메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 18, Issue 2, 2010, Pages 127-151

The right to found a family as a stillborn right to procreate?

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords

ARTICLE; ETHICS; EUROPE; HUMAN; LEGAL ASPECT; REPRODUCTIVE RIGHTS;

EID: 77956405693     PISSN: 09670742     EISSN: 14643790     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1093/medlaw/fwq013     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (8)

References (132)
  • 1
    • 77957233280 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Defining the boundaries of the private versus the public domain seems not just a matter of legal accuracy, but equally an ethical issue.
  • 2
    • 0041035788 scopus 로고
    • The History of the Public/Private Distinction
    • See for example JH Morton, 'The History of the Public/Private Distinction' (1982) 130 University of Pennsylvania Law Review 1423-28.
    • (1982) University of Pennsylvania Law Review , vol.130 , pp. 1423-1428
    • Morton, J.H.1
  • 3
    • 77957223547 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Comment: Autonomy and the Public-Private Distinction in Bioethics and Law
    • And S Williams, 'Comment: Autonomy and the Public-Private Distinction in Bioethics and Law' (2005) 12 Indiana Journal of Global Legal Studies 483-94.
    • (2005) Indiana Journal of Global Legal Studies , vol.12 , pp. 483-494
    • Williams, S.1
  • 4
    • 77957237970 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • This paper will refrain from providing a definition of the right to procreate, as this falls outside the scope of the paper; the aim of this paper is to show that Article 12 no longer covers the concept of the right to procreate and whether Article 8 could take up the traditional role of Article 12 under the evolved scope of the concept. For the purpose of argument, I will, however, presume that the concept of the right to procreate stands for more than a right to have one's innate capacity to reproduce protected.
  • 6
    • 0042142373 scopus 로고
    • The Right to Reproduce
    • T Campbell and others (eds), (Basil Blackwell, Oxford)
    • S McLean, 'The Right to Reproduce' in T Campbell and others (eds), Human Rights: From Rhetoric to Reality (Basil Blackwell, Oxford 1986) 103.
    • (1986) Human Rights: From Rhetoric to Reality , pp. 103
    • McLean, S.1
  • 9
    • 0034752787 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Procreative Beneficence: Why We Should Select the Best Children
    • 15
    • See, for example, J Savulescu, 'Procreative Beneficence: Why We Should Select the Best Children' 15 Bioethics (2001) 15, 413-426.
    • (2001) Bioethics , vol.15 , pp. 413-426
    • Savulescu, J.1
  • 10
    • 84909407579 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Routledge, London)
    • J Harris On cloning (Routledge, London 2004).
    • (2004) On cloning
    • Harris, J.1
  • 11
    • 0034128308 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Is There a Coherent Social Conception of Disability
    • J Harris, 'Is There a Coherent Social Conception of Disability' (2000) 26 Journal of Medical Ethics 95.
    • (2000) Journal of Medical Ethics , vol.26 , pp. 95
    • Harris, J.1
  • 13
    • 77957227453 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • For elaboration on legal origins, see McLean, (n 4) 113.
  • 14
    • 27744525965 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Man not included Single Women, Female Couples and Procreative Freedom in the UK
    • 166
    • And EE Sutherland, '" Man not included" Single Women, Female Couples and Procreative Freedom in the UK' (2003) 15 Child and Family Law Quarterly 155, 166.
    • (2003) Child and Family Law Quarterly , vol.15 , pp. 155
    • Sutherland, E.E.1
  • 15
    • 77957242665 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • As I will show later in this paper, Article 12 has a confined application, and consequently did not offer much protection.
  • 16
    • 77957241975 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • This refers to instances where the desire is not to reproduce, for example, in abortion or when using contraceptives.
  • 17
    • 27144538859 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Right to Parenthood
    • 225
    • D Statman, 'The Right to Parenthood' (2003) 10 Ethical Perspect 224, 225.
    • (2003) Ethical Perspect , vol.10 , pp. 224
    • Statman, D.1
  • 18
    • 47049121540 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Reproductive Liberty: Should the Foundation of Families Be Regulated?
