메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 18, Issue 4, 1999, Pages 407-441

Kant on wrongdoing, desert, and punishment

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0033479999     PISSN: 01675249     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.2307/3505232     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (44)

References (88)
  • 1
    • 0041582209 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • My own project for some time has been to see how far Kant's basic moral theory, properly understood and modified as necessary, can be made plausible as at least a candidate for serious consideration in contemporary philosophical discussions. This requires, I think, sympathetic reconstruction and extension of certain core Kantian ideas but also critically abandoning some of Kant's ideas on particular issues that prove to be untenable and unwarranted by Kant's more basic theory.
  • 2
    • 0004048289 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Harvard University Press
    • John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1971), p. 256.
    • (1971) A Theory of Justice , pp. 256
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 3
    • 0004291536 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • trans. by Mary Gregor Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • See Immanuel Kant, The Metaphysics of Morals, trans. by Mary Gregor (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), hereafter abbreviated MM, pp. 147-156 [6: 383-394] and 198-218 [6: 448-474]. Bracketed numbers refer to the standard Prussian Academy edition, volume and pages.
    • (1996) The Metaphysics of Morals
    • Kant, I.1
  • 4
    • 0042083225 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [6: 383-394] and 198-218 [6: 448-474]. Bracketed numbers refer to the standard Prussian Academy edition, volume and pages
    • See Immanuel Kant, The Metaphysics of Morals, trans. by Mary Gregor (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), hereafter abbreviated MM, pp. 147-156 [6: 383-394] and 198-218 [6: 448-474]. Bracketed numbers refer to the standard Prussian Academy edition, volume and pages.
    • MM , pp. 147-156
  • 5
    • 0042584214 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 6: 218-221
    • MM, pp. 20-22 [6: 218-221].
    • MM , pp. 20-22
  • 6
    • 0011606684 scopus 로고
    • Perpetual Peace
    • Hans Reiss, ed., Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2nd ed.
    • See Kant's Perpetual Peace in Hans Reiss, ed., Kant: Political Writings (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2nd ed., 1991), pp. 112-123.
    • (1991) Kant: Political Writings , pp. 112-123
    • Kant1
  • 7
    • 0042584217 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 6: 331-337
    • See, for example, MM, pp. 104-110 [6: 331-337].
    • MM , pp. 104-110
  • 8
    • 0041582197 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [400-401] and 188-189 [438-440]
    • MM, pp. 160-161 [400-401] and 188-189 [438-440]; and Immanuel Kant, Critique of Practical Reason, trans. Mary Gregor (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997), hereafter abbreviated CPrR, pp. 82-83 [98-99], and Religion Within the Limits of Reason Alone, eds., T. M. Greene and H. H. Hudson (New York: Harper and Row, 1960), pp. 71-72, 135-136, 173-175; Lectures on Ethics, ed. by Peter Heath and J. B. Schneewind (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997), pp. 88-89 [27: 297-298] and 130-135 [27: 351-357].
    • MM , pp. 160-161
  • 9
    • 0004183724 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • trans. Mary Gregor Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • MM, pp. 160-161 [400-401] and 188-189 [438-440]; and Immanuel Kant, Critique of Practical Reason, trans. Mary Gregor (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997), hereafter abbreviated CPrR, pp. 82-83 [98-99], and Religion Within the Limits of Reason Alone, eds., T. M. Greene and H. H. Hudson (New York: Harper and Row, 1960), pp. 71-72, 135-136, 173-175; Lectures on Ethics, ed. by Peter Heath and J. B. Schneewind (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997), pp. 88-89 [27: 297-298] and 130-135 [27: 351-357].
    • (1997) Critique of Practical Reason
    • Kant, I.1
  • 10
    • 0042584218 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [98-99]
    • MM, pp. 160-161 [400-401] and 188-189 [438-440]; and Immanuel Kant, Critique of Practical Reason, trans. Mary Gregor (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997), hereafter abbreviated CPrR, pp. 82-83 [98-99], and Religion Within the Limits of Reason Alone, eds., T. M. Greene and H. H. Hudson (New York: Harper and Row, 1960), pp. 71-72, 135-136, 173-175; Lectures on Ethics, ed. by Peter Heath and J. B. Schneewind (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997), pp. 88-89 [27: 297-298] and 130-135 [27: 351-357].
    • CPrR , pp. 82-83
  • 11
    • 0003411955 scopus 로고
    • New York: Harper and Row
    • MM, pp. 160-161 [400-401] and 188-189 [438-440]; and Immanuel Kant, Critique of Practical Reason, trans. Mary Gregor (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997), hereafter abbreviated CPrR, pp. 82-83 [98-99], and Religion Within the Limits of Reason Alone, eds., T. M. Greene and H. H. Hudson (New York: Harper and Row, 1960), pp. 71-72, 135-136, 173-175; Lectures on Ethics, ed. by Peter Heath and J. B. Schneewind (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997), pp. 88-89 [27: 297-298] and 130-135 [27: 351-357].
