메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 118, Issue 3, 2008, Pages 480-553

Learning Through Policy Variation

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 62549085130     PISSN: 00440094     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.2307/20454719     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (58)

References (231)
  • 1
    • 62549084110 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Learning about policies refers to the process through which the variability in outcomes associated with a policy is reduced. Before implementing a policy, policymakers may have only a dim idea about the effects of the policy. After implementing the policy and observing its effects, policymakers will often have a much better sense of the outcomes associated with the policy in current and future periods. Thus, policymakers will have learned about the policy and have a much greater ability to predict the policy's impacts. It may also be possible to learn about a policy without trying it. For example, one can learn about untried Policy A by extrapolating the effects of a similar but tested Policy B to Policy A. See infra Part III. This form of learning necessarily will be inferior to directly learning about Policy A by trying it
    • "Learning" about policies refers to the process through which the variability in outcomes associated with a policy is reduced. Before implementing a policy, policymakers may have only a dim idea about the effects of the policy. After implementing the policy and observing its effects, policymakers will often have a much better sense of the outcomes associated with the policy in current and future periods. Thus, policymakers will have "learned" about the policy and have a much greater ability to predict the policy's impacts. It may also be possible to "learn" about a policy without trying it. For example, one can learn about untried Policy A by extrapolating the effects of a similar but tested Policy B to Policy A. See infra Part III. This form of learning necessarily will be inferior to directly learning about Policy A by trying it.
  • 2
    • 0000531531 scopus 로고
    • Optimal Search for the Best Alternative, 47
    • developing the mathematical basis of the optimal search approach, See
    • See Martin L. Weitzman, Optimal Search for the Best Alternative, 47 ECONOMETRICA 641 (1979) (developing the mathematical basis of the optimal search approach) ;
    • (1979) ECONOMETRICA , vol.641
    • Weitzman, M.L.1
  • 3
    • 0041656119 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also Philippe Aghion et al., Optimal Learning by Experimentation, 58 REV. ECON. STUD. 621, 642-43 (1991) (same);
    • see also Philippe Aghion et al., Optimal Learning by Experimentation, 58 REV. ECON. STUD. 621, 642-43 (1991) (same);
  • 4
    • 0006250951 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Volker Wieland, Learning by Doing and the Value of Optimal Experimentation, 24 J. ECON. DYNAMICS & CONTROL 501, 513-19 (2000) (characterizing the process of experimentation for economic agents, such as firms with unknown demand curves). This Article examines public policymaking as an optimal search process - a novel perspective in both the economics and legal literatures.
    • Volker Wieland, Learning by Doing and the Value of Optimal Experimentation, 24 J. ECON. DYNAMICS & CONTROL 501, 513-19 (2000) (characterizing the process of experimentation for economic agents, such as firms with unknown demand curves). This Article examines public policymaking as an optimal search process - a novel perspective in both the economics and legal literatures.
  • 5
    • 84897688723 scopus 로고
    • Solomonic Bargaining: Dividing a Legal Entitlement To Facilitate Coasean Trade, 104
    • See, e.g
    • See, e.g., Ian Ayres & Eric Talley, Solomonic Bargaining: Dividing a Legal Entitlement To Facilitate Coasean Trade, 104 YALE L.J. 1027 (1995).
    • (1995) YALE L.J , vol.1027
    • Ayres, I.1    Talley, E.2
  • 6
    • 84937283249 scopus 로고
    • Do Liability Rules Facilitate Bargaining? A Reply to Ayres and Talley, 105
    • See, e.g
    • See, e.g., Louis Kaplow & Steven Shavell, Do Liability Rules Facilitate Bargaining? A Reply to Ayres and Talley, 105 YALE L.J. 221 (1995).
    • (1995) YALE L.J , vol.221
    • Kaplow, L.1    Shavell, S.2
  • 7
    • 62549107707 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Default rules may fail because the assumptions underlying their supposed desirability prove faulty, or they may fail because of an unforeseen hindrance
    • Default rules may fail because the assumptions underlying their supposed desirability prove faulty, or they may fail because of an unforeseen hindrance.
  • 8
    • 62549153805 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is generally known as the real options approach to decisionmaking under uncertainty. For a comprehensive economic account, see AVINASH K. DIXIT & ROBERT S. PINDYCK, INVESTMENT UNDER UNCERTAINTY 1994
    • This is generally known as the "real options" approach to decisionmaking under uncertainty. For a comprehensive economic account, see AVINASH K. DIXIT & ROBERT S. PINDYCK, INVESTMENT UNDER UNCERTAINTY (1994).
  • 9
    • 62549166463 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For legal applications, see IAN AYRES, OPTIONAL LAW: THE STRUCTURE OF LEGAL ENTITLEMENTS (2005) ;
    • For legal applications, see IAN AYRES, OPTIONAL LAW: THE STRUCTURE OF LEGAL ENTITLEMENTS (2005) ;
  • 10
    • 33745254225 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Irreversible and Catastrophic, 91
    • Irreversibility and the real options approach are discussed in detail in Part III
    • and Cass R. Sunstein, Irreversible and Catastrophic, 91 CORNELL L. REV. 841, 862-64 (2006). Irreversibility and the real options approach are discussed in detail in Part III.
    • (2006) CORNELL L. REV , vol.841 , pp. 862-864
    • Sunstein, C.R.1
  • 11
    • 62549166040 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This Part does not provide a full review of the political philosophies of classical liberals or Burkeans. Rather, it briefly sketches their attitudes toward policymaking to demonstrate how the optimal search approach relates to these two schools of thought. For an article applying Burkean and liberal political philosophies to methods of legal interpretation, see Ernest Young, Rediscovering Conservatism: Burkean Political Theory and Constitutional Interpretation, 72 N.C. L. REV. 619 1994
    • This Part does not provide a full review of the political philosophies of classical liberals or Burkeans. Rather, it briefly sketches their attitudes toward policymaking to demonstrate how the optimal search approach relates to these two schools of thought. For an article applying Burkean and liberal political philosophies to methods of legal interpretation, see Ernest Young, Rediscovering Conservatism: Burkean Political Theory and Constitutional Interpretation, 72 N.C. L. REV. 619 (1994).
  • 13
    • 62549138549 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • If the impacts of a policy are uncertain, then reason should be able to predict the probabilities of certain outcomes
    • If the impacts of a policy are uncertain, then reason should be able to predict the probabilities of certain outcomes.
  • 14
    • 0001698009 scopus 로고
    • Cardinal Utility in Welfare Economics and in the Theory of Risk-Taking, 61
    • suggesting a close affinity between the cardinal utility concept of welfare economics and the cardinal utility concept of the theory of choices involving risk [expected utility maximization, thereby implying that policy decisions from a welfarist perspective should maximize expected value or utility, See
    • See John C. Harsanyi, Cardinal Utility in Welfare Economics and in the Theory of Risk-Taking, 61 J. POL. ECON. 434, 434-35 (1953) (suggesting "a close affinity between the cardinal utility concept of welfare economics and the cardinal utility concept of the theory of choices involving risk [expected utility maximization]," thereby implying that policy decisions from a welfarist perspective should maximize expected value or utility).
    • (1953) J. POL. ECON , vol.434 , pp. 434-435
    • Harsanyi, J.C.1
  • 15
    • 62549161969 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See generally JEREMY BENTHAM, AN INTRODUCTION TO THE PRINCIPLES OF MORALS AND LEGISLATION 11-12 (J.H. Burns & H.L.A Hart eds., Oxford Univ. Press 1996) (1789) (describing the principle of utility as that principle which approves or disapproves of every action whatsoever, according to the tendency which it appears to have to augment or diminish the happiness of the party whose interest is in question).
    • See generally JEREMY BENTHAM, AN INTRODUCTION TO THE PRINCIPLES OF MORALS AND LEGISLATION 11-12 (J.H. Burns & H.L.A Hart eds., Oxford Univ. Press 1996) (1789) (describing the "principle of utility" as "that principle which approves or disapproves of every action whatsoever, according to the tendency which it appears to have to augment or diminish the happiness of the party whose interest is in question").
  • 17
    • 34249730115 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Some scholars argue that Burke was himself a classical liberal along many dimensions. Others claim that his reverence for tradition precluded his being a liberal. For a discussion of Burke's work, see CONOR CRUISE O'BRIEN, THE GREAT MELODY: A THEMATIC BIOGRAPHY AND COMMENTED ANTHOLOGY OF EDMUND BURKE 605-18 (1992). For an application of Burke's views to judicial decisionmaking, see Cass R. Sunstein, Burkean Minimalism, 105 MICH. L. REV. 353 (2006);
    • Some scholars argue that Burke was himself a classical liberal along many dimensions. Others claim that his reverence for tradition precluded his being a liberal. For a discussion of Burke's work, see CONOR CRUISE O'BRIEN, THE GREAT MELODY: A THEMATIC BIOGRAPHY AND COMMENTED ANTHOLOGY OF EDMUND BURKE 605-18 (1992). For an application of Burke's views to judicial decisionmaking, see Cass R. Sunstein, Burkean Minimalism, 105 MICH. L. REV. 353 (2006);
  • 18
    • 62549158027 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and Young, supra note 7. The discussion of Burke's thoughts in these articles influenced this Part.
    • and Young, supra note 7. The discussion of Burke's thoughts in these articles influenced this Part.
  • 19
    • 62549107995 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • EDMUND BURKE, REFLECTIONS ON THE REVOLUTION IN FRANCE 74 (Frank M. Turner ed., Yale Univ. Press 2003) (1790).
    • EDMUND BURKE, REFLECTIONS ON THE REVOLUTION IN FRANCE 74 (Frank M. Turner ed., Yale Univ. Press 2003) (1790).
  • 20
    • 62549122279 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Edmund Burke, Speech on the Reform of the Representation of the Commons in Parliament (May 7, 1782), in 4 SELECT WORKS OF EDMUND BURKE: MISCELLANEOUS WRITINGS 15, 21 (E.J. Payne ed., 1990).
    • Edmund Burke, Speech on the Reform of the Representation of the Commons in Parliament (May 7, 1782), in 4 SELECT WORKS OF EDMUND BURKE: MISCELLANEOUS WRITINGS 15, 21 (E.J. Payne ed., 1990).
  • 21
    • 62549156876 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • EDMUND BURKE, AN APPEAL FROM THE NEW TO THE OLD WHIGS 113 (London, J. Dodsley 1791). In this account, the value of past practice is very much empirical. Past practice has worked and is therefore owed deference. There are other values associated with Burke's fealty to tradition, of course. For a comprehensive discussion, see Anthony T. Kronman, Precedent and Tradition, 99 YALE L.J. 1029 (1990).
    • EDMUND BURKE, AN APPEAL FROM THE NEW TO THE OLD WHIGS 113 (London, J. Dodsley 1791). In this account, the value of past practice is very much empirical. Past practice has worked and is therefore owed deference. There are other values associated with Burke's fealty to tradition, of course. For a comprehensive discussion, see Anthony T. Kronman, Precedent and Tradition, 99 YALE L.J. 1029 (1990).
  • 22
    • 62549148002 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • BURKE, supra note 14, at 143-44
    • BURKE, supra note 14, at 143-44.
  • 23
    • 62549126697 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • If some part of a policy reform fails, then policymakers should either return to the old status quo, or, if a partial reform yields better outcomes than the old status quo-maintain the partially reformed policy as a new status quo
    • If some part of a policy reform fails, then policymakers should either return to the old status quo, or - if a partial reform yields better outcomes than the old status quo-maintain the partially reformed policy as a new status quo.
