-
1
-
-
84911023404
-
Of Mercenaries and Prostitutes: Can Private Warriors Be Ethical?”
-
in Andrew Alexandra, Deane-Peter Baker, and Marina Caparini, eds. The exceptions include New York: Routledge
-
The exceptions include Deane-Peter Baker, Of Mercenaries and Prostitutes: Can Private Warriors Be Ethical?” in Andrew Alexandra, Deane-Peter Baker, and Marina Caparini, eds., Private Military and Security Companies: Ethics, Policies and Civil-Military Relations (New York: Routledge, 2008), pp. 30–42
-
(2008)
Private Military and Security Companies: Ethics, Policies and Civil-Military Relations
, pp. 30-42
-
-
Baker, D.-P.1
-
4
-
-
84920456849
-
Outsourcing the Responsibility to Protect: Humanitarian Intervention and Private Military Companies
-
in Hartmut Behr, ed. Lynne Rienner, forthcoming
-
James Pattison, “Outsourcing the Responsibility to Protect: Humanitarian Intervention and Private Military Companies,” in Hartmut Behr, ed., Beyond National Security: New Regional and Global Perspectives on Non-State Violence (Lynne Rienner, forthcoming)
-
Beyond National Security: New Regional and Global Perspectives on Non-State Violence
-
-
Pattison, J.1
-
5
-
-
74549224428
-
It's All Contracts Now: Private Military Firms and a Clash of Legal Culture
-
Kateri Carmola, “It's All Contracts Now: Private Military Firms and a Clash of Legal Culture,” Brown Journal of World Affairs 13, no. 1 (2006), pp. 161–173
-
(2006)
Brown Journal of World Affairs
, vol.13
, Issue.1
, pp. 161-173
-
-
Carmola, K.1
-
8
-
-
51249114444
-
In Humanity's Name: Democracy and the Right to Wage War
-
in Mark Evans, ed. One example is the principle of legitimate authority, which, according to Mark Evans, was invoked to prohibit the waging of ‘war’ by just any group of people (for example, mercenaries).” Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press
-
One example is the principle of legitimate authority, which, according to Mark Evans, was invoked to prohibit the waging of ‘war’ by just any group of people (for example, mercenaries).“ Mark Evans, ”In Humanity's Name: Democracy and the Right to Wage War,” in Mark Evans, ed., Just War Theory: A Reappraisal (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 2005), p. 78.
-
(2005)
Just War Theory: A Reappraisal
, pp. 78
-
-
Evans, M.1
-
9
-
-
33644790557
-
-
Geneva: Geneva Centre for the Democratic Control of Armed Forces See, further available at www.isn.ethz.ch/pubs/ph/details.cfm?lng=en&id=14077
-
See, further, Fred Schreier and Marina Caparini, Privatising Security: Law, Practice and Governance of Private Military and Security Companies, Occasional Paper No. 6 (Geneva: Geneva Centre for the Democratic Control of Armed Forces, 2005), pp. 7–9; available at www.isn.ethz.ch/pubs/ph/details.cfm?lng=en&id=14077.
-
(2005)
Privatising Security: Law, Practice and Governance of Private Military and Security Companies, Occasional Paper No. 6
, pp. 7-9
-
-
Schreier, F.1
Caparini, M.2
-
11
-
-
53849148708
-
Introduction
-
in Chesterman and Lehnardt, eds. As Chesterman and Lehnardt note, this definition does not rely on the dubious distinction between “offensive” and “defensive” operations, which is sometimes used to distinguish between “private military companies” and “private security companies.” In addition, the definition is more precise, since the focus is on firms operating in conflict zones (in a military setting) rather than on those providing security in a stable environment
-
Simon Chesterman and Chia Lehnardt, “Introduction,” in Chesterman and Lehnardt, eds., From Mercenaries to Market, p. 3. As Chesterman and Lehnardt note, this definition does not rely on the dubious distinction between “offensive” and “defensive” operations, which is sometimes used to distinguish between “private military companies” and “private security companies.” In addition, the definition is more precise, since the focus is on firms operating in conflict zones (in a military setting) rather than on those providing security in a stable environment.