    • (1960) Religion Within the Limits of Reason Alone , pp. 71-72
    • Greene, T.M.1    Hudson, H.H.2
  • 12
    • 0004207225 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, [27: 297-298] and 130-135 [27: 351-357]
    • MM, pp. 160-161 [400-401] and 188-189 [438-440]; and Immanuel Kant, Critique of Practical Reason, trans. Mary Gregor (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997), hereafter abbreviated CPrR, pp. 82-83 [98-99], and Religion Within the Limits of Reason Alone, eds., T. M. Greene and H. H. Hudson (New York: Harper and Row, 1960), pp. 71-72, 135-136, 173-175; Lectures on Ethics, ed. by Peter Heath and J. B. Schneewind (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997), pp. 88-89 [27: 297-298] and 130-135 [27: 351-357].
    • (1997) Lectures on Ethics , pp. 88-89
    • Heath, P.1    Schneewind, J.B.2
  • 13
    • 0039122975 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kant's Theory of Punishment: Deterrence in its Threat, Retribution in its Execution
    • This has been argued by several scholars in recent years. See B. Sharon Byrd, "Kant's Theory of Punishment: Deterrence in its Threat, Retribution in its Execution," Law and Philosophy 8(2) (1989), pp. 151-200; Don E. Scheid, "Kant's Retributivism," Ethics 93 (1983), pp. 262-282; Sarah Holtman, "Toward Social Reform: Kant's Penal Theory Reinterpreted," Utilitas 9 (1997), pp. 3-21; Thomas E. Hill, Jr., "Kant on Punishment: A Coherent Mix of Deterrence and Retribution?" in Jahrbuch fur Recht und Ethik: Annual Review of Law and Ethics 5 (1997), pp. 291-314. For other interpretations see Jeffrie Murphy, "Kant's Theory of Criminal Punishment" in Jeffrie Murphy, ed., Retribution, Justice and Therapy: Essays in the Philosophy of Law (Dordrecht, Holland: D. Reidel, 1979), pp. 82- 92, and "Does Kant have a Theory of Punishment?" Columbia Law Review 87(3) (1987), pp. 509-532, and Samuel Fleischacker, "Kant's Theory of Punishment" in Howard L. Williams, ed., Essays on Kant's Political Philosophy (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1992), pp. 191-212.
    • (1989) Law and Philosophy , vol.8 , Issue.2 , pp. 151-200
    • Sharon Byrd, B.1
  • 14
    • 0039122975 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kant's Retributivism
    • This has been argued by several scholars in recent years. See B. Sharon Byrd, "Kant's Theory of Punishment: Deterrence in its Threat, Retribution in its Execution," Law and Philosophy 8(2) (1989), pp. 151-200; Don E. Scheid, "Kant's Retributivism," Ethics 93 (1983), pp. 262-282; Sarah Holtman, "Toward Social Reform: Kant's Penal Theory Reinterpreted," Utilitas 9 (1997), pp. 3-21; Thomas E. Hill, Jr., "Kant on Punishment: A Coherent Mix of Deterrence and Retribution?" in Jahrbuch fur Recht und Ethik: Annual Review of Law and Ethics 5 (1997), pp. 291-314. For other interpretations see Jeffrie Murphy, "Kant's Theory of Criminal Punishment" in Jeffrie Murphy, ed., Retribution, Justice and Therapy: Essays in the Philosophy of Law (Dordrecht, Holland: D. Reidel, 1979), pp. 82- 92, and "Does Kant have a Theory of Punishment?" Columbia Law Review 87(3) (1987), pp. 509-532, and Samuel Fleischacker, "Kant's Theory of Punishment" in Howard L. Williams, ed., Essays on Kant's Political Philosophy (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1992), pp. 191-212.
    • (1983) Ethics , vol.93 , pp. 262-282
    • Scheid, D.E.1
  • 15
    • 0009264395 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Toward Social Reform: Kant's Penal Theory Reinterpreted
    • This has been argued by several scholars in recent years. See B. Sharon Byrd, "Kant's Theory of Punishment: Deterrence in its Threat, Retribution in its Execution," Law and Philosophy 8(2) (1989), pp. 151-200; Don E. Scheid, "Kant's Retributivism," Ethics 93 (1983), pp. 262-282; Sarah Holtman, "Toward Social Reform: Kant's Penal Theory Reinterpreted," Utilitas 9 (1997), pp. 3-21; Thomas E. Hill, Jr., "Kant on Punishment: A Coherent Mix of Deterrence and Retribution?" in Jahrbuch fur Recht und Ethik: Annual Review of Law and Ethics 5 (1997), pp. 291-314. For other interpretations see Jeffrie Murphy, "Kant's Theory of Criminal Punishment" in Jeffrie Murphy, ed., Retribution, Justice and Therapy: Essays in the Philosophy of Law (Dordrecht, Holland: D. Reidel, 1979), pp. 82- 92, and "Does Kant have a Theory of Punishment?" Columbia Law Review 87(3) (1987), pp. 509-532, and Samuel Fleischacker, "Kant's Theory of Punishment" in Howard L. Williams, ed., Essays on Kant's Political Philosophy (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1992), pp. 191-212.
