-
1
-
-
0001691297
-
autonomy has been the focus of intense interest in the literature on free will and determinism
-
Representative examples include
-
And autonomy has been the focus of intense interest in the literature on free will and determinism. Representative examples include Gary Watson, "Free Agency," Journal of Philosophy 72 (1975): 205-20
-
(1975)
Free Agency, Journal of Philosophy
, vol.72
, pp. 205-220
-
-
Watson, G.1
-
2
-
-
0009282256
-
Understanding Free Will
-
Michael Slote, "Understanding Free Will," Journal of Philosophy 77 (1980): 136-51
-
(1980)
Journal of Philosophy
, vol.77
, pp. 136-151
-
-
Slote, M.1
-
3
-
-
0002296027
-
Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person
-
and Harry Frankfurt, "Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person," Journal of Philosophy 68 (1971): 5-20
-
(1971)
Journal of Philosophy
, vol.68
, pp. 5-20
-
-
Frankfurt, H.1
-
4
-
-
79955192842
-
Plea-Bargaining, Constraining Options, and Respect for Autonomy
-
July
-
See for example James Stacey Taylor, "Plea-Bargaining, Constraining Options, and Respect for Autonomy," Public Affairs Quarterly 18, no. 3 (July 2004): 249-64
-
(2004)
Public Affairs Quarterly
, vol.18
, Issue.3
, pp. 249-264
-
-
Taylor, J.S.1
-
5
-
-
79955198968
-
Proactive Law Enforcement, Ambivalence, and Autonomy
-
Paul M. Hughes, "Proactive Law Enforcement, Ambivalence, and Autonomy," Public Affairs Quarterly 19, no. 2 (2005): 127-41
-
(2005)
Public Affairs Quarterly
, vol.19
, Issue.2
, pp. 127-141
-
-
Hughes, P.M.1
-
6
-
-
60949367315
-
What is wrong with entrapment?
-
Paul M. Hughes, "What is wrong with entrapment?" The Southern Journal of Philosophy 42, no. 1 (2004): 45-60
-
(2004)
The Southern Journal of Philosophy
, vol.42
, Issue.1
, pp. 45-60
-
-
Hughes, P.M.1
-
8
-
-
11244344594
-
Markets and Morals: The Case for Organ Sales
-
ed. Gerald Dworkin Westview
-
See Gerald Dworkin, "Markets and Morals: The Case for Organ Sales," in Morality, Harm, and the Law, ed. Gerald Dworkin (Westview, 1994), 155-61
-
(1994)
Morality, Harm, and the Law
, pp. 155-161
-
-
Dworkin, G.1
-
9
-
-
0032023794
-
Exploitation, Autonomy and the Case for Organ Sales
-
Paul M. Hughes, "Exploitation, Autonomy and the Case for Organ Sales," International Journal of Applied Philosophy 12, no. 1 (1998): 89-97
-
(1998)
International Journal of Applied Philosophy
, vol.12
, Issue.1
, pp. 89-97
-
-
Hughes, P.M.1
-
10
-
-
0038681860
-
Autonomy, Constraining Options, and Organ Sales
-
James Stacey Taylor, "Autonomy, Constraining Options, and Organ Sales," Journal of Applied Philosophy 19, no. 3 (2002): 273-85
-
(2002)
Journal of Applied Philosophy
, vol.19
, Issue.3
, pp. 273-285
-
-
Taylor, J.S.1
-
15
-
-
33644681362
-
The Faintest Passion
-
Cambridge University Press
-
Frankfurt, "The Faintest Passion," in Necessity, Volition, and Love (Cambridge University Press, 1999), 99
-
(1999)
Necessity, Volition, and Love
, pp. 99
-
-
Frankfurt1
-
16
-
-
79955244669
-
Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person
-
For a good sample of his contribution to the literature on hierarchical views of autonomy see Frankfurt, "Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person"; "Alternate Possibilities and Moral Responsibility," Journal of Philosophy 66 (1969): 828-39
-
(1969)
Alternate Possibilities and Moral Responsibility, Journal of Philosophy
, vol.66
, pp. 828-839
-
-
-
17
-
-
0001862709
-
Identification and Wholeheartedness
-
ed, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
"Identification and Wholeheartedness," in Responsibility, Character, and the Emotions, ed. Ferdinand Schoeman (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1987), 27-45
-
(1987)
Responsibility, Character, and the Emotions
, pp. 27-45
-
-
-
18
-
-
84927120936
-
Making Do: Troubling Stoic Tendencies in an Otherwise Compelling Theory of Autonomy
-
March
-
David Zimmerman, "Making Do: Troubling Stoic Tendencies in an Otherwise Compelling Theory of Autonomy," Canadian Journal of Philosophy 30 (March 2000): 26
-
(2000)
Canadian Journal of Philosophy