  • 24
    • 62549159616 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • These benefits and costs can be quantified by any social welfare metric. For example, the benefits in dollars may measure the dollar benefits to the least well-off member of society (a social welfare function advocated by John Rawls) rather than measuring total wealth. More generally, the benefits and costs could account for risk aversion in a rationalist framework, as expected utility theory does within economic science. This would make the Burkean and rationalist frameworks more similar to each other, although Burke would presumably doubt the ability of the rationalist to appropriately measure risk aversion. Throughout this Article, I generally adopt a utilitarian framework
    • These benefits and costs can be quantified by any social welfare metric. For example, the benefits in dollars may measure the dollar benefits to the least well-off member of society (a social welfare function advocated by John Rawls) rather than measuring total wealth. More generally, the benefits and costs could account for risk aversion in a rationalist framework, as expected utility theory does within economic science. This would make the Burkean and rationalist frameworks more similar to each other, although Burke would presumably doubt the ability of the rationalist to appropriately measure risk aversion. Throughout this Article, I generally adopt a utilitarian framework.
  • 25
    • 62549099325 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kaldor-Hicks efficiency proposes that a more socially efficient outcome can be reached by moving from the Pareto optimal level if those who would be made better off by the outcome compensate those who would be made worse off by the outcome. For a useful discussion of Kaldor-Hicks efficiency, see Guido Calabresi, The Pointlessness of Pareto: Carrying Coase Further, 100 YALE L.J. 1211 1991
    • Kaldor-Hicks efficiency proposes that a more socially efficient outcome can be reached by moving from the Pareto optimal level if those who would be made better off by the outcome compensate those who would be made worse off by the outcome. For a useful discussion of Kaldor-Hicks efficiency, see Guido Calabresi, The Pointlessness of Pareto: Carrying Coase Further, 100 YALE L.J. 1211 (1991).
  • 26
    • 62549102700 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • An extremely risk-averse classical liberal might advocate cautious policymaking approaches that conform with the Burkean approach. Nevertheless, there is a difference between the sources of caution. For the liberal, caution is a product of a risk-averse response to a probability distribution of different policy outcomes. For the Burkean, caution is warranted by the tendency to underestimate the probability of bad outcomes
    • An extremely risk-averse classical liberal might advocate cautious policymaking approaches that conform with the Burkean approach. Nevertheless, there is a difference between the sources of caution. For the liberal, caution is a product of a risk-averse response to a probability distribution of different policy outcomes. For the Burkean, caution is warranted by the tendency to underestimate the probability of bad outcomes.
  • 27
    • 62549147753 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Adrian Vermeule, Many-Minds Arguments in Legal Theory 11-12 (Harvard Law Sch. Pub. Law & Theory, Working Paper No. 08-02, 2008), available at http://ssrn.com/abstract=1087017.
    • See, e.g., Adrian Vermeule, Many-Minds Arguments in Legal Theory 11-12 (Harvard Law Sch. Pub. Law & Theory, Working Paper No. 08-02, 2008), available at http://ssrn.com/abstract=1087017.
  • 28
    • 0346155286 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A Constitution of Democratic Experimentalism, 98
    • See, e.g
    • See, e.g., Michael C. Dorf & Charles F. Sabel, A Constitution of Democratic Experimentalism, 98 COLUM. L. REV. 267 (1998);
    • (1998) COLUM. L. REV , vol.267
    • Dorf, M.C.1    Sabel, C.F.2
  • 29
    • 62549135464 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Daniel A. Farber, Environmental Protection as a Learning Experience, 27 LOY. L.A. L. REV. 791 (1994) ;
    • Daniel A. Farber, Environmental Protection as a Learning Experience, 27 LOY. L.A. L. REV. 791 (1994) ;
  • 30
    • 0035998683 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bradley C. Karkkainen, Environmental Lawyering in the Age of Collaboration, 2002 WIS. L. REV. 555.
    • Bradley C. Karkkainen, Environmental Lawyering in the Age of Collaboration, 2002 WIS. L. REV. 555.
  • 31
    • 11244303709 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Renew Deal: The Fall of Regulation and the Rise of Governance in Contemporary Legal Thought, 89
    • For a review of this literature, see
    • For a review of this literature, see Orly Lobel, The Renew Deal: The Fall of Regulation and the Rise of Governance in Contemporary Legal Thought, 89 MINN. L. REV. 342 (2004).
    • (2004) MINN. L. REV , vol.342
    • Lobel, O.1
  • 32
    • 62549136781 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Farber, supra note 23, at 791
    • Farber, supra note 23, at 791.
  • 33
    • 62549092910 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a thorough examination of experimentalism in a federalist system, see infra Subsection II.C.4.
    • For a thorough examination of experimentalism in a federalist system, see infra Subsection II.C.4.
  • 34
    • 62549101842 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Farber, supra note 23, at 803 (If a decision has irreparable consequences, then it may be worth delaying the decision in order to obtain new information. Taking an irreversible step forecloses the possibility of future learning, and therefore incurs an extra cost that does not show up in the usual cost-benefit analysis. In a formal sense waiting is equivalent to purchasing an option contract, and under many circumstances that option has positive value. (footnote omitted)). For a detailed discussion, see infra Section III.C.
    • See, e.g., Farber, supra note 23, at 803 ("If a decision has irreparable consequences, then it may be worth delaying the decision in order to obtain new information. Taking an irreversible step forecloses the possibility of future learning, and therefore incurs an extra cost that does not show up in the usual cost-benefit analysis. In a formal sense waiting is equivalent to purchasing an option contract, and under many circumstances that option has positive value." (footnote omitted)). For a detailed discussion, see infra Section III.C.
  • 35
    • 62549098846 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For example, when new policies are irreversible and the outcome of B can be determined without actually implementing B, dynamic analysis suggests that policy A is preferred to policy B. See Sunstein, supra note 6; infra Part III.
    • For example, when new policies are irreversible and the outcome of B can be determined without actually implementing B, dynamic analysis suggests that policy A is preferred to policy B. See Sunstein, supra note 6; infra Part III.
  • 36
    • 62549140830 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Even if there is policy inertia, policies are not set in stone. For a detailed discussion, see Part III
    • Even if there is policy inertia, policies are not set in stone. For a detailed discussion, see infra Part III.
    • infra
  • 37
    • 62549139445 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Dorf & Sabel, supra note 23, at 314 (advocating the construct[ion of] the organizational rudiments of local, or, rather, subnational, pragmatist government, by transposing to the public sphere the institutions of benchmarking, simultaneous engineering, and error detection).
    • See, e.g., Dorf & Sabel, supra note 23, at 314 (advocating the "construct[ion of] the organizational rudiments of local, or, rather, subnational, pragmatist government, by transposing to the public sphere the institutions of benchmarking, simultaneous engineering, and error detection").
  • 38
    • 62549107705 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This example parallels the one found in Weitzman, supra note 2, at 641-43
    • This example parallels the one found in Weitzman, supra note 2, at 641-43.
  • 39
    • 62549114695 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • None of the results in this Article depends upon these assumptions, and they will be relaxed or altered in subsequent Sections
    • None of the results in this Article depends upon these assumptions, and they will be relaxed or altered in subsequent Sections.
  • 40
    • 62549158028 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This assumption is obviously too strong. For many reasons, including the political system and status quo bias, the existing policy is cheapest and easiest to implement in the next period. Previously implemented policies are the next cheapest, and brand new policies are presumably the most expensive. The consequences of the policy inertia that is imposed by this distribution of implementation costs are discussed in detail in Part III
    • This assumption is obviously too strong. For many reasons, including the political system and status quo bias, the existing policy is cheapest and easiest to implement in the next period. Previously implemented policies are the next cheapest, and brand new policies are presumably the most expensive. The consequences of the policy inertia that is imposed by this distribution of implementation costs are discussed in detail in Part III.
  • 41
    • 62549123459 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Alternatively, Policy A may be a very low-risk policy that has not been implemented before.
    • Alternatively, Policy A may be a very low-risk policy that has not been implemented before.
  • 42
    • 62549160232 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • One might ask why Policy B has never been attempted before. There are several responses. One answer may be that Policy B had never been thought of before. A second may be that there has been some potentially permanent change in the environment that changes the payoff distribution of Policy B, making Policy B an essentially new policy.
    • One might ask why Policy B has never been attempted before. There are several responses. One answer may be that Policy B had never been thought of before. A second may be that there has been some potentially permanent change in the environment that changes the payoff distribution of Policy B, making Policy B an essentially new policy.
  • 43
    • 62549125230 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Throughout the remainder of this Article, terms like B being better than A or B beating A will mean that B should be chosen before A. At no point do I mean to suggest that B is better than A in every period; I suggest only that B should be chosen first under many circumstances in spite of its inferiority in expected-value terms.
    • Throughout the remainder of this Article, terms like "B being better than A" or "B beating A" will mean that B should be chosen before A. At no point do I mean to suggest that B is better than A in every period; I suggest only that B should be chosen first under many circumstances in spite of its inferiority in expected-value terms.
  • 44
    • 62549119364 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a rigorous proof of this argument, see Weitzman, supra note 2
    • For a rigorous proof of this argument, see Weitzman, supra note 2.
  • 45
    • 62549126694 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This hypothetical is further examined in Section III.C
    • This hypothetical is further examined in Section III.C.
  • 46
    • 62549088076 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Some of the most important complications are examined in Part III
    • Some of the most important complications are examined in Part III.
  • 47
    • 62549088080 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The problem of irreversible risks is discussed in detail in Part III
    • The problem of irreversible risks is discussed in detail in Part III.
  • 48
    • 62549106848 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Douglas A Kysar, It Might Have Been: Risk, Precaution, and Opportunity Costs 3-4 (Cornell Law Sch. Legal Studies Research Paper Series, Research Paper No. 06-023, 2006), available at http://ssrn.com/abstract= 927995.
    • See Douglas A Kysar, It Might Have Been: Risk, Precaution, and Opportunity Costs 3-4 (Cornell Law Sch. Legal Studies Research Paper Series, Research Paper No. 06-023, 2006), available at http://ssrn.com/abstract= 927995.
  • 49
    • 62549147319 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cost-benefit analysis does not obviously distinguish between reversible and irreversible risks. In addition, some formulations [of the precautionary principle] . . . apply to even theoretically reversible risks. David A. Dana, A Behavioral Economic Defense of the Precautionary Principle, 97 NW. U. L. REV. 1315, 1315-16 (2003).
    • Cost-benefit analysis does not obviously distinguish between reversible and irreversible risks. In addition, "some formulations [of the precautionary principle] . . . apply to even theoretically reversible risks." David A. Dana, A Behavioral Economic Defense of the Precautionary Principle, 97 NW. U. L. REV. 1315, 1315-16 (2003).
  • 50
    • 0037578088 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Discipline of Cost-Benefit Analysis, 29
    • See
    • See Amartya Sen, Discipline of Cost-Benefit Analysis, 29 J. LEGAL STUD. 931 (2000).
    • (2000) J. LEGAL STUD , vol.931
    • Sen, A.1
  • 51
    • 62549110635 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kysar, supra note 40, at 3-4 (quoting Peter Montague, The Precautionary Principle, RACHEL'S ENV'T & HEALTH WKLY., Feb. 19, 1998, at 1, but mistranscribing cause and effect as cause-and-effect). Note that there are many different articulations of the precautionary principle.
    • Kysar, supra note 40, at 3-4 (quoting Peter Montague, The Precautionary Principle, RACHEL'S ENV'T & HEALTH WKLY., Feb. 19, 1998, at 1, but mistranscribing "cause and effect" as "cause-and-effect"). Note that there are many different articulations of the precautionary principle.