    • 192
    • A Alghrani and J Harris, 'Reproductive Liberty: Should the Foundation of Families Be Regulated?' (2006) 18 Child and Family Law Quarterly 191, 192.
    • (2006) Child and Family Law Quarterly , vol.18 , pp. 191
    • Alghrani, A.1    Harris, J.2
  • 20
    • 0037026891 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Deaf Lesbians, designer disability and the future of medicine
    • 772
    • J Savulescu, 'Deaf Lesbians, "designer disability" and the future of medicine' (2002) BMJ 771, 772.
    • (2002) BMJ , pp. 771
    • Savulescu, J.1
  • 21
    • 77957238147 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Dworkin (n 5) 148.
  • 24
    • 77957230229 scopus 로고
    • Manipuleren Met Leven
    • HN Juristen-Vereniging (ed), (WEJ Tjeenk)
    • J de Ruiter and EPR Sutorius, 'Manipuleren Met Leven' in HN Juristen-Vereniging (ed), Preadvies (WEJ Tjeenk 1993).
    • (1993) Preadvies
    • de Ruiter, J.1    Sutorius, E.P.R.2
  • 26
  • 27
    • 33845311172 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Zwangerschap op oudere leeftijd door middel van eiceldonatie
    • M Kortman and others, 'Zwangerschap op oudere leeftijd door middel van eiceldonatie' (2006) 47 Nederlands Tijdschrift Geneeskunde 2591-95.
    • (2006) Nederlands Tijdschrift Geneeskunde , vol.47 , pp. 2591-2595
    • Kortman, M.1
  • 28
    • 77957236177 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Savulescu, above n 13, 10.
  • 29
    • 77957243817 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • O'Neill, above n 3, 54.
  • 30
    • 34548164596 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Storks, Cabbage Patches, and the Right to Procreate
    • 108
    • Y Pearson, 'Storks, Cabbage Patches, and the Right to Procreate' (2007) 4 Bioethical Inquiry 105, 108.
    • (2007) Bioethical Inquiry , vol.4 , pp. 105
    • Pearson, Y.1
  • 31
    • 34547115980 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Slippery Slope to Sperm Smuggling: Prisoners, Artificial Insemination and Human Rights
    • 235
    • H Codd, 'The Slippery Slope to Sperm Smuggling: Prisoners, Artificial Insemination and Human Rights' (2007) Med Law Rev 220, 235.
    • (2007) Med Law Rev , pp. 220
    • Codd, H.1
  • 32
    • 0036583938 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • What Are Families for? Getting to an Ethics of Reproductive Technology
    • T Murray, 'What Are Families for? Getting to an Ethics of Reproductive Technology' (2002) 32 Hastings Centre Report 41, 42.
    • (2002) Hastings Centre Report 41 , vol.32 , pp. 42
    • Murray, T.1
  • 33
    • 69749092213 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Limits of Rights-based Discourse
    • J Spencer and A du-Bois-Pedain (eds), (Hart, Oxford)
    • M Warnock, 'The Limits of Rights-based Discourse', in J Spencer and A du-Bois-Pedain (eds), Freedom and Responsibility in Reproductive Choice (Hart, Oxford 2006) 3.
    • (2006) Freedom and Responsibility in Reproductive Choice , pp. 3
    • Warnock, M.1
  • 34
    • 33845615879 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Harvard Centre for Population and Development Studies, University at Albany/SUNY)
    • B Steinbock, Rethinking the Right to Reproduce (Harvard Centre for Population and Development Studies, University at Albany/SUNY [1998]).
    • (1998) Rethinking the Right to Reproduce
    • Steinbock, B.1
  • 36
    • 77957236471 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • The practices of forced sterilisation of the weak-minded were not only practised in Nazi-Germany, but equally in many other countries including the Scandinavian ones.
  • 37
    • 0033554152 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Eugenics and Human Rights
    • See D Kevles, 'Eugenics and Human Rights', (1999) 319 BMJ 435.
    • (1999) BMJ , vol.319 , pp. 435
    • Kevles, D.1
  • 39
    • 77957227864 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Since Article 12 contains the right to marry as well, part of its historical origins derives from the importance attached to the ability to marry.
