메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 12, Issue 2, 2004, Pages 190-213

Minimalism about human rights: The most we can hope for?

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 2542522411     PISSN: 09638016     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1111/j.1467-9760.2004.00197.x     Document Type: Conference Paper
Times cited : (266)

References (57)
  • 4
    • 0003851654 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • trans. Paul Guyer and Allen Wood (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)
    • Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, trans. Paul Guyer and Allen Wood (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998), A805-B833.
    • (1998) Critique of Pure Reason
    • Kant, I.1
  • 6
    • 0011859126 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I believe that Ignatieff uses the term "minimalism" to cover both; Human Rights, pp. 55-6.
    • Human Rights , pp. 55-56
  • 7
    • 0003624191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Columbia University Press
    • John Rawls, Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1996), pp. 12, 145. My emphasis in this paragraph on how the human rights conception is presented follows Rawls's account of the second feature of a political conception of justice. See Political Liberalism, p. 12.
    • (1996) Political Liberalism , pp. 12
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 8
    • 0003624191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • John Rawls, Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1996), pp. 12, 145. My emphasis in this paragraph on how the human rights conception is presented follows Rawls's account of the second feature of a political conception of justice. See Political Liberalism, p. 12.
    • Political Liberalism , pp. 12
  • 9
    • 0003875144 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, chap. 6
    • For discussion of the merits of this line of argument, see Onora O'Neill, Bounds of Justice (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000), chap. 6; Henry Shue, Basic Rights: Subsistence, Affluence, and US Foreign Policy (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1980); Amartya Sen, "Towards a Theory of Human Rights," unpublished.
    • (2000) Bounds of Justice
    • O'Neill, O.1
  • 10
    • 0003754159 scopus 로고
    • Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press
    • For discussion of the merits of this line of argument, see Onora O'Neill, Bounds of Justice (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000), chap. 6; Henry Shue, Basic Rights: Subsistence, Affluence, and US Foreign Policy (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1980); Amartya Sen, "Towards a Theory of Human Rights," unpublished.
    • (1980) Basic Rights: Subsistence, Affluence, and US Foreign Policy
    • Shue, H.1
  • 11
    • 2542557906 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • unpublished
    • For discussion of the merits of this line of argument, see Onora O'Neill, Bounds of Justice (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000), chap. 6; Henry Shue, Basic Rights: Subsistence, Affluence, and US Foreign Policy (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1980); Amartya Sen, "Towards a Theory of Human Rights," unpublished.
    • Towards a Theory of Human Rights
    • Sen, A.1
  • 12
    • 0003578539 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Random House
    • Cited in Mary Ann Glendon, A World Made New: Eleanor Roosevelt and the Universal Declaration of Human Rights (New York: Random House, 2001). On the background of Maritain's views of human rights in broader efforts to rethink the fundamentals of Catholic social thought - especially the relative significance attached to notions of the human person and the common good - see John T. McGreevy, Catholicism and American Freedom: A History (New York: Norton, 2003), chap. 7.
    • (2001) A World Made New: Eleanor Roosevelt and the Universal Declaration of Human Rights
    • Glendon, M.A.1
  • 13
    • 2142780293 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Norton, chap. 7
    • Cited in Mary Ann Glendon, A World Made New: Eleanor Roosevelt and the Universal Declaration of Human Rights (New York: Random House, 2001). On the background of Maritain's views of human rights in broader efforts to rethink the fundamentals of Catholic social thought - especially the relative significance attached to notions of the human person and the common good - see John T. McGreevy, Catholicism and American Freedom: A History (New York: Norton, 2003), chap. 7.
    • (2003) Catholicism and American Freedom: A History
    • McGreevy, J.T.1
  • 14
    • 0004168076 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Harvard University Press
    • Rawls refers to the public reason of the "society of peoples" in The Law of Peoples (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1999), pp. 54-7. I do not wish here to engage the issue of whether "peoples" are the moral agents in international society. Thus the less theoretically committed term "international society."
    • (1999) The Law of Peoples , pp. 54-57
  • 15
    • 84909280874 scopus 로고
    • The emerging right to democratic governance
    • On the human right to democracy see Thomas Franck, "The emerging right to democratic governance," American Journal of International Law, 86 (1992), 46-91. Rawls rejects the right to democracy as a basic human right in favor of a weaker requirement of organized group consultation.