    • (1997) Utilitas , vol.9 , pp. 3-21
    • Holtman, S.1
  • 16
    • 0039122975 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kant on Punishment: A Coherent Mix of Deterrence and Retribution?
    • This has been argued by several scholars in recent years. See B. Sharon Byrd, "Kant's Theory of Punishment: Deterrence in its Threat, Retribution in its Execution," Law and Philosophy 8(2) (1989), pp. 151-200; Don E. Scheid, "Kant's Retributivism," Ethics 93 (1983), pp. 262-282; Sarah Holtman, "Toward Social Reform: Kant's Penal Theory Reinterpreted," Utilitas 9 (1997), pp. 3-21; Thomas E. Hill, Jr., "Kant on Punishment: A Coherent Mix of Deterrence and Retribution?" in Jahrbuch fur Recht und Ethik: Annual Review of Law and Ethics 5 (1997), pp. 291-314. For other interpretations see Jeffrie Murphy, "Kant's Theory of Criminal Punishment" in Jeffrie Murphy, ed., Retribution, Justice and Therapy: Essays in the Philosophy of Law (Dordrecht, Holland: D. Reidel, 1979), pp. 82- 92, and "Does Kant have a Theory of Punishment?" Columbia Law Review 87(3) (1987), pp. 509-532, and Samuel Fleischacker, "Kant's Theory of Punishment" in Howard L. Williams, ed., Essays on Kant's Political Philosophy (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1992), pp. 191-212.
    • (1997) Jahrbuch fur Recht und Ethik: Annual Review of Law and Ethics , vol.5 , pp. 291-314
    • Hill T.E., Jr.1
  • 17
    • 0039122975 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kant's Theory of Criminal Punishment
    • Jeffrie Murphy, ed., Dordrecht, Holland: D. Reidel
    • This has been argued by several scholars in recent years. See B. Sharon Byrd, "Kant's Theory of Punishment: Deterrence in its Threat, Retribution in its Execution," Law and Philosophy 8(2) (1989), pp. 151-200; Don E. Scheid, "Kant's Retributivism," Ethics 93 (1983), pp. 262-282; Sarah Holtman, "Toward Social Reform: Kant's Penal Theory Reinterpreted," Utilitas 9 (1997), pp. 3-21; Thomas E. Hill, Jr., "Kant on Punishment: A Coherent Mix of Deterrence and Retribution?" in Jahrbuch fur Recht und Ethik: Annual Review of Law and Ethics 5 (1997), pp. 291-314. For other interpretations see Jeffrie Murphy, "Kant's Theory of Criminal Punishment" in Jeffrie Murphy, ed., Retribution, Justice and Therapy: Essays in the Philosophy of Law (Dordrecht, Holland: D. Reidel, 1979), pp. 82-92, and "Does Kant have a Theory of Punishment?" Columbia Law Review 87(3) (1987), pp. 509-532, and Samuel Fleischacker, "Kant's Theory of Punishment" in Howard L. Williams, ed., Essays on Kant's Political Philosophy (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1992), pp. 191-212.
    • (1979) Retribution, Justice and Therapy: Essays in the Philosophy of Law , pp. 82-92
    • Murphy, J.1
  • 18
    • 0039122975 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Does Kant have a Theory of Punishment?
    • This has been argued by several scholars in recent years. See B. Sharon Byrd, "Kant's Theory of Punishment: Deterrence in its Threat, Retribution in its Execution," Law and Philosophy 8(2) (1989), pp. 151-200; Don E. Scheid, "Kant's Retributivism," Ethics 93 (1983), pp. 262-282; Sarah Holtman, "Toward Social Reform: Kant's Penal Theory Reinterpreted," Utilitas 9 (1997), pp. 3-21; Thomas E. Hill, Jr., "Kant on Punishment: A Coherent Mix of Deterrence and Retribution?" in Jahrbuch fur Recht und Ethik: Annual Review of Law and Ethics 5 (1997), pp. 291-314. For other interpretations see Jeffrie Murphy, "Kant's Theory of Criminal Punishment" in Jeffrie Murphy, ed., Retribution, Justice and Therapy: Essays in the Philosophy of Law (Dordrecht, Holland: D. Reidel, 1979), pp. 82- 92, and "Does Kant have a Theory of Punishment?" Columbia Law Review 87(3) (1987), pp. 509-532, and Samuel Fleischacker, "Kant's Theory of Punishment" in Howard L. Williams, ed., Essays on Kant's Political Philosophy (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1992), pp. 191-212.
