메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 94, Issue 4, 2009, Pages 991-1007

Should property scholars embrace virtue ethics? a skeptical comment

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 68949109753     PISSN: 00108847     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: None     Document Type: Note
Times cited : (6)

References (108)
  • 2
    • 68949139795 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Edmund L. Andrews & Mark Landler, U.S. May Take Ownership Stake in Banks to Ease Credit Crisis, N.Y. TIMES, Oct. 9, 2008, at Al;
    • See, e.g., Edmund L. Andrews & Mark Landler, U.S. May Take Ownership Stake in Banks to Ease Credit Crisis, N.Y. TIMES, Oct. 9, 2008, at Al;
  • 4
    • 84869713070 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Edmund L. Andrews et al., Fed in an $85 Billion Rescue of an Insurer Near Failure, N.Y. TIMES, Sept. 17, 2008, at Al;
    • See, e.g., Edmund L. Andrews et al., Fed in an $85 Billion Rescue of an Insurer Near Failure, N.Y. TIMES, Sept. 17, 2008, at Al;
  • 5
    • 68949144417 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Eric Dash & Andrew Ross Sorkin, In Largest Bank Failure, U.S. Seizes, Then Sells, N.Y. TIMES, Sept. 26, 2008, at Al;
    • Eric Dash & Andrew Ross Sorkin, In Largest Bank Failure, U.S. Seizes, Then Sells, N.Y. TIMES, Sept. 26, 2008, at Al;
  • 7
    • 68949084747 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Goodbye to All That
    • See, e.g, Oct. 5, at
    • See, e.g., Tim Arango & Julie Creswell, Goodbye to All That, N.Y. TIMES, Oct. 5, 2008, at BU1;
    • (2008) N.Y. TIMES
    • Arango, T.1    Creswell, J.2
  • 8
    • 68949095363 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Alex Berenson, Power Plays: How Free Should a Free Market Be?, N.Y. TIMES, Oct. 5, 2008, at WK1 (Whoever becomes president in January, lawmakers will be under pressure to strengthen financial regulation and give more resources to agencies like the Food and Drug Administration, which have appeared overwhelmed in recent years.);
    • Alex Berenson, Power Plays: How Free Should a Free Market Be?, N.Y. TIMES, Oct. 5, 2008, at WK1 ("Whoever becomes president in January, lawmakers will be under pressure to strengthen financial regulation and give more resources to agencies like the Food and Drug Administration, which have appeared overwhelmed in recent years.");
  • 9
    • 68949087916 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bob Davis et al., Unraveling Reagan: Amid Turmoil, U.S. Turns Away from Decades of Deregulation, WALL ST. J., July 25, 2008, at Al;
    • Bob Davis et al., Unraveling Reagan: Amid Turmoil, U.S. Turns Away from Decades of Deregulation, WALL ST. J., July 25, 2008, at Al;
  • 10
    • 67949104613 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Taking Hard New Look at a Greenspan Legacy
    • Oct. 9, at
    • Peter S. Goodman, Taking Hard New Look at a Greenspan Legacy, N.Y. TIMES, Oct. 9, 2008, at A1.
    • (2008) N.Y. TIMES
    • Goodman, P.S.1
  • 11
    • 68949134227 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The reference is to THOMAS S. KUHN, THE STRUCTURE OF SCIENTIFIC REVOLUTIONS (3d ed. 1996).
    • The reference is to THOMAS S. KUHN, THE STRUCTURE OF SCIENTIFIC REVOLUTIONS (3d ed. 1996).
  • 12
    • 84869713068 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I use property to refer principally to land and therefore use the terms property law and land law synonymously. As the title Land Virtues implies, Pen̄alver's article is concerned mainly with the paradigm for land law, and when he uses die term property he seems to have land in mind. However, it seems to me that Peñalver's concerns with economic analysis apply beyond its application to land (or property) law and encompass its use in public policy generally. In theory, virtue ethics could be used to guide policy in many fields in addition to land (or property) law.
    • I use "property" to refer principally to land and therefore use the terms "property law" and "land law" synonymously. As the title Land Virtues implies, Pen̄alver's article is concerned mainly with the paradigm for land law, and when he uses die term "property" he seems to have land in mind. However, it seems to me that Peñalver's concerns with economic analysis apply beyond its application to land (or property) law and encompass its use in public policy generally. In theory, virtue ethics could be used to guide policy in many fields in addition to land (or property) law.
