메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 120, Issue 4, 2010, Pages 711-740

The justification of human rights and the basic right to justification: A reflexive approach

(1)  Forst, Rainer a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 77955671112     PISSN: 00141704     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1086/653434     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (163)

References (112)
  • 1
    • 84909583806 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • James Griffin, On Human Rights (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008), 35.
    • (2008) On Human Rights , pp. 35
    • Griffin, J.1
  • 3
    • 73949096985 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The moral reality of human rights
    • ed. Thomas Pogge (Oxford: Oxford University Press)
    • see also John Tasioulas, "The Moral Reality of Human Rights," in Freedom from Poverty as a Human Right, ed. Thomas Pogge (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007), 75-101.
    • (2007) Freedom from Poverty as a Human Right , pp. 75-101
    • Tasioulas, J.1
  • 4
    • 77955696689 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Taking rights out of human rights
    • in this issue
    • "Taking Rights out of Human Rights," Ethics 120 (2010): 647-78 (in this issue).
    • (2010) Ethics , vol.120 , pp. 647-678
  • 5
    • 0004168076 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press), and 79
    • John Rawls, The Law of Peoples (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999), 27 and 79.
    • (1999) The Law of Peoples , pp. 27
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 8
    • 84924665846 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Human rights and the law of peoples
    • ed. Deen K. Chatterjee (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)
    • Charles Beitz, "Human Rights and the Law of Peoples," in The Ethics of Assistance: Morality and the Distant Needy, ed. Deen K. Chatterjee (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004), 196.
    • (2004) The Ethics of Assistance: Morality and the Distant Needy , pp. 196
    • Beitz, C.1
  • 9
    • 84945670327 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Oxford: Oxford University Press), and 102-6, where the idea of a "practical conception" is laid out in detail
    • See also Charles Beitz, The Idea of Human Rights (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009), 7-12 and 102-6, where the idea of a "practical conception" is laid out in detail.
    • (2009) The Idea of Human Rights , pp. 7-12
    • Beitz, C.1
  • 14
    • 77955676476 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Human rights without foundations
    • ed. Samantha Besson and John Tasioulas (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 328
    • Joseph Raz, "Human Rights without Foundations," in The Philosophy of International Law, ed. Samantha Besson and John Tasioulas (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010), 321-38, 328.
    • (2010) The Philosophy of International Law , pp. 321-138
    • Raz, J.1
  • 15
    • 47249089101 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rethinking human rights, democracy, and sovereignty in the age of globalization
    • Jean Cohen also holds the view that the function of human rights is "to override, or set limits to the domestic jurisdiction of states"; thus she argues for a very limited "subset of legally institutionalized and enforceable international human rights" (at 582 and 599)
    • Jean Cohen also holds the view that the function of human rights is "to override, or set limits to the domestic jurisdiction of states"; thus she argues for a very limited "subset of legally institutionalized and enforceable international human rights" ( Jean Cohen, "Rethinking Human Rights, Democracy, and Sovereignty in the Age of Globalization," Political Theory 36 [2008]: 578-606, at 582 and 599).
    • (2008) Political Theory , vol.36 , pp. 578-606
    • Cohen, J.1
  • 19
    • 2542522411 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Minimalism about human rights
    • 192
    • Joshua Cohen, "Minimalism about Human Rights," Journal of Political Philosophy 12 (2004): 190-213, at 192.
    • (2004) Journal of Political Philosophy , vol.12 , pp. 190-213
    • Cohen, J.1
  • 20
    • 2542522411 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Minimalism about human rights
    • Joshua Cohen, "Minimalism about Human Rights," Journal of Political Philosophy Ibid., 197, emphasis in original.
    • (2004) Journal of Political Philosophy , vol.12 , pp. 197
    • Cohen, J.1
  • 21
    • 2542522411 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Minimalism about human rights
    • Joshua Cohen, "Minimalism about Human Rights," Journal of Political Philosophy, 2004, 12, 197 Ibid.
    • (2004) Journal of Political Philosophy , vol.12 , pp. 197
    • Cohen, J.1
  • 24
    • 84920868057 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Is there a human right to democracy?