    • (1987) Columbia Law Review , vol.87 , Issue.3 , pp. 509-532
  • 19
    • 0039122975 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kant's Theory of Punishment
    • Howard L. Williams, ed., Chicago: University of Chicago Press
    • This has been argued by several scholars in recent years. See B. Sharon Byrd, "Kant's Theory of Punishment: Deterrence in its Threat, Retribution in its Execution," Law and Philosophy 8(2) (1989), pp. 151-200; Don E. Scheid, "Kant's Retributivism," Ethics 93 (1983), pp. 262-282; Sarah Holtman, "Toward Social Reform: Kant's Penal Theory Reinterpreted," Utilitas 9 (1997), pp. 3-21; Thomas E. Hill, Jr., "Kant on Punishment: A Coherent Mix of Deterrence and Retribution?" in Jahrbuch fur Recht und Ethik: Annual Review of Law and Ethics 5 (1997), pp. 291-314. For other interpretations see Jeffrie Murphy, "Kant's Theory of Criminal Punishment" in Jeffrie Murphy, ed., Retribution, Justice and Therapy: Essays in the Philosophy of Law (Dordrecht, Holland: D. Reidel, 1979), pp. 82- 92, and "Does Kant have a Theory of Punishment?" Columbia Law Review 87(3) (1987), pp. 509-532, and Samuel Fleischacker, "Kant's Theory of Punishment" in Howard L. Williams, ed., Essays on Kant's Political Philosophy (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1992), pp. 191-212.
    • (1992) Essays on Kant's Political Philosophy , pp. 191-212
    • Fleischacker, S.1
  • 20
    • 79957893237 scopus 로고
    • Guilt and Suffering
    • Here I use the term "suffering" broadly as a stand-in for a variety of terms that mark subtle distinctions that are important in some other contexts (e.g. "pain," "discomfort," "misery," "trouble," "harm," "deprivation," etc.) The connotation of undergoing unwelcome experiences passively is perhaps typically apt in discussions of punishment, but, as Morris points out, experiencing pain is not always suffering pain, for example, if (as in masochism) one is not disposed to avoid the pain. For this reason, though I shall often continue to use the term "suffering" in a broad sense, those who welcome the painful experience of guilt feelings as an inseparable aspect of a process of reform and restoration of relations may not, strictly speaking, be suffering the pangs of guilt. Herbert Morris, "Guilt and Suffering," Philosophy East & West 21(4) (1971), pp. 89-110.
    • (1971) Philosophy East & West , vol.21 , Issue.4 , pp. 89-110
    • Morris, H.1
  • 21
    • 0042584221 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Utilitarianism now comes in many varieties, but my remarks here, I believe, apply to most familiar versions.
  • 22
    • 0041582181 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • When I say that someone aware of doing wrong is "liable to suffer" I mean more than the trivial point that if various, perhaps accidental, circumstances occur something may cause the person to suffer. The point is, rather, that the person is in a condition that makes the ensuing suffering what is an expected, normal, realization of a disposition inherent in the recognition. Thus the utilitarian's answer to the first question, strictly speaking, is "no, there is no such liability in wrongdoing, or even in recognition of one's wrongdoing, there is only a contingent 'likelihood' given favorable social conditions."
  • 23
    • 0004240210 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon Press, ch. 2
    • A modest version would say merely that there is some reason, apart from the consequences, for us to bring it about that wrongdoers suffer. This seems to be W. D. Ross's view, for the prima facie duty of justice, as he presents it, is a duty to promote the proportionality of virtue and happiness. W. D. Ross, The Right and the Good (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1930), ch. 2.
    • (1930) The Right and the Good
    • Ross, W.D.1
  • 24
    • 0042083215 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • By "retributive policies" I mean such principles as that only the guilty ought to be punished, that all the guilty ought to be punished, that the severity of the punishment should be proportionate to the crime, and that the punishment should "fit" the crime in kind, as in "an eye for an eye" and "he who kills must die." An obvious example of a mixed theory would be one that held several of these policies quite firmly but tried to justify doing so by appeal to utilitarian concerns, e.g. their value for deterrence, satisfaction of victims, etc. I shall argue that Kant, with regard to judicial punishment, holds a mixed theory, though he is far from a utilitarian in his account of what justifies legal practices and policies.
  • 25
    • 0002921553 scopus 로고
    • Two Concepts of Rules
    • The distinction between the rules of a practice and what justifies having the practice was made prominent in John Rawls' "Two Concepts of Rules," The Philosophical Review 64 (1955), pp. 3-32. H.L.A. Hart famously employed the distinction in his essays on punishment, e.g. Punishment and Responsibility (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1968). The distinction is also important in essays on Kant's theory of punishment, e.g. in the articles of Byrd and Scheid previously cited, and in Herbert Morris's classic essay, "Persons and Punishment," The Monist (1968), pp. 31-63.
    • (1955) The Philosophical Review , vol.64 , pp. 3-32
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 26
    • 0004244925 scopus 로고
    • famously employed the distinction in his essays on punishment, Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • The distinction between the rules of a practice and what justifies having the practice was made prominent in John Rawls' "Two Concepts of Rules," The Philosophical Review 64 (1955), pp. 3-32. H.L.A. Hart famously employed the distinction in his essays on punishment, e.g. Punishment and Responsibility (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1968). The distinction is also important in essays on Kant's theory of punishment, e.g. in the articles of Byrd and Scheid previously cited, and in Herbert Morris's classic essay, "Persons and Punishment," The Monist (1968), pp. 31-63.