  • 40
    • 77957229931 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • X and Y v United Kingdom (Application 7229/75) (1977) 12 DR 32 (EComHR). In this case, the Court made it clear that the Article could not be extended to include a right to adopt.
  • 41
    • 77957233970 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • See also Section 3 of this paper.
  • 42
    • 77957223951 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • The fact that the judgments such as X and Y v the UK (1977) (above n 32) were established in cases of adoption does not seem to hinder an analogous application to cases of reproduction. Nothing in the statement points to a restrictive application.
  • 43
    • 77957220899 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • In Frette v France (Application No. 36515/97, February 26 2002), para. 31. Marckx v Belgium (Application 6833/74) (1979) 2 EHRR 330, para. 11.
  • 44
    • 77957228006 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • The Consultative Assembly is the second organ of the Council of Europe after the Committee of Ministers, and has been indicated as the Parliamentary Assembly since 1994.
  • 45
    • 77957231446 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Statute of the Council of Europe, [accessed November 26]
    • Statute of the Council of Europe, http://conventions.coe.int/Treaty/en/Treaties/HTML/001.htm#FN1 [accessed November 26 2009].
    • (2009)
  • 48
    • 77957236054 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • This contrasts with the concept of the right to procreate, which is often used in non-traditional contexts.
  • 49
    • 77957224237 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For an extended elaboration on the application of Article 12, and in particular the element of the right to found a family, (4th edn Intersentia, Antwerp) 4 edn
    • For an extended elaboration on the application of Article 12, and in particular the element of the right to found a family, see P van Dijk and others, Theory and Practice of the European Convention on Human Rights (4th edn Intersentia, Antwerp 2006) 4 edn, 853-7.
    • (2006) Theory and Practice of the European Convention on Human Rights , pp. 853-857
    • van Dijk, P.1
  • 50
    • 0032229925 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Philosophical Principles in Reproductive Medicine
    • 28
    • G Lockwood, 'Philosophical Principles in Reproductive Medicine' (1998) 1 Human Fertility 27, 28.
    • (1998) Human Fertility , vol.1 , pp. 27
    • Lockwood, G.1
  • 51
    • 77957225215 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Whereas it seems to have been the original intention of the Convention that the Article would only protect married couples, the protection seems to have been extended to non-married couples. The existence of the couple, however, remains required. The Court seems to stick to a traditional interpretation and to hold that the Article at least requires 'a couple'. X v Belgium and Netherlands (Application 6482/14) (1975) 7 DR 75, under the law 2, EComHR, repeated in DiLazarro (Application No. 31924/96) 90-B EComHR. and Dijk and others (n 39) 842. Also Emonet v Switzerland (Application No 39051/03) (2007) 49 EHRR 234, [92].
  • 52
    • 77957227452 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • The Court has consistently held that Article 12 applies to a 'man and woman' Rees v United Kingdom (Application 9532/81) (1986) 9 EHRR 56 [50] and Eriksson and Goldschmidt v Sweden (Application14573/89) (1989).
  • 53
    • 77957239983 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Marckx v Belgium (n 34) [67] 'The fact that, in law, the parents of an 'illegitimate' child do not have the same rights as a married couple also constitutes a breach of Article 12 (art. 12) in the opinion of the applicants; they thus appear to construe Article 12 as requiring that all the legal effects attaching to marriage should apply equally to situations that are in certain respects comparable to marriage. The Court cannot accept this reasoning; in company with the Commission, the Court finds that the issue under consideration falls outside the scope of Article 12'. Dijk and others (n 39) 856.
  • 55
    • 77957223549 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • P., C. and S. v The United Kingdom (2002) (Application no. 56547/00) European Court on Human Rights, para. 142.
  • 56
    • 77957240543 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • The Commission did foresee that Article 12 could apply to founding a family by adoption, such as in X v the Netherlands (1980) (Application No. 8896/80), but it consistently held that Article 12 does not contain a right to adopt, and relies on Article 8 for the rest of such claims. See for example E.B v France (Application 43546/02) (2008) 47 EHRR 509.
