disagree with those jurisdictions that have prohibited juries from finding out what portion of the extracompensatory damages goes to the state on account that such information will invariably and unduly inflate the amount of damages awarded. See Sharkey, supra note 5, at 438-39 & nn.358-60 (citing cases and statutes establishing that jurors are not informed of the division of extracompensatory damages). At least under my scheme, however, there are a number of robust safeguards and review mechanisms to ensure that this undue inflation of damages is less likely to occur. I share Professor Sharkey's skepticism toward the rationales for keeping juries in the dark about allocation.
    • I therefore find myself likely to disagree with those jurisdictions that have prohibited juries from finding out what portion of the extracompensatory damages goes to the state on account that such information will invariably and unduly inflate the amount of damages awarded. See Sharkey, supra note 5, at 438-39 & nn.358-60 (citing cases and statutes establishing that jurors are not informed of the division of extracompensatory damages). At least under my scheme, however, there are a number of robust safeguards and review mechanisms to ensure that this undue inflation of damages is less likely to occur. I share Professor Sharkey's skepticism toward the rationales for keeping juries in the dark about allocation.
  • 205
    • 67249087328 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 439-40, 440 n.366
    • See id. at 439-40, 440 n.366
  • 206
    • 0032867766 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Goal Conflict in Juror Assessments of Compensatory and Punitive Damages, 23
    • finding both that jurors were actually more likely to award punitive damages when those damages went directiy to plaintiffs, rather than to the government, and that the amount of damages was unaffected by the recipient of the award, citing
    • (citing Michelle Chernikoff Anderson & Robert J. MacCoun, Goal Conflict in Juror Assessments of Compensatory and Punitive Damages, 23 LAW & HUM. BEHAV. 313, 320-22 (1999) (finding both that jurors were actually more likely to award punitive damages when those damages went directiy to plaintiffs, rather than to the government, and that the amount of damages was unaffected by the recipient of the award) ).
    • (1999) LAW & HUM. BEHAV , vol.313 , pp. 320-322
    • Chernikoff Anderson, M.1    MacCoun, R.J.2
  • 207
    • 67249132157 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Cooper Indus., Inc. v. Leatherman Tool Group, Inc., 532 U.S. 424, 436 (2001) (requiring de novo review of the amount of punitive damages awarded in federal cases).
    • See Cooper Indus., Inc. v. Leatherman Tool Group, Inc., 532 U.S. 424, 436 (2001) (requiring de novo review of the amount of punitive damages awarded in federal cases).
  • 208
    • 67249120696 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • And, of course, legislatures may decide to impose caps or multiplier limits on aggravated damages in the way that some jurisdictions do for other damages. See Rustad, supra note 29, at 1300 (listing different types of tort reform).
    • And, of course, legislatures may decide to impose caps or multiplier limits on aggravated damages in the way that some jurisdictions do for other damages. See Rustad, supra note 29, at 1300 (listing different types of "tort reform").
  • 209
    • 67249111071 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note 1, at, providing a critique of the use of caps and multipliers in various cases
    • But see Markel, Retributive Damages, supra note 1, at 330-32 (providing a critique of the use of caps and multipliers in various cases).
    • But see Markel, Retributive Damages, supra , pp. 330-332
  • 210
    • 67249132631 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This limited use of the evidence of wrongs to other persons makes sense in situations where the plaintiff needs to show that the misconduct in question was not an accident or mistake, but rather a malicious denigration of the plaintiff's dignity interests
    • This limited use of the evidence of wrongs to other persons makes sense in situations where the plaintiff needs to show that the misconduct in question was not an accident or mistake, but rather a malicious denigration of the plaintiff's dignity interests.
  • 211
    • 67249151205 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Baker, 128
    • See Exxon Shipping Co. v
    • See Exxon Shipping Co. v. Baker, 128 S. Ct. 2605, 2614 2008.
    • (2008) S. Ct , vol.2605 , pp. 2614
  • 212
    • 67249133244 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See In re Exxon Valdez, 296 F. Supp. 2d 1071, 1077 (D. Alaska 2004) (Exxon officials knew that it was dangerous to have a captain with an alcohol problem commanding a supertanker... [and] knew that carrying huge of crude oil through Prince William Sound was a dangerous business, yet they knowingly permitted a relapsed alcoholic to direct the operation of the Exxon Valdez... .), vacated and remanded, 490 F.3d 1066 (2007), vacated and remanded sub nom., Exxon Shipping Co. v. Baker, 128 S. Ct. 2605 (2008).
    • See In re Exxon Valdez, 296 F. Supp. 2d 1071, 1077 (D. Alaska 2004) ("Exxon officials knew that it was dangerous to have a captain with an alcohol problem commanding a supertanker... [and] knew that carrying huge volumes of crude oil through Prince William Sound was a dangerous business, yet they knowingly permitted a relapsed alcoholic to direct the operation of the Exxon Valdez... ."), vacated and remanded, 490 F.3d 1066 (2007), vacated and remanded sub nom., Exxon Shipping Co. v. Baker, 128 S. Ct. 2605 (2008).
  • 213
    • 67249093859 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • There are some interesting questions relating to time and punishment. The penalty could be based on the net financial condition of the individual/entity at the time of the misconduct (adjusted for inflation) in order to deter the defendant from trying to reengineer its finances to its apparent detriment at adjudication. The goal behind benchmarking the defendant's value or financial condition this way is to ensure that the defendant is not penalized for growth or wealth independent of the tort. On the other hand, if there is a reason to suspect that the defendant's growth or current wealth is driven by the results of the underlying misconduct-say a person profits from wrongfully accessing another's trade secrets-that would be a good reason for instead using the defendant's financial condition at the time of adjudication, assuming it is higher than at the time of the commission of the tort
    • There are some interesting questions relating to time and punishment. The penalty could be based on the net financial condition of the individual/entity at the time of the misconduct (adjusted for inflation) in order to deter the defendant from trying to reengineer its finances to its apparent detriment at adjudication. The goal behind benchmarking the defendant's value or financial condition this way is to ensure that the defendant is not penalized for growth or wealth independent of the tort. On the other hand, if there is a reason to suspect that the defendant's growth or current wealth is driven by the results of the underlying misconduct-say a person profits from wrongfully accessing another's trade secrets-that would be a good reason for instead using the defendant's financial condition at the time of adjudication, assuming it is higher than at the time of the commission of the tort.
  • 215
    • 67249091471 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • BMW of N. Am., Inc. v. Gore, 517 U.S. 559, 563-64 1996.
    • BMW of N. Am., Inc. v. Gore, 517 U.S. 559, 563-64 1996.
  • 216
    • 67249138808 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 570-73.
    • See id. at 570-73.
  • 217
    • 67249127621 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supa subsection II.B.2.
    • See supa subsection II.B.2.
  • 218
    • 67249095108 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. State Farm Mut. Auto. Ins. Co. v. Campbell, 538 U.S. 408, 433-43 (2003) (Ginsburg, J., dissenting) (discussing how the defendant targeted the 'weakest of the herd'-'the elderly, the poor, and other consumers who are ... most vulnerable to trickery and deceit,' including persons like the Campbells and those unlikely to defend themselves and therefore unlikely to take action that would force the defendant to compensate them).
    • Cf. State Farm Mut. Auto. Ins. Co. v. Campbell, 538 U.S. 408, 433-43 (2003) (Ginsburg, J., dissenting) (discussing how the defendant targeted the '"weakest of the herd'-'the elderly, the poor, and other consumers who are ... most vulnerable to trickery and deceit,'" including persons like the Campbells and those "unlikely to defend themselves" and therefore unlikely to take action that would force the defendant to compensate them).
  • 219
    • 67249114945 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In Pacific Mutual Life Insurance Co. v. Haslip, 499 U.S. 1, 12-14 (1991, the defendant was vicariously liable for the embezzlement of plaintiffs' insurance payments, but the company also was on notice that it had a rogue agent, much like in Exxon. The defendants in Haslip and Exxon could plausibly be said to have exercised manifesdy insufficient care to ferret out misconduct by their agents. However, those cases would warrant lower reprehensibility scores than the defendants in TXO Production Corp. v. Alliance Resources Corp, 509 U.S. 443 1993, and State Farm, where the wrongs by the tortfeasors were purposeful and deceitful. Those four cases involved economic torts, however, and should be considered less reprehensible than the misconduct perpetrated by the defendant in Philip Morris, where the defendant's outrageous misconduct years ago effectively amounted to mass manslaughter
    • In Pacific Mutual Life Insurance Co. v. Haslip, 499 U.S. 1, 12-14 (1991), the defendant was vicariously liable for the embezzlement of plaintiffs' insurance payments, but the company also was on notice that it had a rogue agent, much like in Exxon. The defendants in Haslip and Exxon could plausibly be said to have exercised manifesdy insufficient care to ferret out misconduct by their agents. However, those cases would warrant lower reprehensibility scores than the defendants in TXO Production Corp. v. Alliance Resources Corp., 509 U.S. 443 (1993), and State Farm, where the wrongs by the tortfeasors were purposeful and deceitful. Those four cases involved economic torts, however, and should be considered less reprehensible than the misconduct perpetrated by the defendant in Philip Morris, where the defendant's outrageous misconduct years ago effectively amounted to mass manslaughter.
  • 220
    • 56849130970 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • text accompanying notes 55-57 proposing that states create guidelines that would allow juries to measure reprehensibility more objectively
    • See supra text accompanying notes 55-57 (proposing that states create guidelines that would allow juries to measure reprehensibility more objectively).
    • See supra
  • 221
    • 67249123237 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a discussion of safeguards primarily related to wrongs involving torts and complex litigation, see Markel, Punitive Damages, supra note 9
    • For a discussion of safeguards primarily related to wrongs involving torts and complex litigation, see Markel, Punitive Damages, supra note 9.
  • 222
    • 67249114946 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Galanter & Luban, supra note 3, at 1457-58
    • Galanter & Luban, supra note 3, at 1457-58.
  • 223
    • 67249152835 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1457
    • Id. at 1457.
  • 224
    • 67249086887 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • at
    • Id. at 1457-58.
  • 225
    • 67249160267 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Grass, note 7 concluding that punitive damages are penal in nature and therefore are essentially criminal law sanctions
    • See Grass, supra note 7 (concluding that punitive damages are penal in nature and therefore are essentially criminal law sanctions);
    • supra
  • 226
    • 47249091469 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note 12 arguing that the seeking of punitive damages is, effect, a state function that demands constitutional protections
    • Redish & Mathews, supra note 12 (arguing that the seeking of punitive damages is, in effect, a state function that demands constitutional protections);
    • supra
    • Redish1    Mathews2
  • 227
    • 67249161472 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Wheeler, supra note 7 (contending that where the government authorizes private individuals to seek damages for the purposes of punishment-punitive damages-the Constitution requires that criminal law constitutional protections apply);
    • Wheeler, supra note 7 (contending that where the government authorizes private individuals to seek damages for the purposes of punishment-punitive damages-the Constitution requires that criminal law constitutional protections apply);
  • 228
    • 67249104289 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also Colby, supra note 7, at 606 n.73 (providing citations to courts and commentators noting that defendants subject to punitive damages lack the protections provided in criminal trials).
    • see also Colby, supra note 7, at 606 n.73 (providing citations to courts and commentators noting that defendants subject to punitive damages lack the protections provided in criminal trials).
  • 229
    • 67249129572 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Colby, supra note 5, at 415-16
    • Colby, supra note 5, at 415-16.
  • 230
    • 67249111070 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 396
    • Id. at 396.
  • 231
    • 67249113210 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In this respect, Professor Colby is basically embracing the approach endorsed by Professor Sebok, supra note 5
    • In this respect, Professor Colby is basically embracing the approach endorsed by Professor Sebok, supra note 5.
  • 232
    • 67249140741 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Colby, supra note 5, at 396 (Williams thus allows the states to address the underdeterrence concern by implementing the recommendation of law and economics scholars to create a category of extracompensatory damages designed to ensure optimal deterrence.).
    • See Colby, supra note 5, at 396 ("Williams thus allows the states to address the underdeterrence concern by implementing the recommendation of law and economics scholars to create a category of extracompensatory damages designed to ensure optimal deterrence.").
  • 233
    • 67249147027 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Some scholars have questioned whether we in fact need more due process protection for the review of compensatory damages awards. See, e.g, Mark A. Geistfeld, Due Process and the Determination of Pain and Suffering Tort Damages, 55 DEPAUL L. REV. 331 2006, arguing that constitutional due process constraints on punitive damages should also apply to pain and suffering damages
    • Some scholars have questioned whether we in fact need more due process protection for the review of compensatory damages awards. See, e.g., Mark A. Geistfeld, Due Process and the Determination of Pain and Suffering Tort Damages, 55 DEPAUL L. REV. 331 (2006) (arguing that constitutional due process constraints on punitive damages should also apply to pain and suffering damages).
  • 234
    • 67249122820 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Michael P. Allen, The Supreme Court, Punitive Damages and State Sovereignly, 13 GEO. MASON L. REV. 1, 21-25 (2004) (reading State Farm through a federalism lens and finding that the holding rests upon respect for state sovereignty).
    • See Michael P. Allen, The Supreme Court, Punitive Damages and State Sovereignly, 13 GEO. MASON L. REV. 1, 21-25 (2004) (reading State Farm through a federalism lens and finding that the holding rests upon respect for state sovereignty).
  • 235
    • 67249119620 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Colby, supra note 5, at 455-56 n.281.
    • See Colby, supra note 5, at 455-56 n.281.
  • 236
    • 67249102131 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Somewhat relatedly, Professor Romero argues that legislatures should impose limits on all punitive damages. Leo M. Romero, Punitive Damages, Criminal Punishment, and Proportionality: The Importance of Legislative Limits, 41 CONN. L. REV. 109 (2008).
    • Somewhat relatedly, Professor Romero argues that legislatures should impose limits on all punitive damages. Leo M. Romero, Punitive Damages, Criminal Punishment, and Proportionality: The Importance of Legislative Limits, 41 CONN. L. REV. 109 (2008).
  • 237
    • 67249103422 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See note 5, at, describing the ratio rule as regrettable and lacking in principle
    • See Sebok, supra note 5, at 1029 (describing the ratio rule as regrettable and lacking in principle).
    • supra , pp. 1029
    • Sebok1
  • 238
    • 67249130866 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Markel, Retributive Damages, supra note 1, at 290-91 explaining that such income-based practices undermine commitments to human equality
    • See Markel, Retributive Damages, supra note 1, at 290-91 (explaining that such income-based practices undermine commitments to human equality).
  • 239
    • 67249145723 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Geistfeld, supra note 132, at 342 (noting that plaintiffs with similar painand-suffering injuries often are awarded significantly different amounts of damages).
    • See Geistfeld, supra note 132, at 342 (noting that plaintiffs "with similar painand-suffering injuries often are awarded significantly different amounts of damages").
  • 240
    • 67249127619 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For references to other scholars who share my view on Philip Morris's implications, see Colby, supra note 5, at 469 n.337, and sources cited therein.
    • For references to other scholars who share my view on Philip Morris's implications, see Colby, supra note 5, at 469 n.337, and sources cited therein.
  • 241
    • 67249110085 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Specifically I'd imagine that such a reading of Philip Morris would warrant applying the kind of searching appellate review that the Court employed in BMWv. Gore and State Farm, though with less attention to concerns about reprehensibility and more focus on fidelity to the federalism and fair-notice concerns. Colby himself is expressly noncommittal on what constitutional limits would apply to deterrence damages under this scenario.