  • 13
    • 68949109633 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In Kuhn's terms, paradigms provide models from which spring particular coherent traditions of scientific research. KUHN, supra note 5, at 10.
    • In Kuhn's terms, paradigms "provide models from which spring particular coherent traditions of scientific research." KUHN, supra note 5, at 10.
  • 14
    • 84869729861 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Peñalver, supra note 1, at 841
    • Peñalver, supra note 1, at 841.
  • 15
    • 68949111549 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 860
    • Id. at 860.
  • 16
    • 68949095364 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 863
    • Id. at 863.
  • 17
    • 68949144418 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 18
    • 68949126716 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 868
    • Id. at 868.
  • 19
    • 68949135006 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 872-73 (It bears emphasizing that rejecting welfare-maximizing theories of landowner obligation in favor of a virtue-based approach does not lead to an embrace of unrelentingly collective or statist decision making about land use. Even where we reach the conclusion that landowners' self-interested calculations should give way to overriding moral considerations, the question whether to enforce coercively the demands of virtue through the force of law will turn, as virtue theorists have long understood, on a number of considerations. (footnote omitted)).
    • See id. at 872-73 ("It bears emphasizing that rejecting welfare-maximizing theories of landowner obligation in favor of a virtue-based approach does not lead to an embrace of unrelentingly collective or statist decision making about land use. Even where we reach the conclusion that landowners' self-interested calculations should give way to overriding moral considerations, the question whether to enforce coercively the demands of virtue through the force of law will turn, as virtue theorists have long understood, on a number of considerations." (footnote omitted)).
  • 20
    • 84869713069 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Pen̄alver suggests that virtue ethics is compatible with a range of models of human behavior. Id. at 867-68.
    • Pen̄alver suggests that virtue ethics is compatible "with a range of models of human behavior." Id. at 867-68.
  • 21
    • 68949111547 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 823-25, 833.
    • See id. at 823-25, 833.
  • 22
    • 68949091655 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • at, 840
    • See id. at 832, 834-35, 837-38, 840.
    • See id
  • 23
    • 68949136387 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 824 ([A] number of contemporary legal economists, most prominently Louis Kaplow and Steven Shavell, have constructed their legal theories around the maximization of 'welfare,' a category of value that they understand to be significantly broader than 'wealth' and, indeed, to encompass anything and everything that people might desire.).
    • See id. at 824 ("[A] number of contemporary legal economists, most prominently Louis Kaplow and Steven Shavell, have constructed their legal theories around the maximization of 'welfare,' a category of value that they understand to be significantly broader than 'wealth' and, indeed, to encompass anything and everything that people might desire.").
  • 24
    • 84869702902 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sometimes when Pen̄alver recognizes that economic analysts define the value being maximized in broader terms, he introduces a new critique, namely that economic analysis is less useful when it assumes that owners seek to maximize something abstract like welfare. See id. at 835 n.54 (referring to [t]he difficulties of measuring such an open-ended conception of value or welfare or utility, This is a version of the well-known indeterminacy critique of economic analysis
    • Sometimes when Pen̄alver recognizes that economic analysts define the value being maximized in broader terms, he introduces a new critique, namely that economic analysis is less useful when it assumes that owners seek to maximize something abstract like welfare. See id. at 835 n.54 (referring to "[t]he difficulties of measuring such an open-ended conception of value (or welfare or utility)"). This is a version of the well-known indeterminacy critique of economic analysis.
  • 25
    • 0042409519 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Russell B. Korobkin & Thomas S. Ulen, Law and Behavioral Science: Removing the Rationality Assumption from Law and Economics, 88 CAL. L. REV. 1051, 1067-68 (2000) (discussing the inadequacy of thin versions of rational-choice theory). This critique makes the valid point that since values such as utility or welfare are often unknowable by outsiders, economic claims that individuals seek to maximize values such as utility or welfare are difficult to test and hence to falsify.
    • See Russell B. Korobkin & Thomas S. Ulen, Law and Behavioral Science: Removing the Rationality Assumption from Law and Economics, 88 CAL. L. REV. 1051, 1067-68 (2000) (discussing the inadequacy of thin versions of rational-choice theory). This critique makes the valid point that since values such as utility or welfare are often unknowable by outsiders, economic claims that individuals seek to maximize values such as utility or welfare are difficult to test and hence to falsify.