-
From Mercenaries to Market
, pp. 3
-
-
Chesterman, S.1
Lehnardt, C.2
-
12
-
-
78751550990
-
-
Those who discuss this issue include
-
Those who discuss this issue include Baker, “ Of Mercenaries ”
-
Of Mercenaries
-
-
Baker1
-
13
-
-
75849125250
-
Mercenary Morality
-
in A. G. D. Bradney, ed. Stuttgart: Franz Steiner Verlag
-
C. A. J. Coady, “ Mercenary Morality,” in A. G. D. Bradney, ed., International Law and Armed Conflict (Stuttgart: Franz Steiner Verlag, 1992), pp. 55–69
-
(1992)
International Law and Armed Conflict
, pp. 55-69
-
-
Coady, C.A.J.1
-
21
-
-
85022721099
-
Ethics, Mercenaries and African States
-
University of Cape Town, May 29–31 available at www2.gsu.edu/~wwwphl/ ethics/africaconference/papers.html
-
Uwe Steinhoff,“Ethics, Mercenaries and African States ”(paper presented to the Ethics and Africa Conference, University of Cape Town, May 29–31, 2006), p. 8; available at www2.gsu.edu/~wwwphl/ ethics/africaconference/papers.html.
-
(2006)
paper presented to the Ethics and Africa Conference
, pp. 8
-
-
Steinhoff, U.1
-
22
-
-
84945696006
-
Introduction
-
Humanitarian Intervention in Terry Nardin and Melissa Williams, eds. This distinction is common in the literature on humanitarian intervention. See, e.g. New York: New York University Press
-
This distinction is common in the literature on humanitarian intervention. See, e.g., Terry Nardin, “Introduction,” in Terry Nardin and Melissa Williams, eds., NOMOS XLVII: Humanitarian Intervention (New York: New York University Press, 2006), pp. 9–11
-
(2006)
NOMOS
, vol.42
, pp. 9-11
-
-
Nardin, T.1
-
23
-
-
85055360231
-
Humanitarian Intervention and International Law: The Moral Significance of an Intervener's Legal Status
-
James Pattison, “Humanitarian Intervention and International Law: The Moral Significance of an Intervener's Legal Status,” Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 10, no. 3 (2007), pp. 1–19
-
(2007)
Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy
, vol.10
, Issue.3
, pp. 1-19
-
-
Pattison, J.1
-
24
-
-
33847159732
-
Ending Tyranny in Iraq
-
Fernando Teson, “Ending Tyranny in Iraq,” Ethics & International Affairs 19, no. 2 (2005), pp. 1–20.
-
(2005)
Ethics & International Affairs
, vol.19
, Issue.2
, pp. 1-20
-
-
Teson, F.1
-
25
-
-
85022637675
-
-
also notes this distinction
-
Scobbie, “A Reply,” also notes this distinction
-
A Reply
-
-
Scobbie1
-
26
-
-
80053449442
-
Representativeness and Humanitarian Intervention
-
See my
-
See my “Representativeness and Humanitarian Intervention,” Journal of Social Philosophy 38, no. 4 (2007), pp. 569–587.
-
(2007)
Journal of Social Philosophy
, vol.38
, Issue.4
, pp. 569-587
-
-
-
30
-
-
85055307370
-
Between Public Peacekeepers and Private Forces: Can There Be a Third Way?
-
Christopher Spearin, “Between Public Peacekeepers and Private Forces: Can There Be a Third Way?” International Peacekeeping 12, no. 2 (2005), p. 246.
-
(2005)
International Peacekeeping
, vol.12
, Issue.2
, pp. 246
-
-
Spearin, C.1
-
31
-
-
33847362797
-
-
Ontario: Broadview Press
-
Brian Orend, The Morality of War (Ontario: Broadview Press, 2006), pp. 31–32.
-
(2006)
The Morality of War
, pp. 31-32
-
-
Orend, B.1
-
32
-
-
84859957054
-
Summa Theologiae
-
Thomas R. Heath, trans. New York: Blackfriars
-
Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologiae, Vol. 35, Consequences of Charity, Thomas R. Heath, trans. (New York: Blackfriars, 1972), p. 83.
-
(1972)
Consequences of Charity
, vol.35
, pp. 83
-
-
Aquinas, T.1
-
34
-
-
84991555056
-
The Global Reorganization of Legitimate Violence: Military Entrepreneurs and the Private Face of International Humanitarian Law
-
James Cockayne, “The Global Reorganization of Legitimate Violence: Military Entrepreneurs and the Private Face of International Humanitarian Law,” International Review of the Red Cross 88, no. 863 (2006), p. 478.
-
(2006)
International Review of the Red Cross
, vol.88
, Issue.863
, pp. 478
-
-
Cockayne, J.1
-
37
-
-
84941643485
-
-
June 27 Revised available at www.cpa-iraq. org/regulations/20040627_CPAORD_17_Status_of_Coalition__Rev__with_Annex_A.pdf
-
Coalition Provisional Authority Order Number 17 (Revised), June 27, 2004; available at www.cpa-iraq. org/regulations/20040627_CPAORD_17_Status_of_Coalition__Rev__with_Annex_A.pdf.