    • Specifically I'd imagine that such a reading of Philip Morris would warrant applying the kind of searching appellate review that the Court employed in BMWv. Gore and State Farm, though with less attention to concerns about reprehensibility and more focus on fidelity to the federalism and fair-notice concerns. Colby himself is expressly noncommittal on what constitutional limits would apply to deterrence damages under this scenario.
  • 242
    • 67249152069 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 476 n.371.
    • Id. at 476 n.371.
  • 243
    • 67249156387 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • If Professor Sharkey's proposal for nonpunitive com-pensatory societal damages is compatible widi Philip Morris, then it is also a useful place to look for guidance on some of the constitutional issues regarding what I have called deterrence damages. See Sharkey, supra note 5, at 428-40
    • If Professor Sharkey's proposal for nonpunitive com-pensatory societal damages is compatible widi Philip Morris, then it is also a useful place to look for guidance on some of the constitutional issues regarding what I have called deterrence damages. See Sharkey, supra note 5, at 428-40.
  • 244
    • 67249121580 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Colby, supra note 5, at 469
    • Colby, supra note 5, at 469.
  • 245
    • 67249128483 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Galanter & Luban, supra note 3, at 1454-60
    • Galanter & Luban, supra note 3, at 1454-60.
  • 246
    • 34547572622 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See note 5, at, raising the concern that my view of retributive damages basically creates an end-run around the Constitution
    • See Colby, supra note 5, at 445-46 (raising the concern that my view of retributive damages basically creates an end-run around the Constitution).
    • supra , pp. 445-446
    • Colby1
  • 247
    • 67249092296 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Murphy v. Hobbs, 5 P. 119, 121 (Colo. 1884) (criticizing a judge's punitive damages instructions to a jury on the grounds that, inter alia, punishment by fine is inflicted without the defendant being afforded the protections of criminal procedure);
    • See, e.g., Murphy v. Hobbs, 5 P. 119, 121 (Colo. 1884) (criticizing a judge's punitive damages instructions to a jury on the grounds that, inter alia, "punishment by fine is inflicted" without the defendant being afforded the protections of criminal procedure);
  • 248
    • 67249118293 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Spokane Truck & Dray Co. v. Hoefer, 25 P. 1072, 1074 (Wash. 1891) (It seems to us that there are many valid objections to interjecting into a purely civil action the elements of a criminal trial, intermingling into a sort of a medley or legal jumble two distinct systems of judicial procedure.);
    • Spokane Truck & Dray Co. v. Hoefer, 25 P. 1072, 1074 (Wash. 1891) ("It seems to us that there are many valid objections to interjecting into a purely civil action the elements of a criminal trial, intermingling into a sort of a medley or legal jumble two distinct systems of judicial procedure.");
  • 249
    • 84900225389 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note 7 arguing that punitive damages perform the same function as criminal law and therefore demand the same constitutional protections
    • Grass, supra note 7 (arguing that punitive damages perform the same function as criminal law and therefore demand the same constitutional protections);
    • supra
    • Grass1
  • 250
    • 76949104938 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note 7, at, outlining the constitutional provisions suggesting that punitive damages should trigger the protections of criminal procedure
    • Wheeler, supra note 7, at 322-51 (outlining the constitutional provisions suggesting that punitive damages should trigger the protections of criminal procedure).
    • supra , pp. 322-351
    • Wheeler1
  • 251
    • 67249124742 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Cooper Indus., Inc. v. Leatherman Tool Group, Inc., 532 U.S. 424, 432 (2001) (acknowledging that punitive damages have been labeled quasi-criminal (citing Pac. Mut. Life Ins. Co. v. Haslip, 499 U.S. 1, 19 (1991)));
    • See Cooper Indus., Inc. v. Leatherman Tool Group, Inc., 532 U.S. 424, 432 (2001) (acknowledging that punitive damages have been labeled "quasi-criminal" (citing Pac. Mut. Life Ins. Co. v. Haslip, 499 U.S. 1, 19 (1991)));
  • 252
    • 67249136257 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Gertz v. Robert Welch, Inc. 418 U.S. 323, 350 (1974) (stating that punitive damages punish reprehensible conduct and deter its future occurrence).
    • Gertz v. Robert Welch, Inc. 418 U.S. 323, 350 (1974) (stating that punitive damages "punish reprehensible conduct" and "deter its future occurrence").
  • 253
    • 67249094257 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Gertz, 418 U.S. at 350.
    • Gertz, 418 U.S. at 350.
  • 254
    • 67249148675 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Haslip, 499 U.S. at 47-48 (O'Connor, J., dissenting)
    • Haslip, 499 U.S. at 47-48 (O'Connor, J., dissenting)
  • 255
    • 67249152074 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (citing Gertz, 418 U.S. at 350);
    • (citing Gertz, 418 U.S. at 350);
  • 256
    • 67249121967 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also Browning-Ferris Indus, of Vt., Inc. v. Kelco Disposal, Inc., 492 U.S. 257, 275 (1989) ([P]unitive damages are imposed through the aegis of courts and serve to advance governmental interests ....).
    • see also Browning-Ferris Indus, of Vt., Inc. v. Kelco Disposal, Inc., 492 U.S. 257, 275 (1989) ("[P]unitive damages are imposed through the aegis of courts and serve to advance governmental interests ....").
  • 257
    • 67249093016 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Exxon Shipping Co. v. Baker, 128 S. Ct. 2605, 2621 (2008) (The consensus today is that punitives are aimed not at compensation but principally at retribution and deterring harmful conduct.); Philip Morris USA v. Williams, 549 U.S. 346, 352 (2007) (This Court has long made clear that '[p]unitive damages may properly be imposed to further a State's legitimate interests in punishing unlawful conduct and deterring its repetition.' (quoting BMW of N. Am. v. Gore, 517 U.S. 559, 568 (1996))).
    • See Exxon Shipping Co. v. Baker, 128 S. Ct. 2605, 2621 (2008) ("The consensus today is that punitives are aimed not at compensation but principally at retribution and deterring harmful conduct."); Philip Morris USA v. Williams, 549 U.S. 346, 352 (2007) ("This Court has long made clear that '[p]unitive damages may properly be imposed to further a State's legitimate interests in punishing unlawful conduct and deterring its repetition.'" (quoting BMW of N. Am. v. Gore, 517 U.S. 559, 568 (1996))).
  • 258
    • 67249150257 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • After I showed Colby a draft of this paper, he revised his paper, supra note 5, to clarify that punitive damages for public wrongs (i.e, retributive damages) should receive only the amount of procedural protections that criminal fines receive, which is a more nuanced position than the claim that public-minded punitive damages require all procedural safeguards from the criminal context. Importandy, Colby's final position is still different from mine. I see retributive damages as a civil sanction that is qualitatively different from criminal penalties because such damages entail no resulting conviction, less of a stigma, and no intended collateral consequences. Nonetheless, Colby sees such retributive damages as constitutionally equivalent to criminal fines.Significandy, Colby is not alone in claiming that such retributive damages (or publicly minded punitive damages) would likely equate to criminal penalties warranting criminal procedural safeguards
    • After I showed Colby a draft of this paper, he revised his paper,
  • 259
    • 67249133242 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Redish & Mathews, supra note 12, at 20 (Financial penalties imposed for no purpose other than to punish are appropriately categorized as coercive, just as imprisonment is. This conclusion is reinforced by the simple fact that the same special constitutional protections apply in criminal cases seeking only the imposition of financial penalties as apply in cases in which imprisonment is at issue.);
    • See, e.g., Redish & Mathews, supra note 12, at 20 ("Financial penalties imposed for no purpose other than to punish are appropriately categorized as coercive, just as imprisonment is. This conclusion is reinforced by the simple fact that the same special constitutional protections apply in criminal cases seeking only the imposition of financial penalties as apply in cases in which imprisonment is at issue.");
  • 260
    • 67249086432 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Wheeler, supra note 7, at 337 (Either the purpose of the sanction is punitive, in which case all of the procedural safeguards apply, or the purpose is not punitive, in which case none applies.). But these views are, to my mind, incorrect. As illuminated in the text, there is no right to counsel for criminal fines, nor is there a right to a jury trial in that context.
    • Wheeler, supra note 7, at 337 ("Either the purpose of the sanction is punitive, in which case all of the procedural safeguards apply, or the purpose is not punitive, in which case none applies."). But these views are, to my mind, incorrect. As illuminated in the text, there is no right to counsel for criminal fines, nor is there a right to a jury trial in that context.
  • 261
    • 67249115386 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See generally Scott v. Illinois, 440 U.S. 367 (1979) (holding that counsel is only required where actual imprisonment results); Duncan v. Louisiana, 391 U.S. 145, 159 (1968) (holding that a jury trial is not constitutionally required for cases where the maximum penalty is incarceration of less than six months). Moreover, these accounts similarly fail to contemplate the possibility, developed in the text, that retributive damages could serve as a designated civil and intermediate sanction, thus warranting a smaller or otherwise different bundle of safeguards than would exist if criminal fines were applied.
    • See generally Scott v. Illinois, 440 U.S. 367 (1979) (holding that counsel is only required where actual imprisonment results); Duncan v. Louisiana, 391 U.S. 145, 159 (1968) (holding that a jury trial is not constitutionally required for cases where the maximum penalty is incarceration of less than six months). Moreover, these accounts similarly fail to contemplate the possibility, developed in the text, that retributive damages could serve as a designated civil and intermediate sanction, thus warranting a smaller or otherwise different bundle of safeguards than would exist if criminal fines were applied.
  • 262
    • 11144305014 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Some constitutional safeguards may also be scaled to the severity of the misconduct involved. See Eugene Volokh, Crime Severity and Constitutional Line-Drawing, 90 VA. L. REV. 1957 (2004) (outlining potential approaches to balancing the strength of constitutional protections against the crime that the government actor is seeking to prevent).
    • Some constitutional safeguards may also be scaled to the severity of the misconduct involved. See Eugene Volokh, Crime Severity and Constitutional Line-Drawing, 90 VA. L. REV. 1957 (2004) (outlining potential approaches to balancing the strength of constitutional protections against the crime that the government actor is seeking to prevent).
  • 263
    • 84868973838 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See generally 1 WAYNE R. LAFAVE ET AL. CRIMINAI. PROCIEDURE §1.8(e) (3d ed. 2008) (discussing special constitutional rules in the capital punishment context);
    • See generally 1 WAYNE R. LAFAVE ET AL. CRIMINAI. PROCIEDURE §1.8(e) (3d ed. 2008) (discussing special constitutional rules in the capital punishment context);
  • 264
    • 37349050409 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Stuart P. Green, Rationing Criminal Procedure: A Comment on Ashworth and Zedner, 2 CRIM. L. & PHIL. 53, 54 (2008) ([Defendants charged with capital offenses are entitled to additional protections not generally available to defendants in non-capital cases, including a bifurcated trial at which guilt and sentencing are decided separately, special jury se-lection procedures, special rules regarding the introduction of aggravating and mitigating evidence, and an automatic right of appeal.).
    • Stuart P. Green, Rationing Criminal Procedure: A Comment on Ashworth and Zedner, 2 CRIM. L. & PHIL. 53, 54 (2008) ("[Defendants charged with capital offenses are entitled to additional protections not generally available to defendants in non-capital cases, including a bifurcated trial at which guilt and sentencing are decided separately, special jury se-lection procedures, special rules regarding the introduction of aggravating and mitigating evidence, and an automatic right of appeal.").
  • 265
    • 84868993547 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See generally 1 LAFAVE ET AI.., supra note 150, §1.8(c) (discussing special constitutional rules applying only to crimes involving a certain period of time in prison).
    • See generally 1 LAFAVE ET AI.., supra note 150, §1.8(c) (discussing special constitutional rules applying only to crimes involving a certain period of time in prison).
  • 266
    • 67249148258 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Scott, 440 U.S. 367 (holding that defendants may not be imprisoned absent the enjoyment of a right to counsel but that no right to counsel exists for less severe punishments);
    • See Scott, 440 U.S. 367 (holding that defendants may not be imprisoned absent the enjoyment of a right to counsel but that no right to counsel exists for less severe punishments);
  • 267
    • 67249138395 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Callan v. Wilson, 127 U.S. 540 (1888) (guaranteeing a jury trial only for nonpetty criminal offenses);
    • Callan v. Wilson, 127 U.S. 540 (1888) (guaranteeing a jury trial only for nonpetty criminal offenses);
  • 268
    • 67249146596 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Mackin v. United States, 117 U.S. 348, 351 (1885) (requiring a grand jury indictment for crimes punishable by imprisonment);
    • Mackin v. United States, 117 U.S. 348, 351 (1885) (requiring a grand jury indictment for crimes punishable by imprisonment);
  • 269
    • 67249147026 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • LAFAVE ET AI.., supra note 150 (discussing special constitutional rules applying only to crimes involving some time in prison).
    • LAFAVE ET AI.., supra note 150 (discussing special constitutional rules applying only to crimes involving some time in prison).
  • 270
    • 67249130871 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Scott, 440 U.S. at 373-74 (appointed counsel); Codispoti v. Pennsylvania, 418 U.S. 506, 512 (1974) (jury trial);
    • Scott, 440 U.S. at 373-74 (appointed counsel); Codispoti v. Pennsylvania, 418 U.S. 506, 512 (1974) (jury trial);
  • 271
    • 67249088173 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Duncan, 391 U.S. at 159 (jury trial).
    • Duncan, 391 U.S. at 159 (jury trial).
  • 272
    • 67249100038 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Green, supra note 150, at 57 n.13 (citing cases where, inter alia, the Court either has given the government more leeway in construing what counts as a search or seizure in cases involving relatively insignificant offenses or has limited the obligation to read a defendant her Miranda rights in minor cases).
    • See Green, supra note 150, at 57 n.13 (citing cases where, inter alia, the Court either has given the government more leeway in construing what counts as a search or seizure in cases involving relatively insignificant offenses or has limited the obligation to read a defendant her Miranda rights in minor cases).
  • 273
    • 67249113638 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See generally Gabriel J. Chin, Race, the War on Drugs, and the Collateral Consequences of Criminal Conviction, 6 J. GENDER RACE &JUST. 253 (2002) (providing an overview of the range of collateral consequences).
    • See generally Gabriel J. Chin, Race, the War on Drugs, and the Collateral Consequences of Criminal Conviction, 6 J. GENDER RACE &JUST. 253 (2002) (providing an overview of the range of collateral consequences).
  • 274
    • 67249110088 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Comment, Criminal Safeguards and the Punitive Damages Defendant, 34 U. CHI. L. REV. 408, 411-12 (1967, arguing that the stigma from a criminal fine is more apparent than the reputational loss from punitive damages even though the amount of a punitive damages award might exceed that of a fine for comparable conduct, Admittedly, some criminal offenses are strict liability in nature and thus might not be viewed as conveying as much condemnation as a retributive damages finding that says that one acted with malice or recklessness, but the broader point still holds that criminal sanctions are generally viewed as more condemnatory than those currently associated with punitive damages (or retributive damages, per this proposal).If retributive damages are truly going to be intermediate in nature, then jurisdictions adopting retributive damages schemes may also have to adjust fines in the criminal context to always be some amount greater than th
    • Cf. Comment, Criminal Safeguards and the Punitive Damages Defendant, 34 U. CHI. L. REV. 408, 411-12 (1967) (arguing that the stigma from a criminal fine is more apparent than the reputational loss from punitive damages even though the amount of a punitive damages award might exceed that of a fine for comparable conduct). Admittedly, some criminal offenses are "strict liability" in nature and thus might not be viewed as conveying as much condemnation as a retributive damages finding that says that one acted with malice or recklessness, but the broader point still holds that criminal sanctions are generally viewed as more condemnatory than those currently associated with punitive damages (or retributive damages, per this proposal).If retributive damages are truly going to be intermediate in nature, then jurisdictions adopting retributive damages schemes may also have to adjust fines in the criminal context to always be some amount greater than the amount awarded in retributive damages for similar misconduct. But it is not clear that a conventional fine needs to be higher than a retributive damages award in order to signal that it is a steeper penalty; the mere fact of a criminal conviction (and the process leading to and consequences flowing from that conviction) may do the work of ensuring that the social meaning of a fine remains more distinctively condemnatory than the intermediate sanction associated with a retributive damages award.