  • 57
    • 77957230228 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • In the case of Goodwin v UK (Application No. 28957/95, July 11 2002) [80] and [100], the Court held that Article 12 had to be interpreted more flexibly for the right to marry. It reasoned that the determination of gender criteria would no longer be determined by biological criteria. Moreover, it held that the ability to found a family was not required as a condition for a right to marry. (It must be noted that the Court did not determine the opposite; that founding a family could be a right outside of life in a couple or in a married situation.) See also Johnston v Ireland (Application 9697/82) (1986) 9 EHRR 203.
  • 58
    • 77957229930 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • X v Belgium and the Netherlands and Di Lazzaro (1997) (n 41).
  • 59
    • 77957223950 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • In Goodwin v UK (2002), the Court seemed to insist that Article 12 could only apply to couples of the opposite gender [100] (n 42).
  • 60
    • 77957221168 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Also P., C. and S. v The United Kingdom (43) [142].
  • 61
    • 77957239026 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • The Court has ruled that restrictions in national laws may not impinge on the essence of the right, but it is not clear how valuable this is. The essence of Article 12 remains very vague. Rees v United Kingdom (1986) (n 42). Also, for example, in the recent case of Emonet (n 41), the core of the right seems to have been at stake, but the appeal was dismissed. Since the Swiss legislation did not recognise the parties' relationship as a formal couple, they could not claim the right to found a family. See also Dijk (n 39) 842.
  • 62
    • 77957244383 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Dickson v United Kingdom (Application No 44362/04)(2006) 44 EHRR 419 [41].
  • 63
    • 77957231321 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • S.H. and others v Austria (Application No. 57813/00, November 15 2007).
  • 64
    • 77957232323 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Sijakova and Others v The Former Yugoslav Republic (Application No. 67914/01, March 6 2003).
  • 65
    • 77957244382 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • The Government concluded that a claim under Article 12 had to be rejected, since the restriction was not disproportional and did not 'impair the very essence of the right to found a family'. Nevertheless, the Government did not apply for a dismissal of the Article. See also under number 5 in the S.H. and Others (n 51).
  • 66
    • 77957235770 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Sijakova and others (n 52) was declared inadmissible. Nevertheless, the Court officially refers to it the judgement of the fourth Chamber.
  • 67
    • 77957240679 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Or as in Sijakova and others, the claim to have a grandchild (n 52).
  • 68
    • 77957233279 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Especially in S.H. and others (n 51) the right to beget a child seems to be the core issue.
  • 69
    • 77957235116 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • The decision in the case of S.H and others (n 51) could be enlightening in this respect. The complaint relates to the prohibition of the legislation to use these forms of assisted conception. If the Court would envisage a change of the legislation, would such a change then be seen as a positive obligation so to facilitate the conception by those who need assistance, or would it be seen as a negative interference; the legislation interfering with an ultimately personal decision so that it should actually refrain from involvement.
  • 70
    • 77957225075 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • It is fixed case law of the Court to require leaving the core of the right intact. Rees (n 42) [50].
  • 71
    • 77957226798 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Wicks (n 29) 162.
  • 72
    • 77957236321 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Dickson v The United Kingdom (2007) 46 EHHR 927 [76].
  • 74
    • 77957225214 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Jacobs and White (n 43) and Deech (n 6) 5.
  • 75
    • 77957241974 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Evans v The United Kingdom (2007) EHRR 728 [71].
  • 76
    • 77957231911 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Gender Bias in Judicial Decisions Concerning IVF and Embryo Implantation: Evans v The United Kingdom (Grand Chamber of the European Court of Human Rights) as a Case in Point
    • See for example S Grover, 'Gender Bias in Judicial Decisions Concerning IVF and Embryo Implantation: Evans v The United Kingdom (Grand Chamber of the European Court of Human Rights) as a Case in Point' (2007) 3 Original Law Review, 86-98.
    • (2007) Original Law Review , vol.3 , pp. 86-98
    • Grover, S.1
  • 77
    • 77957241561 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Evans v United Kingdom: Paradigms of Parenting
    • C Morris, 'Evans v United Kingdom: Paradigms of Parenting' (2007) 70 Modern Law Review 979-100.