  • 52
    • 62549128021 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Sunstein, supra note 6, at 848-50. The one stated here is merely one oftcited statement of the principle. A full characterization of the precautionary principle or of cost-benefit analysis is beyond the scope of this paper.
    • See, e.g., Sunstein, supra note 6, at 848-50. The one stated here is merely one oftcited statement of the principle. A full characterization of the precautionary principle or of cost-benefit analysis is beyond the scope of this paper.
  • 53
    • 62549127546 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See C.A. BOWERS, MINDFUL CONSERVATISM: RETHINKING THE IDEOLOGICAL AND EDUCATIONAL BASIS OF AN ECOLOGICALLY SUSTAINABLE FUTURE 91-94 (2003, drawing a link between environmental conservation and Burke's approach, Curiously, while legal scholars have spilled considerable ink on the precautionary principle (a search in Westlaw's Journals and Law Reviews database for [precautionary principle] on October 31, 2008 yielded over 2100 documents) and on Burke a search in Westlaw's Journals and Law Reviews database for [Edmund /5 Burke, on October 31, 2008 yielded over 1400 documents, they have not explored the seemingly obvious linkage between Burkean political philosophy and the precautionary principle. A search in Westlaw's Journals and Law Reviews database for [precautionary principle /50 Burke, on October 31, 2008 yielded only six documents, five of which are related
    • See C.A. BOWERS, MINDFUL CONSERVATISM: RETHINKING THE IDEOLOGICAL AND EDUCATIONAL BASIS OF AN ECOLOGICALLY SUSTAINABLE FUTURE 91-94 (2003) (drawing a link between environmental conservation and Burke's approach). Curiously, while legal scholars have spilled considerable ink on the precautionary principle (a search in Westlaw's Journals and Law Reviews database for ["precautionary principle"] on October 31, 2008 yielded over 2100 documents) and on Burke (a search in Westlaw's Journals and Law Reviews database for [Edmund /5 Burke!] on October 31, 2008 yielded over 1400 documents), they have not explored the seemingly obvious linkage between Burkean political philosophy and the precautionary principle. A search in Westlaw's Journals and Law Reviews database for ["precautionary principle" /50 Burke!] on October 31, 2008 yielded only six documents, five of which are related to a different Burke and the last of which makes only a casual allusion to the similarity between the precautionary principle and Burkean conservatism.
  • 54
    • 0142138790 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Daniel A. Farber, From Here to Eternity: Environmental Law and Future Generations, 2003 U. ILL. L. REV. 289, 305-06 n.90. It is important to note that Westlaw's Journals and Law Reviews database neither catalogues all of currently published law journals, nor includes scholarship in non-law disciplines.
    • See Daniel A. Farber, From Here to Eternity: Environmental Law and Future Generations, 2003 U. ILL. L. REV. 289, 305-06 n.90. It is important to note that Westlaw's Journals and Law Reviews database neither catalogues all volumes of currently published law journals, nor includes scholarship in non-law disciplines.
  • 55
    • 62549132282 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Both issuing new regulations and allowing some polluters to change their technology for pollution reduction entail costs
    • Both issuing new regulations and allowing some polluters to change their technology for pollution reduction entail costs.
  • 56
    • 62549165614 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The benefits of either technology are realized in the form of reduced pollution
    • The benefits of either technology are realized in the form of reduced pollution.
  • 57
    • 84963456897 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note 43 and accompanying text
    • See supra note 43 and accompanying text.
    • See supra
  • 58
    • 84869251961 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Exec. Order No. 12,866 § 6(a)(3)(c), 3 C.F.R. 638 (1993), reprinted in 5 U.S.C § 601 (2000).
    • Exec. Order No. 12,866 § 6(a)(3)(c), 3 C.F.R. 638 (1993), reprinted in 5 U.S.C § 601 (2000).
  • 59
    • 62549091703 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • OFFICE OF MGMT. & BUDGET, CIRCULAR A-4, REGULATORY ANALYSIS (2003), available at http://www.whitehouse.gov/omb/circulars/aoo4/a-4.pdf.
    • OFFICE OF MGMT. & BUDGET, CIRCULAR A-4, REGULATORY ANALYSIS (2003), available at http://www.whitehouse.gov/omb/circulars/aoo4/a-4.pdf.
  • 60
    • 62549154315 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The OMB Circular makes no mention of measuring the information benefit estimates of a particular regulation under its guidelines. Id
    • The OMB Circular makes no mention of measuring the information benefit estimates of a particular regulation under its guidelines. Id
  • 61
    • 62549149672 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1
    • Id. at 1.
  • 62
    • 62549132281 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The precautionary principle often assumes that probabilities cannot be estimated, a condition called uncertainty. See Kysar, supra note 40, at 10-12. So long as the risks involved are not irreversible, uncertainty does not require drastic changes in the lessons of the optimal search approach. With uncertain but reversible risks, one can assume the worstthat is, place heavy probability on bad outcomes - and still favor risky policies, rather than safe ones.
    • The precautionary principle often assumes that probabilities cannot be estimated, a condition called uncertainty. See Kysar, supra note 40, at 10-12. So long as the risks involved are not irreversible, uncertainty does not require drastic changes in the lessons of the optimal search approach. With uncertain but reversible risks, one can assume the worstthat is, place heavy probability on bad outcomes - and still favor risky policies, rather than safe ones.
  • 63
    • 0039623483 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Regulatory Costs of Mythic Proportions, 107
    • See
    • See Lisa Heinzerling, Regulatory Costs of Mythic Proportions, 107 YALE L.J. 1981, 2043-56 (1998).
    • (1998) YALE L.J. 1981 , pp. 2043-2056
    • Heinzerling, L.1
  • 64
    • 62549156462 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id
    • See id.
  • 65
    • 62549143325 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See ROBERT E. SCOTT & JODY S. KRAUS, CONTRACT LAW AND THEORY 26-27 (4th ed. 2007).
    • See ROBERT E. SCOTT & JODY S. KRAUS, CONTRACT LAW AND THEORY 26-27 (4th ed. 2007).
  • 66
    • 62549126242 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 90
    • Id. at 90.
  • 67
    • 0002692296 scopus 로고
    • Filling Gaps in Incomplete Contracts: An Economic Theory of Default Rules, 99
    • SEE Ian Ayres & Robert Gertner, Filling Gaps in Incomplete Contracts: An Economic Theory of Default Rules, 99 YALE L.J. 87 (1989).
    • (1989) YALE L.J , vol.87
    • Ian Ayres, S.1    Gertner, R.2
  • 68
    • 0000949337 scopus 로고
    • Information and the Scope of Liability for Breach of Contract: The Rule of Hadley v. Baxendale, 7
    • See
    • See Lucian Ayre Bebchuk & Steven Shavell, Information and the Scope of Liability for Breach of Contract: The Rule of Hadley v. Baxendale, 7 J.L. ECON. & ORG. 284 (1991).
    • (1991) J.L. ECON. & ORG , vol.284
    • Ayre Bebchuk, L.1    Shavell, S.2
  • 69
    • 0348241171 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hadley v. Baxendale, (1854) 9 Ex. 341, 156 Eng. Rep. 145; see Barry E. Adler, The Questionable Ascent of Hadley v. Baxendale, 51 STAN. L. REV. 1547, 1547-48 (1999). Following the literature, this discussion will emphasize the Hadley rule. The same conclusions apply to other information-forcing or penalty default rules.
    • Hadley v. Baxendale, (1854) 9 Ex. 341, 156 Eng. Rep. 145; see Barry E. Adler, The Questionable Ascent of Hadley v. Baxendale, 51 STAN. L. REV. 1547, 1547-48 (1999). Following the literature, this discussion will emphasize the Hadley rule. The same conclusions apply to other information-forcing or penalty default rules.
  • 70
    • 62549159355 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Ayres & Gertner, supra note 57, at 112-15;
    • See Ayres & Gertner, supra note 57, at 112-15;
  • 71
    • 62549107996 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • rule would be the choice of most parties considering the rule, the rule was not chosen for this reason
    • Bebchuk & Shavell, supra note 58, at 308. Even if the Hadley rule would be the choice of most parties considering the rule, the rule was not chosen for this reason.
    • supra note 58, at 308. Even if the Hadley
    • Bebchuk1    Shavell2
  • 72
    • 62549126241 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Ayres & Gertner, supra note 57, at 106-07.
    • See Ayres & Gertner, supra note 57, at 106-07.
  • 73
    • 67649301769 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • There Are No Penalty Default Rules in Contract Law, 33
    • arguing that penalty default rules do not exist in practice, See
    • See Eric A Posner, There Are No Penalty Default Rules in Contract Law, 33 FLA. ST. U. L. REV. 563 (2006) (arguing that penalty default rules do not exist in practice).
    • (2006) FLA. ST. U. L. REV , vol.563
    • Posner, E.A.1
  • 74
    • 62549138075 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • But see Ian Ayres, Ya-Huh: There Are and Should Be Penalty Defaults, 33 FLA. ST. U. L. REV. 589 (2006) (contradicting Posner's assertions and claiming that there are many examples of penalty default rules) .
    • But see Ian Ayres, Ya-Huh: There Are and Should Be Penalty Defaults, 33 FLA. ST. U. L. REV. 589 (2006) (contradicting Posner's assertions and claiming that there are many examples of penalty default rules) .
  • 76
    • 62549105539 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Adler, supra note 59, at 1547-48
    • See Adler, supra note 59, at 1547-48.
  • 77
    • 62549143756 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1556
    • Id. at 1556.
  • 78
    • 62549156878 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 1559-70.
    • See id. at 1559-70.
  • 79
    • 62549139918 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1552
    • Id. at 1552.
  • 80
    • 62549123141 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Since most contract default rules have been chosen using the majoritarian paradigm, see SCOTT & KRAUS, supra note 55, at 89-90, the majoritarian rule is the existing default law in most cases.
    • Since most contract default rules have been chosen using the majoritarian paradigm, see SCOTT & KRAUS, supra note 55, at 89-90, the majoritarian rule is the existing default law in most cases.
  • 81
    • 62549161131 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Posner, supra note 62, at 565, 573-86
    • Posner, supra note 62, at 565, 573-86.
  • 82
    • 62549143324 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Intriguingly, penalty default rules may entail less variance than majoritarian rules when the penalty rule is the existing default rule - as in the case of the Hadley damages rule. When the penalty rule is the status quo, majoritarian rules become more attractive, all else equal. When neither the majoritarian rule nor the penalty rule is the default rule, however, the majoritarian rule will generally entail less variance.
    • Intriguingly, penalty default rules may entail less variance than majoritarian rules when the penalty rule is the existing default rule - as in the case of the Hadley damages rule. When the penalty rule is the status quo, majoritarian rules become more attractive, all else equal. When neither the majoritarian rule nor the penalty rule is the default rule, however, the majoritarian rule will generally entail less variance.
  • 83
    • 62549134685 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In Example 2, Policy B has a small probability of producing a favorable outcome. Penalty defaults probably have higher probabilities of success, but success is not quite as advantageous as in the example. If necessary, the example could be altered. The basic principle remains the same. So long as a penalty default rule provides some possibility of a better outcome while involving more risk than the majoritarian rule, then the optimal search approach dictates that the penalty default rule should be tried first in some cases.
    • In Example 2, Policy B has a small probability of producing a favorable outcome. Penalty defaults probably have higher probabilities of success, but success is not quite as advantageous as in the example. If necessary, the example could be altered. The basic principle remains the same. So long as a penalty default rule provides some possibility of a better outcome while involving more risk than the majoritarian rule, then the optimal search approach dictates that the penalty default rule should be tried first in some cases.