  • 275
    • 67249164187 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Supreme Court extends great deference to a legislative determination that a penalty is civil or criminal, but occasionally, a multifactor test is used to illuminate (but not decide dispositively) whether a civil law intends and effects a criminal punishment instead:Whether the sanction involves an affirmative disability or restraint, whether it has historically been regarded as a punishment, whether it comes into play only on a finding of scienter, whether its operation will promote the traditional aims of punishment-retribution and deterrence, whther the behavior to which it applies is already a crime, whether an alternative purpose to which it may rationally be connected is assignable for it, and whether it appears excessive in relation to the alternative purpose assigned are all relevant to the inquiry, Kennedy v. Mendoza-Martinez, 372 U.S. 144, 168-69 1963, footnotes omitted, Under this test, retributive damages would likely qualify as some form of punishment, but t
    • The Supreme Court extends great deference to a legislative determination that a penalty is civil or criminal, but occasionally, a multifactor test is used to illuminate (but not decide dispositively) whether a civil law intends and effects a criminal punishment instead:Whether the sanction involves an affirmative disability or restraint, whether it has historically been regarded as a punishment, whether it comes into play only on a finding of scienter, whether its operation will promote the traditional aims of punishment-retribution and deterrence, whther the behavior to which it applies is already a crime, whether an alternative purpose to which it may rationally be connected is assignable for it, and whether it appears excessive in relation to the alternative purpose assigned are all relevant to the inquiry....Kennedy v. Mendoza-Martinez, 372 U.S. 144, 168-69 (1963) (footnotes omitted). Under this test, retributive damages would likely qualify as some form of punishment, but they do not involve the "affirmative disability or restraint" typically associated with criminal punishment through incarceration. See Hudson v. United States, 522 U.S. 93, 104 (1997). Nonetheless, retributive damages do share many characteristics with criminal sanctions: they are only assessed upon a finding of malice or recklessness; they promote the distinct end of retribution; they involve conduct that is frequendy the trigger of criminal sanction; and they have no alternative purpose as compensation, first, because the structure for extracompensatory damages specifically contemplates the plaintiff's receiving compensation for traditional and aggravated damages, and second, because the only money that a defendant pays in retributive damages to the plaintiff, per my proposal, is a small "reward" (not compensation) for channeling awareness of undetected misconduct into the public eye. With all of that said, in Hud- son the Court nevertheless found that the civil penalties of both fines and debarment were not sufficiendy "criminal" in nature to trigger the double jeopardy protection against multiple criminal punishments for the same conduct. Id. at 105. If Hudson is still good law, retributive damages would permissibly operate as only a moderate form of civil sanction for several reasons: first, the legislature's explicit characterization of the sanction as civil will carry great weight; second, the liability for retributive damages will not be equivalent to the status of a conviction; and third, per my proposal, they would not be intended to trigger any collateral consequences.
  • 276
    • 67249092298 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For an earlier instructive overview of punitive-civil-sanctions jurisprudence focusing primarily on agencyinitiated civil punishment, see Kenneth Mann, Punitive Civil Sanctions: The Middleground Between Criminal and Civil Law, 101 YALE LJ. 1795, 1800 1992
    • For an earlier instructive overview of punitive-civil-sanctions jurisprudence focusing primarily on agencyinitiated civil punishment, see Kenneth Mann, Punitive Civil Sanctions: The Middleground Between Criminal and Civil Law, 101 YALE LJ. 1795, 1800 (1992).
  • 277
    • 84872078460 scopus 로고
    • The Need for Constitutional Protections for Defendants in Civil Penally Cases, 59
    • See also
    • See also Jonathan I. Charney, The Need for Constitutional Protections for Defendants in Civil Penally Cases, 59 CORNELL L. REV. 478 (1974);
    • (1974) CORNELL L. REV , vol.478
    • Charney, J.I.1
  • 278
    • 0041013966 scopus 로고
    • Constitutional Limits on Using Civil Remedies to Achieve Criminal Law Objectives: Understanding and Transcending the CriminalCivil Law Distinction, 42
    • Mary M. Cheh, Constitutional Limits on Using Civil Remedies to Achieve Criminal Law Objectives: Understanding and Transcending the CriminalCivil Law Distinction, 42 HASTINGS L.J. 1325 (1991).
    • (1991) HASTINGS L.J , vol.1325
    • Cheh, M.M.1
  • 279
    • 34547819674 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See l, note 150, §1.8c
    • See l LAFAVE ET AL., supra note 150, §1.8(c);
    • supra
    • ET AL, L.1
  • 280
    • 67249084454 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also Mann, supra note 157, at 1870 (noting the constitutional idea that the more severe the sanction, the more the procedure must protect against the sanctioning of the innocent).
    • see also Mann, supra note 157, at 1870 (noting the constitutional idea that "the more severe the sanction, the more the procedure must protect against the sanctioning of the innocent").
  • 281
    • 67249085771 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Galanter & Luban, supra note 3, at 1461 (The appropriate measure to control punitive damages consists of a requirement that juries provide a plausible rationale for the size of punitive awards, coupled with a large dollop of judicial deference to the retributive sentiments jurors express in those awards.).
    • See Galanter & Luban, supra note 3, at 1461 ("The appropriate measure to control punitive damages consists of a requirement that juries provide a plausible rationale for the size of punitive awards, coupled with a large dollop of judicial deference to the retributive sentiments jurors express in those awards.").
  • 283
    • 67249141173 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • cf. Darren Weirnick, Punitive Damages Against Corporations: Functionalist Retributivism (2001) (unpublished manuscript, on file with author) (Because punitive damages exact only monetary penalties and are filed by private plaintiffs, it is not at all obvious that a higher standard of proof, or constitutional rights ... should apply even when individuals are the defendants in punitive damages cases.... When corporations are the defendants, the parallels are even less obvious.).
    • cf. Darren Weirnick, Punitive Damages Against Corporations: Functionalist Retributivism (2001) (unpublished manuscript, on file with author) ("Because punitive damages exact only monetary penalties and are filed by private plaintiffs, it is not at all obvious that a higher standard of proof, or constitutional rights ... should apply even when individuals are the defendants in punitive damages cases.... When corporations are the defendants, the parallels are even less obvious.").
  • 284
    • 67249145302 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The violence might also apply to criminal fines or forfeitures if the defendant's noncompliance triggers a court's contempt-the same outcome that might occur in the context of civil punitive damages
    • The violence might also apply to criminal fines or forfeitures if the defendant's noncompliance triggers a court's contempt-the same outcome that might occur in the context of civil punitive damages.
  • 285
    • 67249103427 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Galanter & Luban, supra note 3, at 1457-58
    • Galanter & Luban, supra note 3, at 1457-58.
  • 286
    • 67249137979 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A judge presides over and rules on matters of law (and, in some cases, fact), and appellate courts subject damages awards to searching review. Moreover, it is the state that enforces the judgment against the losing party. So the state's role is by no means insignificant or radically different from the role that the state plays in a criminal law case; this overlap was even more pronounced during the hundreds of years in which private litigants prosecuted criminal cases and would even capture the fines imposed against a defendant. See, e.g., Steel Co. v. Citizens for a Better Env't, 523 U.S. 83, 127-28 (1998) (Stevens.J., concurring) (explaining the historical role of private parties in the criminal justice system).
    • A judge presides over and rules on matters of law (and, in some cases, fact), and appellate courts subject damages awards to searching review. Moreover, it is the state that enforces the judgment against the losing party. So the state's role is by no means insignificant or radically different from the role that the state plays in a criminal law case; this overlap was even more pronounced during the hundreds of years in which private litigants prosecuted criminal cases and would even capture the fines imposed against a defendant. See, e.g., Steel Co. v. Citizens for a Better Env't, 523 U.S. 83, 127-28 (1998) (Stevens.J., concurring) (explaining the historical role of private parties in the criminal justice system).
  • 287
    • 67249088626 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Zipursky, supra note 5, at 146 (If the private plaintiffs are really delegees of state power, then the awesome power of the state is being used, albeit in a decentralized way.).
    • See Zipursky, supra note 5, at 146 ("If the private plaintiffs are really delegees of state power, then the awesome power of the state is being used, albeit in a decentralized way.").
  • 288
    • 67249131306 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Eg., United States v. Ely, 142 F.3d 1113, 1121-22 (9th Cir. 1997) (holding that the government could still criminally prosecute the defendants, even though the Federal Deposit Insurance Commission (FDIC), acting as receiver for a failed bank, had already sued for punitive damages).
    • Eg., United States v. Ely, 142 F.3d 1113, 1121-22 (9th Cir. 1997) (holding that the government could still criminally prosecute the defendants, even though the Federal Deposit Insurance Commission (FDIC), acting as receiver for a failed bank, had already sued for punitive damages).
  • 289
    • 67249129989 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • An analogy might be found by reference to privacy intrusions. If a private investigator for a plaintiff comes rummaging (with no notice or temporary audiorization) through my garage, I am reasonably upset or resentful. I can imagine I may reasonably be even more upset when the government is the intruder instead of a private investigator for a third party-after all, the government purports to act in my name. But to the extent that my choice is to shield something from exposure to public view, the legitimacy of the interest that I have in keeping that information private doesn't hinge simply on whether the intruder wears a government badge. Galanter and Luban seem to think that the Bill of Rights is normatively relevant only in actions where the state is also the prosecutor (and not just the punisher) and they rely for support on the expressly political fears that classical liberals had about the government's capacity to use its prosecutorial force to marginalize or attack political diss
    • An analogy might be found by reference to privacy intrusions. If a private investigator for a plaintiff comes rummaging (with no notice or temporary audiorization) through my garage, I am reasonably upset or resentful. I can imagine I may reasonably be even more upset when the government is the intruder instead of a private investigator for a third party-after all, the government purports to act in my name. But to the extent that my choice is to shield something from exposure to public view, the legitimacy of the interest that I have in keeping that information private doesn't hinge simply on whether the intruder wears a government badge. Galanter and Luban seem to think that the Bill of Rights is normatively relevant only in actions where the state is also the prosecutor (and not just the punisher) and they rely for support on the expressly political fears that classical liberals had about the government's capacity to use its prosecutorial force to marginalize or attack political dissidents. Galanter & Luban, supra note 3, at 1457. That might be a basis for limiting the government's investigative powers through something like the Fourth Amendment, but it is not a basis for limiting the reach of procedural safeguards during trial or punishment where the fear that a person has about abuse sis predicated on what the government does as judge or enforcer of punishment.
  • 290
    • 67249128484 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 167I should note that collateral consequences are sometimes products of regulatory decisions as opposed to punitive ones, and in some contexts, they appear as a result of proof of misconduct, not of conviction. However, the dominant recent approach to the imposition of collateral consequences is to look at the defendant's convictions, rather than other sources of evidence regarding the defendant's misconduct. See Gabriel J. Chin, Are Collateral Sanctions Premised on Conduct or Conviction, The Case of Abortion Doctors, 30 FORDHAM URB. L.J. 1685 2003
    • 167I should note that collateral consequences are sometimes products of regulatory decisions as opposed to "punitive" ones, and in some contexts, they appear as a result of proof of misconduct, not of conviction. However, the dominant recent approach to the imposition of collateral consequences is to look at the defendant's convictions, rather than other sources of evidence regarding the defendant's misconduct. See Gabriel J. Chin, Are Collateral Sanctions Premised on Conduct or Conviction?: The Case of Abortion Doctors, 30 FORDHAM URB. L.J. 1685 (2003).
  • 291
    • 67249088172 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See also Markel, Punitive Damages, supra note 9 (addressing the appropriate safeguards for complex litigation).
    • See also Markel, Punitive Damages, supra note 9 (addressing the appropriate safeguards for complex litigation).
  • 292
    • 67249151200 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Sebok, supra note 5, at 1002 (discussing the claim that the full panoply of constitutional safeguards should apply to punitive damages).
    • Cf. Sebok, supra note 5, at 1002 (discussing the claim that the full panoply of constitutional safeguards should apply to punitive damages).
  • 293
    • 67249096753 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • calling for sentencing guidelines and commentaries to inform the finding of a defendant's reprehensibility on a scale, which would ensure that determinations of the amount of retributive damages are not made on an ad hoc basis, jury by jury, See, at
    • See Markel, Retributive Damages, supra note 1, at 287-89 (calling for sentencing guidelines and commentaries to inform the finding of a defendant's reprehensibility on a scale, which would ensure that determinations of the amount of retributive damages are not made on an ad hoc basis, jury by jury).
    • Retributive Damages, supra note , vol.1 , pp. 287-289
    • Markel1
  • 295
    • 67249102133 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Pac. Mut. Life Ins. Co. v. Haslip, 499 U.S. 1, 22 n.11 (1991).
    • See Pac. Mut. Life Ins. Co. v. Haslip, 499 U.S. 1, 22 n.11 (1991).
  • 296
    • 67249153684 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See In reWinship, 397 U.S. 358, 364 (1970) (confirming that due process mandates the beyond a reasonable doubt standard).
    • See In reWinship, 397 U.S. 358, 364 (1970) (confirming that due process mandates the beyond a reasonable doubt standard).
  • 297
    • 84868973835 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 1 LINDA L. SCHLUETER & KENNETH R. REDDEN, PUNITIVE DAMAGES, §5.3 (H)(2) (5th ed. 2005). One state, Colorado, requires juries to find that the proof establishes culpability beyond a reasonable doubt for punitive damages to attach. COLO. REV. STAT. §13-25-127(2) (2008).
    • 1 LINDA L. SCHLUETER & KENNETH R. REDDEN, PUNITIVE DAMAGES, §5.3 (H)(2) (5th ed. 2005). One state, Colorado, requires juries to find that the proof establishes culpability beyond a reasonable doubt for punitive damages to attach. COLO. REV. STAT. §13-25-127(2) (2008).
  • 298
    • 67249139876 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Santosky v. Kramer, 455 U.S. 745, 756 (1982) (discussing the use of the clear and convincing evidence standard for civil cases involving the potential imposition of stigma or deprivation of liberty). Whether all jurors differentiate among the different standards is hard to know, but inasmuch as it is a problem, clear instructions about the different standards along with examples may help.
    • Cf. Santosky v. Kramer, 455 U.S. 745, 756 (1982) (discussing the use of the clear and convincing evidence standard for civil cases involving the potential imposition of stigma or deprivation of liberty). Whether all jurors differentiate among the different standards is hard to know, but inasmuch as it is a problem, clear instructions about the different standards along with examples may help.
  • 299
    • 67249089707 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Galanter & Luban, supra note 3, at 1459-60;
    • See Galanter & Luban, supra note 3, at 1459-60;
  • 300
    • 67249110091 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Weirnick, supra note 160
    • Weirnick, supra note 160.
  • 301
    • 67249150709 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Those who view aggravated damages as private punishment, rather than as compensation for uncompensated injuries to dignity, may welcome a higher standard of proof, though they have not all said as much
    • Those who view aggravated damages as "private punishment," rather than as compensation for uncompensated injuries to dignity, may welcome a higher standard of proof, though they have not all said as much.