    • (2007) Modern Law Review , vol.70 , pp. 979-100
    • Morris, C.1
  • 78
    • 85138279588 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Evans v United Kingdom: Frozen Embryos and Conflicting Rights
    • L Zucca, 'Evans v United Kingdom: Frozen Embryos and Conflicting Rights' (2007) 11 The Edinburgh Law Review 446-9.
    • (2007) The Edinburgh Law Review , vol.11 , pp. 446-449
    • Zucca, L.1
  • 79
    • 77957222751 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Dickson (n 64).
  • 80
    • 77957235374 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Codd (n 24).
  • 81
    • 47049100396 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Case Commentary: The Right to Procreate Is not Aborted
    • And M Eijkholt 'Case Commentary: The Right to Procreate Is not Aborted' (2008) 16 Med Law Rev 284.
    • (2008) Med Law Rev , vol.16 , pp. 284
    • Eijkholt, M.1
  • 82
    • 77957221972 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • The Secretary of State offered, for example, the public confidence in the penal system and the absence of the parent for a long period of time as public interests. See Dickson (n 64) [74-76].
  • 83
    • 77957244514 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • The Court established a violation of Article 8 in conjunction with Article 14 on April 1 2010. S.H. and Others (Application No 57813/00, April 1 2010).
  • 84
    • 77957236053 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • S.H. and Others (n 51) The Court declares the complaint admissible as it 'violated their rights under Article 8 of the Convention, read alone [emphasis added] and in conjunction with Article 14'.
  • 85
    • 77957230914 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • See number 2, last paragraph.
  • 86
    • 77957234653 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • This is remarkable since the right to found a family is Article 12, and not Article 8.
  • 87
    • 77957225995 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • th paragraph under heading 2 under heading of 'the law'.
  • 88
    • 77957230075 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • See under number 5 of the judgment.
  • 89
    • 77957235643 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Dickson (n 64) [86].
  • 90
    • 77957230519 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • See the dissenting opinion of Judge Mularoni in E.B. (n 47).
  • 91
    • 77957241562 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • This section will not provide a definition of the right to procreate. The right is an opaque analytic tool that does not lend itself to clarification in this analysis. It suffices to establish that the right to procreate these days stands for more than a right to have one's innate capacity to reproduce protected.
  • 93
    • 77957225074 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Murray (n 25).
  • 94
    • 77957221441 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • The case refers here to the case of Pretty v UK (Application No. 2346/02) [2002] 2 FLR 45.
  • 95
    • 77957242236 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • See Dickson (n 64) [71].
  • 96
    • 77957227451 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • See Dijk and others (n 39) 66.
  • 97
    • 23144453913 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Parenthood Should Be Regarded as a Right
    • J Boivin and G Pennings, 'Parenthood Should Be Regarded as a Right' (2005) Arch Dis Child 784.
    • (2005) Arch Dis Child , pp. 784
    • Boivin, J.1    Pennings, G.2
  • 98
    • 77957245465 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • X v Belgium and the Netherlands (n 41).
  • 99
    • 77957227450 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Positive obligations are norms that require active interference of the government to establish the conditions in which a specific right can be exercised.
  • 100
    • 77957226669 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Any other positive obligation than a financial one, or an obligation to provide the service, is harder to imagine. An obligation to provide for, for example, a partner required for conception is unthinkable.
  • 101
    • 77957232988 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • The possibility of Article 8 having 'positive effects' can be shown by cases as early as Rees (n 42).
  • 102
    • 77957241827 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • In Evans (n 66), the notion of 'respect' caused the grounds for appeal to disappear. According to the Court, it was up to the Government to decide whether or not to formulate legislation, and equally to decide which elements herein to regulate or not to regulate. The Court required only that the regulation would be made carefully. Seemingly, this attitude implies that as the considerations were careful, the outcome did not matter; there was no direct right to be upheld but only respect. The contents of the regulations would be irrelevant; carefully made regulation would always show respect.
  • 103
    • 77957235909 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Even though two gametes (of two different persons) are required in order to reproduce, and arguably reproduction therefore is not a private matter, the notion of 'family privacy' seems to obviate this drawback. This remark does not take reproductive cloning into account.