    • (1968) Punishment and Responsibility
    • Hart, H.L.A.1
  • 27
    • 0042534377 scopus 로고
    • Persons and Punishment
    • The distinction between the rules of a practice and what justifies having the practice was made prominent in John Rawls' "Two Concepts of Rules," The Philosophical Review 64 (1955), pp. 3-32. H.L.A. Hart famously employed the distinction in his essays on punishment, e.g. Punishment and Responsibility (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1968). The distinction is also important in essays on Kant's theory of punishment, e.g. in the articles of Byrd and Scheid previously cited, and in Herbert Morris's classic essay, "Persons and Punishment," The Monist (1968), pp. 31-63.
    • (1968) The Monist , pp. 31-63
    • Morris, H.1
  • 28
    • 0042584220 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • As Gerald Postema has pointed out to me, there are significant distinctions that a fuller discussion would need to take into account. For example, advocates of the nonpractical version might have different grounds for rejecting the reason-giving implications that the terms "good in itself", "fitting," and "reasonably to be wished" ordinarily have for us. Most obviously, it might be thought that, due to human imperfection, we lack the knowledge and power required for us to have the authority, or standing, to judge and punish wrongdoers in proportionate to their inner moral qualities. Alternatively, it might be held assessments of what we have reason to do are fundamentally distinct from, and partially independent of evaluations of states of affairs as (intrinsically) good, or fitting, in the sense that they are (in themselves) reasonably to be wished for. Thus, apart from our limitations of knowledge and power, Kant might have embraced the proportionate suffering of wrongdoers, as he did the success of the French Revolution, as an outcome that good people can reasonably hope for without his thereby implying that these are causes to which he, and others, have reason to contribute. This is an implausible view, I think, because of its initial assumption that suffering proportionate to wrongdoing is in itself "to be wished" and not because "to be wished" implies "reasons to seek." There are complex issues here, however, that I cannot pursue now.
  • 29
    • 0043084996 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • A person's faith, hopes, and wishes about what God ("fittingly") will do may, of course, have an indirect influence on the person's conduct. The crucial point is that the belief that "God has reasons to make the wicked suffer" does not license us to "help" in the project.
  • 30
    • 0004207225 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [27: 287], 309 [27: 553]
    • See, for example, Kant's Lectures on Ethics, pp. 79 [27: 287], 309 [27: 553], CPrR, pp. 34-35 [5: 37-38], 53 [5: 61], 84 [5: 1099-1100], and 103-110 [5: 124-132]; Religion within the Limits of Reason Alone, pp. 63, 67, 107, 117.
    • Lectures on Ethics , pp. 79
    • Kant1
  • 31
    • 0041582194 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [5: 37-38], 53 [5: 61], 84 [5: 1099-1100], and 103-110 5: 124-132
    • See, for example, Kant's Lectures on Ethics, pp. 79 [27: 287], 309 [27: 553], CPrR, pp. 34-35 [5: 37-38], 53 [5: 61], 84 [5: 1099-1100], and 103-110 [5: 124-132]; Religion within the Limits of Reason Alone, pp. 63, 67, 107, 117.
    • CPrR , pp. 34-35
  • 32
    • 84905878412 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, for example, Kant's Lectures on Ethics, pp. 79 [27: 287], 309 [27: 553], CPrR, pp. 34-35 [5: 37-38], 53 [5: 61], 84 [5: 1099-1100], and 103-110 [5: 124-132]; Religion within the Limits of Reason Alone, pp. 63, 67, 107, 117.
    • Religion Within the Limits of Reason Alone , pp. 63
  • 33
    • 0043085005 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Throughout my discussion I mean "wrongdoing" in an ordinary sense, broad enough to include many morally objectionable acts that are not crimes. In his philosophy of law (the Rechtslehre) Kant uses terms translated as "right" (recht) and "wrong" (unrecht) in a narrower sense, implying legal enforceability. Thus, in this narrower sense, we would not call an act wrong (unrecht) unless convinced that it is a kind that persons can be justifiably coerced to avoid. This, however, leaves open the question what makes acts wrong in the sense that implies justifiability of coercion, for example, whether this depends on contingent facts as it does under utilitarianism.
  • 34
    • 0041582205 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [6: 211-221].
    • MM, pp. 11-22 [6: 211-221]. For a fuller explanation, see "Kant's Theory of Practical Reason," in my Dignity and Practical Reason in Kant's Moral Theory (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1992), hereafter DPrR, pp. 123-146.
    • MM , pp. 11-22
  • 35
    • 60949475816 scopus 로고
    • Kant's Theory of Practical Reason
    • Ithaca: Cornell University Press
    • MM, pp. 11-22 [6: 211-221]. For a fuller explanation, see "Kant's Theory of Practical Reason," in my Dignity and Practical Reason in Kant's Moral Theory (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1992), hereafter DPrR, pp. 123-146.
    • (1992) Dignity and Practical Reason in Kant's Moral Theory
  • 36
    • 0041582195 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MM, pp. 11-22 [6: 211-221]. For a fuller explanation, see "Kant's Theory of Practical Reason," in my Dignity and Practical Reason in Kant's Moral Theory (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1992), hereafter DPrR, pp. 123-146.