  • 302
    • 48049097943 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Three Faces of Deference, 83
    • analyzing epistemic superiority as the basis for deference, See generally
    • See generally Paul Horwitz, Three Faces of Deference, 83 NOTRE DAME L. REV. 1061, 1085-90 (2008) (analyzing epistemic superiority as the basis for deference).
    • (2008) NOTRE DAME L. REV , vol.1061 , pp. 1085-1090
    • Horwitz, P.1
  • 303
    • 67249120695 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Rustad, supra note 29, at 1305 (labeling as radical the idea of allowing judges to assess punitive damages).
    • See Rustad, supra note 29, at 1305 (labeling as "radical" the idea of allowing judges to assess punitive damages).
  • 304
    • 67249147435 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 1305-06.
    • See id. at 1305-06.
  • 305
    • 67249143186 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Compare David G. Owen, Punitive Damages in Products Liability Litigation, 74 MLCH. L. REV. 1257, 1320-22 (1976) (suggesting that the trial judge, rather than the jury, should measure awards of punitive damages, in order to protect against excessive awards),
    • Compare David G. Owen, Punitive Damages in Products Liability Litigation, 74 MLCH. L. REV. 1257, 1320-22 (1976) (suggesting that the trial judge, rather than the jury, should measure awards of punitive damages, in order to protect against excessive awards),
  • 306
    • 67249088625 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • with note 38, at, defending a robust role for juries in punitive damages cases on the basis of republican theory
    • with Pardett, supra note 38, at 1411-12 (defending a robust role for juries in punitive damages cases on the basis of republican theory),
    • supra , pp. 1411-1412
    • Pardett1
  • 307
    • 84922577124 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note 37, at, arguing that juries should continue to measure punitive damages awards
    • arad Wenger & Hoffman, supra note 37, at 1148 (arguing that juries should continue to measure punitive damages awards).
    • supra , pp. 1148
    • arad Wenger1    Hoffman2
  • 308
    • 67249142325 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Michael T. Cahill, Punishment Decisions at Conviction: Recognizing the Jury as Fault-Finder, 2005 U. CHI. LEGAL F. 91, 96-108 (arguing that criminal juries already play a significant role, through their determinations of guilt or innocence, in the punishment process and that this role in punishment should be made more explicit);
    • See Michael T. Cahill, Punishment Decisions at Conviction: Recognizing the Jury as Fault-Finder, 2005 U. CHI. LEGAL F. 91, 96-108 (arguing that criminal juries already play a significant role, through their determinations of guilt or innocence, in the punishment process and that this role in punishment should be made more explicit);
  • 309
    • 80052767912 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Requiring a Jury Vote of Censure to Convict, 88
    • proposing, as a means of reinforcing criminal law's condemnatory role, a requirement that juries vote to censure a defendant before convicting her, forthcoming
    • Richard E. Myers II, Requiring a Jury Vote of Censure to Convict, 88 N.C. L. REV. (forthcoming 2009) (proposing, as a means of reinforcing criminal law's condemnatory role, a requirement that juries vote to "censure" a defendant before convicting her).
    • (2009) N.C. L. REV
    • Myers II, R.E.1
  • 310
    • 67249128926 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This view might underlie the rule adopted in federal criminal cases that requires both the prosecution and the court to consent to a defendant's waiver of a jury trial. FED. R. CRIM. P. 23a
    • This view might underlie the rule adopted in federal criminal cases that requires both the prosecution and the court to consent to a defendant's waiver of a jury trial. FED. R. CRIM. P. 23(a).
  • 311
    • 67249154102 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Blanton v. City of N. Las Vegas, 489 U.S. 538, 541-42 (1989);
    • Blanton v. City of N. Las Vegas, 489 U.S. 538, 541-42 (1989);
  • 312
    • 84868966221 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also United States v. Nachtigal, 507 U.S. 1, 4-5 (1993) (per curiam) (holding that an offense was not constitutionally serious even though it carried a penalty of up to six montfis' incarceration, a $5,000 fine, a five-year term of probation as an alternative to incarceration, and other penalties).
    • see also United States v. Nachtigal, 507 U.S. 1, 4-5 (1993) (per curiam) (holding that an offense was not constitutionally "serious" even though it carried a penalty of up to six montfis' incarceration, a $5,000 fine, a five-year term of probation as an alternative to incarceration, and other penalties).
  • 313
    • 67249161876 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Chauffeurs, Teamsters and Helpers Local No. 391 v. Terry, 494 U.S. 558, 573-74 (1990) (holding that the monetary damages sought were the type of relief traditionally awarded by courts of law and that the Seventh Amendment therefore created an entidement to a jury trial).
    • See Chauffeurs, Teamsters and Helpers Local No. 391 v. Terry, 494 U.S. 558, 573-74 (1990) (holding that the monetary damages sought were "the type of relief traditionally awarded by courts of law" and that the Seventh Amendment therefore created an entidement to a jury trial).
  • 314
    • 67249099107 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 530 U.S. 466, 490 (2000). The Apprendi Court held that, outside of a prior conviction, any factual finding that increases the statutory-maximum penalty for an offense must be proven beyond a reasonable doubt.
    • 530 U.S. 466, 490 (2000). The Apprendi Court held that, outside of a prior conviction, any factual finding that increases the statutory-maximum penalty for an offense must be proven beyond a reasonable doubt.
  • 315
    • 67249159826 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 542 U.S. 296, 313 (2004). Blakely affirmed and extended Appendts holding.
    • 542 U.S. 296, 313 (2004). Blakely affirmed and extended Appendts holding.
  • 316
    • 67249088169 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Grass, supra note 7, at 243 n.13.
    • See, e.g., Grass, supra note 7, at 243 n.13.
  • 317
    • 67249146181 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 406 U.S. 404 1972
    • 406 U.S. 404 (1972).
  • 318
    • 67249136254 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 406 U.S. 356 1972
    • 406 U.S. 356 (1972).
  • 319
    • 67249155010 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Williams v. Florida, 399 U.S. 78,103 (1970) (holding that a six-person jury is sufficient). The Court did later clarify that, in cases involving nonpetty crimes, if a sixperson jury were used, it would have to reach a unanimous verdict to convict.
    • See Williams v. Florida, 399 U.S. 78,103 (1970) (holding that a six-person jury is sufficient). The Court did later clarify that, in cases involving nonpetty crimes, if a sixperson jury were used, it would have to reach a unanimous verdict to convict.
  • 320
    • 67249122821 scopus 로고
    • U.S
    • Burch v. Louisiana, 441 U.S. 130,138 (1979).
    • (1979) Louisiana , vol.441 , pp. 130-138
    • Burch, V.1
  • 321
    • 67249138392 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Ethan J. Leib, Supermajoritarianism and the American Criminal Jury, 33 HASTINGS CONST. L.Q. 141, 142-45 (2006) (arguing against the obsession with unanimity in the criminal justice system's decision rules).
    • See Ethan J. Leib, Supermajoritarianism and the American Criminal Jury, 33 HASTINGS CONST. L.Q. 141, 142-45 (2006) (arguing against "the obsession with unanimity" in the criminal justice system's decision rules).
  • 323
    • 67249165900 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Scott v. Illinois, 440 U.S. 367, 373-74 (1979) (holding that counsel is only required under the Constitution if the defendant had actual imprisonment imposed). For the most part, there is no constitutional right to appointed counsel in the civil context, but some states do provide appointed counsel in some civil contexts, such as where indigent parents face termination of their parental rights.
    • See Scott v. Illinois, 440 U.S. 367, 373-74 (1979) (holding that counsel is only required under the Constitution if the defendant had "actual imprisonment" imposed). For the most part, there is no constitutional right to appointed counsel in the civil context, but some states do provide appointed counsel in some civil contexts, such as where indigent parents face termination of their parental rights.
  • 324
    • 67249114944 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • E.g., In re K.L.J., 813 P.2d 276 (Alaska 1991).
    • E.g., In re K.L.J., 813 P.2d 276 (Alaska 1991).
  • 325
    • 67249156389 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Compare, e.g., Gideon v. Wainwright, 372 U.S. 335, 344 (1963) (describing contributions of lawyers to truth seeking),
    • Compare, e.g., Gideon v. Wainwright, 372 U.S. 335, 344 (1963) (describing contributions of lawyers to truth seeking),
  • 326
    • 67249135037 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • with WILLIAM TWINING, THEORIES OF EVIDENCE: BENTHAM AND WLGMORE 75-79 (1985) (describing Bentham's view that lawyers impede the factfinding mission of courts).
    • with WILLIAM TWINING, THEORIES OF EVIDENCE: BENTHAM AND WLGMORE 75-79 (1985) (describing Bentham's view that lawyers impede the factfinding mission of courts).
  • 327
    • 67249132630 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See 4 WILLIAM BLACKSTONE, COMMENTARIES *352 ([I]t is better that ten guilty persons escape, than that one innocent suffer.);
    • See 4 WILLIAM BLACKSTONE, COMMENTARIES *352 ("[I]t is better that ten guilty persons escape, than that one innocent suffer.");
  • 328
    • 67249146595 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • cf. In re Winship, 397 U.S. 358, 372 (1970) (Harlan, J., concurring) (relying on the fundamental value determination of our society that it is far worse to convict an innocent man than to let a guilty man go free).
    • cf. In re Winship, 397 U.S. 358, 372 (1970) (Harlan, J., concurring) (relying on the "fundamental value determination of our society that it is far worse to convict an innocent man than to let a guilty man go free").
  • 329
    • 67249159395 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., TWINING, supra note 194, at 75 (identifying, as one of Bentham's primary concerns, the sinister interests of the legal fraternity).
    • See, e.g., TWINING, supra note 194, at 75 (identifying, as one of Bentham's primary concerns, "the sinister interests of the legal fraternity").
  • 330
    • 67249084457 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Larry Laudan, The Social Contract and the Rules of Trial: Re-Thinking Procedural Rules 31-43 (2008) (unpublished manuscript), available at http:// ssrn.com/abstract=1075403 (noting that the social contract requires the state to reduce aggregate risk under the Laplace-Nozick thesis).
    • See Larry Laudan, The Social Contract and the Rules of Trial: Re-Thinking Procedural Rules 31-43 (2008) (unpublished manuscript), available at http:// ssrn.com/abstract=1075403 (noting that the social contract requires the state to reduce aggregate risk under the Laplace-Nozick thesis).
  • 331
    • 67249084006 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • But see Posting of Dan Markel to PrawfsBlawg, Legal Epistemology Is Ninety Per Cent Quantitative. The Odier Half Is Qualitative., http://prawfsblawg.blogs.com/prawfsblawg/2008/08/legal- epistemol.html (Aug. 10, 2008) (urging greater granularity in the comparisons that Laudan makes and more mindfulness toward the potentially unjust distributive patterns associated with who bears the consequences of tradeoffs between Type I and Type II error-reduction strategies).
    • But see Posting of Dan Markel to PrawfsBlawg, "Legal Epistemology Is Ninety Per Cent Quantitative. The Odier Half Is Qualitative.," http://prawfsblawg.blogs.com/prawfsblawg/2008/08/legal- epistemol.html (Aug. 10, 2008) (urging greater granularity in the comparisons that Laudan makes and more mindfulness toward the potentially unjust distributive patterns associated with who bears the consequences of tradeoffs between Type I and Type II error-reduction strategies).
  • 332
    • 0035649969 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See generally Tom Baker, Blood Money, New Money, and the Moral Economy of Tort Law in Action, 35 LAW & SOC'Y REV. 275 (2001) (analyzing the incentives of plaintiffs' lawyers in tort cases).
    • See generally Tom Baker, Blood Money, New Money, and the Moral Economy of Tort Law in Action, 35 LAW & SOC'Y REV. 275 (2001) (analyzing the incentives of plaintiffs' lawyers in tort cases).
  • 333
    • 67249096755 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • suggesting various permutations for institutional design that would reduce Type I and Type II errors, See, at
    • See Markel, Retributive Damages, supra note 1, at 297-300 (suggesting various permutations for institutional design that would reduce Type I and Type II errors).
    • Retributive Damages, supra note , vol.1 , pp. 297-300
    • Markel1
  • 334
    • 67249158937 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • U.S. CONST, amend. V.
    • U.S. CONST, amend. V.
  • 335
  • 336
    • 67249084874 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also Carlson v. United States, 209 F.2d 209, 214 (1st Cir. 1954) (stating that a person invoking the privilege in bad faith may be found guilty of perjury).
    • see also Carlson v. United States, 209 F.2d 209, 214 (1st Cir. 1954) (stating that a person invoking the privilege in bad faith may be found guilty of perjury).
  • 337
    • 67249090598 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Lefkowitz v. Turley, 414 U.S. 70, 77 (1973) (The [Fifth] Amendment... privileges [the individual] not to answer official questions put to him in any other proceeding, civil or criminal, formal or informal....).
    • See Lefkowitz v. Turley, 414 U.S. 70, 77 (1973) ("The [Fifth] Amendment... privileges [the individual] not to answer official questions put to him in any other proceeding, civil or criminal, formal or informal....").
  • 338
    • 67249085769 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Spevack v. Klein, 385 U.S. 511, 515-16 (1967) (finding a threat of disbarment sufficient to invoke privilege).
    • See Spevack v. Klein, 385 U.S. 511, 515-16 (1967) (finding a threat of disbarment sufficient to invoke privilege).
  • 339
    • 67249126717 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See United States v. Ward, 448 U.S. 242, 251-55 (1980) (finding that in establishing a civil penalty, Congress did not impose a scheme that was so punitive as to allow invocation of the privilege).
    • See United States v. Ward, 448 U.S. 242, 251-55 (1980) (finding that in establishing a civil penalty, Congress did not impose a scheme that was so punitive as to allow invocation of the privilege).
  • 340
    • 67249098056 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Baxter v. Palmigiano, 425 U.S. 308, 318 (1976) (declaring the prevailing rule to be that the Fifth Amendment does not forbid adverse inferences against parties to civil actions when they refuse to testify in response to probative evidence offered against them).
    • See Baxter v. Palmigiano, 425 U.S. 308, 318 (1976) (declaring "the prevailing rule" to be that "the Fifth Amendment does not forbid adverse inferences against parties to civil actions when they refuse to testify in response to probative evidence offered against them").
  • 341
    • 67249146593 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Hale v. Henkel, 201 U.S. 43, 67 (1906);
    • See, e.g., Hale v. Henkel, 201 U.S. 43, 67 (1906);
  • 342
    • 84868990997 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also 18 U.S.C. §6003 2006, providing the procedure for granting immunity
    • see also 18 U.S.C. §6003 (2006) (providing the procedure for granting immunity).
  • 343
    • 67249163000 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Ronald J. Allen, Theorizing About Self-incrimination, 30 CARDOZO L. REV. 729, 730-39, 734 n.25 (2008) (canvassing much of the literature and demonstrating why most efforts to explain or justify the privilege against self-incrimination are uniformly unconvincing);
    • See Ronald J. Allen, Theorizing About Self-incrimination, 30 CARDOZO L. REV. 729, 730-39, 734 n.25 (2008) (canvassing much of the literature and demonstrating why most efforts to explain or justify the privilege against self-incrimination are "uniformly unconvincing");
  • 344
    • 42349097057 scopus 로고
    • Self-incrimination and Excuse, 88
    • It is probably fair to say that most people familiar with the doctrine surrounding the privilege against self-incrimination believe that it cannot be squared with any rational theory
    • William J. Stuntz, Self-incrimination and Excuse, 88 COLUM. L. REV. 1227, 1228 (1988) ("It is probably fair to say that most people familiar with the doctrine surrounding the privilege against self-incrimination believe that it cannot be squared with any rational theory.").