-
(2004)
Coalition Provisional Authority Order Number 17
-
-
-
38
-
-
63249117782
-
-
Although the United States has recently extended the Uniform Code of Military Justice to PMC personnel, it is not clear whether this will be enforced
-
Percy, Regulating the Private Security Industry, p. 29. Although the United States has recently extended the Uniform Code of Military Justice to PMC personnel, it is not clear whether this will be enforced.
-
Regulating the Private Security Industry
, pp. 29
-
-
Percy1
-
39
-
-
84875150918
-
The Law Catches Up to Private Militaries, Embeds
-
January 3 See available at www.defensetech.org/archives/003123.html
-
See P. W. Singer, “The Law Catches Up to Private Militaries, Embeds,” Defense Tech, January 3, 2007; available at www.defensetech.org/archives/003123.html.
-
(2007)
Defense Tech
-
-
Singer, P.W.1
-
40
-
-
85022616852
-
Outsourcing the War
-
May 28 available at www.thenation.com/doc/ 20070528/scahill
-
Jeremy Scahill,“ Outsourcing the War,” Nation, May 28, 2007; available at www.thenation.com/doc/ 20070528/scahill.
-
(2007)
Nation
-
-
Scahill, J.1
-
41
-
-
85055311546
-
Private Military Companies: A Second Best Peacekeeping Option?
-
Oldrich Bures,“ Private Military Companies: A Second Best Peacekeeping Option?” International Peacekeeping 12, no. 4 (2005), pp. 541–542.
-
(2005)
International Peacekeeping
, vol.12
, Issue.4
, pp. 541-542
-
-
Bures, O.1
-
42
-
-
54549120732
-
From Errand to Fatal Shot to Hail of Fire to 17 Deaths
-
October 3 available at www.nytimes.com/2007/10/03/world/middleeast/03firefight. html?scp=2&sq=nisour+square(fc'st=nyt
-
James Glanz and Alissa J. Rubin,“ From Errand to Fatal Shot to Hail of Fire to 17 Deaths,” New York Times, October 3, 2007; available at www.nytimes.com/2007/10/03/world/middleeast/03firefight. html?scp=2&sq=nisour+square(fc'st=nyt.
-
(2007)
New York Times
-
-
Glanz, J.1
Rubin, A.J.2
-
43
-
-
85064802377
-
Messiahs or Mercenaries? The Future of International Private Military Services
-
Brooks also argues that what worries the international community about PMCs is not any particular past incident, but simply the potential to harm
-
Doug Brooks,“ Messiahs or Mercenaries? The Future of International Private Military Services,” International Peacekeeping 7, no. 4 (2000), pp. 129–44. Brooks also argues that what worries the international community about PMCs is not any particular past incident, but simply the potential to harm.
-
(2000)
International Peacekeeping
, vol.7
, Issue.4
, pp. 129-144
-
-
Brooks, D.1
-
46
-
-
0000248716
-
Kant, Liberal Legacies, and Foreign Affairs: Part I
-
Notable defenders of the democratic peace thesis include
-
Notable defenders of the democratic peace thesis include Michael Doyle,“ Kant, Liberal Legacies, and Foreign Affairs: Part I,” Philosophy & Public Affairs 12, no. 3 (1983), pp. 205–235
-
(1983)
Philosophy & Public Affairs
, vol.12
, Issue.3
, pp. 205-235
-
-
Doyle, M.1
-
47
-
-
0000248716
-
Kant, Liberal Legacies, and Foreign Affairs: Part II
-
“Kant, Liberal Legacies, and Foreign Affairs: Part II,” Philosophy & Public Affairs 12, no. 4 (1983), pp. 323–353
-
(1983)
Philosophy & Public Affairs
, vol.12
, Issue.4
, pp. 323-353
-
-
-
48
-
-
2042420611
-
How Liberalism Produces Democratic Peace
-
John M. Owen, “How Liberalism Produces Democratic Peace,” International Security 19, no. 2 (1994),pp. 97–125.
-
(1994)
International Security
, vol.19
, Issue.2
, pp. 97-125
-
-
Owen, J.M.1
-
49
-
-
22544475128
-
-
I say “largely” (rather than wholly) consistent with traditional notions of legitimate authority because Anna Leander argues that PMCs can directly and indirectly affect a state's decision to use military force. Not only do they influence the definition of national interests by lobbying, they also create a link between the public and private that is ripe for political corruption…and can result in hawkish behavior by governmental officials Rome: Centro Militare di Studi Strategici
-
I say “largely” (rather than wholly) consistent with traditional notions of legitimate authority because Anna Leander argues that PMCs can directly and indirectly affect a state's decision to use military force. Not only do they influence the definition of national interests by lobbying, they also create a link between the public and private that is ripe for political corruption…and can result in hawkish behavior by governmental officials. Anna Leander, Eroding State Authority? Private Military Companies and the Legitimate Use of Force (Rome: Centro Militare di Studi Strategici, 2006), p. 108.