    • (1992) American Journal of International Law , vol.86 , pp. 46-91
    • Franck, T.1
  • 17
    • 0004262558 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press
    • See Stephen D. Krasner, Sovereignty: Organized Hypocrisy (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1999). I am indebted to Thomas Christensen for discussion of the point in the text.
    • (1999) Sovereignty: Organized Hypocrisy
    • Krasner, S.D.1
  • 18
    • 0003686151 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Thus Article 2 of the Covenant on Civil and Political Rights requires states to adopt the "legislative and other measures" needed to give effect to the rights; Steiner and Allston, International Human Rights in Context, p. 1382.
    • International Human Rights in Context , pp. 1382
    • Steiner1    Allston2
  • 19
    • 0035533806 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Human rights as a common concern
    • Charles Beitz, "Human rights as a common concern," American Political Science Review, 95 (2001), 269-82; "What human rights mean," Daedalus, 132 (2003), 36-46; "Human rights and The Law of Peoples," unpublished.
    • (2001) American Political Science Review , vol.95 , pp. 269-282
    • Beitz, C.1
  • 20
    • 2542588308 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • What human rights mean
    • Charles Beitz, "Human rights as a common concern," American Political Science Review, 95 (2001), 269-82; "What human rights mean," Daedalus, 132 (2003), 36-46; "Human rights and The Law of Peoples," unpublished.
    • (2003) Daedalus , vol.132 , pp. 36-46
  • 21
    • 0035533806 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • unpublished
    • Charles Beitz, "Human rights as a common concern," American Political Science Review, 95 (2001), 269-82; "What human rights mean," Daedalus, 132 (2003), 36-46; "Human rights and The Law of Peoples," unpublished.
    • Human Rights and the Law of Peoples
  • 22
    • 2542556353 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • One might argue that human rights are the result of applying natural rights to the circumstances of an organized political society. So, for example, the right to equality before the law might be derived from a natural right to bodily security, along with some reasonable assumptions about the conditions for protecting that right in a society with a legal system. I do not find this argument compelling, but cannot pursue the reasons here.
  • 23
    • 0001956628 scopus 로고
    • Human rights, rationality, and sentimentality
    • ed. Stephen Shute and Susan Hurley (New York: Basic Books)
    • Richard Rorty, "Human rights, rationality, and sentimentality," in On Human Rights, ed. Stephen Shute and Susan Hurley (New York: Basic Books, 1993).
    • (1993) On Human Rights
    • Rorty, R.1
  • 25
    • 0004220262 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • See H. L. A. Hart, Concept of Law, 2nd edn (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1994), pp. 193-200; Michael Walzer, Thick and Thin: Moral Argument at Home and Abroad (South Bend, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press, 1994), chap. 1.
    • (1994) Concept of Law, 2nd Edn , pp. 193-200
    • Hart, H.L.A.1
  • 26
    • 0003685593 scopus 로고
    • (South Bend, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press), chap. 1
    • See H. L. A. Hart, Concept of Law, 2nd edn (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1994), pp. 193-200; Michael Walzer, Thick and Thin: Moral Argument at Home and Abroad (South Bend, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press, 1994), chap. 1.
    • (1994) Thick and Thin: Moral Argument at Home and Abroad
    • Walzer, M.1
  • 27
    • 0003243880 scopus 로고
    • Moral pluralism and political consensus
    • ed. David Copp, Jean Hampton and John Roemer (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)
    • The empirical interpretation parallels a conventional misunderstanding of Rawls's conception of an overlapping consensus. For discussion of the misunderstanding, see Joshua Cohen, "Moral pluralism and political consensus," The Idea of Democracy, ed. David Copp, Jean Hampton and John Roemer (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), pp. 270-91.
    • (1993) The Idea of Democracy , pp. 270-291
    • Cohen, J.1
  • 29
    • 2542580622 scopus 로고
    • Declaration on religious freedom
    • Westminster, Md.: Newman Press
    • See "Declaration on Religious Freedom," The Teachings of the Second Vatican Council: Complete Texts of the Constitutions, Decrees, and Declarations (Westminster, Md.: Newman Press, 1966), pp. 366-7. The quotations in this paragraph all come from the Introduction to the Declaration, and from its first chapter, on the "General Principles of Religious Liberty."