    • (1988) COLUM. L. REV , vol.1227 , pp. 1228
    • Stuntz, W.J.1
  • 345
    • 67249098057 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ward, 448 U.S. at 248
    • Ward, 448 U.S. at 248
  • 347
    • 67249133708 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • To be sure, there are other values important to retributivism, but I will limit my discussion to these core issues
    • To be sure, there are other values important to retributivism, but I will limit my discussion to these core issues.
  • 348
    • 67249141639 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 5 JEREMY BENTHAM, RATIONALE OF JUDICIAL EVIDENCE 1 (Littleton, Colo., Fred B. Rothman & Co. 1995) (1827).
    • 5 JEREMY BENTHAM, RATIONALE OF JUDICIAL EVIDENCE 1 (Littleton, Colo., Fred B. Rothman & Co. 1995) (1827).
  • 349
    • 67249133241 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a particularly incisive analysis of this point, see Allen, supra note 207, at 734-36.
    • For a particularly incisive analysis of this point, see Allen, supra note 207, at 734-36.
  • 350
    • 67249145726 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 149 U.S. 60, 66 (1893).
    • 149 U.S. 60, 66 (1893).
  • 351
    • 0042225061 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Daniel J. Seidmann & Alex Stein, The Right to Silence Helps the Innocent: A Game-Theoretic Analysis of the Fifth Amendment Privilege, 114 HARV. L. REV. 430, 430 2000, Because the right to silence is available, innocent defendants still tell the truth while guilty defendants may rationally exercise the right. Thus, guilty defendants do not pool with innocent defendants by lying, and as a result, triers of fact do not wrongfully convict innocent defendants
    • See Daniel J. Seidmann & Alex Stein, The Right to Silence Helps the Innocent: A Game-Theoretic Analysis of the Fifth Amendment Privilege, 114 HARV. L. REV. 430, 430 (2000) ("Because the right to silence is available, innocent defendants still tell the truth while guilty defendants may rationally exercise the right. Thus, guilty defendants do not pool with innocent defendants by lying, and as a result, triers of fact do not wrongfully convict innocent defendants.").
  • 352
    • 0037229619 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Stephanos Bibas, The Right to Remain Silent Helps Only the Guilty, 88 IOWA L. REV. 421, 421 (2003) (Though [the Seidmann-Stein] theory predicts that rational suspects remain silent, roughly eighty to ninety percent of suspects talk to the police.).
    • See Stephanos Bibas, The Right to Remain Silent Helps Only the Guilty, 88 IOWA L. REV. 421, 421 (2003) ("Though [the Seidmann-Stein] theory predicts that rational suspects remain silent, roughly eighty to ninety percent of suspects talk to the police.").
  • 354
    • 67249119161 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • But see Alex Stein, The Right to Silence Helps the Innocent: A Response to Critics, 30 CARDOZO L. REV. 1115 (2008).
    • But see Alex Stein, The Right to Silence Helps the Innocent: A Response to Critics, 30 CARDOZO L. REV. 1115 (2008).
  • 355
    • 67249111899 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Palko v. Connecticut, 302 U.S. 319, 326 (1937) (Cardozo, J.) (Justice ... would not perish if the accused were subject to a duty to respond to orderly inquiry.).
    • See Palko v. Connecticut, 302 U.S. 319, 326 (1937) (Cardozo, J.) ("Justice ... would not perish if the accused were subject to a duty to respond to orderly inquiry.").
  • 356
    • 67249117058 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • There is obviously much more to be said on the policies underlying the privilege embedded in the Fifth Amendment. A good starting point would be the recent symposium in the Cardozo Law Review. See Symposium, The Future of Self-incrimination: Fifth Amendment, Confessions, & Guilty Pleas, 30 CARDOZO L. REV. 717 2008
    • There is obviously much more to be said on the policies underlying the privilege embedded in the Fifth Amendment. A good starting point would be the recent symposium in the Cardozo Law Review. See Symposium, The Future of Self-incrimination: Fifth Amendment, Confessions, & Guilty Pleas, 30 CARDOZO L. REV. 717 (2008).
  • 357
    • 67249144110 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In the successor article, supra note 9, I will address, among other things, concerns of duplicative punishment arising from multiple injuries inflicted by the same course of conduct.
    • In the successor article, supra note 9, I will address, among other things, concerns of duplicative punishment arising from multiple injuries inflicted by the same course of conduct.
  • 358
    • 67249106852 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • United States v. Halper, 490 U.S. 435, 440 (1989), overruled on other grounds by Hudson v. United States, 522 U.S. 93, 95-96 (1997). The Court has also made clear that notwithstanding the text of the Fifth Amendment's reference to life or limb, it also covers monetary penalties and incarceration.
    • United States v. Halper, 490 U.S. 435, 440 (1989), overruled on other grounds by Hudson v. United States, 522 U.S. 93, 95-96 (1997). The Court has also made clear that notwithstanding the text of the Fifth Amendment's reference to "life or limb," it also covers monetary penalties and incarceration.
  • 359
    • 67249115813 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Dep't of Revenue v. Kurth Ranch, 511 U.S. 767, 769 n.l (1994) ([I]t is well settled that the [Fifth] Amendment covers imprisonment and monetary penalties.).
    • See Dep't of Revenue v. Kurth Ranch, 511 U.S. 767, 769 n.l (1994) ("[I]t is well settled that the [Fifth] Amendment covers imprisonment and monetary penalties.").
  • 360
    • 67249107281 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Helvering v. Mitchell, 303 U.S. 391, 399 (1938) (holding that a legislature can impose both a criminal and a civil sanction in respect to the same act or omission; for the double jeopardy clause prohibits merely punishing twice, or attempting a second time to punish criminally, for the same offense);
    • See, e.g., Helvering v. Mitchell, 303 U.S. 391, 399 (1938) (holding that a legislature can "impose both a criminal and a civil sanction in respect to the same act or omission; for the double jeopardy clause prohibits merely punishing twice, or attempting a second time to punish criminally, for the same offense");
  • 361
    • 67249159393 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • United States v. Ely, 142 F.3d 1113, 1121 (9th Cir. 1997) (finding that a prior recovery of punitive damages by the FDIC against bank directors for federal bank fraud did not preclude subsequent criminal prosecution);
    • United States v. Ely, 142 F.3d 1113, 1121 (9th Cir. 1997) (finding that a prior recovery of punitive damages by the FDIC against bank directors for federal bank fraud did not preclude subsequent criminal prosecution);
  • 362
    • 67249138393 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hansen v. Johns-Manville Prods. Corp., 734 F.2d 1036, 1042 (5th Cir. 1984) (holding that because punitive damages awards are not criminal sanctions, multiple awards of punitive damages are consistent with the Double Jeopardy Clause of the Fifth Amendment);
    • Hansen v. Johns-Manville Prods. Corp., 734 F.2d 1036, 1042 (5th Cir. 1984) (holding that because punitive damages awards are not criminal sanctions, multiple awards of punitive damages are consistent with the Double Jeopardy Clause of the Fifth Amendment);
  • 363
    • 67249103426 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • cf. Hudson, 522 U.S. at 99 (holding that double jeopardy only protects against multiple criminal punishments for the same offense).
    • cf. Hudson, 522 U.S. at 99 (holding that double jeopardy only protects against "multiple criminal punishments for the same offense").
  • 364
    • 67249100035 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Shore v. Gurnett, 18 Cal. Rptr. 3d 583, 586-87 (Ct. App. 2004) (finding that double jeopardy did not apply to punitive damages awarded in a wrongful-death suit following the conviction of the defendant for vehicular manslaughter).
    • See, e.g., Shore v. Gurnett, 18 Cal. Rptr. 3d 583, 586-87 (Ct. App. 2004) (finding that double jeopardy did not apply to punitive damages awarded in a wrongful-death suit following the conviction of the defendant for vehicular manslaughter).
  • 365
    • 67249098055 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See State v. McDowell, 699 A.2d 987, 989 (Conn. 1997) 'Jeopardy attaches only to proceedings which are 'essentially criminal.'
    • See State v. McDowell, 699 A.2d 987, 989 (Conn. 1997) ('Jeopardy attaches only to proceedings which are 'essentially criminal.'"
  • 366
    • 67249144113 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (quoting Breed v. Jones, 421 U.S. 519, 528 (1975))).
    • (quoting Breed v. Jones, 421 U.S. 519, 528 (1975))).
  • 367
    • 67249094696 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Halper, 490 U.S. at 451 (The protections of the Double Jeopardy Clause are not triggered by litigation between private parties.);
    • See Halper, 490 U.S. at 451 ("The protections of the Double Jeopardy Clause are not triggered by litigation between private parties.");
  • 368
    • 67249141638 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also Hudson, 522 U.S. at 110-11 (Stevens, J., concurring) (observing that the purpose of the Double Jeopardy Clause is to prevent the State from mak[ing] repeated attempts to convict an individual).
    • see also Hudson, 522 U.S. at 110-11 (Stevens, J., concurring) (observing that the purpose of the Double Jeopardy Clause is to prevent the State from "mak[ing] repeated attempts to convict an individual").
  • 369
    • 67249097627 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Ely, 142 F.3d at 1121;
    • See Ely, 142 F.3d at 1121;
  • 370
    • 67249146592 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • United States v. Beszborn, 21 F.3d 62, 67-68 (5th Cir. 1994) (allowing a federal agency first to pursue punitive damages against defendants and then to pursue criminal indictments).
    • United States v. Beszborn, 21 F.3d 62, 67-68 (5th Cir. 1994) (allowing a federal agency first to pursue punitive damages against defendants and then to pursue criminal indictments).
  • 371
    • 67249164186 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Dep't of Revenue v. Kurth Ranch, 511 U.S. 767, 784 (1994) (This drug tax is not the kind of remedial sanction that may follow the first punishment of a criminal offense. Instead, it is a second punishment within the contemplation of a constitutional protection . ...).
    • See Dep't of Revenue v. Kurth Ranch, 511 U.S. 767, 784 (1994) ("This drug tax is not the kind of remedial sanction that may follow the first punishment of a criminal offense. Instead, it is a second punishment within the contemplation of a constitutional protection . ...").
  • 372
    • 67249160311 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Colby, supra note 5, at 452-53 (noting that punitive damages only call for criminal procedural protection when they are understood as punishment for public, not private, wrongs);
    • See Colby, supra note 5, at 452-53 (noting that punitive damages only call for criminal procedural protection when they are understood as punishment for public, not private, wrongs);
  • 373
    • 67249155013 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Wheeler, supra note 7, at 272 (concluding that the procedural safeguards in the Fourth, Fifth, and Sixth Amendments could apply to punitive damages where the action is criminal in substance).
    • Wheeler, supra note 7, at 272 (concluding that the procedural safeguards in the Fourth, Fifth, and Sixth Amendments could apply to punitive damages where the action is criminal in substance).
  • 374
    • 67249086427 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Roginsky v. Richardson-Merrell, Inc., 378 F.2d 832, 841 (2d Cir. 1967) (Friendly, J.) (discussing the danger of overkill from multiple punishments).
    • See, e.g., Roginsky v. Richardson-Merrell, Inc., 378 F.2d 832, 841 (2d Cir. 1967) (Friendly, J.) (discussing the danger of overkill from multiple punishments).
  • 375
    • 67249164185 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Blockburger v. United States, 284 U.S. 299, 304 (1932) ([T]he test to be applied to determine whether there are two offenses or only one, is whether each provision requires proof of a fact which the other does not.).
    • See Blockburger v. United States, 284 U.S. 299, 304 (1932) ("[T]he test to be applied to determine whether there are two offenses or only one, is whether each provision requires proof of a fact which the other does not.").
  • 376
    • 67249086428 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See MARC L. MILLER & RONALD F. WRIGHT, CRIMINAL PROCEDURES 1002-05 (3d ed. 2007) (providing a survey of double jeopardy doctrines around the states).
    • See MARC L. MILLER & RONALD F. WRIGHT, CRIMINAL PROCEDURES 1002-05 (3d ed. 2007) (providing a survey of double jeopardy doctrines around the states).
  • 377
    • 23744507095 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Paul H. Robinson & Michael T. Cahill, The Accelerating Degradation of American Criminal Codes, 56 HASTINGS L.J. 633, 635 (2005) (lamenting legislative hyperactivity culminating in unnecessary and often inconsistent statutes).
    • Cf. Paul H. Robinson & Michael T. Cahill, The Accelerating Degradation of American Criminal Codes, 56 HASTINGS L.J. 633, 635 (2005) (lamenting "legislative hyperactivity" culminating in "unnecessary and often inconsistent" statutes).
  • 378
    • 67249099110 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SeeBartkus v. Illinois, 359 U.S. 121, 132-33 (1959) (holding that state and federal prosecutions based on the same actions do not violate the Fifth Amendment);
    • SeeBartkus v. Illinois, 359 U.S. 121, 132-33 (1959) (holding that state and federal prosecutions based on the same actions do not violate the Fifth Amendment);
  • 379
    • 67249124740 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • United States v. Lanza, 260 U.S. 377, 382 (1922) ([A]n act denounced as a crime by both national and state sovereignties is an offense against the peace and dignity of both and may be punished by each.).
    • United States v. Lanza, 260 U.S. 377, 382 (1922) ("[A]n act denounced as a crime by both national and state sovereignties is an offense against the peace and dignity of both and may be punished by each.").
  • 380
    • 67249125174 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Headi v. Alabama, 474 U.S. 82, 88 (1985) (applying the dual sovereigns doctrine to permit prosecution in two states for the murder of a victim who was kidnapped in one state and killed in another).
    • See Headi v. Alabama, 474 U.S. 82, 88 (1985) (applying the dual sovereigns doctrine to permit prosecution in two states for the murder of a victim who was kidnapped in one state and killed in another).
  • 381
    • 67249132156 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See MILLER & WRIGHT, supra note 229, at 1002-05 (discussing the various ways that states define double jeopardy provisions).
    • See MILLER & WRIGHT, supra note 229, at 1002-05 (discussing the various ways that states define double jeopardy provisions).
  • 382
    • 84868993531 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Galanter and Luban recognize that multiple punitive damages awards are extremely troublesome from their perspective because if each award has been appropriately scaled to the heinousness of the deed, multiple awards amount to overpunishment. Galanter & Luban, supra note 3, at 1455 n.302. Nonetheless, Galanter and Luban fail to address how punitive damages might also raise similar concerns of unfairness vis-à-vis the criminal justice system.
    • Galanter and Luban recognize that multiple punitive damages awards are "extremely troublesome" from their perspective because "if each award has been appropriately scaled to the heinousness of the deed, multiple awards amount to overpunishment." Galanter & Luban, supra note 3, at 1455 n.302. Nonetheless, Galanter and Luban fail to address how punitive damages might also raise similar concerns of unfairness vis-à-vis the criminal justice system.
  • 383
    • 67249142757 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • discussing the private attorney general (PAG) structure, One might fairly question whether the PAG benefits are as strong in the context of a retributive damages action following a defendant who was acquitted in a criminal case. See, at
    • See Markel, Retributive Damages, supra note 1, at 280-86 (discussing the private attorney general (PAG) structure). One might fairly question whether the PAG benefits are as strong in the context of a retributive damages action following a defendant who was acquitted in a criminal case.
    • Retributive Damages, supra note , vol.1 , pp. 280-286
    • Markel1
  • 384
    • 67249112775 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I leave aside for now concerns that persons might reasonably raise about being punished in polities with universal jurisdiction over certain forms of extreme wrongdoing
    • I leave aside for now concerns that persons might reasonably raise about being punished in polities with universal jurisdiction over certain forms of extreme wrongdoing.