    • ed. Christine Sypnowich (Oxford: Oxford University Press)
    • Joshua Cohen, "Is There a Human Right to Democracy?" in The Egalitarian Conscience: Essays in Honour of G. A. Cohen, ed. Christine Sypnowich (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006), 226-48.
    • (2006) The Egalitarian Conscience: Essays in Honour of G. A. Cohen , pp. 226-248
    • Cohen, J.1
  • 25
    • 77955704579 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The egalitarianism of human rights
    • I agree with point that neglect of the historical dimension of human rights might be a reason for the inattention in recent human rights discourse to the status-egalitarianism expressed by human rights. See his, at 688 (in this issue)
    • I agree with Allen Buchanan's point that neglect of the historical dimension of human rights might be a reason for the inattention in recent human rights discourse to the status-egalitarianism expressed by human rights. See his "The Egalitarianism of Human Rights," Ethics 120 (2010): 679-710, at 688 (in this issue).
    • (2010) Ethics , vol.120 , pp. 679-710
    • Buchanan, A.1
  • 26
    • 0039109944 scopus 로고
    • It is important to note that this was often qualified as "well-affected," restricting the claim to political equality to persons with a certain degree of economic independence. On this, see the famous Putney Debates of 1647 documented in Arthur S. P. Woodhouse, ed., (Chicago: University of Chicago Press). What I point to here is a certain logic of the historical argument for human rights that has also been used to criticize their concrete historical forms
    • It is important to note that this was often qualified as "well-affected," restricting the claim to political equality to persons with a certain degree of economic independence. On this, see the famous Putney Debates of 1647 documented in Arthur S. P. Woodhouse, ed., Puritanism and Liberty (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1953). What I point to here is a certain logic of the historical argument for human rights that has also been used to criticize their concrete historical forms.
    • (1953) Puritanism and Liberty
  • 27
    • 77955684686 scopus 로고
    • England's birth-right justified
    • (1645), ed. W. Haller (New York: Octagon)
    • John Lilburne, "England's Birth-Right Justified" (1645), in Tracts on Liberty in the Puritan Revolution, vol. 3, ed. W. Haller (New York: Octagon, 1965), 303.
    • (1965) Tracts on Liberty in the Puritan Revolution , vol.3 , pp. 303
    • Lilburne, J.1
  • 28
    • 33749396496 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Frankfurt/Main: Suhrkamp), chaps. 5 and 6 (an English translation titled Toleration in Conflict is forthcoming from Cambridge University Press)
    • See also Rainer Forst, Toleranz im Konflikt: Geschichte, Gehalt und Gegenwart eines umstrittenen Begriffs (Frankfurt/Main: Suhrkamp, 2003), chaps. 5 and 6 (an English translation titled Toleration in Conflict is forthcoming from Cambridge University Press).
    • (2003) Toleranz im Konflikt: Geschichte, Gehalt und Gegenwart eines umstrittenen Begriffs
    • Forst, R.1
  • 31
    • 0003337163 scopus 로고
    • Politics and human rights
    • The democratic point of human rights is also stressed by Lefort's reading of the declaration in Claude Lefort, ed. John B. Thompson, trans. Alan Sheridan (Cambridge: Polity)
    • The democratic point of human rights is also stressed by Lefort's reading of the declaration in Claude Lefort, "Politics and Human Rights," in The Political Forms of Modern Society, ed. John B. Thompson, trans. Alan Sheridan (Cambridge: Polity, 1986), 239-72.
    • (1986) The Political Forms of Modern Society , pp. 239-272
  • 32
    • 77954423266 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [Hamburg: Junius]) also stress the political character of the Universal Declaration as a reaction to totalitarian government, yet they see this as a historical break rather than a continuation
    • Christoph Menke and Arnd Pollmann (Philosophie der Menschenrechte [Hamburg: Junius, 2007]) also stress the political character of the Universal Declaration as a reaction to totalitarian government, yet they see this as a historical break rather than a continuation.