  • 84
    • 84869252579 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Current law requires credit card issuers to prominently state their rates, but the issuers reserve the right to change the rates unilaterally. See Truth in Lending Act, 15 U.S.C §§ 1601-1693r (2000).
    • Current law requires credit card issuers to prominently state their rates, but the issuers reserve the right to change the rates unilaterally. See Truth in Lending Act, 15 U.S.C §§ 1601-1693r (2000).
  • 85
    • 0003207194 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Critics of enhanced shareholder democracy may argue that policy variance is unnecessary in this context because federalism in corporate law already produces sufficient policy variance, see, e.g, Roberta Romano, Empowering Investors: A Market Approach to Securities Regulation, 107 YALE L.J. 2359, 2392 1998, with the race to the top leading all states to adopt value-enhancing policy variants. If one accepts this proposition, then high-variance policies are unhelpful because the variance they provide is unlikely to find innovative policies missed by the states. Others, however, argue that state competition for corporate charters produces relatively little variance
    • Critics of enhanced shareholder democracy may argue that policy variance is unnecessary in this context because federalism in corporate law already produces sufficient policy variance, see, e.g., Roberta Romano, Empowering Investors: A Market Approach to Securities Regulation, 107 YALE L.J. 2359, 2392 (1998), with the "race to the top" leading all states to adopt value-enhancing policy variants. If one accepts this proposition, then high-variance policies are unhelpful because the variance they provide is unlikely to find innovative policies missed by the states. Others, however, argue that state competition for corporate charters produces relatively little variance.
  • 86
    • 1342263213 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Lucian Arye Bebchuk & Assaf Hamdani, Vigorous Race or Leisurely Walk: Reconsidering the Competition over Corporate Charters, 112 YALE L.J. 553, 605-06 (2002). These arguments echo a broader debate about whether state competition for corporate charters produces a race to the top - with all states providing efficient and ever-improving laws - or a race to the bottom - with states undercutting each other by offering laws that favor management or other interested parties.
    • See, e.g., Lucian Arye Bebchuk & Assaf Hamdani, Vigorous Race or Leisurely Walk: Reconsidering the Competition over Corporate Charters, 112 YALE L.J. 553, 605-06 (2002). These arguments echo a broader debate about whether state competition for corporate charters produces a "race to the top" - with all states providing efficient and ever-improving laws - or a "race to the bottom" - with states undercutting each other by offering laws that favor management or other interested parties.
  • 87
    • 0000821053 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Compare Roberta Romano, Law As a Product: Some Pieces of the Incorporation Puzzle, 1 J.L. ECON. & ORG. 225, 280-81 (1985) (arguing that corporate law competition creates a race to the top),
    • Compare Roberta Romano, Law As a Product: Some Pieces of the Incorporation Puzzle, 1 J.L. ECON. & ORG. 225, 280-81 (1985) (arguing that corporate law competition creates a race to the top),
  • 88
    • 62549128449 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and Ralph K. Winter, Jr, State Law, Shareholder Protection, and the Theory of the Corporation, 6 J. LEGAL STUD. 251 (1977, characterizing corporate law competition as a race to the top, with Lucian Arye Bebchuk, Federalism and the Corporation: The Desirable Limits on State Competition in Corporate Law, 105 HARV. L. REV. 1435, 1441 (1992, describing how state competition in corporate law does not invariably lead to a race to the top, and William L. Cary, Federalism and Corporate Law: Reflections upon Delaware, 83 YALE L.J. 663 1974, describing state-based corporate law as race to the bottom, The optimal search approach to corporate law described in this Article may be valuable to this debate for two reasons. First, if Bebchuk and Hamdani's lack-of-innovation argument is the better one, then high-variance optimal search policies at the federal level offer the potential for great benefits. Secon
    • and Ralph K. Winter, Jr., State Law, Shareholder Protection, and the Theory of the Corporation, 6 J. LEGAL STUD. 251 (1977) (characterizing corporate law competition as a race to the top), with Lucian Arye Bebchuk, Federalism and the Corporation: The Desirable Limits on State Competition in Corporate Law, 105 HARV. L. REV. 1435, 1441 (1992) (describing how state competition in corporate law does not invariably lead to a race to the top), and William L. Cary, Federalism and Corporate Law: Reflections upon Delaware, 83 YALE L.J. 663 (1974) (describing state-based corporate law as race to the bottom). The optimal search approach to corporate law described in this Article may be valuable to this debate for two reasons. First, if Bebchuk and Hamdani's lack-of-innovation argument is the better one, then high-variance optimal search policies at the federal level offer the potential for great benefits. Second, attempting new policies offers the possibility of resolving the seemingly never-ending debate about the value of state competition in corporate law. If innovative corporate law policies are attempted but consistently prove to be failures, then this provides strong evidence of a "race to the top." For a thorough discussion of the relation between federalism and the optimal search approach, see infra Subsection II.C.4 and Section IV.C.
  • 89
    • 13244272076 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Case for Increasing Shareholder Power, 118
    • See
    • See Lucian Arye Bebchuk, The Case for Increasing Shareholder Power, 118 HARV. L. REV. 833, 843-46 (2005).
    • (2005) HARV. L. REV , vol.833 , pp. 843-846
    • Arye Bebchuk, L.1
  • 90
    • 62549118476 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id
    • See id.
  • 91
    • 62549135463 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 844-46.
    • See id. at 844-46.
  • 92
    • 62549133800 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id
    • See id.
  • 93
    • 33646431446 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Stephen M. Bainbridge, Director Primacy and Shareholder Disempowerment, 119 HARV. L. REV. 1735, 1758 (2006) [hereinafter Bainbridge, Shareholder Disempowerment];
    • See, e.g., Stephen M. Bainbridge, Director Primacy and Shareholder Disempowerment, 119 HARV. L. REV. 1735, 1758 (2006) [hereinafter Bainbridge, Shareholder Disempowerment];
  • 94
    • 26644444110 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Director Primacy: The Means and Ends of Corporate Governance, 97
    • Stephen M. Bainbridge, Director Primacy: The Means and Ends of Corporate Governance, 97 NW. U. L. REV. 547, 605-06 (2003);
    • (2003) NW. U. L. REV , vol.547 , pp. 605-606
    • Bainbridge, S.M.1
  • 95
    • 33645140387 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Some Skepticism About Increasing Shareholder Power, 53
    • Iman Anabtawi, Some Skepticism About Increasing Shareholder Power, 53 UCLA L. REV. 561, 598 (2006) ;
    • (2006) UCLA L. REV , vol.561 , pp. 598
    • Anabtawi, I.1
  • 96
    • 62549128451 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A. Gilchrist Sparks, III, Corporate Democracy: What It Is, What It Isn't, and What It Should Be, INSIGHTS, Mar. 2006, at 20, 23 (noting the overwhelming historical success of the existing governance system) ;
    • A. Gilchrist Sparks, III, Corporate Democracy: What It Is, What It Isn't, and What It Should Be, INSIGHTS, Mar. 2006, at 20, 23 (noting the "overwhelming historical success of the existing governance system") ;
  • 97
    • 33646415078 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also Leo E. Strine, Jr., Toward a True Corporate Republic: A Traditionalist Response to Bebchuk's Solution for Improving Corporate America, 119 HARV. L. REV. 1759, 1759 (2006) (critiquing Bebchuk's proposal to increase shareholder power from the perspective of traditionalist investors).
    • see also Leo E. Strine, Jr., Toward a True Corporate Republic: A Traditionalist Response to Bebchuk's Solution for Improving Corporate America, 119 HARV. L. REV. 1759, 1759 (2006) (critiquing Bebchuk's proposal to increase shareholder power from the perspective of "traditionalist investors").
  • 98
    • 62549119802 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note 78, at, Note the Burkean allusions in Bainbridge's argument
    • Bainbridge, Shareholder Disempowerment, supra note 78, at 1758. Note the Burkean allusions in Bainbridge's argument.
    • Shareholder Disempowerment, supra , pp. 1758
    • Bainbridge1
  • 99
    • 62549083241 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1749 (quoting KENNETH J. ARROW, THE LIMITS OF ORGANIZATION 69 (1974)).
    • Id. at 1749 (quoting KENNETH J. ARROW, THE LIMITS OF ORGANIZATION 69 (1974)).
  • 100
    • 62549116385 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Blasius Indus., Inc. v. Atlas Corp., 564 A.2d 651,659 (Del. Ch. 1988).
    • Blasius Indus., Inc. v. Atlas Corp., 564 A.2d 651,659 (Del. Ch. 1988).
  • 101
    • 34250001205 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Compare Lucian A. Bebchuk, The Myth of the Shareholder Franchise, 93 VA. L. REV. 675 (2007) (arguing that the shareholder franchise is illusory), with Martin Lipton & William Savitt, The Many Myths of Lucian Bebchuk, 93 VA. L. REV. 733, 734 (2007) (arguing that the 'myth of the shareholder franchise' is no myth at all).
    • Compare Lucian A. Bebchuk, The Myth of the Shareholder Franchise, 93 VA. L. REV. 675 (2007) (arguing that the shareholder franchise is illusory), with Martin Lipton & William Savitt, The Many Myths of Lucian Bebchuk, 93 VA. L. REV. 733, 734 (2007) (arguing "that the 'myth of the shareholder franchise' is no myth at all").
  • 102
    • 62549124362 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Unocal Corp. v. Mesa Petroleum Co., 493 A.2d 946, 959 (Del. 1985) (If the stockholders are displeased with the action of their elected representatives, the powers of corporate democracy are at their disposal to turn the board out.).
    • See Unocal Corp. v. Mesa Petroleum Co., 493 A.2d 946, 959 (Del. 1985) ("If the stockholders are displeased with the action of their elected representatives, the powers of corporate democracy are at their disposal to turn the board out.").
  • 103
    • 62549088077 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Yair Listokin, Corporate Voting vs. Market Price Setting (July 3, 2008) (unpublished manuscript, on file with author), available at http://ssrn.com/abstract=1112671.
    • See Yair Listokin, Corporate Voting vs. Market Price Setting (July 3, 2008) (unpublished manuscript, on file with author), available at http://ssrn.com/abstract=1112671.
  • 104
    • 62549131864 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id
    • See id.
  • 105
    • 62549160625 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Bebchuk, supra note 82, at 682-88 (arguing that the small number of contested elections indicates some problems with the shareholder franchise).
    • See Bebchuk, supra note 82, at 682-88 (arguing that the small number of contested elections indicates some problems with the shareholder franchise).
  • 106
    • 34250016360 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • But see Jonathan R. Macey, Too Many Notes and Not Enough Votes: Lucian Bebchuk and Emperor Joseph II Kvetch About Contested Director Elections and Mozart's Seraglio, 93 VA. L. REV. 759 (2007) (arguing that Bebchuk has no baseline for determining the appropriate number of contested elections).
    • But see Jonathan R. Macey, Too Many Notes and Not Enough Votes: Lucian Bebchuk and Emperor Joseph II Kvetch About Contested Director Elections and Mozart's Seraglio, 93 VA. L. REV. 759 (2007) (arguing that Bebchuk has no baseline for determining the appropriate number of contested elections).
  • 107
    • 62549111157 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Letter from Wachtell, Lipton, Rosen & Katz to Jonathan G. Katz, Sec'y, SEC (June 11, 2003), available at http://www.sec.gov/rules/other/ s71003/wachtello61103.htm; see also Lipton & Savitt, supra note 82 (defending shareholder franchise).
    • Letter from Wachtell, Lipton, Rosen & Katz to Jonathan G. Katz, Sec'y, SEC (June 11, 2003), available at http://www.sec.gov/rules/other/ s71003/wachtello61103.htm; see also Lipton & Savitt, supra note 82 (defending shareholder franchise).