  • 104
    • 0007842475 scopus 로고
    • Artikel 8 en 12 in verband met kunstmatige voortplanting en draagmoederschap
    • JKM Gevers (ed), (Ars Aequi Libri, Nijmegen)
    • LE Kalkman-Bogerd. 'Artikel 8 en 12 in verband met kunstmatige voortplanting en draagmoederschap', in JKM Gevers (ed), Het EVRM en de gezondheidszorg (Ars Aequi Libri, Nijmegen 1994) 122.
    • (1994) Het EVRM en de gezondheidszorg , pp. 122
    • Kalkman-Bogerd, L.E.1
  • 105
    • 77957229122 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • In R (on the application of Countryside Alliance and others and others (appellants)) v Her Majesty's Attorney General and another (Respondents) [2007] ([UKHL] - 52) House of Lords widely elaborated on the scope of 'private life' of Article 8 ECHR. Lord Roger of Earlsferry seems to set out here a distinction between 'private private acts' and 'public private acts'. In the latter category, the act has a direct influence on the public domain, so that it can hardly be a private matter. Accordingly, in the above examples, the question whether the involvement of the surrogate or fertility clinic would classify as a public-private act or as a private-private act could depend on the way in which the surrogate would be 'recruited', and the fertility clinic 'paid' for. However, whether the ECHR would follow a similar categorisation is unclear. The Court held in Niemietz v Germany (1992) 16 EHRR 97, 11, that respect for private life also comprises, to some extent, a right to establish and develop relationships with other human beings and so extended the Article outside the 'inner circle'. Yet, where the exact boundaries lie between public and private acts, the 'inner circle' and the outside world, the ECHR has not yet defined.
  • 106
    • 77957230074 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • See Section IV.
  • 107
    • 77957233278 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Deech (n 6) 137.
  • 108
    • 77957245075 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Can Reproductive Rights Be Human Rights? Some Thoughts on the Inclusion of Women's Rights in Mainstream Human Rights Discourse
    • C Bateup, 'Can Reproductive Rights Be "Human" Rights? Some Thoughts on the Inclusion of Women's Rights in Mainstream Human Rights Discourse' (2000) 6 Australian Journal of Human Rights 33.
    • (2000) Australian Journal of Human Rights , vol.6 , pp. 33
    • Bateup, C.1
  • 109
    • 77957232321 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Although Bateup refers to a reluctant attitude of the Government in respect to negative procreation: 'by basing a woman's right to abortion upon the right to privacy and the notion of the private sphere, it is possible to avoid any duty to ensure that women can, as a practical matter, have access to abortion services', there seems to be no good reason why this statement could not be extended to the context of this paper: positive procreation.
  • 110
    • 77957241359 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Kalkman-Bogerd (n 94) 68.
  • 111
    • 77957221712 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The wide range of possible exceptions to the Article is also a result of the doctrine of the margin of appreciation under Article 8. For an elaboration on this topic, (3rd edn Kluwer Law International, the Hague)
    • The wide range of possible exceptions to the Article is also a result of the doctrine of the margin of appreciation under Article 8. For an elaboration on this topic, see P van Dijk and GJH van Hoof, Theory and practice of the European Convention on Human Rights (3rd edn Kluwer Law International, the Hague 1998) 82-95.
    • (1998) Theory and practice of the European Convention on Human Rights , pp. 82-95
    • van Dijk, P.1    van Hoof, G.J.H.2
  • 112
    • 77957240388 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • The dissenting judges criticise that the Court fails to consider many of the important public interests that contraindicate upholding of the private interests, such as the absence of the father in an important part of the child's youth and the violent history of Dickson. See dissenting Judges Wildhaber and colleagues in Dickson (n 64).
  • 113
    • 77957245464 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Pearson (n 23) 110.
  • 114
    • 77957234507 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Murray (n 25) 42.
  • 116
    • 77957235504 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Murray (n 25) 42.
  • 117
    • 77957239559 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Dijk et al. (n 39).