-
(2006)
Eroding State Authority? Private Military Companies and the Legitimate Use of Force
, pp. 108
-
-
Leander, A.1
-
52
-
-
85022736576
-
-
Orend, Morality, pp. 127–137.
-
Morality
, pp. 127-137
-
-
Orend1
-
53
-
-
85022736576
-
-
Note that JWT is increasingly being viewed as a “scalar” approach, according to which the overall justice of a war is a matter of degree, rather than a “checklist,” according to which all criteria of jus ad bellum, jus in bello, and jus post bellum must be met for a war to be just. As such, although these three solutions may provide extra restrictions on warfare, they do not mean that the bar for a just war will be set unattainably high (i.e., by adding extra “boxes to tick”). For further discussion of the scalar and checklist approaches, see
-
Note that JWT is increasingly being viewed as a “scalar” approach, according to which the overall justice of a war is a matter of degree, rather than a “checklist,” according to which all criteria of jus ad bellum, jus in bello, and jus post bellum must be met for a war to be just. As such, although these three solutions may provide extra restrictions on warfare, they do not mean that the bar for a just war will be set unattainably high (i.e., by adding extra “boxes to tick”). For further discussion of the scalar and checklist approaches, see Orend, Morality, pp. 105–106
-
Morality
, pp. 105-106
-
-
Orend1
-
54
-
-
85044815873
-
Legitimacy and Humanitarian Intervention: Who Should Intervene?
-
my
-
my “Legitimacy and Humanitarian Intervention: Who Should Intervene?” International Journal of Human Rights 12, no. 3 (2008), pp. 395–413
-
(2008)
International Journal of Human Rights
, vol.12
, Issue.3
, pp. 395-413
-
-
-
57
-
-
85022613638
-
Democratic Majority Staff of the House Committee on Oversight and Government Reform
-
For details of DynCorp's alleged combat roles in Colombia USA, October 1 Although Blackwater are officially employed to guard officials and perform other defensive functions in Iraq, they have, according to some accounts, conducted a number of offensive operations. For instance, the Democratic Majority Staff of the House Committee on Oversight and Government Reform suggest that the vast majority of Blackwater weapons discharges have been preemptive: “Blackwater personnel have participated in 195 incidents in Iraq from January 1, 2005, through September 12, 2007, that involved firearms discharges by Blackwater personnel … on 163 occasions (84% of the shooting incidents), Blackwater personnel were the first to fire.”
-
Although Blackwater are officially employed to guard officials and perform other defensive functions in Iraq, they have, according to some accounts, conducted a number of offensive operations. For instance, the Democratic Majority Staff of the House Committee on Oversight and Government Reform suggest that the vast majority of Blackwater weapons discharges have been preemptive: “Blackwater personnel have participated in 195 incidents in Iraq from January 1, 2005, through September 12, 2007, that involved firearms discharges by Blackwater personnel … on 163 occasions (84% of the shooting incidents), Blackwater personnel were the first to fire.” Democratic Majority Staff of the House Committee on Oversight and Government Reform, Memorandum: Additional Information about Blackwater USA, October 1, 2007, p. 6. For details of DynCorp's alleged combat roles in Colombia.
-
(2007)
Memorandum: Additional Information about Blackwater
, pp. 6
-
-
-
61
-
-
8644284846
-
The Ethics of Killing in War
-
Jeff McMahan, “The Ethics of Killing in War,” Ethics 114 (2004), pp. 693–733.
-
(2004)
Ethics
, vol.114
, pp. 693-733
-
-
McMahan, J.1
-
62
-
-
85019404963
-
Liability and Just Cause
-
Thomas Hurka, “Liability and Just Cause,” Ethics & International Affairs 21, no. 2 (2007), p. 210.
-
(2007)
Ethics & International Affairs
, vol.21
, Issue.2
, pp. 210
-
-
Hurka, T.1
-
63
-
-
33750689931
-
On the Moral Equality of Combatants
-
Jeff McMahan, “On the Moral Equality of Combatants,” Journal of Political Philosophy 14, no. 4 (2006), p. 381.
-
(2006)
Journal of Political Philosophy
, vol.14
, Issue.4
, pp. 381
-
-
McMahan, J.1
-
66
-
-
85022663821
-
The Sources and Status of Just War Principles
-
Jeff McMahan, “The Sources and Status of Just War Principles,” Journal of Military Ethics 6, no. 2 (2007), p. 104.
-
(2007)
Journal of Military Ethics
, vol.6
, Issue.2
, pp. 104
-
-
McMahan, J.1
-
67
-
-
85022736576
-
-
Orend, Morality, pp. 108–109.
-
Morality
, pp. 108-109
-
-
Orend1
|