  • 108
    • 62549123915 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Bebchuk, supra note 82, at 688-94
    • See Bebchuk, supra note 82, at 688-94.
  • 109
    • 58149131557 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See generally Yair Listokin, Management Always Wins the Close Ones, 10 AM. L. & ECON. REV. 159 (2008) (discussing management advantages in corporate voting).
    • See generally Yair Listokin, Management Always Wins the Close Ones, 10 AM. L. & ECON. REV. 159 (2008) (discussing management advantages in corporate voting).
  • 110
    • 62549128874 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bebchuk, supra note 82, at 688-94
    • Bebchuk, supra note 82, at 688-94.
  • 111
    • 62549126695 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 112
    • 62549120570 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 113
    • 62549092911 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See,e.g, id
    • See,e.g., id.
  • 114
    • 62549098387 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 677
    • Id. at 677.
  • 115
    • 62549165613 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 116
    • 0742306255 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Lucian Arye Bebchuk, The Case for Shareholder Access to the Ballot, 59 BUS. LAW. 43 (2003).
    • See, e.g., Lucian Arye Bebchuk, The Case for Shareholder Access to the Ballot, 59 BUS. LAW. 43 (2003).
  • 117
    • 62549088079 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • At present, dissident slates of directors must mail their own proxy forms to shareholders. See Bebchuk, supra note 82, at 696-98
    • At present, dissident slates of directors must mail their own proxy forms to shareholders. See Bebchuk, supra note 82, at 696-98.
  • 118
    • 62549113705 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g, Lipton & Savitt, supra note 82;
    • See, e.g., Lipton & Savitt, supra note 82;
  • 119
    • 62549124789 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also Macey, supra note 86 (arguing that Bebchuk has no baseline for determining the appropriate number of contested elections).
    • see also Macey, supra note 86 (arguing that Bebchuk has no baseline for determining the appropriate number of contested elections).
  • 120
    • 62549159354 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note 82, at, Again, note the strong Burkean tone to the arguments in favor of the status quo
    • Lipton & Savitt, supra note 82, at 733-34. Again, note the strong Burkean tone to the arguments in favor of the status quo.
    • supra , pp. 733-734
    • Lipton1    Savitt2
  • 121
    • 62549096132 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Annette L. Nazareth, Comm'r, SEC, Speech by SEC Commissioner: Remarks Before the International Corporate Governance Network (Oct. 29, 2007) (transcript available at http://www.sec.gov/news/speech/2007/spch102907aln.htm) [hereinafter Nazareth Speech].
    • See Annette L. Nazareth, Comm'r, SEC, Speech by SEC Commissioner: Remarks Before the International Corporate Governance Network (Oct. 29, 2007) (transcript available at http://www.sec.gov/news/speech/2007/spch102907aln.htm) [hereinafter Nazareth Speech].
  • 122
    • 62549158910 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g, Macey, supra note 86;
    • See, e.g., Macey, supra note 86;
  • 123
    • 34249977113 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Professor Bebchuk's Brave New World: A Reply to "The Myth of the Shareholder Franchise," 93
    • John F. Olson, Professor Bebchuk's Brave New World: A Reply to "The Myth of the Shareholder Franchise," 93 VA. L. REV. 773 (2007);
    • (2007) VA. L. REV , vol.773
    • Olson, J.F.1
  • 124
    • 34250024408 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Mythical Benefits of Shareholder Control, 93
    • Lynn A Stout, The Mythical Benefits of Shareholder Control, 93 VA. L. REV. 789 (2007);
    • (2007) VA. L. REV , vol.789
    • Stout, L.A.1
  • 125
    • 34249980178 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Stockholder Franchise Is Not a Myth: A Response to Professor Bebchuk, 93
    • It is extremely unlikely that the issue would have engendered so many comment letters if its proponents did not think it was likely to have significantly positive effects and its detractors did not think the reform would have negative implications
    • E. Norman Veasey, The Stockholder Franchise Is Not a Myth: A Response to Professor Bebchuk, 93 VA. L. REV. 811 (2007). It is extremely unlikely that the issue would have engendered so many comment letters if its proponents did not think it was likely to have significantly positive effects and its detractors did not think the reform would have negative implications.
    • (2007) VA. L. REV , vol.811
    • Norman Veasey, E.1
  • 126
    • 62549118920 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • WILLIAM H. RIKER, FEDERALISM: ORIGIN, OPERATION, SIGNIFICANCE 11 (1964).
    • WILLIAM H. RIKER, FEDERALISM: ORIGIN, OPERATION, SIGNIFICANCE 11 (1964).
  • 127
    • 62549145111 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Of course, there are many other arguments for federalism. For a comprehensive review of these arguments, see DAVID L. SHAPIRO, FEDERALISM: A DIALOGUE 58-106 1995, This Article does not examine these powerful alternative justifications for federalism
    • Of course, there are many other arguments for federalism. For a comprehensive review of these arguments, see DAVID L. SHAPIRO, FEDERALISM: A DIALOGUE 58-106 (1995). This Article does not examine these powerful alternative justifications for federalism.
  • 128
    • 62549119801 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New State Ice Co. v. Liebmann, 285 U.S. 262, 311 (1932) (Brandeis, J., dissenting). Justice Brandeis's argument for federalism has been adopted by many scholars examining a wide variety of different contexts. A Westlaw search for law review articles quoting Justice Brandeis's federalism-as-laboratory quotation retrieved almost seven hundred articles.
    • New State Ice Co. v. Liebmann, 285 U.S. 262, 311 (1932) (Brandeis, J., dissenting). Justice Brandeis's argument for federalism has been adopted by many scholars examining a wide variety of different contexts. A Westlaw search for law review articles quoting Justice Brandeis's federalism-as-laboratory quotation retrieved almost seven hundred articles.
  • 129
    • 62549084950 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dorf & Sabel, supra note 23, at 287-88
    • Dorf & Sabel, supra note 23, at 287-88.
  • 130
    • 62549125692 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See generally id. at 314-24 (discussing how diversity can lead to local differences in policy and how policy should be benchmarked to produce new policies that are better than previous policies).
    • See generally id. at 314-24 (discussing how diversity can lead to local differences in policy and how policy should be "benchmarked" to produce new policies that are better than previous policies).
  • 131
    • 62549115105 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 287
    • Id. at 287.
  • 132
    • 62549113704 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Susan Rose-Ackerman questions the argument that federalism promotes innovation. See Susan Rose-Ackerman, Risk Taking and Reelection: Does Federalism Promote Innovation?, 9 J. LEGAL STUD. 593 (1980). Public choice considerations, such as public policymakers' desire for reelection, may diminish incentives for risk taking by policymakers in a federal system. After a thorough analysis of these incentives, Rose-Ackerman concludes that few useful experiments will be carried out in [state and local governments].
    • Susan Rose-Ackerman questions the argument that federalism promotes innovation. See Susan Rose-Ackerman, Risk Taking and Reelection: Does Federalism Promote Innovation?, 9 J. LEGAL STUD. 593 (1980). Public choice considerations, such as public policymakers' desire for reelection, may diminish incentives for risk taking by policymakers in a federal system. After a thorough analysis of these incentives, Rose-Ackerman concludes that "few useful experiments will be carried out in [state and local governments]."
  • 133
    • 62549090813 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 594
    • Id. at 594.
  • 134
    • 62549092169 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Dorf & Sabel, supra note 23
    • See Dorf & Sabel, supra note 23.
  • 135
    • 0348080698 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Preemption, 86
    • For a thorough examination of preemption, see
    • For a thorough examination of preemption, see Caleb Nelson, Preemption, 86 VA. L. REV. 225 (2000).
    • (2000) VA. L. REV , vol.225
    • Nelson, C.1
  • 136
    • 62549150578 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Boggs v. Boggs, 520 U.S. 833, 844 (1997) (quoting Gade v. Nat'l Solid Wastes Mgmt. Ass'n, 505 U.S. 88, 98 (1921)).
    • Boggs v. Boggs, 520 U.S. 833, 844 (1997) (quoting Gade v. Nat'l Solid Wastes Mgmt. Ass'n, 505 U.S. 88, 98 (1921)).
  • 137
    • 62549104443 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Nelson, supra note 110, at 229 n.16 (cataloguing and summarizing the primary critiques of preemption, including critiques found in KENNETH STARR ET AL., THE LAW OF PREEMPTION 47-56 (1991) ;
    • See Nelson, supra note 110, at 229 n.16 (cataloguing and summarizing the primary critiques of preemption, including critiques found in KENNETH STARR ET AL., THE LAW OF PREEMPTION 47-56 (1991) ;
  • 138
    • 0031484804 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Congress Speak Clearly: Federal Preemption of State Tort Remedies, 77
    • Betsy J. Grey, Make Congress Speak Clearly: Federal Preemption of State Tort Remedies, 77 B.U. L. REV. 559,561 (1997);
    • (1997) B.U. L. REV , vol.559 , pp. 561
    • Betsy, J.1    Grey, M.2
  • 139
    • 0039182239 scopus 로고
    • Preemption Pathologies and Civic Republican Values, 71
    • S. Candice Hoke, Preemption Pathologies and Civic Republican Values, 71 B.U. L. REV. 685, 687-88 (1991);
    • (1991) B.U. L. REV , vol.685 , pp. 687-688
    • Candice Hoke, S.1
  • 140
    • 62549105538 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Donald P. Rothschild, A Proposed Tonic with Florida Lime To Celebrate Our New Federalism: How To Deal with the Headache of Preemption, 38 U. MIAMI L. REV. 829, 830 n.3 (1984);
    • Donald P. Rothschild, A Proposed "Tonic" with Florida Lime To Celebrate Our New Federalism: How To Deal with the "Headache" of Preemption, 38 U. MIAMI L. REV. 829, 830 n.3 (1984);
  • 141
    • 62549108896 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Paul Wolfson, Preemption and Federalism: The Missing Link, 16 HASTINGS CONST. L.Q. 69, 114 (1988)).
    • Paul Wolfson, Preemption and Federalism: The Missing Link, 16 HASTINGS CONST. L.Q. 69, 114 (1988)).
  • 142
    • 62549158465 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 112
    • See supra note 112.
  • 143
    • 62549127547 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Electric power production provides an excellent example. Coal-fired plants are considerably cheaper than gas-fired plants for producing electricity. Burning coal, however, produces more externalities than does gas. A national regulator might decide that these externalities outweigh the benefit of cheaper power production. If the acid rain harms other states but does not harm the state where the power is produced, however, then a state regulator may decide to approve coal power production
    • Electric power production provides an excellent example. Coal-fired plants are considerably cheaper than gas-fired plants for producing electricity. Burning coal, however, produces more externalities than does gas. A national regulator might decide that these externalities outweigh the benefit of cheaper power production. If the acid rain harms other states but does not harm the state where the power is produced, however, then a state regulator may decide to approve coal power production.
  • 144
    • 35348990323 scopus 로고
    • U.S. 52
    • Hines v. Davidowitz, 312 U.S. 52, 67 (1941).
    • (1941) Davidowitz , vol.312 , pp. 67
    • Hines, V.1
  • 145
    • 62549103170 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This conclusion arises from the optimal search approach rather than the experimentalist approach to federalism. See infra Section IV.C
    • This conclusion arises from the optimal search approach rather than the experimentalist approach to federalism. See infra Section IV.C.
  • 146
    • 62549095101 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This does not mean that the benefits of standardization should be ignored. Instead, they should be compared with the underappreciated informational benefits of variation
    • This does not mean that the benefits of standardization should be ignored. Instead, they should be compared with the underappreciated informational benefits of variation.