  • 26
    • 68949153236 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id.; see also Robert C. Ellickson, Bringing Culture and Human Frailty to Rational Actors: A Critique of Classical Law and Economics, 65 CHI.-KENT L. REV. 23, 23 (1989) (discussing Ardiur Leff's argument in his 1974 review of Richard Posner's Economic Analysis of Law that because a person's received utility is unobservable, the assumption of rational utility-maximization is strictly nonfalsifiable).
    • See id.; see also Robert C. Ellickson, Bringing Culture and Human Frailty to Rational Actors: A Critique of Classical Law and Economics, 65 CHI.-KENT L. REV. 23, 23 (1989) (discussing Ardiur Leff's argument in his 1974 review of Richard Posner's Economic Analysis of Law that "because a person's received utility is unobservable, the assumption of rational utility-maximization is strictly nonfalsifiable").
  • 27
    • 68949122201 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Korobkin and Ulen make the same suggestion with regard to the economic analysis of law generally. See Korobkin & Ulen, supra note 17, at 1075 (The answer, we believe, is to . . . develop [ ] a more subtle, textured understanding of how actors make decisions in various situations, relying extensively on empirical data.).
    • Korobkin and Ulen make the same suggestion with regard to the economic analysis of law generally. See Korobkin & Ulen, supra note 17, at 1075 ("The answer, we believe, is to . . . develop [ ] a more subtle, textured understanding of how actors make decisions in various situations, relying extensively on empirical data.").
  • 28
    • 68949115722 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Journal of Empirical Legal Studies, http://www.wiley.com/bw/aims.asp?ref= 17401453&site=l (last visited Mar. 10, 2009).
    • Journal of Empirical Legal Studies, http://www.wiley.com/bw/aims.asp?ref= 17401453&site=l (last visited Mar. 10, 2009).
  • 29
    • 68949093507 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Journal of Empirical Legal Studies, http://www.blackwellpublishing.com/ society. asp?ref=1740-1453&site=l (last visited Mar. 10, 2009).
    • Journal of Empirical Legal Studies, http://www.blackwellpublishing.com/ society. asp?ref=1740-1453&site=l (last visited Mar. 10, 2009).
  • 30
    • 84869716349 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Indeed, Pen̄alver is careful to underscore that his critique that economic analysis presumes an overly simplified model of human motivation would not apply to analyses that draw on behavioral economics or new institutional economics. Pen̄alver, supra note 1, at 824-25
    • Indeed, Pen̄alver is careful to underscore that his critique that economic analysis presumes an overly simplified model of human motivation would not apply to analyses that draw on behavioral economics or new institutional economics. Pen̄alver, supra note 1, at 824-25.
  • 31
    • 68949128476 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 826, Part II.B.2.
    • See id. at 826, Part II.B.2.
  • 33
    • 84869716350 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Pen̄alver offers two reasons for doubting that private decision makers will necessarily make decisions that will maximize land values. In analyzing their options, private decision makers may not value goods that are not commonly traded in the market, such as the health of wetlands and ecosystems, the extinction of species, or housing for the homeless. Id. at 850
    • Pen̄alver offers two reasons for doubting that private decision makers will necessarily make decisions that will maximize land values. In analyzing their options, private decision makers may not value goods that are not commonly traded in the market, "such as the health of wetlands and ecosystems, the extinction of species, or housing for the homeless." Id. at 850.
  • 34
    • 68949122202 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In addition, private landowners may not consider the impacts of their decisions on future generations or heavily discount die future if they do consider it. See id. at 854
    • In addition, private landowners may not consider the impacts of their decisions on future generations or heavily discount die future if they do consider it. See id. at 854.
  • 35
    • 68949119260 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 857-58.
    • See id. at 857-58.
  • 36
    • 68949089766 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • RICHARD L. REVESZ & MICHAEL A. LIVERMORE, RETAKING RATIONALITY: HOW COSTBENEFIT ANALYSIS CAN BETTER PROTECT THE ENVIRONMENT AND OUR HEALTH 18 (2008).
    • RICHARD L. REVESZ & MICHAEL A. LIVERMORE, RETAKING RATIONALITY: HOW COSTBENEFIT ANALYSIS CAN BETTER PROTECT THE ENVIRONMENT AND OUR HEALTH 18 (2008).