  • 118
    • 77957226412 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Arguably, allocation policies are just a matter of scarcity that rights are confronted with and have no influence upon its meaning. However, when we consider that a claim for help would not be met in a long-lasting couple relationship to conceive a second child, whereas someone who changed partners would each time have a new right to found a family, such interpretation of the Article would have discriminatory consequences.
  • 119
    • 0020732129 scopus 로고
    • Procreative Liberty and the Control of Conception, Pregnancy, and Childbirth
    • JA Robertson, 'Procreative Liberty and the Control of Conception, Pregnancy, and Childbirth' (1983) 69 Virginia Law Review 405-65.
    • (1983) Virginia Law Review , vol.69 , pp. 405-465
    • Robertson, J.A.1
  • 120
    • 77957224388 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Dijk and others (n 39) 234. For example, we could see such interpretations in the case of J.S v Denmark (application No. 1287/61, 4 October 1962) European Commission of Human Rights or in Dickson (n 64). In the former case, a man complained before the Court that his wife had herself sterilised without his consent. He unsuccessfully argued that his right to found a family was infringed, as he could no longer found a family with her. This latter judgment seems to imply that the couple should at least have been allowed the opportunity to access AI treatment. The ability to procreate would be part of their rights.
  • 121
    • 77957219777 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Eijkholt (n 82).
  • 122
    • 77957230518 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Interestingly, we can also see the opposite question and ask whether the right to found a family is the same as the right to procreate. Whereas the right to found a family seems to include a right to gestate (the whole process towards birth and the establishment of the family would be included in the concept), it is questionable whether the right to procreate includes a right to gestate. The right to procreate, seems in first instance, to be cut loose from the outcome so that the result, a family, is not always endeavoured.
  • 123
    • 77957226125 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Procreative Reasons-Relevance: On the Moral Significance of Why We Have Children
    • Lotz holds that distinguishing procreative reasons is unjustified
    • Lotz holds that distinguishing procreative reasons is unjustified M Lotz, 'Procreative Reasons-Relevance: On the Moral Significance of Why We Have Children' (2008) 22 Bioethics 1.
    • (2008) Bioethics , vol.22 , pp. 1
    • Lotz, M.1
  • 124
    • 77957219916 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • We see that aspects of self-determination may be relevant in issues concerning the (im)possibility to found a family, but also as an underpinning choice, for example, for the characteristics of the child.
  • 125
    • 77957227182 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Steinbock (n 27) 23.
  • 126
    • 77957223424 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Boivin (n 87) 784.
  • 127
    • 77957242729 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Some have argued that the intention to rear a child is the essence of the right to procreate. That is to say that the importance of anyone for the right is expressed in the right to rear a child. It is even said that without the intention to rear the child one has a reduced right to procreate. See O'Neill, above n 3. The question why anyone would want to procreate without having an intention to raise the child is responded to by arguing that reasons could lie in having a choice, for an individual's identity and as it is an original and basic condition for having a genetically related child. M Eijkholt (82) 110, and Robertson (n 108) 408.
  • 129
    • 77957231760 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • See Pearson (n 23) and Murray (n 104) 42.
  • 130
    • 77957227047 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • It must be noted that point 2 here deals with the moral context and moral responsibility that could, arguably, come with founding a family by the person who procreates. Where I comment on the self-centredness of Article 8, I thus refer to a moral attitude. This implies that I do not yet deal with the exceptions in Article 8.2. These exceptions are more relevant on a political level. They will be subject of discussions in point 3.
  • 131
    • 77957222634 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • The prima facie adjective is chosen to highlight that Article 8 does allow public interests to interfere with the right. These are provided for in paragraph 2. However, these limitation criteria are posed as an exception to the rule, so that they are only a hindsight justification for the breach.
  • 132
    • 77957228153 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • We can see an example of this in Emonet (n 41) [92]. The couple was not allowed a right to adopt under Article 12, since the national legislation did not confer such right in the given circumstances. Admittedly, this comment has two sides. Here I argue that in order to establish the essence of the right, there is the possibility to take account of the public interests when defining its core. See for the critical side of this comment paragraph III, holding that Article 12 allows a wide range of exceptions. This comment applies where the core of the right is not established.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.