  • 147
    • 62549118921 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Again, the argument will be presented in risk-neutral terms for the sake of clarity. Parallel arguments could be made in utility terms for a risk-averse utilitarian rationalist
    • Again, the argument will be presented in risk-neutral terms for the sake of clarity. Parallel arguments could be made in utility terms for a risk-averse utilitarian rationalist.
  • 148
    • 84869252575 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • While Burke was opposed to innovation in the form of abrupt change in policy, he was more receptive to extremely gradual policy modifications. See Ian Harris, Edmund Burke, in STANFORD ENCYCLOPEDIA OF PHILOSOPHY §8 Edward N. Zalta ed, 2004, last visited Oct. 27, 2008
    • While Burke was opposed to "innovation" in the form of abrupt change in policy, he was more receptive to extremely gradual policy modifications. See Ian Harris, Edmund Burke, in STANFORD ENCYCLOPEDIA OF PHILOSOPHY §8 (Edward N. Zalta ed., 2004), http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/burke/ (last visited Oct. 27, 2008).
  • 149
    • 62549129627 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra Part I.
    • See supra Part I.
  • 150
    • 62549138074 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Young, supra note 7, at 646
    • Young, supra note 7, at 646.
  • 151
    • 62549154675 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • There is some rational judgment required for the Burkean approach as well. Unless Burkeans want to have rigid laws, which Burke (at least) did not, there must be some rational evaluation of new policies and debate about the scope by which they change existing policy
    • There is some rational judgment required for the Burkean approach as well. Unless Burkeans want to have rigid laws, which Burke (at least) did not, there must be some rational evaluation of new policies and debate about the scope by which they change existing policy.
  • 152
    • 62549101843 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • That is, suppose that the range of possible outcomes is much wider than an expert thinks, but the increase in variability occurs on both the positive side and the negative side. If the negative consequences of a policy change increase but the positive consequences do not, then the expected value of a policy change goes down and the policy change becomes less attractive under the optimal search approach
    • That is, suppose that the range of possible outcomes is much wider than an expert thinks, but the increase in variability occurs on both the positive side and the negative side. If the negative consequences of a policy change increase but the positive consequences do not, then the expected value of a policy change goes down and the policy change becomes less attractive under the optimal search approach.
  • 153
    • 62549123139 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SEE Kronman, supra note 16, at 1066-68
    • SEE Kronman, supra note 16, at 1066-68.
  • 154
    • 62549126239 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • EDMUND BURKE, REFLECTIONS ON THE REVOLUTION IN FRANCE 81 (Frank M. Turner ed., 2003).
    • EDMUND BURKE, REFLECTIONS ON THE REVOLUTION IN FRANCE 81 (Frank M. Turner ed., 2003).
  • 155
    • 62549146891 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This does not mean that the present generation is behaving altruistically. The optimal search approach benefits all members of the present generation who will enjoy the potential benefits of policy innovation in future periods. Alternatively, the present generation could consume some of the surplus created by the optimal search approach for future generations by leaving less for future generations along other dimensions. Because the optimal search approach creates value, such gain sharing could leave all generations better off
    • This does not mean that the present generation is behaving altruistically. The optimal search approach benefits all members of the present generation who will enjoy the potential benefits of policy innovation in future periods. Alternatively, the present generation could consume some of the surplus created by the optimal search approach for future generations by leaving less for future generations along other dimensions. Because the optimal search approach creates value, such gain sharing could leave all generations better off.
  • 156
    • 62549087642 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This will be discussed in detail in Section III.C
    • This will be discussed in detail in Section III.C.
  • 157
    • 62549122280 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a detailed description of the real options approach, see infra Subsection III.C.1.
    • For a detailed description of the "real options" approach, see infra Subsection III.C.1.
  • 158
    • 62549135129 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Sunstein, supra note 6, at 860-64 (distinguishing between irreversibility as seriousness and irreversibility as sunk costs). The definition provided here resembles the sunk cost definition. A cost is sunk if it cannot be retrieved. A policy with long-lasting effects can therefore be represented as having a high initial cost-measured as the present discounted value of the future effects - or it can be represented as having costs distributed over a long time period. In the numerical examples, I choose to equate irreversibility with long-lasting effects, but the two methods are mathematically equivalent.
    • See Sunstein, supra note 6, at 860-64 (distinguishing between irreversibility as "seriousness" and irreversibility as "sunk costs"). The definition provided here resembles the sunk cost definition. A cost is sunk if it cannot be retrieved. A policy with long-lasting effects can therefore be represented as having a high initial cost-measured as the present discounted value of the future effects - or it can be represented as having costs distributed over a long time period. In the numerical examples, I choose to equate irreversibility with long-lasting effects, but the two methods are mathematically equivalent.
  • 159
    • 62549132280 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Almost all sources of irreversibility can be placed within these two broad categories. For example, inertia can be described as resulting from high formulation and implementation costs
    • Almost all sources of irreversibility can be placed within these two broad categories. For example, inertia can be described as resulting from high formulation and implementation costs.
  • 160
    • 62549142920 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • There are many policies that may have positive expected value, but cannot be implemented because of the scarcity of legislative time and effort. These time and effort expenditures are irretrievable opportunity costs of formulating a particular policy
    • There are many policies that may have positive expected value, but cannot be implemented because of the scarcity of legislative time and effort. These time and effort expenditures are irretrievable opportunity costs of formulating a particular policy.
  • 161
    • 62549146420 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Daniel Kahneman, Jack L. Knetsch & Richard H. Thaler, Anomalies: The Endowment Effect, Loss Aversion, and Status Quo Bias, J. ECON. PERSP., Winter 1991, at 193, 197-99.
    • Daniel Kahneman, Jack L. Knetsch & Richard H. Thaler, Anomalies: The Endowment Effect, Loss Aversion, and Status Quo Bias, J. ECON. PERSP., Winter 1991, at 193, 197-99.
  • 162
    • 62549086778 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See DIXIT & PINDYCK, supra note 6, at 8-9. The effects of a policy in the current period are obviously irreversible. If a policy is a failure, these effects cannot be recouped by changing the policy in the future period. These costs are accounted for in both the optimal search approach and the real options approach, which have countervailing benefits that surpass these per-period costs in many cases.
    • See DIXIT & PINDYCK, supra note 6, at 8-9. The effects of a policy in the current period are obviously irreversible. If a policy is a failure, these effects cannot be recouped by changing the policy in the future period. These costs are accounted for in both the optimal search approach and the real options approach, which have countervailing benefits that surpass these per-period costs in many cases.
  • 163
    • 84890638058 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., NICHOLAS STERN, THE ECONOMICS OF CLIMATE CHANGE: THE STERN REVIEW 28 (2007) (The impacts of climate change are persistent and develop over time. Once in the atmosphere, some [greenhouse gases] stay there for hundreds of years.).
    • See, e.g., NICHOLAS STERN, THE ECONOMICS OF CLIMATE CHANGE: THE STERN REVIEW 28 (2007) ("The impacts of climate change are persistent and develop over time. Once in the atmosphere, some [greenhouse gases] stay there for hundreds of years.").
  • 164
    • 62549153804 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Sunstein, supra note 6, at 860-69
    • See Sunstein, supra note 6, at 860-69.
  • 165
    • 62549158911 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sunstein makes exactly this argument in his article, Irreversible and Catastrophic. See Sunstein, supra note 6, at 855-64. His article assumes that cost-benefit analysis is superior to the precautionary principle when risks are reversible and does not consider the possibility that reversibility may imply a deviation from expected-value maximization that is similar in logic but very different in outcome from the irreversible harm precautionary principle.
    • Sunstein makes exactly this argument in his article, Irreversible and Catastrophic. See Sunstein, supra note 6, at 855-64. His article assumes that cost-benefit analysis is superior to the precautionary principle when risks are reversible and does not consider the possibility that reversibility may imply a deviation from expected-value maximization that is similar in logic but very different in outcome from the irreversible harm precautionary principle.
  • 166
    • 62549133360 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This discussion is not meant to minimize the harms caused by catastrophic occurrences, but to develop an analytical distinction between catastrophic and irreversible
    • This discussion is not meant to minimize the harms caused by catastrophic occurrences, but to develop an analytical distinction between catastrophic and irreversible.
  • 167
    • 84869243128 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The choice of four periods is arbitrary, but this choice demonstrates how partial reversibility brings optimal policy choices closer to naïve expected-value maximization. Partial reversibility could also be denoted by imposing a significant switching cost on any change in policy. The two methods can be made mathematically equivalent, as the longevity of a policy that should be changed imposes a cost that is directly analogous to a high switching cost
    • The choice of four periods is arbitrary, but this choice demonstrates how partial reversibility brings optimal policy choices closer to naïve expected-value maximization. Partial reversibility could also be denoted by imposing a significant switching cost on any change in policy. The two methods can be made mathematically equivalent, as the longevity of a policy that should be changed imposes a cost that is directly analogous to a high switching cost.
  • 168
    • 62549116386 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As in Example 4, the true impact of Policy B can be learned without actually implementing Policy B.
    • As in Example 4, the true impact of Policy B can be learned without actually implementing Policy B.
  • 169
    • 62549162831 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Policy A, like Policy B, can only be changed after four periods in this example. Policy A has no variance in outcomes, so the delay is not caused by the time needed to observe the effects of Policy A. The delay could be caused by a delay in the ability to evaluate Policy B when Policy B is not being implemented. (Recall that the only reason to change Policy A under the real options approach is after Policy B has been proven effective.)
    • Policy A, like Policy B, can only be changed after four periods in this example. Policy A has no variance in outcomes, so the delay is not caused by the time needed to observe the effects of Policy A. The delay could be caused by a delay in the ability to evaluate Policy B when Policy B is not being implemented. (Recall that the only reason to change Policy A under the real options approach is after Policy B has been proven effective.)
  • 170
    • 62549112811 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This assumption is relaxed in later Sections
    • This assumption is relaxed in later Sections.
  • 171
    • 62549164975 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • U.S. CONST, art. V.
    • U.S. CONST, art. V.
  • 172
    • 59349094667 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Price of Public Action: Constitutional Doctrine and the Judicial Manipulation of Legislative Enactment Costs, 118
    • See
    • See Matthew C. Stephenson, The Price of Public Action: Constitutional Doctrine and the Judicial Manipulation of Legislative Enactment Costs, 118 YALE L.J. 2, 15-16 (2008).
    • (2008) YALE L.J , vol.2 , pp. 15-16
    • Stephenson, M.C.1
  • 173
    • 62549151079 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It should be acknowledged, of course, that even constitutional policymaking is not impossible to reverse. The Eighteenth Amendment implementing Prohibition can be seen as an innovative constitutional policy, there are compelling theoretical arguments in favor of Prohibition, that was judged a failure and then repealed. See U.S. CONST, amends. XVIII, XXI. The long lag between Prohibition and repeal, however, demonstrates the inertia of constitutional policymaking
    • It should be acknowledged, of course, that even constitutional policymaking is not impossible to reverse. The Eighteenth Amendment implementing Prohibition can be seen as an innovative constitutional policy - there are compelling theoretical arguments in favor of Prohibition - that was judged a failure and then repealed. See U.S. CONST, amends. XVIII, XXI. The long lag between Prohibition and repeal, however, demonstrates the inertia of constitutional policymaking.
  • 174
    • 84869247277 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I, § 7, cl. 2
    • U.S. CONST, art. I, § 7, cl. 2.