  • 37
    • 68949128478 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 10 (This book challenges the liberal camp to rethink its position on costbenefit analysis .... [B]iases [against regulation] are not inherent to the methodology [of cost-benefit analysis]. If those biases were identified and eliminated, cost-benefit analysis would become a powerful tool for neutral policy analysis.).
    • See id. at 10 ("This book challenges the liberal camp to rethink its position on costbenefit analysis .... [B]iases [against regulation] are not inherent to the methodology [of cost-benefit analysis]. If those biases were identified and eliminated, cost-benefit analysis would become a powerful tool for neutral policy analysis.").
  • 38
    • 84869702899 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Pen̄alver, supra note 1, at 823 & n.5 (noting that [t] he literature critiquing law and economics is vast and rich and citing a few prominent examples).
    • See Pen̄alver, supra note 1, at 823 & n.5 (noting that " [t] he literature critiquing law and economics is vast and rich" and citing "a few prominent examples").
  • 39
    • 34249085148 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • at, 872
    • See, e.g., id. at 827-28, 872, 873-74.
    • See, e.g., id
  • 40
    • 84869729860 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For example, Richard Posner's early classic, Economic Analysis of Law, intermixed normative and positive analysis. RICHARD A. POSNER, ECONOMIC ANALYSIS OF LAW §1.2 (1972). More recently, Louis Kaplow and Steven Shavell attracted considerable attention among legal academics with their normative claim that the law should be designed to maximize individual well-being.
    • For example, Richard Posner's early classic, Economic Analysis of Law, intermixed normative and positive analysis. RICHARD A. POSNER, ECONOMIC ANALYSIS OF LAW §1.2 (1972). More recently, Louis Kaplow and Steven Shavell attracted considerable attention among legal academics with their normative claim that the law should be designed to maximize individual well-being.
  • 41
    • 0042421849 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Louis Kaplow & Steven Shavell, Fairness Versus Welfare, 114 HARV. L. REV. 961, 967 (2001) (Our central claim is that the welfare-based normative approach should be exclusively employed in evaluating legal rules. That is, legal rules should be selected entirely with respect to their effects on the well-being of individuals in society.).
    • See, e.g., Louis Kaplow & Steven Shavell, Fairness Versus Welfare, 114 HARV. L. REV. 961, 967 (2001) ("Our central claim is that the welfare-based normative approach should be exclusively employed in evaluating legal rules. That is, legal rules should be selected entirely with respect to their effects on the well-being of individuals in society.").
  • 42
    • 84869702900 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Pen̄alver, supa note 1, at 827-28, 872, 873-74.
    • See, e.g., Pen̄alver, supa note 1, at 827-28, 872, 873-74.
  • 43
    • 84869729856 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In three sentences that I already have quoted in part, Pen̄alver states: The challenge for property and land-use theorists is to find a way to put the valuable tools of economic analysis to use [within land-use discussions] while restricting the normative ambition of those tools to their proper domain. Meeting this challenge calls for resort to a broader moral framework, one that is sufficiently capacious to encompass the value of personhood, the demands of liberty, and the important goal of enhanced social welfare. A theory of owner obligation rooted in the Aristotelian tradition provides such an inclusive vision.
    • In three sentences that I already have quoted in part, Pen̄alver states: The challenge for property and land-use theorists is to find a way to put the valuable tools of economic analysis to use [within land-use discussions] while restricting the normative ambition of those tools to their proper domain. Meeting this challenge calls for resort to a broader moral framework, one that is sufficiently capacious to encompass the value of personhood, the demands of liberty, and the important goal of enhanced social welfare. A theory of owner obligation rooted in the Aristotelian tradition provides such an inclusive vision.
  • 44
    • 68949093508 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 863
    • Id. at 863.
  • 45
    • 68949103366 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 882
    • Id. at 882.
  • 46
    • 68949111540 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 876-77
    • Id. at 876-77.
  • 47
    • 68949095359 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 877
    • Id. at 877.
  • 48
    • 68949144412 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Id
    • See Id.
  • 49
    • 68949139575 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 880
    • Id. at 880.
  • 50
    • 68949111541 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 51
    • 68949132319 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 884
    • Id. at 884.
  • 52
    • 68949115723 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 885.
    • See id. at 885.