    • (2007) Philosophie der Menschenrechte
    • Menke, C.1    Pollmann, A.2
  • 33
    • 0003266374 scopus 로고
    • Discourse ethics: Notes on a program of philosophical justification
    • trans. Christian Lenhardt and Shierry Weber Nicholsen (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press)
    • Jürgen Habermas, "Discourse Ethics: Notes on a Program of Philosophical Justification," in Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action, trans. Christian Lenhardt and Shierry Weber Nicholsen (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1990), 43-115;
    • (1990) Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action , pp. 43-115
    • Habermas, J.1
  • 34
    • 0002494274 scopus 로고
    • Foundations of liberal equality
    • ed. Grethe B. Peterson (Salt Lake City: University of Utah Press), here at 9
    • Ronald Dworkin, "Foundations of Liberal Equality," in The Tanner Lectures on Human Values XI, ed. Grethe B. Peterson (Salt Lake City: University of Utah Press, 1990), 1-119, here at 9.
    • (1990) The Tanner Lectures on Human Values XI , pp. 1-119
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 35
    • 3142524543 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I have adapted the distinction in Rainer Forst, trans. John M. M. Farrell (Berkeley: University of California Press)
    • I have adapted the distinction in Rainer Forst, Contexts of Justice: Political Philosophy beyond Liberalism and Communitarianism, trans. John M. M. Farrell (Berkeley: University of California Press, 2002).
    • (2002) Contexts of Justice: Political Philosophy beyond Liberalism and Communitarianism
  • 36
    • 84925143605 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), chap. 6, also argues for a norm of moral respect as the basis for a publicly justifiable basic structure; he restricts this, however, to the political realm of justification
    • Charles Larmore, The Autonomy of Morality (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2008), chap. 6, also argues for a norm of moral respect as the basis for a publicly justifiable basic structure; he restricts this, however, to the political realm of justification.
    • (2008) The Autonomy of Morality
    • Larmore, C.1
  • 52
    • 34247254373 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Frankfurt/Main: Suhrkamp, English translation forthcoming as The Right to Justification from Columbia University Press), chaps. 1 and 2, I discuss the moral foundations of this view. As opposed to the interpretation of my approach by Menke and Pollmann, Philosophie der Menschenrechte, I see the duty of justification as a duty of both practical reason and morality. The ground of human rights is the moral recognition of the other as having a right to justification, but that kind of recognition is an imperative of moral practical reason
    • In Rainer Forst, Das Recht auf Rechtfertigung: Elemente einer konstruktivistischen Theorie der Gerechtigkeit (Frankfurt/Main: Suhrkamp, 2007, English translation forthcoming as The Right to Justification from Columbia University Press), chaps. 1 and 2, I discuss the moral foundations of this view. As opposed to the interpretation of my approach by Menke and Pollmann, Philosophie der Menschenrechte, 57-68, I see the duty of justification as a duty of both practical reason and morality. The ground of human rights is the moral recognition of the other as having a right to justification, but that kind of recognition is an imperative of moral practical reason.
    • (2007) Das Recht auf Rechtfertigung: Elemente einer konstruktivistischen Theorie der Gerechtigkeit , pp. 57-68
    • Forst, R.1
  • 56
    • 84997889634 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I have discussed this more fully in my
    • I have discussed this more fully in my Toleranz im Konflikt, 736-42.
    • Toleranz im Konflikt , pp. 736-742
  • 57
    • 77955690355 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is not to say that ethical considerations are irrelevant for the justification of rights claims; rather, they are insufficient to establish the normative character of such claims as reciprocally and generally binding
    • This is not to say that ethical considerations are irrelevant for the justification of rights claims; rather, they are insufficient to establish the normative character of such claims as reciprocally and generally binding.
  • 59
    • 79955968861 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Human rights and the autonomy of international law
    • see also his critique of Raz in
    • see also his critique of Raz in James Griffin, "Human Rights and the Autonomy of International Law," in Besson and Tasioulas, The Philosophy of International Law, 339-56.
    • Besson and Tasioulas, The Philosophy of International Law , pp. 339-356
    • Griffin, J.1
  • 61
    • 33645953824 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Whose sovereignty? Empire versus international law
    • A more skeptical view is expressed in
    • A more skeptical view is expressed in Jean Cohen, "Whose Sovereignty? Empire versus International Law," Ethics and International Affairs 18 (2004): 1-24.