    • CONST, U.S.1    art2
  • 175
    • 62549084520 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Judges are policymakers in the sense that they create rules affecting future behavior. See Republican Party of Minn. v. White, 536 U.S. 765, 784 (2002) (noting the power of state judges to make common law).
    • Judges are policymakers in the sense that they create rules affecting future behavior. See Republican Party of Minn. v. White, 536 U.S. 765, 784 (2002) (noting the power of state judges to "make" common law).
  • 176
    • 62549160627 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Planned Parenthood of Se. Pa. v. Casey, 505 U.S. 833, 854-69 (1992).
    • See Planned Parenthood of Se. Pa. v. Casey, 505 U.S. 833, 854-69 (1992).
  • 177
    • 62549104441 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is not to say, however, that administrative agencies are inclined to change policies. Indeed, they may have incentives not to make frequent policy changes. These incentives will be examined in Part IV. See also JERRY L. MASHAW & DAVID L. HARFST, THE STRUGGLE FOR AUTO SAFETY 1990, discussing inertia in administrative agencies
    • This is not to say, however, that administrative agencies are inclined to change policies. Indeed, they may have incentives not to make frequent policy changes. These incentives will be examined in Part IV. See also JERRY L. MASHAW & DAVID L. HARFST, THE STRUGGLE FOR AUTO SAFETY (1990) (discussing inertia in administrative agencies).
  • 178
    • 84869247273 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Administrative Procedure Act of 1946, 5 U.S.C §§ 551-559 (2000).
    • Administrative Procedure Act of 1946, 5 U.S.C §§ 551-559 (2000).
  • 179
    • 84869247274 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Section 551 of the APA defines a rule as the whole or a part of an agency statement of general or particular applicability and future effect designed to implement, interpret, or prescribe law or policy. Id. § 551(4).
    • Section 551 of the APA defines a rule as "the whole or a part of an agency statement of general or particular applicability and future effect designed to implement, interpret, or prescribe law or policy." Id. § 551(4).
  • 180
    • 47249126847 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Anne Joseph O'Connell, Political Cycles of Rulemaking: An Empirical Portrait of the Modern Administrative State, 94 VA. L. REV. 889, 901-02 (2008) (providing a comprehensive description of notice-and-comment rulemaking).
    • See Anne Joseph O'Connell, Political Cycles of Rulemaking: An Empirical Portrait of the Modern Administrative State, 94 VA. L. REV. 889, 901-02 (2008) (providing a comprehensive description of notice-and-comment rulemaking).
  • 181
    • 62549100242 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Stephenson, supra note 143, at 15-16 (acknowledging that judicially imposed costs to the enactment of new legislation may lead to the prevention of socially desirable, constitutionally justifiable legislation if, for example, the judiciary has incomplete information).
    • See, e.g., Stephenson, supra note 143, at 15-16 (acknowledging that judicially imposed costs to the enactment of new legislation may lead to the prevention of "socially desirable, constitutionally justifiable legislation" if, for example, the judiciary has incomplete information).
  • 182
    • 62549104037 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Myers v. United States, 272 U.S. 52, 293 (1926) (Brandeis, J., dissenting) (recognizing that the separation of powers aims not to promote efficiency but to preclude the exercise of arbitrary power);
    • See, e.g., Myers v. United States, 272 U.S. 52, 293 (1926) (Brandeis, J., dissenting) (recognizing that the separation of powers aims "not to promote efficiency but to preclude the exercise of arbitrary power");
  • 183
    • 0041557883 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Most Dangerous Branch, 105
    • praising separation of powers but recognizing that it hinders action
    • Martin S. Flaherty, The Most Dangerous Branch, 105 YALE L.J. 1725, 1826-28 (1996) (praising separation of powers but recognizing that it hinders "action").
    • (1996) YALE L.J , vol.1725 , pp. 1826-1828
    • Flaherty, M.S.1
  • 184
    • 0041805374 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Legislative Entrenchment: A Reappraisal, 111
    • For an examination of legislative entrenchment doctrines, see
    • For an examination of legislative entrenchment doctrines, see Eric A Posner & Adrian Vermeule, Legislative Entrenchment: A Reappraisal, 111 YALE L.J. 1665, 1665-66 (2002).
    • (2002) YALE L.J , vol.1665 , pp. 1665-1666
    • Posner, E.A.1    Vermeule, A.2
  • 185
    • 62549159614 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Newton v. Comm'rs, 100 U.S. 548, 559 (1879);
    • See Newton v. Comm'rs, 100 U.S. 548, 559 (1879);
  • 187
    • 62549156460 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Posner & Vermeule, supra note 154, at 1667
    • Posner & Vermeule, supra note 154, at 1667.
  • 188
    • 62549109753 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1676
    • Id. at 1676.
  • 189
    • 62549102245 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1666
    • Id. at 1666.
  • 190
    • 62549139444 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 1670-73.
    • See id. at 1670-73.
  • 191
    • 62549103596 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1666
    • Id. at 1666.
  • 192
    • 62549113703 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See THE FEDERALIST NOS. 48, 51 (James Madison).
    • See THE FEDERALIST NOS. 48, 51 (James Madison).
  • 193
    • 62549144207 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The New Separation of Powers, 113
    • SEE Bruce Ackerman, The New Separation of Powers, 113 HARV. L. REV. 633, 650 (2000).
    • (2000) HARV. L. REV , vol.633 , pp. 650
    • Bruce Ackerman, S.1
  • 194
    • 62549116387 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See THE FEDERALIST NO. 47 (James Madison).
    • See THE FEDERALIST NO. 47 (James Madison).
  • 195
    • 62549143323 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Douglas W. Kmiec, Of Balkanized Empires and Cooperative Allies: A Bicentennial Essay on the Separation of Powers, 37 CATH. U. L. REV. 73, 75-76 (1987).
    • See Douglas W. Kmiec, Of Balkanized Empires and Cooperative Allies: A Bicentennial Essay on the Separation of Powers, 37 CATH. U. L. REV. 73, 75-76 (1987).
  • 196
    • 34547814457 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note 153 quoting Justice Brandeis
    • See, e.g., supra note 153 (quoting Justice Brandeis).
    • See, e.g., supra
  • 197
    • 33845526369 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Separation of Powers and the Criminal Law, 58
    • Rachel E. Barkow, Separation of Powers and the Criminal Law, 58 STAN. L. REV. 989, 991 (2006).
    • (2006) STAN. L. REV , vol.989 , pp. 991
    • Barkow, R.E.1
  • 198
    • 62549111968 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For an illuminating discussion of stare decisis, see RICHARD A. POSNER, THE FEDERAL COURTS: CHALLENGE AND REFORM 371-82 (1996).
    • For an illuminating discussion of stare decisis, see RICHARD A. POSNER, THE FEDERAL COURTS: CHALLENGE AND REFORM 371-82 (1996).
  • 199
    • 33745225920 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Rule of Law and the Law of Precedents, 90
    • For one recent discussion, see
    • For one recent discussion, see Daniel A. Farber, The Rule of Law and the Law of Precedents, 90 MINN. L. REV. 1173 (2006).
    • (2006) MINN. L. REV , vol.1173
    • Farber, D.A.1
  • 200
    • 62549116774 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Lewis F. Powell, Jr., Stare Decisis and Judicial Restraint, 47 WASH. & LEE L. REV. 281, 289-90 (1990).
    • Lewis F. Powell, Jr., Stare Decisis and Judicial Restraint, 47 WASH. & LEE L. REV. 281, 289-90 (1990).
  • 201
    • 62549108897 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • South Carolina v. Gathers, 490 U.S. 805, 825 (1989) (Scalia, J., dissenting).
    • South Carolina v. Gathers, 490 U.S. 805, 825 (1989) (Scalia, J., dissenting).
  • 202
    • 62549094190 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Judges can choose policies explicitly under the common law. See Republican Party of Minn. v. White, 536 U.S. 765, 784 (2002) (noting the power of state judges to make common law). When they are interpreting statutes, judges enjoy less discretion, as they are constrained by principles of statutory interpretation. Nevertheless, judges can choose interpretive methods to implement a variety of different outcomes when interpreting statutes.
    • Judges can choose policies explicitly under the common law. See Republican Party of Minn. v. White, 536 U.S. 765, 784 (2002) (noting the power of state judges to "make" common law). When they are interpreting statutes, judges enjoy less discretion, as they are constrained by principles of statutory interpretation. Nevertheless, judges can choose interpretive methods to implement a variety of different outcomes when interpreting statutes.
  • 203
    • 47349093151 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g, Alexander Volokh, Choosing Interpretive Methods: A Positive Theory of Judges and Everyone Else, 83 N.Y.U. L. REV. 769 2008, Thus, even when engaged in statutory interpretation, judges effectively choose policies to a certain degree, though they are constrained by principles of statutory interpretation
    • See, e.g., Alexander Volokh, Choosing Interpretive Methods: A Positive Theory of Judges and Everyone Else, 83 N.Y.U. L. REV. 769 (2008). Thus, even when engaged in statutory interpretation, judges effectively "choose" policies to a certain degree, though they are constrained by principles of statutory interpretation.
  • 204
    • 62549130529 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The discussion in this Part is influenced by Rose-Ackerman, supra note 108
    • The discussion in this Part is influenced by Rose-Ackerman, supra note 108.
  • 205
    • 34247837861 scopus 로고
    • Risktaking and Electoral Competition, 7 EUR
    • See
    • See Susan Rose-Ackerman, Risktaking and Electoral Competition, 7 EUR. J. POL. ECON. 527, 527 (1991).
    • (1991) J. POL. ECON , vol.527 , pp. 527
    • Rose-Ackerman, S.1
  • 206
    • 62549132890 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 207
    • 41249103497 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Race and Democratic Contestation, 117
    • arguing that competitive electoral districts are less important than creating conditions of democratic contestation
    • Cf Michael S. Kang, Race and Democratic Contestation, 117 YALE L.J. 734 (2008) (arguing that competitive electoral districts are less important than creating conditions of "democratic contestation").
    • (2008) YALE L.J , vol.734
    • Cf1    Michael, S.2    Kang3
  • 208
    • 0346786775 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • But see Samuel Issacharoff & Richard H. Pildes, Politics as Markets: Partisan Lockups of the Democratic Process, 50 STAN. L. REV. 643, 646 (1998) (Only through an appropriately competitive partisan environment can one of the central goals of democratic politics be realized: that the policy outcomes of the political process be responsive to the interests and views of citizens.).
    • But see Samuel Issacharoff & Richard H. Pildes, Politics as Markets: Partisan Lockups of the Democratic Process, 50 STAN. L. REV. 643, 646 (1998) ("Only through an appropriately competitive partisan environment can one of the central goals of democratic politics be realized: that the policy outcomes of the political process be responsive to the interests and views of citizens.").
  • 209
    • 62549131865 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a thorough examination of the effects of federalism on innovation from a positive political theory perspective, see Rose-Ackerman, supra note 108
    • For a thorough examination of the effects of federalism on innovation from a positive political theory perspective, see Rose-Ackerman, supra note 108.