  • 385
    • 67249142755 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This position is consistent with, and expressive of, the institutional account of retributivism discussed in Part II of Markel, Retributive Damages, supra note 1, which acknowledges that the same conduct can be subject to sanction in several jurisdictions, even consecutively. A pure moral retributivist might think that punishments for the same conduct that separately are proportional would in the aggregate be an unfair piling on because they offend a prepolitical conception of desert. For some discussion of the shortcomings of a purely moral, as opposed to political, account of retributivism
    • This position is consistent with, and expressive of, the institutional account of retributivism discussed in Part II of Markel, Retributive Damages, supra note 1, which acknowledges that the same conduct can be subject to sanction in several jurisdictions, even consecutively. A pure "moral" retributivist might think that punishments for the same conduct that separately are proportional would in the aggregate be an unfair "piling on" because they offend a prepolitical conception of desert. For some discussion of the shortcomings of a purely moral, as opposed to political, account of retributivism,
  • 387
    • 67249164184 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As I explain in Markel, Punitive Damages, supra note 9, defendants worried about the dangers of seriatim punishment by different plaintiffs should be able to obtain a defensive class action that would aggregate all plaintiffs for retributive damages purposes arising from specific misconduct.
    • As I explain in Markel, Punitive Damages, supra note 9, defendants worried about the dangers of seriatim punishment by different plaintiffs should be able to obtain a defensive class action that would aggregate all plaintiffs for retributive damages purposes arising from specific misconduct.
  • 388
    • 67249092591 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See generally Exxon Shipping Co. v. Baker, 128 S. Ct. 2605, 2611 (2008) (dealing with the aggregate claims for punitive damages of the plaintiff and others, including commercial fisherman and Native Alaskans). These aggregative strategies would ultimately offer more protection than criminal defendants receive now because if a defendant commits a crime with a jurisdictional nexus available to twenty states, she can be punished separately and consecutively twenty times.
    • See generally Exxon Shipping Co. v. Baker, 128 S. Ct. 2605, 2611 (2008) (dealing with the aggregate claims for punitive damages of the plaintiff and "others, including commercial fisherman and Native Alaskans"). These aggregative strategies would ultimately offer more protection than criminal defendants receive now because if a defendant commits a crime with a jurisdictional nexus available to twenty states, she can be punished separately and consecutively twenty times.
  • 390
    • 67249134141 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Peter J. Boyer, The Bribe, NEW YORKER, May 19, 2008, at 44, 54 (describing how employees of State Farm Insurance, suspicious of the company's fraudulent practices, shared inculpatory information with private plaintiffs' lawyers who then passed that information on to law enforcement officers).
    • Cf. Peter J. Boyer, The Bribe, NEW YORKER, May 19, 2008, at 44, 54 (describing how employees of State Farm Insurance, suspicious of the company's fraudulent practices, shared inculpatory information with private plaintiffs' lawyers who then passed that information on to law enforcement officers).
  • 391
    • 67249153269 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Ann M. Simmons, Metrolink Killer Is Sentenced to 11 Life Terms in Prison, L.A. TIMES, Aug. 21, 2008, at B5 (reporting on a defendant who faced eleven consecutive counts of incarceration for the murders of eleven people caused by one action).
    • See, e.g., Ann M. Simmons, Metrolink Killer Is Sentenced to 11 Life Terms in Prison, L.A. TIMES, Aug. 21, 2008, at B5 (reporting on a defendant who faced eleven consecutive counts of incarceration for the murders of eleven people caused by one action).
  • 392
    • 67249120263 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The advantage to the state gained by making X litigate in two fora simultaneously is an unfair one, achieved only through the chance of having the wrongdoer distracted by two simultaneous proceedings.
    • The advantage to the state gained by making X litigate in two fora simultaneously is an unfair one, achieved only through the chance of having the wrongdoer distracted by two simultaneous proceedings.
  • 393
    • 67249110555 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It will be the defendant's responsibility to bring information of prior adjudications to the court's attention, since the defendant will be in the best position to inform a civil plaintiff that she has already been indicted. If there is a block because of coincidental criminal prosecution, the courts should allow the relevant statute of limitations to equitably toll in the event that the prosecution fails.
    • It will be the defendant's responsibility to bring information of prior adjudications to the court's attention, since the defendant will be in the best position to inform a civil plaintiff that she has already been indicted. If there is a "block" because of coincidental criminal prosecution, the courts should allow the relevant statute of limitations to equitably toll in the event that the prosecution fails.
  • 394
    • 67249103424 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See MILLER & WRIGHT, supra note 229, at 1002-05.
    • See MILLER & WRIGHT, supra note 229, at 1002-05.
  • 395
    • 67249155436 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Browning-Ferris Indus, of Vt., Inc. v. Kelco Disposal, Inc., 492 U.S. 257 (1989).
    • Browning-Ferris Indus, of Vt., Inc. v. Kelco Disposal, Inc., 492 U.S. 257 (1989).
  • 396
    • 67249135035 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 275-76
    • Id. at 275-76.
  • 397
    • 67249165050 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 275 n.21.
    • Id. at 275 n.21.
  • 398
    • 67249147434 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • If there were such review, it would likely follow the framework established under United States v. Bajakajian, 524 U.S. 321 (1998). That doctrinal framework, by emphasizing whether the punishment is grossly disproportionate to the underlying offense,
    • If there were such review, it would likely follow the framework established under United States v. Bajakajian, 524 U.S. 321 (1998). That doctrinal framework, by emphasizing whether the punishment is "grossly disproportionate" to the underlying offense,
  • 400
    • 84868993522 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See UTAH CODE ANN. §78B-8-201(3) (a) (2008) (granting to the plaintiff the first $50,000 of a punitive damages award and one-half of the excess of punitive damages over $50,000);
    • See UTAH CODE ANN. §78B-8-201(3) (a) (2008) (granting to the plaintiff the first $50,000 of a punitive damages award and one-half of the excess of punitive damages over $50,000);
  • 401
    • 84868990978 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • OR. REV. STAT. §31.735(a) (2007) (granting forty percent of the punitive damages award to the plaintiff).
    • OR. REV. STAT. §31.735(a) (2007) (granting forty percent of the punitive damages award to the plaintiff).
  • 402
    • 67249162291 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • That said, when the state collects damages from private entities, other practical problems worthy of attention can arise. See, at
    • See Markel, Retributive Damages, supra note 1, at 327-32. That said, when the state collects damages from private entities, other practical problems worthy of attention can arise.
    • Retributive Damages, supra note , vol.1 , pp. 327-332
    • Markel1
  • 403
    • 23044517542 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Governments, Citizens, and Injurious Industries, 75
    • See, e.g
    • See, e.g., Hanoch Dagan & James J. White, Governments, Citizens, and Injurious Industries, 75 N.Y.U. L. REV. 354 (2000).
    • (2000) N.Y.U. L. REV , vol.354
    • Dagan, H.1    White, J.J.2
  • 404
    • 67249121581 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Ewing v. California, 538 U.S. 11, 29-31 (2003) (finding that the defendant's history of felony recidivism helped to justify his sentence under a three-strikes law).
    • See Ewing v. California, 538 U.S. 11, 29-31 (2003) (finding that the defendant's "history of felony recidivism" helped to justify his sentence under a three-strikes law).
  • 405
    • 67249137558 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Bajakajian, 524 U.S. at 336 (observing the need for deference to the legislative penalty scheme and a willingness to strike down only those fines that are grossly disproportionate to the severity of the offense).
    • Cf. Bajakajian, 524 U.S. at 336 (observing the need for deference to the legislative penalty scheme and a willingness to strike down only those fines that are grossly disproportionate to the severity of the offense).
  • 406
    • 0346408771 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Tom Baker, Reconsidering Insurance for Punitive Damages, 1998 WIS. L. REV. 101, 115 ([T]here is little dispute that, on their face, most primary general and automobile policies provide coverage for punitive damages.). Nonetheless, insurers employ a variety of strategies to limit their exposure to paying punitive damages claims.
    • See Tom Baker, Reconsidering Insurance for Punitive Damages, 1998 WIS. L. REV. 101, 115 ("[T]here is little dispute that, on their face, most primary general and automobile policies provide coverage for punitive damages."). Nonetheless, insurers employ a variety of strategies to limit their exposure to paying punitive damages claims.
  • 408
    • 78149445628 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Revisiting the Noninsurable Costs of Accidents, 64
    • T] he legislative and judicial trend in the past several decades has been squarely in the direction of expanded insurability, See
    • See Catherine M. Sharkey, Revisiting the Noninsurable Costs of Accidents, 64 MD. L. REV. 409, 430 (2005) ("[T] he legislative and judicial trend in the past several decades has been squarely in the direction of expanded insurability.");
    • (2005) MD. L. REV , vol.409 , pp. 430
    • Sharkey, C.M.1
  • 410
    • 67249145725 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 428-29
    • Id. at 428-29.
  • 412
    • 67249132626 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also George L. Priest, Insurability and Punitive Damages, 40 ALA. L. REV. 1009, 1031 (1989).
    • see also George L. Priest, Insurability and Punitive Damages, 40 ALA. L. REV. 1009, 1031 (1989).
  • 413
    • 67249139469 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Eg., Nw. Nat'l Cas. Co. v. McNulty, 307 F.2d 432, 440 (5th Cir. 1962) (The policy considerations in a state where . .. punitive damages are awarded for punishment and deterrence, would seem to require that the damages rest ultimately as well [as] nominally on the party actually responsible for the wrong.),
    • Eg., Nw. Nat'l Cas. Co. v. McNulty, 307 F.2d 432, 440 (5th Cir. 1962) ("The policy considerations in a state where . .. punitive damages are awarded for punishment and deterrence, would seem to require that the damages rest ultimately as well [as] nominally on the party actually responsible for the wrong."),
  • 414
    • 84868993520 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • superseded by statute, VA. CODE ANN. §38.2-227 (2007) (providing that it is not against Virginia public policy to obtain insurance providing coverage for punitive damages owed due to negligence, including willful and wanton negligence, but that it is contrary to public policy to obtain insurance covering punitive damages owed because of intentional misconduct),
    • superseded by statute, VA. CODE ANN. §38.2-227 (2007) (providing that it is not against Virginia public policy to obtain insurance providing coverage for punitive damages owed due to "negligence, including willful and wanton negligence," but that it is contrary to public policy to obtain insurance covering punitive damages owed because of intentional misconduct),
  • 415
    • 67249138807 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • as recognized in United Servs. Auto. Ass'n v. Webb, 369 S.E.2d 196, 197 (Va. 1988).
    • as recognized in United Servs. Auto. Ass'n v. Webb, 369 S.E.2d 196, 197 (Va. 1988).
  • 416
    • 67249162999 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Priest, supra note 255, at 1029;
    • Priest, supra note 255, at 1029;
  • 417
    • 67249095857 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also Baker, supra note 252, at 114-25 (detailing insurance company mechanisms for coping with the moral hazard problem associated with punitive damages). Moral hazard has been defined as the phenomenon by which injury and activity rates increase as a response to a decrease in the expected costs of injury.
    • see also Baker, supra note 252, at 114-25 (detailing insurance company mechanisms for coping with the moral hazard problem associated with punitive damages). Moral hazard has been defined as the phenomenon by which injury and activity rates increase as a response to a decrease in the expected costs of injury.
  • 418
    • 67249114052 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Priest, supra note 255, at 1023 n.55.
    • See, e.g., Priest, supra note 255, at 1023 n.55.
  • 419
    • 67249085316 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Priest, supra note 255, at 1015 noting that in every insurance and punitive damages case studied by the author, the insurance policy excluded intentional acts and covered only harms neither expected nor intended from the standpoint of the insured
    • See, e.g., Priest, supra note 255, at 1015 (noting that in every insurance and punitive damages case studied by the author, the insurance policy excluded intentional acts and covered only harms "neither expected nor intended from the standpoint of the insured"
  • 420
    • 67249085766 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (quoting Am. Home Assurance Co. v. Safeway Steel Prods. Co., 743 S.W.2d 693, 695 (Tex. App. 1987))). Priest also explains how the exclusion of intentional conduct from insurance policies works to the benefit of lowering premiums for those insureds not intentionally engaging in acts causing harm and prevents losses to those who would suffer from intentional harms if insurance for such harms were permitted.
    • (quoting Am. Home Assurance Co. v. Safeway Steel Prods. Co., 743 S.W.2d 693, 695 (Tex. App. 1987))). Priest also explains how the exclusion of intentional conduct from insurance policies works to the benefit of lowering premiums for those "insureds not intentionally engaging in acts causing harm" and prevents losses to those who would suffer from intentional harms if insurance for such harms were permitted.
  • 421
    • 67249102134 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1026
    • Id. at 1026.
  • 422
    • 67249144111 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sharkey, supra note 253, at 432 n.118 (listing these states).
    • Sharkey, supra note 253, at 432 n.118 (listing these states).
  • 423
    • 67249115383 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The same complexity attaches when a state predicates retributive damages liability on a mens rea formula like wanton disregard
    • The same complexity attaches when a state predicates retributive damages liability on a mens rea formula like "wanton disregard."
  • 424
    • 67249142058 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Am. Sur. Co. of N.Y. v. Gold, 375 F.2d 523, 525 (10th Cir. 1966) ([W]e are convinced from the weight and logic of the case law that Kansas would hold a policy insuring against punitive damage awards to be violative of the public policy of that state . . ..);
    • See, e.g., Am. Sur. Co. of N.Y. v. Gold, 375 F.2d 523, 525 (10th Cir. 1966) ("[W]e are convinced from the weight and logic of the case law that Kansas would hold a policy insuring against punitive damage awards to be violative of the public policy of that state . . ..");
  • 425
    • 67249164618 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • McNulty, 307 F.2d at 433-34 (holding that an insurance policy providing coverage for punitive damages would contravene public policy);
    • McNulty, 307 F.2d at 433-34 (holding that an insurance policy providing coverage for punitive damages would "contravene public policy");
  • 426
    • 67249132155 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Crull v. Gleb, 382 S.W.2d 17, 23 (Mo. Ct. App. 1964) (We hold that to allow a motorist to insure himself against judgments imposed against him for punitive damages, which were assessed against him for his wanton, reckless or willful acts, would be contrary to public policy.).
    • Crull v. Gleb, 382 S.W.2d 17, 23 (Mo. Ct. App. 1964) ("We hold that to allow a motorist to insure himself against judgments imposed against him for punitive damages, which were assessed against him for his wanton, reckless or willful acts, would be contrary to public policy.").
  • 427
    • 67249143641 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • To be sure, the line between reckless misconduct and malicious misconduct can be hard to draw at times. Drunk driving-the conduct that motivates many punitive damages cases involving insurance coverage-might be thought of as a hard case. In most cases, the defendant's state of mind is understood to be reckless because there is a substantial and unjustifiable risk of serious injury to both the defendant (which thereby lessens the moral hazard effect) and to others. The defendant usually does not intend to or know that she will crash and hurt someone, and the risk of harm caused might not result in actual harm. Still, the conduct, even when harmless, is itself condemnable as a serious wrong because of the manifestly insufficient regard for the well-being of others that such conduct evinces. And if someone died as a result of the defendant's drunk driving, prosecutors might plausibly say that the defendant acted with such depraved-heart recklessness that the mens rea for common law murder
    • To be sure, the line between reckless misconduct and malicious misconduct can be hard to draw at times. Drunk driving-the conduct that motivates many punitive damages cases involving insurance coverage-might be thought of as a hard case. In most cases, the defendant's state of mind is understood to be reckless because there is a substantial and unjustifiable risk of serious injury to both the defendant (which thereby lessens the moral hazard effect) and to others. The defendant usually does not intend to or know that she will crash and hurt someone, and the risk of harm caused might not result in actual harm. Still, the conduct, even when harmless, is itself condemnable as a serious wrong because of the manifestly insufficient regard for the well-being of others that such conduct evinces. And if someone died as a result of the defendant's drunk driving, prosecutors might plausibly say that the defendant acted with such depraved-heart recklessness that the mens rea for common law murder would be satisfied.