    • (1966) The Teachings of the Second Vatican Council: Complete Texts of the Constitutions, Decrees, and Declarations , pp. 366-367
  • 30
    • 2542571502 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • In the case of revealed religions, a large issue about the relationship between revelation (including the manifestation of truths about human beings) and history looms in the background - about whether the whole truth is revealed at a determinate moment in history or is instead revealed over the course of history. I do not propose to explore this disagreement here.
  • 31
    • 0004247732 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • chap. 5
    • The same of course can be said for utilitarianism and for perfectionist views founded on an Aristotelian understanding of human nature and human flourishing. For proposals about how to bring ideas about rights without parentage in positive legislation into utilitarianism, see John Stuart Mill, Utilitarianism, chap. 5 and H. L. A. Hart, "Natural rights: Bentham and John Stuart Mill," in Essays on Bentham (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1982), chap. 4.
    • Utilitarianism
    • Mill, J.S.1
  • 32
    • 2542612669 scopus 로고
    • Natural rights: Bentham and John Stuart Mill
    • (Oxford: Oxford University Press), chap. 4
    • The same of course can be said for utilitarianism and for perfectionist views founded on an Aristotelian understanding of human nature and human flourishing. For proposals about how to bring ideas about rights without parentage in positive legislation into utilitarianism, see John Stuart Mill, Utilitarianism, chap. 5 and H. L. A. Hart, "Natural rights: Bentham and John Stuart Mill," in Essays on Bentham (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1982), chap. 4.
    • (1982) Essays on Bentham
    • Hart, H.L.A.1
  • 33
    • 2542535021 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • To be sure, we have a strong case that that terrain cannot be occupied if paradigmatic human rights are incompatible with the doctrine.
  • 34
    • 0004635837 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Epilogue
    • Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press
    • See his "Epilogue," Confucian Traditions in East Asian Modernity, ed. Tu Wei-Ming (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1996), p. 347.
    • (1996) Confucian Traditions in East Asian Modernity , pp. 347
    • Tu, W.-M.1
  • 35
    • 15244340660 scopus 로고
    • trans. James Legge (New York: Paragon)
    • My statement of the elements of Confucianism draws on the Four Books (Analects, Great Learning, Doctrine of the Mean, and Mencius). See The Four Books, trans. James Legge (New York: Paragon, 1966); The Analects of Confucius: A Philosophical Translation, trans. Roger Ames and Henry Rosemont (New York: Ballentine, 1998). For helpful discussion, see the Introduction by Ames and Rosement to The Analects, pp. 1-66; Kwong-Loi Shun, Mencius and Early Chinese Thought (Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press, 1997).
    • (1966) The Four Books
  • 36
    • 0141729568 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • trans. Roger Ames and Henry Rosemont (New York: Ballentine)
    • My statement of the elements of Confucianism draws on the Four Books (Analects, Great Learning, Doctrine of the Mean, and Mencius). See The Four Books, trans. James Legge (New York: Paragon, 1966); The Analects of Confucius: A Philosophical Translation, trans. Roger Ames and Henry Rosemont (New York: Ballentine, 1998). For helpful discussion, see the Introduction by Ames and Rosement to The Analects, pp. 1-66; Kwong-Loi Shun, Mencius and Early Chinese Thought (Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press, 1997).
    • (1998) The Analects of Confucius: A Philosophical Translation
  • 37
    • 85013014366 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • My statement of the elements of Confucianism draws on the Four Books (Analects, Great Learning, Doctrine of the Mean, and Mencius). See The Four Books, trans. James Legge (New York: Paragon, 1966); The Analects of Confucius: A Philosophical Translation, trans. Roger Ames and Henry Rosemont (New York: Ballentine, 1998). For helpful discussion, see the Introduction by Ames and Rosement to The Analects, pp. 1-66; Kwong-Loi Shun, Mencius and Early Chinese Thought (Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press, 1997).