  • 210
    • 84869253597 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • To see this point, consider two jurisdictions that face the choice between Policy A and Policy B of Example 2. Section II.A demonstrated that in a uni-jurisdictional world, the optimal search approach dictates that Policy B is the efficient choice. When there are two jurisdictions, the choice of innovation (Policy B) versus no innovation (Policy A) can be modeled as the following game: The value of $628 in the game modeled above comes from retaining Policy A in the first period and observing the outcome of Policy B in the other jurisdiction. If Policy B fails in the other jurisdiction, then continue with Policy A in the second period. If Policy B succeeds in the other jurisdiction and is observed, then switch to Policy B in the next period and enjoy the high upside of Policy B. In other words, one jurisdiction can free-ride off the other jurisdiction's experimentation with Policy B
    • To see this point, consider two jurisdictions that face the choice between Policy A and Policy B of Example 2. Section II.A demonstrated that in a uni-jurisdictional world, the optimal search approach dictates that Policy B is the efficient choice. When there are two jurisdictions, the choice of innovation (Policy B) versus no innovation (Policy A) can be modeled as the following game: The value of $628 in the game modeled above comes from retaining Policy A in the first period and observing the outcome of Policy B in the other jurisdiction. If Policy B fails in the other jurisdiction, then continue with Policy A in the second period. If Policy B succeeds in the other jurisdiction (and is observed), then switch to Policy B in the next period and enjoy the high upside of Policy B. In other words, one jurisdiction can free-ride off the other jurisdiction's experimentation with Policy B.
  • 211
    • 62549152916 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • There is no pure strategy Nash Equilibrium to this game and therefore no unique solution. See, e.g, ANDREU MAS-COLELL, MICHAEL D. WHINSTON & JERRY R. GREEN, MICROECONOMIC THEORY 248-50 1995, Choosing either policy is a rationalizable strategy for both jurisdictions, however. Therefore, we can make no definitive predictions about whether there will be innovation in this simple multi-jurisdictional world. The unijurisdictional world, by contrast, provides innovation using the optimal search approach. In this example, federalism can decrease innovation, but cannot increase it. When innovation is less attractive in the uni-jurisdictional world, however, there can be cases where federalism produces more innovation than does the optimal search approach
    • There is no pure strategy Nash Equilibrium to this game and therefore no unique solution. See, e.g., ANDREU MAS-COLELL, MICHAEL D. WHINSTON & JERRY R. GREEN, MICROECONOMIC THEORY 248-50 (1995). Choosing either policy is a rationalizable strategy for both jurisdictions, however. Therefore, we can make no definitive predictions about whether there will be innovation in this simple multi-jurisdictional world. The unijurisdictional world, by contrast, provides innovation using the optimal search approach. In this example, federalism can decrease innovation, but cannot increase it. When innovation is less attractive in the uni-jurisdictional world, however, there can be cases where federalism produces more innovation than does the optimal search approach.
  • 212
    • 21844507244 scopus 로고
    • Corporations, Corporate Law, and Networks of Contracts, 81
    • See
    • See Michael Klausner, Corporations, Corporate Law, and Networks of Contracts, 81 VA. L. REV. 757, 764 (1995).
    • (1995) VA. L. REV , vol.757 , pp. 764
    • Klausner, M.1
  • 213
    • 62549114696 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Corporate law has a longstanding debate about whether state competition for corporate charters entails a race to the bottom or a race to the top. For important contributions to this literature, see supra note 73
    • Corporate law has a longstanding debate about whether state competition for corporate charters entails a race to the bottom or a race to the top. For important contributions to this literature, see supra note 73.
  • 214
    • 62549127548 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Kahneman et al, supra note 132
    • See Kahneman et al., supra note 132.
  • 215
    • 15544377384 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note, however, that there have been several examples of regulatory bodies running innovative policy experiments, such as the Moving to Opportunity experiment, see Jeffrey R. Kling, Jens Ludwig & Lawrence F. Katz, Neighborhood Effects on Crime for Female and Male Youth: Evidence from a Randomized Housing Voucher Experiment, 120 Q.J. ECON. 87 (2005), and the SECs pilot order restricting short sales of certain securities,
    • Note, however, that there have been several examples of regulatory bodies running innovative policy experiments, such as the Moving to Opportunity experiment, see Jeffrey R. Kling, Jens Ludwig & Lawrence F. Katz, Neighborhood Effects on Crime for Female and Male Youth: Evidence from a Randomized Housing Voucher Experiment, 120 Q.J. ECON. 87 (2005), and the SECs pilot order restricting short sales of certain securities,
  • 216
    • 62549130089 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see Order Extending Term of Short Sale Pilot, Exchange Act Release No. 53,684, 71 Fed. Reg. 24,765 (Apr. 20, 2006).
    • see Order Extending Term of Short Sale Pilot, Exchange Act Release No. 53,684, 71 Fed. Reg. 24,765 (Apr. 20, 2006).
  • 217
    • 42549157941 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For example, Judge Baron Alderson gained considerable notoriety for instituting an information-forcing default rule in Hadley v. Baxendale. An interesting avenue for future research would be to compare life-appointed judges with elected judges to determine whether electoral incentives promote innovation through variation in private law rulemaking. One might hypothesize that life-appointed judges, removed from electoral pressures to avoid negative-expected-value common law rules, are more willing to enact new legal doctrines with high variance. See David E. Pozen, The Irony of Judicial Elections, 108 COLUM. L. REV. 265, 324-28 2008, describing scholarly support for elected judges' more innovative or activist approaches and noting that state courts' common-law lawmaking powers are broadly respected and [their] decisions are relatively easily reversed through constitutional amendment or legislative action, I thank William J. Rinner for
    • For example, Judge Baron Alderson gained considerable notoriety for instituting an information-forcing default rule in Hadley v. Baxendale. An interesting avenue for future research would be to compare life-appointed judges with elected judges to determine whether electoral incentives promote innovation through variation in private law rulemaking. One might hypothesize that life-appointed judges, removed from electoral pressures to avoid negative-expected-value common law rules, are more willing to enact new legal doctrines with high variance. See David E. Pozen, The Irony of Judicial Elections, 108 COLUM. L. REV. 265, 324-28 (2008) (describing scholarly support for elected judges' more innovative or activist approaches and noting that state courts' "common-law lawmaking powers are broadly respected and [their] decisions are relatively easily reversed through constitutional amendment or legislative action"). I thank William J. Rinner for raising this point.
  • 218
    • 62549156461 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Gratter v. Bollinger, 539 U.S. 306 (2003). In Grutter, the Court noted that it expect[s] that 25 years from now, the use of racial preferences will no longer be necessary to further the interest approved today.
    • See Gratter v. Bollinger, 539 U.S. 306 (2003). In Grutter, the Court noted that it "expect[s] that 25 years from now, the use of racial preferences will no longer be necessary to further the interest approved today."
  • 219
    • 62549103171 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 343
    • Id. at 343.
  • 220
    • 62549097520 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • One concern, of course, is that differences between nations are so great that one cannot infer the effects of a variation in Country X will be similar to the effects of the same variation in Country
    • Note how international differences can also serve to produce useful variation in laws
    • Note how international differences can also serve to produce useful variation in laws. One concern, of course, is that differences between nations are so great that one cannot infer the effects of a variation in Country X will be similar to the effects of the same variation in Country Y.
    • Y
  • 221
    • 33846023671 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Sourafel Girma, Steve Thompson & Peter W. Wright, Corporate Governance Reforms and Executive Compensation Determination: Evidence from the UK, 75 MANCHESTER SCH. 65, 66-67 n.5 (2007).
    • See Sourafel Girma, Steve Thompson & Peter W. Wright, Corporate Governance Reforms and Executive Compensation Determination: Evidence from the UK, 75 MANCHESTER SCH. 65, 66-67 n.5 (2007).
  • 222
    • 62549128875 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Roei C. Campos, Comm'r, SEC, Speech by SEC Commissioner: The SECs Shareholder Access Proposal (Jan. 10, 2005) (transcript available at http://www.sec.gov/news/speech/spch011005rcc.htm) (Based on these considerations, I believe that the [shareholder access] rule is fully within our authority. I am not alone in my view. Several academics have expressed support for the SECs authority to adopt the proxy access rule.).
    • See Roei C. Campos, Comm'r, SEC, Speech by SEC Commissioner: The SECs Shareholder Access Proposal (Jan. 10, 2005) (transcript available at http://www.sec.gov/news/speech/spch011005rcc.htm) ("Based on these considerations, I believe that the [shareholder access] rule is fully within our authority. I am not alone in my view. Several academics have expressed support for the SECs authority to adopt the proxy access rule.").
  • 223
    • 62549160626 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • But see Bus. Roundtable v. SEC, 905 F.2d 406 (D.C Cir. 1990) (suggesting limitations on the SECs power to regulate substantive aspects of corporate voting).
    • But see Bus. Roundtable v. SEC, 905 F.2d 406 (D.C Cir. 1990) (suggesting limitations on the SECs power to regulate substantive aspects of corporate voting).
  • 224
    • 62549157597 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The SEC received over thirty-four thousand comments on the issue. See Nazareth Speech, supra note 100
    • The SEC received over thirty-four thousand comments on the issue. See Nazareth Speech, supra note 100.
  • 225
    • 62549104442 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Broc Romanek, SEC Quickly Adopts Non-Shareholder Access Rule - Then Fireworks Ensue, TheCorporateCounsel.net Blog, Nov. 29, 2007, http://www.thecorporatecounsel.ner/blog/archive/oo1638.html (The real fireworks began right after the meeting, when all sorts of investor groups, members of Congress, etc. issued statements disapproving the SECs rulemaking (eg. CalPERS; CII; RiskMetrics; AFL-CIO; Rep. Frank; Sen. Dodd) - and some approved (eg. Marty Lipton). It's notable that the opposition is fairly organized on this issue; I can't imagine something like this happening even five years ago.).
    • See, e.g., Broc Romanek, SEC Quickly Adopts Non-Shareholder Access Rule - Then Fireworks Ensue, TheCorporateCounsel.net Blog, Nov. 29, 2007, http://www.thecorporatecounsel.ner/blog/archive/oo1638.html ("The real fireworks began right after the meeting, when all sorts of investor groups, members of Congress, etc. issued statements disapproving the SECs rulemaking (eg. CalPERS; CII; RiskMetrics; AFL-CIO; Rep. Frank; Sen. Dodd) - and some approved (eg. Marty Lipton). It's notable that the opposition is fairly organized on this issue; I can't imagine something like this happening even five years ago.").
  • 226
    • 62549137212 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Rose-Ackerman, supra note 108, at 594
    • See Rose-Ackerman, supra note 108, at 594.
  • 227
    • 62549111969 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 615-16.
    • See id. at 615-16.
  • 228
    • 62549105104 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 616.
    • See id. at 616.
  • 229
    • 62549108447 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • While random assignment may appear draconian, note that the SEC has randomly assigned corporations to different short-sale restriction regimes. See Order Extending Term of Short Sale Pilot, Exchange Act Release No. 53,684, 71 Fed. Reg. 24,765 (Apr. 20, 2006);
    • While random assignment may appear draconian, note that the SEC has randomly assigned corporations to different short-sale restriction regimes. See Order Extending Term of Short Sale Pilot, Exchange Act Release No. 53,684, 71 Fed. Reg. 24,765 (Apr. 20, 2006);
  • 230
    • 62549159615 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SEC OFFICE OF ECON. ANALYSIS, ECONOMIC ANALYSIS OF THE SHORT SALE PRICE RESTRICTIONS UNDER THE REGULATION SHO PILOT (2007), http://www.sec.gov/news/studies/2007/ regshopiloto20607.pdf.
    • SEC OFFICE OF ECON. ANALYSIS, ECONOMIC ANALYSIS OF THE SHORT SALE PRICE RESTRICTIONS UNDER THE REGULATION SHO PILOT (2007), http://www.sec.gov/news/studies/2007/ regshopiloto20607.pdf.
  • 231
    • 62549088954 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, Sept., unpublished manuscript, on file with author
    • See Ian Ayres & Yair Listokin, Randomizing Law (Sept. 2008) (unpublished manuscript, on file with author).
    • (2008)
    • Ayres, I.1    Listokin, Y.2    Law, R.3


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.