  • 428
    • 84890464415 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See note 255, at, explaining the math and reasoning of the law of large numbers
    • See Priest, supra note 255, at 1021-22 (explaining the math and reasoning of the law of large numbers).
    • supra , pp. 1021-1022
    • Priest1
  • 429
    • 34548349188 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • But see Tom Baker & Sean J. Griffith, The Missing Monitor in Corporate Governance: The Directors' & Officers' Liability Insurer, 95 GEO. L.J. 1795, 1807-17 (2007) (providing some empirical qualitative evidence of instances in which insurers did not seek to invest in monitoring during the life of the insurance policy).
    • But see Tom Baker & Sean J. Griffith, The Missing Monitor in Corporate Governance: The Directors' & Officers' Liability Insurer, 95 GEO. L.J. 1795, 1807-17 (2007) (providing some empirical qualitative evidence of instances in which insurers did not seek to invest in monitoring during the life of the insurance policy).
  • 431
    • 34547457486 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Tom Baker & Sean J. Griffith, Predicting Corporate Governance Risk: Evidence from the Directors' & Officers'Liability Insurance Market, 74 U. CHI. L. REV. 487, 517 2007, noting that directors' and officers' liability insurance underwriters repeatedly told the authors that corporate culture and character are important considerations in assessing risk, Perhaps the insurers are making an economic mistake, but they would not be doing this risk sorting unless they thought that it was to their advantage to do so; in making the risk-selection choices, they are pricing the expected cost of punitive damages vis-àvis a particular client into the premium they charge. That said, Baker and Griffith argue that, at least in the context of directors' and officers' insurance, the levels of insurance purchased by management for the benefit of the shareholders will be inefficient and strongly influenced by agency costs
    • See Tom Baker & Sean J. Griffith, Predicting Corporate Governance Risk: Evidence from the Directors' & Officers'Liability Insurance Market, 74 U. CHI. L. REV. 487, 517 (2007) (noting that directors' and officers' liability insurance underwriters repeatedly told the authors that corporate culture and character are important considerations in assessing risk). Perhaps the insurers are making an economic mistake, but they would not be doing this risk sorting unless they thought that it was to their advantage to do so; in making the risk-selection choices, they are pricing the expected cost of punitive damages vis-àvis a particular client into the premium they charge. That said, Baker and Griffith argue that, at least in the context of directors' and officers' insurance, the levels of insurance purchased by management for the benefit of the shareholders will be inefficient and strongly influenced by agency costs.
  • 432
    • 67249152071 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Baker & Griffith, supra note 264, at 1800 (arguing that managers buy certain forms of directors' and officers' insurance for selfserving reasons).
    • See Baker & Griffith, supra note 264, at 1800 (arguing that managers buy certain forms of directors' and officers' insurance for "selfserving" reasons).
  • 433
    • 67249144525 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As Professor Miriam Baer rightly pointed out in a comment on an earlier draft, the possibility of experience-rating the insured should not obscure the fact that other factors (whether there is a hard or soft market for insurance, for example) can drown out the experience aspect of the premium. In other words, many market entrants might lower the premiums even for those who are prone to driving recklessly. Conversely, it is possible that the reduction in premium that one gets from driving extremely carefully might be overcome by the overall increase in car insurance when a major insurer goes belly-up and the insurance markets contract suddenly
    • As Professor Miriam Baer rightly pointed out in a comment on an earlier draft, the possibility of experience-rating the insured should not obscure the fact that other factors (whether there is a hard or soft market for insurance, for example) can drown out the experience aspect of the premium. In other words, many market entrants might lower the premiums even for those who are prone to driving recklessly. Conversely, it is possible that the reduction in premium that one gets from driving extremely carefully might be overcome by the overall increase in car insurance when a major insurer goes belly-up and the insurance markets contract suddenly.
  • 434
    • 67249140739 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As discussed supra note 265, however, insurers often have incentives to reduce information costs associated with specific investigations and simply follow the portfoliotheory views of insurance or actuarial tables associated with particular kinds of risk borne by particular buyers of insurance.
    • As discussed supra note 265, however, insurers often have incentives to reduce information costs associated with specific investigations and simply follow the portfoliotheory views of insurance or actuarial tables associated with particular kinds of risk borne by particular buyers of insurance.
  • 435
    • 33845776606 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Too Big to Fail: Moral Hazard in Auditing and the Need to Restructure the Industry Before It Unravels, 106
    • Most insurance underwriting exercises involve classifying risks using general actuarial tools rather than specific investigation, See also
    • See also Lawrence A. Cunningham, Too Big to Fail: Moral Hazard in Auditing and the Need to Restructure the Industry Before It Unravels, 106 COLUM. L. REV. 1698, 1743 (2006) ("Most insurance underwriting exercises involve classifying risks using general actuarial tools rather than specific investigation.").
    • (2006) COLUM. L. REV , vol.1698 , pp. 1743
    • Cunningham, L.A.1
  • 436
    • 67249119621 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • But see id. at 1743-44 discussing the types of insurance products that typically involve specific investigations, The fact that insurance companies choose to conduct their business this way is relevant; under my proposal, one is not mandating the availability of an insurance policy for retributive damages, but rather is permitting it. And if it is permitted, the insurance company should be able, within reason, to set the terms of the agreement and how it thinks it should proceed. Thus, I am not especially concerned that insurance companies might lose money by failing to monitor insureds closely during the life of the policy
    • But see id. at 1743-44 (discussing the types of insurance products that typically involve specific investigations). The fact that insurance companies choose to conduct their business this way is relevant; under my proposal, one is not mandating the availability of an insurance policy for retributive damages, but rather is permitting it. And if it is permitted, the insurance company should be able, within reason, to set the terms of the agreement and how it thinks it should proceed. Thus, I am not especially concerned that insurance companies might lose money by failing to monitor insureds closely during the life of the policy.
  • 437
    • 67249115812 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Baker & Griffith, supra note 264, at 1813
    • See Baker & Griffith, supra note 264, at 1813.
  • 438
    • 67249094695 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Should a legislature require that insurers only be able to write insurance policies that have a coinsurance scheme? It would be a practical concession to the negative appearance that some judges and scholars have said is created by permitting insurance for punitive damages. But it would also ensure that there is a direct, rather than muted, setback to the defendant's interests that would be independendy justifiable and warranted
    • Should a legislature require that insurers only be able to write insurance policies that have a coinsurance scheme? It would be a practical concession to the negative appearance that some judges and scholars have said is created by permitting insurance for punitive damages. But it would also ensure that there is a direct, rather than muted, setback to the defendant's interests that would be independendy justifiable and warranted.
  • 439
    • 33644604839 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Does Criminal Law Deter? A Behavioural Science Investigation, 24
    • providing reasons for skepticism about defendants' amenability to deterrence signals, See generally
    • See generally Paul H. Robinson & John Darley, Does Criminal Law Deter? A Behavioural Science Investigation, 24 OXFORD J. LEGAL STUD. 173 (2004) (providing reasons for skepticism about defendants' amenability to deterrence signals).
    • (2004) OXFORD J. LEGAL STUD , vol.173
    • Robinson, P.H.1    Darley, J.2
  • 440
    • 67249119160 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See CALABRESI, supra note 18, at 269-70 (arguing that in cases such as careless driving, when normal individuals can choose whether or not to engage in wrongful conduct before an accident, an appropriate noninsurable penalty is necessarily a more effective deterrent than an already paid insurance premium).
    • See CALABRESI, supra note 18, at 269-70 (arguing that in cases such as careless driving, when "normal individuals can choose whether or not to engage in wrongful conduct before an accident, an appropriate noninsurable penalty is necessarily a more effective deterrent than an already paid insurance premium").
  • 441
    • 67249134138 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Say a law student sees her drunk professor leaving the bar, stumbling into a car, and starting that car; the student then follows the professor (with a camcorder) for a mile, watching the professor swerve across the road. The professor ultimately drives off the road into some grass, hurting no one, and falls asleep. My scheme would have legislatures authorize persons to bring actions for retributive damages in instances like this. See Markel, Retributive Damages, supra note 1, at 279-86.
    • Say a law student sees her drunk professor leaving the bar, stumbling into a car, and starting that car; the student then follows the professor (with a camcorder) for a mile, watching the professor swerve across the road. The professor ultimately drives off the road into some grass, hurting no one, and falls asleep. My scheme would have legislatures authorize persons to bring actions for retributive damages in instances like this. See Markel, Retributive Damages, supra note 1, at 279-86.
  • 442
    • 67249097626 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Baker, supra note 252, at 129 (concluding that insurance availability will increase the likelihood that plaintiffs will bring suit).
    • Cf. Baker, supra note 252, at 129 (concluding that insurance availability will increase the likelihood that plaintiffs will bring suit).
  • 443
    • 67249151201 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In the context of purchasers of insurance, we also need to think carefully about the differences in treatment of defendants who are individuals versus those that are partnerships, and between public- versus private-firm defendants. First, with corporate entities, there is an agency-cost problem worth spotting: managers may underpurchase-or overpurchase-the amount of insurance needed to protect the interests of the owners. Second, the determination of how much insurance to purchase and who makes that decision may not relate well to who can nimbly respond to the appropriate signals established through insurance markets and who deserves the attribution of blame for failing to make good decisions. Thanks to Dave Hoffman for helping me recognize this. Additionally, the idea of moral hazard in the publicly held corporation has a different valence than when applied to an individual, for example. In the public corporation, the shareholders are indirectly paying for the insurance, while
    • In the context of purchasers of insurance, we also need to think carefully about the differences in treatment of defendants who are individuals versus those that are partnerships, and between public- versus private-firm defendants. First, with corporate entities, there is an agency-cost problem worth spotting: managers may underpurchase-or overpurchase-the amount of insurance needed to protect the interests of the owners. Second, the determination of how much insurance to purchase and who makes that decision may not relate well to who can nimbly respond to the appropriate signals established through insurance markets and who deserves the attribution of blame for failing to make good decisions. Thanks to Dave Hoffman for helping me recognize this. Additionally, the idea of moral hazard in the publicly held corporation has a different valence than when applied to an individual, for example. In the public corporation, the shareholders are indirectly paying for the insurance, while some risk manager is arranging for the corporation's yearly insurance policy, and some manager or director violates the law. In that case of disaggregation, insurance for retributive damages may be creating a hazard, but it is not necessarily a "moral" one, in the sense that the purchaser of the insurance is trying to benefit unduly through its lack of adequate care. For more on this,
  • 444
    • 49049085671 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see Miriam Hechler Baer, Insuring Corporate Crime, 83 IND L.J. 1035, 1083-84 (2008). Of course, ex ante, it is unclear why shareholders should be benefiting from structures that would insulate them from punishment for the wrongs that these structures of ownership and management perpetrate.
    • see Miriam Hechler Baer, Insuring Corporate Crime, 83 IND L.J. 1035, 1083-84 (2008). Of course, ex ante, it is unclear why shareholders should be benefiting from structures that would insulate them from punishment for the wrongs that these structures of ownership and management perpetrate.
  • 445
    • 67249161877 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Markel, Punitive Damages, supra note 9
    • See Markel, Punitive Damages, supra note 9.
  • 446
    • 67249092297 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See RICHARD V. ERICSON ET AL., INSURANCE AS GOVERNANCE ch. 8 (2003) (detailing ways in which insurers actively encourage those that they insure to adopt measures to limit risk and prevent loss);
    • See RICHARD V. ERICSON ET AL., INSURANCE AS GOVERNANCE ch. 8 (2003) (detailing ways in which insurers actively encourage those that they insure to adopt measures to limit risk and prevent loss);
  • 447
    • 67249114496 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sharkey, supra note 253, at 413 (Insurance companies, as private regulators, are well positioned to achieve deterrence through experience rating of firms and other actors, as well as by providing risk management services.).
    • Sharkey, supra note 253, at 413 ("Insurance companies, as private regulators, are well positioned to achieve deterrence through experience rating of firms and other actors, as well as by providing risk management services.").
  • 448
    • 67249107952 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Baker, supra note 252, at 110-11 (discussing how philosopher Jean Hampton's retributive theory incorporates concerns for prevention);
    • See Baker, supra note 252, at 110-11 (discussing how philosopher Jean Hampton's retributive theory incorporates concerns for prevention);
  • 449
    • 67249108819 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • arguing that under the theory of confrontational retributivism, the establishment of institutions furthering retributive justice will in practice facilitate the prevention of future wrongdoing, at
    • Markel, Retributive Damages, supra note 1, at 268 (arguing that under the theory of confrontational retributivism, the establishment of institutions furthering retributive justice will in practice facilitate the prevention of future wrongdoing).
    • Retributive Damages, supra note , vol.1 , pp. 268
    • Markel1
  • 450
    • 67249087325 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Whether such an insurance market is likely to develop in practice or to become too concentrated are questions left for another day. Cf. Baer, supra note 273, at 1092-94 (addressing these questions).
    • Whether such an insurance market is likely to develop in practice or to become too concentrated are questions left for another day. Cf. Baer, supra note 273, at 1092-94 (addressing these questions).
  • 451
    • 67249125173 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This concern for prevention is an aspect of the ex ante function of retributivism, discussed in Part II of Markel, Retributive Damages, supra note 1, and this rationale applies, quite naturally, to permitting insurance for compensatory, aggravated, and deterrence damages purposes too
    • This concern for prevention is an aspect of the ex ante function of retributivism, discussed in Part II of Markel, Retributive Damages, supra note 1, and this rationale applies, quite naturally, to permitting insurance for compensatory, aggravated, and deterrence damages purposes too.
  • 452
    • 67249084873 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Baker, supra note 252, at 112. Baker wrote this paragraph under the inspiration of Galanter and Luban's account of punitive damages as victim vindication.
    • Baker, supra note 252, at 112. Baker wrote this paragraph under the inspiration of Galanter and Luban's account of punitive damages as victim vindication.
  • 454
    • 67249149078 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (quoting Galanter & Luban, supra note 3, at 1432)). But with the right adjustment-replacing the value of the victim with the value of the social interest in equal liberty under law-I think the rest of the paragraph is exacdy correct in reflecting the public values of the retributive account in this project
    • (quoting Galanter & Luban, supra note 3, at 1432)). But with the right adjustment-replacing "the value of the victim" with the "value of the social interest in equal liberty under law"-I think the rest of the paragraph is exacdy correct in reflecting the public values of the retributive account in this project
  • 455
    • 67249117871 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • But cf. Nw. Nat'l Cas. Co. v. McNulty, 307 F.2d 432, 440 (5th Cir. 1962) (Wisdom, J.) (It is not disputed that insurance against criminal fines or penalties would be void as violative of public policy. The same public policy should invalidate any contract of insurance against the civil punishment that punitive damages represent),
    • But cf. Nw. Nat'l Cas. Co. v. McNulty, 307 F.2d 432, 440 (5th Cir. 1962) (Wisdom, J.) ("It is not disputed that insurance against criminal fines or penalties would be void as violative of public policy. The same public policy should invalidate any contract of insurance against the civil punishment that punitive damages represent"),
  • 456
    • 84868990970 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • superseded by statute, VA. CODE ANN. §38.2-227 (1986), as recognized in United Servs. Auto. Ass'n v. Webb, 369 S.E.2d 196, 197 (Va. 1988). Judge Wisdom, however, goes too far, for reasons that I hope my account explains.