    • (2004) Ethics and International Affairs , vol.18 , pp. 1-24
    • Cohen, J.1
  • 63
    • 0007639855 scopus 로고
    • The moral standing of states
    • at 214
    • following MichaelWalzer, "The Moral Standing of States," Philosophy and Public Affairs 9 (1980): 209-29, at 214.
    • (1980) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.9 , pp. 209-229
    • Walzer, M.1
  • 67
    • 84945670327 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Even though Beitz criticizes minimalist views of human rights (and 142), his own critique of the human right to democratic institutions (ibid., 185) attests to the reductivist tendency in "practical" approaches
    • Even though Beitz criticizes minimalist views of human rights (see Beitz, The Idea of Human Rights, 106 and 142), his own critique of the human right to democratic institutions (ibid., 185) attests to the reductivist tendency in "practical" approaches.
    • The Idea of Human Rights , pp. 106
    • Beitz1
  • 68
    • 77955682463 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The domain of the political and overlapping consensus
    • ed. Samuel Freeman (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press), 491
    • John Rawls, "The Domain of the Political and Overlapping Consensus," in Collected Papers, ed. Samuel Freeman (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999), 473-96, 491.
    • (1999) Collected Papers , pp. 473-496
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 79
    • 79851473285 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On this point, see also argument based on the idea of a "right to have rights" in her, The Lindley Lecture, University of Kansas
    • On this point, see also Seyla Benhabib's argument based on the idea of a "right to have rights" in her "Is There a Human Right to Democracy? Beyond Interventionism and Indifference," The Lindley Lecture, University of Kansas, 2007.
    • (2007) Is There a Human Right to Democracy? Beyond Interventionism and Indifference
    • Benhabib, S.1
  • 82
    • 84923218804 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Political liberty: Integrating five conceptions of autonomy
    • ed. John Christman and Joel Anderson (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)
    • See Rainer Forst, "Political Liberty: Integrating Five Conceptions of Autonomy," in Autonomy and the Challenges to Liberalism: New Essays, ed. John Christman and Joel Anderson (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005), 226-42.
    • (2005) Autonomy and the Challenges to Liberalism: New Essays , pp. 226-242
    • Forst, R.1
  • 86
    • 84867442087 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See also my critique of Rawls in Contexts of Justice, chaps. 3.1 and 4.2, as well as my chap. 4
    • See also my critique of Rawls in Contexts of Justice, chaps. 3.1 and 4.2, as well as my The Right to Justification, chap. 4.
    • The Right to Justification
  • 87
    • 0001778060 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Conditions of an unforced consensus on human rights
    • I do not deny that a free-standing notion of respect can be incorporated into different "background justifications" of cultural and religious kinds, to use a phrase by, ed. Joanne R. Bauer and Daniel A. Bell (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). However, these backgrounds must not lead to interpretations of what kind of respect is owed to whom that reproduce the inequalities and asymmetries that human rights are supposed to correct. Given the moral grammar and social function of human rights, they need to have a moral weight of their own that can counterbalance "traditional" hierarchical or patriarchal normative outlooks
    • I do not deny that a free-standing notion of respect can be incorporated into different "background justifications" of cultural and religious kinds, to use a phrase by Charles Taylor, "Conditions of an Unforced Consensus on Human Rights," in The East Asian Challenge for Human Rights, ed. Joanne R. Bauer and Daniel A. Bell (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999), 124-44. However, these backgrounds must not lead to interpretations of what kind of respect is owed to whom that reproduce the inequalities and asymmetries that human rights are supposed to correct. Given the moral grammar and social function of human rights, they need to have a moral weight of their own that can counterbalance "traditional" hierarchical or patriarchal normative outlooks.
    • (1999) The East Asian Challenge for Human Rights , pp. 124-144
    • Taylor, C.1
  • 88
    • 0003739463 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As discussed, e.g., in Bauer and Bell, The East Asian Challenge for Human Rights, and in (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press)
    • As discussed, e.g., in Bauer and Bell, The East Asian Challenge for Human Rights, and in Daniel A. Bell, East Meets West: Human Rights and Democracy in East Asia (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2000).
    • (2000) East Meets West: Human Rights and Democracy in East Asia
    • Bell, D.A.1
  • 89
    • 79959114171 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In the remainder of this section, I condense an argument I make at greater length in Rainer Forst, "The Basic Right to Justification: Toward a Constructivist Conception of Human Rights," trans.