    • DPrR , pp. 123-146
  • 37
    • 0004305896 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • trans. Mary Gregor Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Immanuel Kant, Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, trans. Mary Gregor (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997), hereafter abbreviated as G, pp. 56-66 [4: 450-463].
    • (1997) Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals
    • Kant, I.1
  • 38
    • 0042083232 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 4: 450-463
    • Immanuel Kant, Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, trans. Mary Gregor (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997), hereafter abbreviated as G, pp. 56-66 [4: 450-463].
    • G , pp. 56-66
  • 39
    • 0042083230 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [4: 428-437]
    • G, pp. 37-44 [4: 428-437].
    • G , pp. 37-44
  • 40
    • 0041582203 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [4: 431-432]
    • G, pp. 39-40 [4: 431-432].
    • G , pp. 39-40
  • 41
    • 0043084995 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 43 [4: 433-437]
    • G, pp. 41-43 [4: 433-437]. For interpretative comments, see DPrR, pp. 58- 66, 226-250.
    • G , pp. 41
  • 42
    • 0042584182 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • G, pp. 41-43 [4: 433-437]. For interpretative comments, see DPrR, pp. 58-66, 226-250.
    • DPrR , pp. 58-66
  • 43
    • 0042584215 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [6: 386-394]
    • MM, pp. 150-156 [6: 386-394].
    • MM , pp. 150-156
  • 44
    • 0039035769 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Happiness and Human Flourishing
    • I argue for this in "Happiness and Human Flourishing," Social Philosophy and Policy 16(1) (1999), pp. 143-175.
    • (1999) Social Philosophy and Policy , vol.16 , Issue.1 , pp. 143-175
  • 45
    • 4243440748 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [6: 477ff]
    • MM, pp. 221ff [6: 477ff]; also Immanuel Kant, Education (Ann Arbor: The University of Michigan Press, 1960), pp. 83-121.
    • MM
  • 46
    • 0004224742 scopus 로고
    • Ann Arbor: The University of Michigan Press
    • MM, pp. 221ff [6: 477ff]; also Immanuel Kant, Education (Ann Arbor: The University of Michigan Press, 1960), pp. 83-121.
    • (1960) Education , pp. 83-121
    • Kant, I.1
  • 47
    • 0043084998 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [6: 393-394]
    • Kant suggests that the duty to promote the happiness of others leads to an indirect duty to be concerned with their moral well-being insofar as their doing wrong will lead them to suffer pangs of conscience. Beneficence also should lead us to want to prevent others from wrongfully interfering with the happiness of others, but the basic end here is the (permissible) happiness of those who would be harmed, not the moral goodness of those who would wrongfully harm them. MM, pp. 156 [6: 393-394].
    • MM , pp. 156
  • 48
    • 0042083221 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Our failure could be with respect to satisfying an "indirectly ethical" duty to obey the law, but, if so, we are concerned with it here as a moral offense, not merely as a legal one.
  • 49
    • 0042218931 scopus 로고
    • Guilt and Suffering
    • "A Paternalistic Theory of Punishment,"
    • See, for example, Herbert Morris, "Guilt and Suffering" and "A Paternalistic Theory of Punishment," American Philosophical Quarterly 18(4) (1981), pp. 263-271, reprinted in Jeffrie G. Murphy, ed., Punishment and Rehabilitation, Third edition (Belmont, CA: Wadsworth Publishing Co., 1995), pp. 154-168.
    • (1981) American Philosophical Quarterly , vol.18 , Issue.4 , pp. 263-271
    • Morris, H.1
  • 50
    • 0002602123 scopus 로고
    • Belmont, CA: Wadsworth Publishing Co.
    • See, for example, Herbert Morris, "Guilt and Suffering" and "A Paternalistic Theory of Punishment," American Philosophical Quarterly 18(4) (1981), pp. 263-271, reprinted in Jeffrie G. Murphy, ed., Punishment and Rehabilitation, Third edition (Belmont, CA: Wadsworth Publishing Co., 1995), pp. 154-168.
    • (1995) Punishment and Rehabilitation, Third Edition , pp. 154-168
    • Murphy, J.G.1
  • 51
    • 0041582187 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The following points are not intended as criticisms of utilitarianism, for the resources of subtle variations of utilitarianism are plentiful and the points in question are themselves open to reasonable controversy.
  • 52
    • 0041582166 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [6: 362]
    • MM, 130 [6: 362], CPrR, pp. 34-35 [5: 37-38].
    • MM , pp. 130
  • 53
    • 0041582188 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [5: 37-38]
    • MM, 130 [6: 362], CPrR, pp. 34-35 [5: 37-38].
  • 54
    • 0042083203 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [6: 229-231], 31-32 [6: 239], 145-148 [6: 380-383]
    • For Kant's distinction between legal offenses and merely "ethical" failings, see MM, pp. 23-25 [6: 229-231], 31-32 [6: 239], 145-148 [6: 380-383].
    • MM , pp. 23-25
  • 55
    • 0042584203 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [4: 393]
    • G, p. 7 [4: 393].