    • superseded by statute, VA. CODE ANN. §38.2-227 (1986), as recognized in United Servs. Auto. Ass'n v. Webb, 369 S.E.2d 196, 197 (Va. 1988). Judge Wisdom, however, goes too far, for reasons that I hope my account explains.
  • 457
    • 67249141637 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., id. at 440 (Where a person is able to insure himself against punishment he gains a freedom of misconduct inconsistent with the establishment of sanctions against such misconduct.).
    • See, e.g., id. at 440 ("Where a person is able to insure himself against punishment he gains a freedom of misconduct inconsistent with the establishment of sanctions against such misconduct.").
  • 458
    • 67249123831 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • To facilitate the likelihood of greater monitoring and reduce the possibility of this kind of collusion, it might make sense for a jurisdiction to prefer insisting on an occurrence policy over a claims made policy. Under the former, the insurer at the time of the occurrence is required to pay, while under the claims made policy, the insurer who pays is the insurer at the time the claim is made. See Baer, supra note 273, at 1087 & n.255
    • To facilitate the likelihood of greater monitoring and reduce the possibility of this kind of collusion, it might make sense for a jurisdiction to prefer insisting on an "occurrence" policy over a "claims made" policy. Under the former, the insurer at the time of the occurrence is required to pay, while under the "claims made" policy, the insurer who pays is the insurer at the time the claim is made. See Baer, supra note 273, at 1087 & n.255
  • 459
    • 67249124267 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (citingjames D. Cox, Private Litigation and the Deterrence of Corporate Misconduct, LAW & CONTEMP. PROBS., Aug. 1997, at 1, 33).
    • (citingjames D. Cox, Private Litigation and the Deterrence of Corporate Misconduct, LAW & CONTEMP. PROBS., Aug. 1997, at 1, 33).
  • 460
    • 62549156836 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, note 5, at, expressing general support for insurance for the purpose of cost internalization damages
    • See Polinsky & Shavell, supra note 5, at 932 (expressing general support for insurance for the purpose of cost internalization damages);
    • supra , pp. 932
    • Polinsky1    Shavell2
  • 461
    • 67249146591 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • id. at 932 n.194 (citing others who share the authors' view).
    • id. at 932 n.194 (citing others who share the authors' view).
  • 462
    • 67249130439 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • But see supra note 91.
    • But see supra note 91.
  • 463
    • 0346408770 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See generally Tom Baker, Transforming Punishment into Compensation: In the Shadow of Punitive Damages, 1998 WIS. L. REV. 211, 234-45 (listing factors that may alter incentives in allocating damages);
    • See generally Tom Baker, Transforming Punishment into Compensation: In the Shadow of Punitive Damages, 1998 WIS. L. REV. 211, 234-45 (listing factors that may alter incentives in allocating damages);
  • 464
    • 0347669695 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Thomas Koenig, The Shadow Effect of Punitive Damages on Settlements, 1998 WIS. L. REV. 169, 172 ([H]yperbole and simple confusion may shape settlements in a more powerful way than empirical truths.).
    • Thomas Koenig, The Shadow Effect of Punitive Damages on Settlements, 1998 WIS. L. REV. 169, 172 ("[H]yperbole and simple confusion may shape settlements in a more powerful way than empirical truths.").
  • 465
    • 67249129570 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • But see Polinsky & Che, supra note 91, at 568 (noting that from an optimal deterrence perspective, settlements are good because they reduce litigation costs).
    • But see Polinsky & Che, supra note 91, at 568 (noting that from an optimal deterrence perspective, settlements are good because they reduce litigation costs).
  • 466
    • 67249095106 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The clergy sex-abuse scandal manifested these problems. See TIMOTHY D. LYT-TON, HOLDING BISHOPS ACCOUNTABLE: HOW LAWSUITS HELPED THE CATHOLIC CHURCH CONFRONT CLERGY SEXUAL ABUSE pt. 2 (2008) (describing the use of sealed setdements);
    • The clergy sex-abuse scandal manifested these problems. See TIMOTHY D. LYT-TON, HOLDING BISHOPS ACCOUNTABLE: HOW LAWSUITS HELPED THE CATHOLIC CHURCH CONFRONT CLERGY SEXUAL ABUSE pt. 2 (2008) (describing the use of sealed setdements);
  • 467
    • 33947511154 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also Scott Moss, Illuminating Secrecy: A New Economic Analysis of Confidential Settlements, 105 MICH. L. REV. 867, 870 (2007) (With so many lawsuits beginning with allegations of grievous social harm but ending with the legal equivalent of 'never mind,' confidential setdements have drawn increasingly fierce criticism recendy, attacked as ways defendants conceal serious misdeeds such as dissemination of hazardous products, discrimination, pollution, or sexual abuse. (footnotes omitted));
    • see also Scott Moss, Illuminating Secrecy: A New Economic Analysis of Confidential Settlements, 105 MICH. L. REV. 867, 870 (2007) ("With so many lawsuits beginning with allegations of grievous social harm but ending with the legal equivalent of 'never mind,' confidential setdements have drawn increasingly fierce criticism recendy, attacked as ways defendants conceal serious misdeeds such as dissemination of hazardous products, discrimination, pollution, or sexual abuse." (footnotes omitted));
  • 468
    • 67249155920 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Adam Liptak, Judges Seek to Ban Secret Settlements in South Carolina, N.Y. TIMES, Sept. 2, 2002, at Al (South Carolina's 10 active federal trial judges have unanimously voted to ban se-cret legal settlements, saying such agreements have made the courts complicit in hiding the truth about hazardous products, inept doctors and sexually abusive priests.).
    • Adam Liptak, Judges Seek to Ban Secret Settlements in South Carolina, N.Y. TIMES, Sept. 2, 2002, at Al ("South Carolina's 10 active federal trial judges have unanimously voted to ban se-cret legal settlements, saying such agreements have made the courts complicit in hiding the truth about hazardous products, inept doctors and sexually abusive priests.").
  • 469
    • 84868966191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The compensatory part of personal-injury awards is not taxable income for the victim, but most federal courts have said that punitive damages awards are taxable income. See I.R.C. §104(a) (2006) (providing that compensation received, whether by suit or agreement, on account of personal injuries or physical sickness is not included in gross income, with the exception of punitive damages). All the money in a settlement, however, would likely be described as compensatory, which creates a reason for the plaintiff to try to collude with the defendant against the state (or the insurance company).
    • The compensatory part of personal-injury awards is not taxable income for the victim, but most federal courts have said that punitive damages awards are taxable income. See I.R.C. §104(a) (2006) (providing that compensation received, whether by suit or agreement, on account of personal injuries or physical sickness is not included in gross income, with the exception of punitive damages). All the money in a settlement, however, would likely be described as "compensatory," which creates a reason for the plaintiff to try to collude with the defendant against the state (or the insurance company).
  • 470
    • 84868990964 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Baker, supra note 284, at 227-28 ([B]oth plaintiffs' and defense lawyers would prefer to see those aggravated damages 'in the guise of compensatory damages' rather than 'in the guise of punitive damages.' ⋯ For plaintiffs, the state share, the possibility of remittitur or reversal on appeal, and tax law are all important factors .... (footnotes omitted)).
    • Cf. Baker, supra note 284, at 227-28 ("[B]oth plaintiffs' and defense lawyers would prefer to see those aggravated damages 'in the guise of compensatory damages' rather than 'in the guise of punitive damages.' ⋯ For plaintiffs, the state share, the possibility of remittitur or reversal on appeal, and tax law are all important factors ...." (footnotes omitted)).
  • 471
    • 67249105964 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Iowa has a split-recovery scheme in which the state plays an active role, for example, in monitoring litigation. For a description of this scheme, see Sharkey, supra note 5, at 435
    • Iowa has a split-recovery scheme in which the state plays an active role, for example, in monitoring litigation. For a description of this scheme, see Sharkey, supra note 5, at 435.
  • 472
    • 22744456273 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Perhaps the state should be able to sell the action to a third party too. See generally Michael Abramowicz, On the Alienability of Legal Claims, 114 YALE L.J. 697, 699 (2004) (Courts increasingly have tolerated claim sales and have begun to view restraints on alienation skeptically.);
    • Perhaps the state should be able to sell the action to a third party too. See generally Michael Abramowicz, On the Alienability of Legal Claims, 114 YALE L.J. 697, 699 (2004) ("Courts increasingly have tolerated claim sales and have begun to view restraints on alienation skeptically.");
  • 473
    • 67249125171 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • cf. David Rosenberg, Deregulating Insurance Subrogation: Towards an Ex Ante Market in Tort Claims 307 (Harvard Law Sch. Pub. Law Research Paper No. 043, 2002), available at http://ssrn.com/abstract= 350940 (Competitive ex ante claims markets (including secondary markets for claim re-sale and aggregation) provide the most efficient and effective means of achieving the deterrence ends of tort liability and generating the highest clearance price for sellers of potential tort claims.).
    • cf. David Rosenberg, Deregulating Insurance Subrogation: Towards an Ex Ante Market in Tort Claims 307 (Harvard Law Sch. Pub. Law Research Paper No. 043, 2002), available at http://ssrn.com/abstract= 350940 ("Competitive ex ante claims markets (including secondary markets for claim re-sale and aggregation) provide the most efficient and effective means of achieving the deterrence ends of tort liability and generating the highest clearance price for sellers of potential tort claims.").
  • 474
    • 67249094693 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • There is a risk that the government will not obtain all the information that it needs to make a good decision, but the government has various civil and criminal strategies to ensure that there is a full reporting by the lawyers involved
    • There is a risk that the government will not obtain all the information that it needs to make a good decision, but the government has various civil and criminal strategies to ensure that there is a full reporting by the lawyers involved.
  • 475
    • 67249149810 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • But cf. Sharkey, supra note 5, at 445 (noting that the risk of sham litigation in the context of the author's proposal for compensatory societal damages still looms large). On setdement pressure generally,
    • But cf. Sharkey, supra note 5, at 445 (noting that the risk of sham litigation in the context of the author's proposal for compensatory societal damages still "looms large"). On setdement pressure generally,
  • 476
    • 0242287360 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • We're Scared to Death: Class Certification and Blackmail, 78
    • see
    • see Charles Silver, "We're Scared to Death": Class Certification and Blackmail, 78 N.Y.U. L. REV. 1357 (2003).
    • (2003) N.Y.U. L. REV , vol.1357
    • Silver, C.1
  • 478
    • 28344441525 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Once the defendant admitted to wrongdoing and settled with the state, such information could be stored in a registry of the sort described by Jim Gash, Solving the Multiple Punishments Problem: A Call for a National Punitive Damages Registry, 99 NW. U. L. REV. 1613, 1617 (2005), though some modifications would need to be made to be compatible with the structure proposed here.
    • Once the defendant admitted to wrongdoing and settled with the state, such information could be stored in a registry of the sort described by Jim Gash, Solving the Multiple Punishments Problem: A Call for a National Punitive Damages Registry, 99 NW. U. L. REV. 1613, 1617 (2005), though some modifications would need to be made to be compatible with the structure proposed here.
  • 479
    • 67249155435 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • One might think that this supervisory role would necessitate large-scale hiring efforts on the part of government bureaucracies, but such fears seem overstated in light of the relative infrequency with which punitive damages are awarded in most jurisdictions. See Sebok, supra note 5 (surveying empirical literature on the infrequency of punitive damages). That said, the structure proposed here would change the litigation game substantially, so it is inappropriate to dismiss these fears altogether.
    • One might think that this supervisory role would necessitate large-scale hiring efforts on the part of government bureaucracies, but such fears seem overstated in light of the relative infrequency with which punitive damages are awarded in most jurisdictions. See Sebok, supra note 5 (surveying empirical literature on the infrequency of punitive damages). That said, the structure proposed here would change the litigation game substantially, so it is inappropriate to dismiss these fears altogether.
  • 480
    • 34548637846 scopus 로고
    • Against Settlement, 93
    • For discussions of the of the problems associated with concealing settlements, see generally
    • For discussions of the of the problems associated with concealing settlements, see generally Owen M. Fiss, Against Settlement, 93 YALE L.J. 1073 (1984);
    • (1984) YALE L.J , vol.1073
    • Fiss, O.M.1
  • 481
    • 0347351058 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Under Cloak of Settlement, 82
    • Susan P. Koniak & George M. Cohen, Under Cloak of Settlement, 82 VA. L. REV. 1051 (1996);
    • (1996) VA. L. REV , vol.1051
    • Koniak, S.P.1    Cohen, G.M.2
  • 482
    • 67249149811 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Liptak, supra note 286
    • Liptak, supra note 286.
  • 483
    • 67249143643 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Moss, supra note 286 (arguing that the economic perspective on sealed settlements is more ambiguous than previously conceived).
    • See, e.g., Moss, supra note 286 (arguing that the economic perspective on sealed settlements is more ambiguous than previously conceived).
  • 484
    • 67249133239 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Judges already have a heightened obligation to supervise settlement classes, but they should not shirk their responsibility to consider nonclass setttlments that may have profound effects on similarly situated litigants in the future
    • Judges already have a heightened obligation to supervise settlement classes, but they should not shirk their responsibility to consider nonclass setttlments that may have profound effects on similarly situated litigants in the future.
  • 485
    • 84868988284 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Pain-and-Suffering Awards Let Juries Avoid New Limits
    • analyzing ways in which lawyers and juries circumvent state limits on punitive damages, and noting a particular case where a jury awarded a woman who endured sexual harassment at work $20 million in compensatory damages for pain and suffering, See, Oct. 28, at
    • See Adam Liptak, Pain-and-Suffering Awards Let Juries Avoid New Limits, N.Y. TIMES, Oct. 28, 2002, at A14 (analyzing ways in which lawyers and juries circumvent state limits on punitive damages, and noting a particular case where a jury awarded a woman who endured sexual harassment at work $20 million in compensatory damages for pain and suffering).
    • (2002) N.Y. TIMES
    • Liptak, A.1
  • 486
    • 67249108380 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • discussing the rationale of retributive damages as a tool to counteract misconduct by wealthy and powerful persons and entities, See
    • See Markel, Retributive Damages, supra note 1, pt. IV (discussing the rationale of retributive damages as a tool to counteract misconduct by wealthy and powerful persons and entities).
    • Retributive Damages, supra note , vol.1 , Issue.PART. IV
    • Markel1
  • 487
    • 38949164664 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • These instructions are a substantially modified version of the kind found, note 5, app, some places, having mostly to do with cost internalization, I expressly borrow the language from their proposed jury instructions
    • These instructions are a substantially modified version of the kind found in Polinsky & Shavell, supra note 5, app. In some places, having mostly to do with cost internalization, I expressly borrow the language from their proposed jury instructions.
    • supra
    • in Polinsky1    Shavell2
  • 489
    • 67249157642 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note that these instructions accord with what I view to be the correct reading of Philip Morris, not what I think would logically be entailed by an unbridled prioritization of cost internalization.
    • Note that these instructions accord with what I view to be the correct reading of Philip Morris, not what I think would logically be entailed by an unbridled prioritization of cost internalization.
  • 490
    • 67249103858 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • These amounts should ultimately be adjusted to reflect appropriate taxsensitivity judgments, as developed in a subsequent article on the taxation of punitive damages that I am writing with Gregg Polsky. Markel & Polsky, supra note 9
    • These amounts should ultimately be adjusted to reflect appropriate taxsensitivity judgments, as developed in a subsequent article on the taxation of punitive damages that I am writing with Gregg Polsky. Markel & Polsky, supra note 9.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.