, vol.30
, pp. 26
-
-
Zimmerman, D.1
-
19
-
-
70349589705
-
real-self accounts (of autonomy) are promising because they match well our intuitions concerning the nature and appropriate ascription of moral responsibility (Lippert-Rasmussen
-
agrees with Zimmerman when he writes, generally speaking But note that Watson in Free Agency argues that Frankfurt's talk of whole-hearted identification with second-order desires as a condition of autonomy is weak. Lippert-Rasmussen argues that Watson's view suffers from a comparable weakness of its own
-
Kasper Lippert-Rasmussen agrees with Zimmerman when he writes, "generally speaking, real-self accounts (of autonomy) are promising because they match well our intuitions concerning the nature and appropriate ascription of moral responsibility" (Lippert-Rasmussen, "Identification and Responsibility," Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 6, no. 4 (2003): 349-76). But note that Watson in "Free Agency" argues that Frankfurt's talk of "whole-hearted" identification with second-order desires as a condition of autonomy is weak. Lippert-Rasmussen argues that Watson's view suffers from a comparable weakness of its own
-
(2003)
Identification and Responsibility, Ethical Theory and Moral Practice
, vol.6
, Issue.4
, pp. 349-376
-
-
Lippert-Rasmussen, K.1
-
21
-
-
79954073234
-
-
second edition
-
Oxford English Dictionary, second edition, 17 (1989): 759
-
(1989)
Oxford English Dictionary
, vol.17
, pp. 759
-
-
-
22
-
-
34548690782
-
The Logic of Temptation
-
Temptations may be nonmoral, as when one is tempted to have another cup of coffee, or stay up late and watch a movie. Even in these cases, however, people typically regard what they are tempted to do as in some way inappropriate, even if not morally inappropriate. Of course, there are uses of the term temptation in which nothing inappropriate is connoted, and instances of temptation in which the act or object of temptation is regarded as right or good. My description of the psychology of being tempted as typically desiring what one regards as in some sense evil or wrong is offered as a partial account of temptation in its main moral sense. For more on this view of temptation
-
Temptations may be nonmoral, as when one is tempted to have another cup of coffee, or stay up late and watch a movie. Even in these cases, however, people typically regard what they are tempted to do as in some way inappropriate, even if not morally inappropriate. Of course, there are uses of the term temptation in which nothing inappropriate is connoted, and instances of temptation in which the act or object of temptation is regarded as right or good. My description of the psychology of being tempted as typically desiring what one regards as in some sense evil or wrong is offered as a partial account of temptation in its main moral sense. For more on this view of temptation see Paul M. Hughes, "The Logic of Temptation," Philosophia 29 (2002): 89-110
-
(2002)
Philosophia
, vol.29
, pp. 89-110
-
-
Hughes, P.M.1
-
23
-
-
0033196268
-
Temptation and the Manipulation of Desire
-
and Paul M. Hughes, "Temptation and the Manipulation of Desire," The Journal of Value Inquiry 33 (1999): 371-79
-
(1999)
The Journal of Value Inquiry
, vol.33
, pp. 371-379
-
-
Hughes, P.M.1
-
26
-
-
0012949522
-
-
See Wilkinson, Bodies for Sale, chapter 5, for a detailed analysis and discussion of some of the invalid consent arguments that invoke one or more of these claims
-
Bodies for Sale
-
-
Wilkinson1
-
27
-
-
0009233715
-
Temptation
-
This point is made in various ways in recent literature on temptation
-
This point is made in various ways in recent literature on temptation. See J. P. Day, "Temptation," American Philosophical Quarterly 30, no. 2 (1993): 175-83
-
(1993)
American Philosophical Quarterly
, vol.30
, Issue.2
, pp. 175-183
-
-
Day, J.P.1
-
28
-
-
33645939429
-
The Mathematical Pull of Temptation
-
Joseph Fulda, "The Mathematical Pull of Temptation," Mind 101, no. 402 (1992): 305-07
-
(1992)
Mind
, vol.101
, Issue.402
, pp. 305-307
-
-
Fulda, J.1
|