    • The Analects , pp. 1-66
    • Ames1    Rosement2
  • 38
    • 0141757688 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press
    • My statement of the elements of Confucianism draws on the Four Books (Analects, Great Learning, Doctrine of the Mean, and Mencius). See The Four Books, trans. James Legge (New York: Paragon, 1966); The Analects of Confucius: A Philosophical Translation, trans. Roger Ames and Henry Rosemont (New York: Ballentine, 1998). For helpful discussion, see the Introduction by Ames and Rosement to The Analects, pp. 1-66; Kwong-Loi Shun, Mencius and Early Chinese Thought (Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press, 1997).
    • (1997) Mencius and Early Chinese Thought
    • Shun, K.-L.1
  • 39
    • 79957107478 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the view of human nature, and its metaphysical background, see Ames and Rosemont, "Introduction," pp. 23-9.
    • Introduction , pp. 23-29
    • Ames1    Rosemont2
  • 40
    • 2542617283 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I have included all references to the Analects in the text, and I cite the Ames and Rosemont translation.
  • 41
  • 42
    • 0004168076 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In this case, the human rights belong, as Rawls puts it, to "an associationist social form . . . which sees persons first as members of groups - associations, corporations, and estates. As such members, persons have rights and liberties enabling them to meet their duties and obligations and to engage in a decent system of social cooperation." Rawls, Law of Peoples, p. 68.
    • Law of Peoples , pp. 68
    • Rawls1
  • 43
    • 2542642855 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • chap. 6
    • The line of argument noted in the text is not the only one available within Confucianism. Angle points to two alternative strategies of early twentieth-century Confucian argument for "ethical aggressiveness: struggling to exercise those abilities and receive those benefits that properly belong to one"; Angle, Human Rights, chap. 6. Throughout, Angle rightly distinguishes the idea that doctrinal evolution sometimes represents a response to external provocations from the idea that such evolution consists simply in embracing ideas that are external to an ethical tradition.
    • Human Rights
    • Angle1
  • 45
    • 2542583617 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), esp. chap. 6, which describes both contextualist/historicist and holistic styles of interpretation
    • For an illuminating discussion of approaches to interpretation within Islamic law, see Wael B. Hallaq, A History of Islamic Legal Theories: An Introduction to Sunni Usul Al-Fiqh (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997), esp. chap. 6, which describes both contextualist/historicist and holistic styles of interpretation.
    • (1997) A History of Islamic Legal Theories: An Introduction to Sunni Usul Al-Fiqh
    • Hallaq, W.B.1
  • 46
    • 2542635449 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Qur'an, 2:281. I have used The Holy Qur'an, trans. Abdullah Yusuf Ali, tenth edition (Beltsville, Md.: Amana Publications, 1999). Hereafter, references are in the text.
    • Qur'an , vol.2 , pp. 281
  • 47
    • 0040789710 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • trans. Abdullah Yusuf Ali, tenth edition (Beltsville, Md.: Amana Publications). Hereafter, references are in the text
    • Qur'an, 2:281. I have used The Holy Qur'an, trans. Abdullah Yusuf Ali, tenth edition (Beltsville, Md.: Amana Publications, 1999). Hereafter, references are in the text.
    • (1999) The Holy Qur'an
  • 49
    • 33644598120 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Islam and the challenge of democracy
    • April-May
    • I have been helped in my discussion here by Khaled Abou El Fadl, "Islam and the challenge of democracy," Boston Review (April-May 2003).
    • (2003) Boston Review
    • El Fadl, K.A.1
  • 51
    • 0010701535 scopus 로고
    • trans. John B. Hardie (Oneonta, N.Y.: Islamic Publications International)
    • Qutb's account of freedom of conscience and responsibility seems to be of this kind. See Sayyid Qutb, Social Justice in Islam, trans. John B. Hardie (Oneonta, N.Y.: Islamic Publications International, 1953). Thus freedom of conscience is a matter of, among other things, freedom from false worship, fear (of death, injury, and humiliation), and false social values (pp. 53-68). The fundamental metaphysical idea in Qutb's view - his idea of the absolute unity of existence - appears to limit any role for basic human rights.
    • (1953) Social Justice in Islam
    • Qutb, S.1
  • 53
    • 84937381655 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Are human rights universal?
    • See Thomas M. Franck, "Are human rights universal?," Foreign Affairs 80 (2001), p. 195.
    • (2001) Foreign Affairs , vol.80 , pp. 195
    • Franck, T.M.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.