  • 53
    • 68949119255 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • David Lametti, The Objects of Virtue (2008) (unpublished manuscript, on file with author).
    • David Lametti, The Objects of Virtue (2008) (unpublished manuscript, on file with author).
  • 54
    • 68949107173 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 11
    • Id. at 11.
  • 55
    • 68949087908 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 14 (The virtue in the city is founded on the virtue of individuals and virtue of individuals is based on the virtue of the city. Each forms the other through laws and education, and the actions of virtuous individuals leading to a virtuous state of character aimed at the good.).
    • See id. at 14 ("The virtue in the city is founded on the virtue of individuals and virtue of individuals is based on the virtue of the city. Each forms the other through laws and education, and the actions of virtuous individuals leading to a virtuous state of character aimed at the good.").
  • 56
    • 68949122322 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the meaning of eudaimonia, see Eric R. Claeys, Virtue and Rights in American Property Law, 94 CORNELL L. REV. 889, 902 (2009).
    • On the meaning of eudaimonia, see Eric R. Claeys, Virtue and Rights in American Property Law, 94 CORNELL L. REV. 889, 902 (2009).
  • 57
    • 68949132321 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Lametti, supra note 41, at 38
    • See Lametti, supra note 41, at 38.
  • 58
    • 68949132318 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 59
    • 68949122207 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • private property is an instrumental good (analogous to utility) but in the service of human development (dignity, development) within a Christian framework
    • arguing that for Aquinas
    • Id. See also id. (arguing that for Aquinas, "private property is an instrumental good (analogous to utility) but in the service of human development (dignity, development) within a Christian framework").
    • Id. See also id
  • 60
    • 84869729857 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Pen̄alver describes his purpose as to reintroduce the Aristotelian ethical tradition into discussions of property and land-use as an approach with much to offer. Pen̄alver, supra note 1, at 864.
    • Pen̄alver describes his purpose as "to reintroduce the Aristotelian ethical tradition into discussions of property and land-use as an approach with much to offer." Pen̄alver, supra note 1, at 864.
  • 61
    • 68949119256 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 867
    • Id. at 867.
  • 62
    • 68949122203 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kaplow & Shavell, supra note 30, at 967
    • Kaplow & Shavell, supra note 30, at 967.
  • 63
    • 68949103368 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 980 n.35.
    • Id. at 980 n.35.
  • 64
    • 68949117391 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 983-85, 1339-42 (arguing that the moral force and appeal of welfare economics comes from the fact that it promotes a person's actual well-being instead of some hypothetical notion of satisfaction) ;
    • See id. at 983-85, 1339-42 (arguing that the "moral force and appeal of welfare economics" comes from the fact that it promotes a person's actual well-being instead of "some hypothetical notion of satisfaction") ;
  • 65
    • 68949132317 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • id. at 1346 (Under a welfare economic analysis, any actual preference is given weight because it reflects an individual's actual wellbeing; there is no a priori basis under welfare economics for ignoring certain preferences.). However, Kaplow and Shavell do not support giving weight to individual preferences based on imperfect information.
    • id. at 1346 ("Under a welfare economic analysis, any actual preference is given weight because it reflects an individual's actual wellbeing; there is no a priori basis under welfare economics for ignoring certain preferences."). However, Kaplow and Shavell do not support giving weight to individual preferences based on imperfect information.
  • 66
    • 68949084742 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 1331.
    • See id. at 1331.
  • 67
    • 84869729855 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Pen̄alver, supra note 1, at 866 ([Vjirtue ethicists typically derive the content of their accounts of the virtues from an objective conception of what it means to live well or flourish in a distinctively human way.);
    • Pen̄alver, supra note 1, at 866 ("[Vjirtue ethicists typically derive the content of their accounts of the virtues from an objective conception of what it means to live well or flourish in a distinctively human way.");
  • 68
    • 68949107177 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • id. (Depending on the theorist, the conceptions of the well-lived human life underlying virtue ethics will have varying degrees of thickness and content. Virtue theories agree, however, in this focus on flourishing and in refusing to assign value to some state of affairs merely because an individual happens subjectively to desire or prefer it. (footnote omitted));
    • id. ("Depending on the theorist, the conceptions of the well-lived human life underlying virtue ethics will have varying degrees of thickness and content. Virtue theories agree, however, in this focus on flourishing and in refusing to assign value to some state of affairs merely because an individual happens subjectively to desire or prefer it." (footnote omitted));
  • 69
    • 68949122206 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also Martha C. Nussbaum, TAe Supeme Court, 2006 Term-Forward: Constitutions and Capabilities: Perceptions Against Lofty Formalism, 121 HARV. L. REV. 5, 14 (2007) (The [capabilities approach] focuses on what people are actually able to do and be, not on whether their desires are satisfied. Desire is a malleable and inconstant element of people's lives.).