    • G , pp. 7
  • 56
    • 0042584212 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ibid.
    • G , pp. 7
  • 57
    • 84977354757 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Is a Good Will Overrated?
    • This interpretation is developed at more length in my essay "Is a Good Will Overrated?" in Midwest Studies in Philosophy: Moral Concepts XX (1996), pp. 299-317.
    • (1996) Midwest Studies in Philosophy: Moral Concepts , vol.20 , pp. 299-317
  • 58
    • 0041582165 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [6: 380-482]
    • MM, pp. 223-225 [6: 380-482].
    • MM , pp. 223-225
  • 59
    • 0042083202 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [481]
    • MM, p. 224 [481].
    • MM , pp. 224
  • 60
    • 0042083226 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [5: 123-132]
    • CPrR, pp. 103-110 [5: 123-132].
    • CPrR , pp. 103-110
  • 61
    • 0041582189 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [5: 110-11]
    • CPrR 93 [5: 110-11].
    • CPrR , pp. 93
  • 62
    • 0042584213 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid.
    • CPrR , pp. 93
  • 63
    • 0041582169 scopus 로고
    • The Concept of the Highest Good in Kant's Moral Theory
    • See Stephen Engstrom, "The Concept of the Highest Good in Kant's Moral Theory," Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 52 (1992), pp. 747-780, and Andrews Reath, "Two Conceptions of the Highest Good in Kant," Journal of the History of Philosophy 26 (1988), pp. 593-619.
    • (1992) Philosophy and Phenomenological Research , vol.52 , pp. 747-780
    • Engstrom, S.1
  • 64
    • 0043084985 scopus 로고
    • Two Conceptions of the Highest Good in Kant
    • See Stephen Engstrom, "The Concept of the Highest Good in Kant's Moral Theory," Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 52 (1992), pp. 747-780, and Andrews Reath, "Two Conceptions of the Highest Good in Kant," Journal of the History of Philosophy 26 (1988), pp. 593-619.
    • (1988) Journal of the History of Philosophy , vol.26 , pp. 593-619
    • Reath, A.1
  • 65
    • 0042584188 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This point, of course, is compatible with the common sense idea that, in particular contexts, one's estimate of the goodness or evil of others' deeds and motives will make some difference to how one judges, from basic principles, that one should treat them
    • That is, the basic general principles of duty are not so restricted. (For text citations, see DPrR, pp. 176-195.) This point, of course, is compatible with the common sense idea that, in particular contexts, one's estimate of the goodness or evil of others' deeds and motives will make some difference to how one judges, from basic principles, that one should treat them.
    • DPrR , pp. 176-195
  • 66
    • 0043084988 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [5: 37-38] and 53 [5: 61] and
    • I limit my discussion here to Kant's main discussion of punishment in The Metaphysics of Morals. Kant comments occasionally on punishment elsewhere. See, for example, CPrR, pp. 34-35 [5: 37-38] and 53 [5: 61] and Lectures on Ethics, pp. 80 [27: 286], 307-312 [27: 551-558], 284-285 [27: 552], and 181 [27: 418]. These texts are not without ambiguity, but the Lectures clearly assign a deterrence role to state punishment. Both, however, contain suggestions of the intrinsic desert thesis as at least appropriate for a Being of infinite wisdom and power.
    • CPrR , pp. 34-35
  • 67
    • 0004207225 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [27: 286], 307-312 [27: 551-558], 284-285 [27: 552], and 181 [27: 418]. These texts are not without ambiguity, but the Lectures clearly assign a deterrence role to state punishment. Both, however, contain suggestions of the intrinsic desert thesis as at least appropriate for a Being of infinite wisdom and power
    • I limit my discussion here to Kant's main discussion of punishment in The Metaphysics of Morals. Kant comments occasionally on punishment elsewhere. See, for example, CPrR, pp. 34-35 [5: 37-38] and 53 [5: 61] and Lectures on Ethics, pp. 80 [27: 286], 307-312 [27: 551-558], 284-285 [27: 552], and 181 [27: 418]. These texts are not without ambiguity, but the Lectures clearly assign a deterrence role to state punishment. Both, however, contain suggestions of the intrinsic desert thesis as at least appropriate for a Being of infinite wisdom and power.
    • Lectures on Ethics , pp. 80
  • 68
    • 0041582163 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [6: 218-221]
    • MM, pp. 20-22 [6: 218-221].
    • MM , pp. 20-22
  • 69
    • 0041582168 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [6: 230-231]
    • MM, pp. 24-25 [6: 230-231]; see also Sharon Byrd, op. cit.
    • MM , pp. 24-25
  • 70
    • 0043084971 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MM, pp. 24-25 [6: 230-231]; see also Sharon Byrd, op. cit.
    • MM
    • Byrd, S.1
  • 71
    • 0042083216 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [6: 331-337].
    • MM, pp. 04-09 [6: 331-337].
    • MM , pp. 4-9
  • 72
    • 0043084986 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [6: 333], 130 [6: 362-363], 209-210 [6: 462-464]
    • MM, pp. 106 [6: 333], 130 [6: 362-363], 209-210 [6: 462-464].