    • In the remainder of this section, I condense an argument I make at greater length in Rainer Forst, "The Basic Right to Justification: Toward a Constructivist Conception of Human Rights," trans. Jonathan M. Caver, Constellations 6 (1999): 35-60.
    • (1999) Constellations , vol.6 , pp. 35-60
    • Caver, J.M.1
  • 90
    • 0009811341 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Contesting cultures: Westernization, respect for cultures, and third-world feminists
    • ed. LindaNicholson (New York: Routledge), at 412
    • Uma Narayan, "Contesting Cultures: Westernization, Respect for Cultures, and Third-World Feminists," in The Second Wave: A Reader in Feminist Theory, ed. LindaNicholson (New York: Routledge, 1997), 396-418, at 412.
    • (1997) The Second Wave: A Reader in Feminist Theory , pp. 396-418
    • Narayan, U.1
  • 91
    • 0141917009 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Essence of culture and a sense of history: A feminist critique of cultural essentialism
    • ed. Uma Narayan and Sandra Harding (Bloomington: Indiana University Press), at 91
    • Uma Narayan, "Essence of Culture and a Sense of History: A Feminist Critique of Cultural Essentialism," in Decentering the Center: Philosophy for a Multicultural, Postcolonial and FeministWorld, ed.Uma Narayan and Sandra Harding (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2000), 80-100, at 91.
    • (2000) Decentering the Center: Philosophy for a Multicultural, Postcolonial and Feminist World , pp. 80-100
    • Narayan, U.1
  • 92
    • 84884481713 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The rule of reasons: Three models of deliberative democracy
    • On the notion of democracy implied here
    • On the notion of democracy implied here, see Rainer Forst, "The Rule of Reasons: Three Models of Deliberative Democracy," Ratio Juris 14 (2001): 345-78.
    • (2001) Ratio Juris , vol.14 , pp. 345-378
    • Forst, R.1
  • 93
    • 77955669938 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This also holds true for persons who cannot use their right to justification in an active sense, such as (to some extent) children or mentally disabled persons; the passive status of having that right does not depend on its active exercise
    • This also holds true for persons who cannot use their right to justification in an active sense, such as (to some extent) children or mentally disabled persons; the passive status of having that right does not depend on its active exercise.
  • 94
    • 77955682869 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I explain the difference to Rawls in Forst
    • I explain the difference to Rawls in Forst, "The Basic Right to Justification," 45-46.
    • The Basic Right to Justification , pp. 45-46
  • 96
    • 0003867020 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I modify here the "not reasonable to reject" formulation of Scanlon's contractualist theory of justification; (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press), esp. chap. 5. I discuss the differences between Scanlon's contractualism and discursive constructivism in The Right to Justification, chaps. 1 and 2
    • I modify here the "not reasonable to reject" formulation of Scanlon's contractualist theory of justification; see Thomas Scanlon, What We Owe to Each Other (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1998), esp. chap. 5. I discuss the differences between Scanlon's contractualism and discursive constructivism in The Right to Justification, chaps. 1 and 2.
    • (1998) What We Owe to Each Other
    • Scanlon, T.1
  • 97
    • 77955677987 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This also captures the historical meaning of these rights; in briefly mentioning the social struggles of the Levellers, I pointed out that they were directed against feudalism as a social order as well as against absolute monarchy as a political order
    • This also captures the historical meaning of these rights; in briefly mentioning the social struggles of the Levellers, I pointed out that they were directed against feudalism as a social order as well as against absolute monarchy as a political order.
  • 98
    • 77955678282 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • That worry has been raised, in different ways, by Allen Buchanan, James Griffin, and John Tasioulas, to whom I am particularly grateful
    • That worry has been raised, in different ways, by Allen Buchanan, James Griffin, and John Tasioulas, to whom I am particularly grateful.
  • 99
    • 84909583806 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I agree with on that point
    • I agree with Griffin (On Human Rights, 41) on that point.