    • see also Martha C. Nussbaum, TAe Supeme Court, 2006 Term-Forward: Constitutions and Capabilities: "Perceptions" Against Lofty Formalism, 121 HARV. L. REV. 5, 14 (2007) ("The [capabilities approach] focuses on what people are actually able to do and be, not on whether their desires are satisfied. Desire is a malleable and inconstant element of people's lives.").
  • 70
    • 0242511209 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Daphna Lewinsohn-Zamir is the leading exponent of a welfarist approach to property law that relies on an objective, rather than a subjective, definition of well-being. See Daphna Lewinsohn-Zamir, TAe Objectivity of Weil-Being and the Objectives of Property Law, 78 N.Y.U. L. REV. 1669, 1673 2003, A]ny adequate criterion of welfare must consist of strong objective components
    • Daphna Lewinsohn-Zamir is the leading exponent of a welfarist approach to property law that relies on an objective, rather than a subjective, definition of well-being. See Daphna Lewinsohn-Zamir, TAe Objectivity of Weil-Being and the Objectives of Property Law, 78 N.Y.U. L. REV. 1669, 1673 (2003) ("[A]ny adequate criterion of welfare must consist of strong objective components.").
  • 71
    • 68949091658 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Nussbaum, supra note 52, at 10 n.7 (listing sources explaining Nussbaum's and Sen's capabilities approaches and the differences between their approaches). Nussbaum provides a useful overview of her capabilities approach.
    • See, e.g., Nussbaum, supra note 52, at 10 n.7 (listing sources explaining Nussbaum's and Sen's capabilities approaches and the differences between their approaches). Nussbaum provides a useful overview of her capabilities approach.
  • 72
    • 68949128477 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 10-16. Gregory Alexander's article TAe Social-Obligation Norm in American Property Law argues that property law does and should embody a commitment to promoting human flourishing as capability theorists such as Sen and Nussbaum define the concept. 94 CORNELL L. REV. 745, 751 (2009).
    • See id. at 10-16. Gregory Alexander's article TAe Social-Obligation Norm in American Property Law argues that property law does and should embody a commitment to promoting human flourishing as capability theorists such as Sen and Nussbaum define the concept. 94 CORNELL L. REV. 745, 751 (2009).
  • 73
    • 68949120701 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Another article applying Sen's capability theory to property law, with a different goal than Alexander's, is Jedediah Purdy's A Freedom-Promoting Appoach to Property: A Renewed Tradition for New Debates, 72 U. CHI. L. REV. 1237, 1242-44 (2005).
    • Another article applying Sen's capability theory to property law, with a different goal than Alexander's, is Jedediah Purdy's A Freedom-Promoting Appoach to Property: A Renewed Tradition for New Debates, 72 U. CHI. L. REV. 1237, 1242-44 (2005).
  • 74
    • 68949124737 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • government is charged with securing for citizens a comprehensive set of necessary conditions for a life worthy of human dignity
    • note 52, at, arguing that under the capabilities approach
    • Nussbaum, supra note 52, at 11 (arguing that under the capabilities approach, "government is charged with securing for citizens a comprehensive set of necessary conditions for a life worthy of human dignity");
    • supra , pp. 11
    • Nussbaum1
  • 75
    • 68949153233 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • id. at 12 (Government ought to give people a full and meaningful choice; at that point, the decision whether to take up a given opportunity must be their own.).
    • id. at 12 ("Government ought to give people a full and meaningful choice; at that point, the decision whether to take up a given opportunity must be their own.").
  • 77
    • 84869702897 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Pen̄alver, supra note 1, at 864
    • Pen̄alver, supra note 1, at 864.
  • 78
    • 68949136384 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • KWAME ANTHONY APPIAH, EXPERIMENTS IN ETHICS 38-39 (2008). Rob Howse drew my attention to the chapter in the book on virtue ethics.