    • MM , pp. 106
  • 73
    • 0042584191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [331]
    • MM, pp. 105 [331].
    • MM , pp. 105
  • 74
    • 0042584189 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [332]
    • MM, pp. 105 [332].
    • MM , pp. 105
  • 75
    • 0042584190 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid.
    • MM , pp. 105
  • 76
    • 0042584200 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [333]
    • MM, p. 106 [333].
    • MM , pp. 106
  • 77
    • 0041582190 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [333-334]
    • MM, pp. 106-107 [333-334].
    • MM , pp. 106-107
  • 78
    • 0042584208 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Note that Mary Gregor translates "strafbar" here as "deserving," which misleadingly favors the idea that punishment is for inner desert. (A page earlier, MM 106 [332], she had rendered "strafbar" as "punishable," thereby avoiding the misleading connotation in others' translations.) In the same paragraph about the Scottish rebels, she renders "inneren Bösartigkeit" as "inner wickedness," which is clearly a deep moral quality of will, whereas the term naturally and more consistently can be rendered as "inner maliciousness," which could be a trait of character imputed on empirical evidence. Although Kant held that we cannot know for certain what a person's maxims are and especially whether a person has a good will or not, it would be a mistake, I think, to suppose that everything he refers to as "inner" in a person is inaccessible and so cannot be attributed on the basis of empirical evidence.
  • 79
    • 0041582192 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [6: 228], 106 [6: 332-333]
    • MM, pp. 19-20 [6: 228], 106 [6: 332-333].
    • MM , pp. 19-20
  • 80
    • 0042584201 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [6: 335-337]
    • Kant describes two cases in which he apparently regarded the motive of "honor" as a mitigating factor, at least in our imperfect world: the woman who kills her illegitimate baby and the soldier who kills another in a duel. MM, pp. 108-109 [6: 335-337].
    • MM , pp. 108-109
  • 82
    • 0043085003 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ch. 2, ch. 10, pp. 196-225, and ch. 11, pp. 226-250
    • The Kantian moral legislative perspective is the moral point of view that is relevant to deliberations and debates about what more specific moral principles should govern various aspects of life. Attempts to interpret and reconstruct a Kantian account of this vary considerably. My partial attempts to characterize it are in DPrR, ch. 2, pp. 58-66, ch. 10, pp. 196-225, and ch. 11, pp. 226-250, and several essays in Respect, Pluralism, and Justice: A Kantian Perspective (Oxford University Press, forthcoming).
    • DPrR , pp. 58-66
  • 83
    • 0043084982 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford University Press, forthcoming
    • The Kantian moral legislative perspective is the moral point of view that is relevant to deliberations and debates about what more specific moral principles should govern various aspects of life. Attempts to interpret and reconstruct a Kantian account of this vary considerably. My partial attempts to characterize it are in DPrR, ch. 2, pp. 58-66, ch. 10, pp. 196-225, and ch. 11, pp. 226-250, and several essays in Respect, Pluralism, and Justice: A Kantian Perspective (Oxford University Press, forthcoming).
    • Respect, Pluralism, and Justice: a Kantian Perspective
  • 84
    • 0041445589 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For example, Herbert Morris, "A Paternalistic Theory of Punishment" and Joel Feinberg, "The Expressive Function of Punishment," in The Monist (1965), pp. 397-423, reprinted in his Doing and Deserving (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1970), pp. 95-118.
    • A Paternalistic Theory of Punishment
    • Morris, H.1
  • 85
    • 0040557276 scopus 로고
    • The Expressive Function of Punishment
    • For example, Herbert Morris, "A Paternalistic Theory of Punishment" and Joel Feinberg, "The Expressive Function of Punishment," in The Monist (1965), pp. 397-423, reprinted in his Doing and Deserving (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1970), pp. 95-118.
    • (1965) The Monist , pp. 397-423
    • Feinberg, J.1
  • 86
    • 0004156082 scopus 로고
    • Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press
    • For example, Herbert Morris, "A Paternalistic Theory of Punishment" and Joel Feinberg, "The Expressive Function of Punishment," in The Monist (1965), pp. 397-423, reprinted in his Doing and Deserving (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1970), pp. 95-118.
    • (1970) Doing and Deserving , pp. 95-118
  • 87
    • 34248347185 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Punishment, Conscience, and Moral Worth
    • I develop this theme in "Punishment, Conscience, and Moral Worth," The Southern Journal of Philosophy XXXVI, Supplement (1997), pp. 51-71.
    • (1997) The Southern Journal of Philosophy , vol.36 , Issue.SUPPL. , pp. 51-71
  • 88
    • 0041582196 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I am grateful for the support of the Social Philosophy and Policy Center at Bowling Green University while completing this essay. Participants in discussions at Bowling Green and Santa Clara Universities offered helpful comments, and I want especially to thank Bernard Boxill, Sarah Holtman, Jeffrie Murphy, and Gerald Postema for their help and encouragement on this and other projects.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.