    • On Human Rights , pp. 41
    • Griffin1
  • 100
    • 0003576528 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In an important sense, I share Habermas's idea of the "equiprimordiality" of personal and political autonomy as well as of human rights and popular sovereignty, as explained in, trans. William Rehg (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press), esp. chap. 3
    • In an important sense, I share Habermas's idea of the "equiprimordiality" of personal and political autonomy as well as of human rights and popular sovereignty, as explained in Jürgen Habermas, Between Facts and Norms: Contributions to a Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy, trans. William Rehg (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1996), esp. chap. 3.
    • (1996) Between Facts and Norms: Contributions to a Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy
    • Habermas, J.1
  • 101
    • 84908982032 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The justification of justice: Rawls's political liberalism and habermas's discourse theory in dialogue
    • In another sense, however, I diverge from it, for my notion of equiprimordiality sees the right to justification as one source for both, while Habermas sees different sources at work. In addition, none of these has the moral status of the right to justification for which I argue. For a discussion of this, chap. 4
    • In another sense, however, I diverge from it, for my notion of equiprimordiality sees the right to justification as one source for both, while Habermas sees different sources at work. In addition, none of these has the moral status of the right to justification for which I argue. For a discussion of this, see Rainer Forst, "The Justification of Justice: Rawls's Political Liberalism and Habermas's Discourse Theory in Dialogue," in The Right to Justification, chap. 4.
    • The Right to Justification
    • Forst, R.1
  • 102
    • 2542588308 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • What human rights mean
    • at 44
    • Charles Beitz, "What Human Rights Mean," Daedalus 132 (2003), 36-46, at 44.
    • (2003) Daedalus , vol.132 , pp. 36-46
    • Beitz, C.1
  • 103
    • 76849109677 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In his, Beitz distances himself from this view, however. For another example of that position
    • In his The Idea of Human Rights, 142-43, Beitz distances himself from this view, however. For another example of that position.
    • The Idea of Human Rights , pp. 142-143
  • 105
    • 29144470984 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Towards a critical theory of transnational justice
    • ed. Thomas Pogge (Oxford: Blackwell)
    • See Rainer Forst, "Towards a Critical Theory of Transnational Justice," in Global Justice, ed. Thomas Pogge (Oxford: Blackwell, 2001), 169-87.
    • (2001) Global Justice , pp. 169-187
    • Forst, R.1
  • 107
    • 84891290995 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Pogge discusses the case in which the state is not willing to act and categorizes it as a kind of "official disrespect"
    • Pogge discusses the case in which the state is not willing to act and categorizes it as a kind of "official disrespect" (ibid., 61).
    • World Poverty and Human Rights , pp. 61
  • 108
    • 84900247308 scopus 로고
    • Mediating duties
    • For the notion of "mediation" here
    • For the notion of "mediation" here, see Henry Shue, "Mediating Duties," Ethics 98 (1988): 687-704.
    • (1988) Ethics , vol.98 , pp. 687-704
    • Shue, H.1
  • 109
    • 19844366233 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Remarks on legitimation through human rights
    • This point is stressed by in his, trans. Max Pensky (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press)
    • This point is stressed by Jürgen Habermas in his "Remarks on Legitimation through Human Rights," in The Postnational Constellation, trans. Max Pensky (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2001), 113-30,
    • (2001) The Postnational Constellation , pp. 113-130
    • Habermas, J.1
  • 110
    • 47249085830 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Does the constitutionalization of international law still have a chance?
    • trans. Ciaran Cronin (Cambridge: Polity)
    • "Does the Constitutionalization of International Law Still Have a Chance?" in The Divided West, trans. Ciaran Cronin (Cambridge: Polity, 2006), 113-93.
    • (2006) The Divided West , pp. 113-193
  • 111
    • 0004175858 scopus 로고
    • (New York: Harcourt, Brace, Jovanovich), chap. 9
    • See Hannah Arendt, The Origins of Totalitarianism (New York: Harcourt, Brace, Jovanovich, 1979), chap. 9;
    • (1979) The Origins of Totalitarianism
    • Arendt, H.1
  • 112
    • 84911213386 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • for an interpretation and application of this thought, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), chap. 2
    • for an interpretation and application of this thought, see Seyla Benhabib, The Rights of Others (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004), chap. 2.
    • (2004) The Rights of Others
    • Benhabib, S.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.