    • KWAME ANTHONY APPIAH, EXPERIMENTS IN ETHICS 38-39 (2008). Rob Howse drew my attention to the chapter in the book on virtue ethics.
  • 80
    • 84869716343 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Pen̄alver, supra note 1, at 864
    • Pen̄alver, supra note 1, at 864.
  • 81
    • 68949103372 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • APPIAH, supra note 58, at 39
    • APPIAH, supra note 58, at 39.
  • 83
    • 68949103373 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 41
    • Id. at 41.
  • 84
    • 0015308592 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. (referring to Alice M. Isen & Paula F. Levin, The Effect of Feeling Good on Helping: Cookies and Kindness, 21 J. PERSONALITY & SOC. PSYCHOL. 384 (1972)).
    • Id. (referring to Alice M. Isen & Paula F. Levin, The Effect of Feeling Good on Helping: Cookies and Kindness, 21 J. PERSONALITY & SOC. PSYCHOL. 384 (1972)).
  • 85
    • 84973703269 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. (citing Robert A. Baron Sc Jill Thormley, A Whiff of Reality: Positive Affect as a Potential Mediator of the Effects of Pleasant Fragrances on Task Performance and Helping, 26 ENV'T & BEHAV. 766 (1994)).
    • Id. (citing Robert A. Baron Sc Jill Thormley, A Whiff of Reality: Positive Affect as a Potential Mediator of the Effects of Pleasant Fragrances on Task Performance and Helping, 26 ENV'T & BEHAV. 766 (1994)).
  • 86
    • 68949119259 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 46 (There are some philosophers . . . who take the social-science literature about character and conduct to pose a serious and perhaps lethal challenge to the virtue ethicist's worldview. Talk all you like about virtuous dispositions, the challenge goes: we're just not built that way.).
    • Id. at 46 ("There are some philosophers . . . who take the social-science literature about character and conduct to pose a serious and perhaps lethal challenge to the virtue ethicist's worldview. Talk all you like about virtuous dispositions, the challenge goes: we're just not built that way.").
  • 88
    • 20444455952 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Lack of Character? Situationism Critiqued, 115
    • John Sabini & Maury Silver, Lack of Character? Situationism Critiqued, 115 ETHICS 535 (2005);
    • (2005) ETHICS , vol.535
    • Sabini, J.1    Silver, M.2
  • 89
    • 3543089307 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Errors About Errors: Virtue Theory and Trait Attribution, 111
    • Gopal Sreenivasan, Errors About Errors: Virtue Theory and Trait Attribution, 111 MIND 441 (2002).
    • (2002) MIND , vol.441
    • Sreenivasan, G.1
  • 90
    • 68949124736 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Thanks to Lisa Austin for highlighting for me the possibility that law may not be compatible with promoting virtue as virtue ethicists understand the concept
    • Thanks to Lisa Austin for highlighting for me the possibility that law may not be compatible with promoting virtue as virtue ethicists understand the concept.
  • 91
    • 84869716341 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Pen̄alver, supra note 1, at 864-65 (providing the example of a person who saves a drowning child solely for the purpose of the acclaim and publicity that the act brings).
    • Pen̄alver, supra note 1, at 864-65 (providing the example of a person who saves a drowning child solely for the purpose of the acclaim and publicity that the act brings).
  • 92
    • 68949153234 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 865
    • Id. at 865.
  • 93
    • 68949134225 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. (citing ROSALIND HURSTHOUSE, ON VIRTUE ETHICS (1999)).
    • Id. (citing ROSALIND HURSTHOUSE, ON VIRTUE ETHICS (1999)).
  • 94
    • 68949135008 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 871
    • Id. at 871.
  • 95
    • 68949144415 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See also id. 871 n.207 (citing sources discussing the role of law in promoting virtue).
    • See also id. 871 n.207 (citing sources discussing the role of law in promoting virtue).
  • 96
    • 68949134226 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 871
    • Id. at 871.
  • 97
    • 68949105256 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In his response in this issue, Eric Claeys rejects the concern that when politics legislates on virtue, it makes it impossible for actors to act virtuously. Claeys, supra note 43, at 921. Later, though, Claeys seems to acknowledge that some virtues probably cannot be achieved through law, referring specifically to charity. Quoting Robert George, Claeys states that legally coerced charity is in an important sense not really charity at all: 'compelling the expressing of gratitude, or the giving of gifts . . . where people ought to express gratitude [or] give gifts . . . would have the effect of robbing these important practices of their meaning and value in social life.'
    • In his response in this issue, Eric Claeys rejects the concern that "when politics legislates on virtue, it makes it impossible for actors to act virtuously." Claeys, supra note 43, at 921. Later, though, Claeys seems to acknowledge that some virtues probably cannot be achieved through law, referring specifically to charity. Quoting Robert George, Claeys states that "legally coerced charity is in an important sense not really charity at all: 'compelling the expressing of gratitude, or the giving of gifts . . . where people ought to express gratitude [or] give gifts . . . would have the effect of robbing these important practices of their meaning and value in social life.'"
  • 98
    • 68949089769 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 944 (quoting ROBERT P. GEORGE, MAKING MEN MORAL: CIVIL LIBERTIES AND PUBLIC: MORALITY 44 (1993)).
    • Id. at 944 (quoting ROBERT P. GEORGE, MAKING MEN MORAL: CIVIL LIBERTIES AND PUBLIC: MORALITY 44 (1993)).
  • 99
    • 84869729851 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Pen̄alver, supra note 1, at 866
    • Pen̄alver, supra note 1, at 866.
  • 100
    • 84869716339 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Pen̄alver acknowledges that [a] complete virtue theory of property would obviously include (or endorse) a fully elaborated and fully defended account of human flourishing, among other things, and that his article does not include such an account. Id. at 869.
    • Pen̄alver acknowledges that "[a] complete virtue theory of property would obviously include (or endorse) a fully elaborated and fully defended account of human flourishing," among other things, and that his article does not include such an account. Id. at 869.
  • 101
    • 68949124740 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Lewinsohn-Zamir, supra note 53, at 1688
    • Lewinsohn-Zamir, supra note 53, at 1688.
  • 102
    • 68949138325 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • There are, of course, downsides to structuring law to promote individual preference satisfaction. For example, an individual's preferences may not be in her interests if her preferences arise from a lack of information or societal inequalities. For an overview of the problems often identified with preference theories of well-being, see id. at
    • There are, of course, downsides to structuring law to promote individual preference satisfaction. For example, an individual's preferences may not be in her interests if her preferences arise from a lack of information or societal inequalities. For an overview of the problems often identified with preference theories of well-being, see id. at 1677-86.
  • 103
    • 68949136385 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In his response in this issue, Professor Claeys eloquently discusses the dangers of a politics focused on virtue, warning that [w]hen politics is about legislating virtue and not about securing rights, it tempts sectarian believers to gain political power to compel subjects to be virtuous as defined by the teachings of their particular sect. Claeys, supra note 43, at 926
    • In his response in this issue, Professor Claeys eloquently discusses the dangers of a politics focused on virtue, warning that "[w]hen politics is about legislating virtue and not about securing rights, it tempts sectarian believers to gain political power to compel subjects to be virtuous as defined by the teachings of their particular sect." Claeys, supra note 43, at 926.
  • 104
    • 68949138326 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nussbaum, supra note 52, at 14 n.13.
    • Nussbaum, supra note 52, at 14 n.13.
  • 105
    • 68949135007 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.; see also id. at 20 (The [capabilities approach] ... is quite abstemious: it identifies a very short list of core entidements that should be secured to all citizens as the basic entidements of a just society. Beyond that short list, the [capabilities approach] does not make sweeping claims about the overall good. It allows people to make their own choices based on their different views of the good life.).
    • Id.; see also id. at 20 ("The [capabilities approach] ... is quite abstemious: it identifies a very short list of core entidements that should be secured to all citizens as the basic entidements of a just society. Beyond that short list, the [capabilities approach] does not make sweeping claims about the overall good. It allows people to make their own choices based on their different views of the good life.").
  • 106
    • 84869702895 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The only concrete implication Pen̄alver mentions is that using land law to promote justice might require more redistribution of land rights via in-kind transfers of ownership or occupancy. Pen̄alver, supra note 1, at 882
    • The only concrete implication Pen̄alver mentions is that using land law to promote "justice" might require more "redistribution of land rights via in-kind transfers of ownership or occupancy." Pen̄alver, supra note 1, at 882.
  • 107
    • 68949095362 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 878
    • Id. at 878.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.