메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 30, Issue 1, 2000, Pages 25-53

Making do: Troubling stoic tendencies in an otherwise compelling theory of autonomy

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 84927120936     PISSN: 00455091     EISSN: 19110820     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1080/00455091.2000.10717524     Document Type: Note
Times cited : (16)

References (23)
  • 1
    • 0009280816 scopus 로고
    • Alternate Possibilities and Moral Responsibility
    • Frankfurt. 1969. ‘Alternate Possibilities and Moral Responsibility,’. Journal of Philosophy, 66: 828–39.
    • (1969) Journal of Philosophy , vol.66 , pp. 828-839
    • Frankfurt1
  • 2
    • 0002296027 scopus 로고
    • Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person
    • Frankfurt. 1971. ‘Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person,’. Journal of Philosophy, 68: 5–20.
    • (1971) Journal of Philosophy , vol.68 , pp. 5-20
    • Frankfurt1
  • 3
    • 0001862709 scopus 로고
    • ‘Identification and Wholeheartedness,’ in
    • Schoeman F., (ed), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,. Edited by
    • Frankfurt. 1987. “ ‘Identification and Wholeheartedness,’ in ”. In Responsibility, Character and the Emotions Edited by: Schoeman, F., 27–45. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
    • (1987) Responsibility, Character and the Emotions , pp. 27-45
    • Frankfurt1
  • 4
    • 79954746257 scopus 로고
    • Free Agency
    • Some philosophers worry that Frankfurt does not include enough the ‘motivational mesh’ which grounds autonomy ([] 316–39; C. Taylor, ‘Human Agency,’ T. Mischel, The Self [Oxford: Blackwell 1977] 103–35; S. Wolf, Freedom within Reason [Oxford: Oxford University Press 1990]). Others worry that no such mesh, however supplemented by further structural conditions, can do the job without help from historical constraints on desire-acquisition (M. Slote, ‘Understanding Free Will,’ Journal of Philosophy78 [1980] 136–51; J.M. Fischer and M. Ravizza, Responsibility and Control [Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 1998]; A. Mele, Autonomous Agents [Oxford: Oxford University Press 1995]). I take up the first objection ‘Hierarchical Motivation and Freedom of the Will,’ Pacific Philosophical Quarterly62 (1981) and the second ‘Doing and Time: Psychological Structure vs Personal History Compatibilist Theories of Autonomy,’ forthcoming
    • Watson, G., 1977. ‘Free Agency,’. Journal of Philosophy, 75: 254–368. Some philosophers worry that Frankfurt does not include enough in the ‘motivational mesh’ which grounds autonomy ([] 316–39; C. Taylor, ‘Human Agency,’ in T. Mischel, The Self [Oxford: Blackwell 1977] 103–35; S. Wolf, Freedom within Reason [Oxford: Oxford University Press 1990]). Others worry that no such mesh, however supplemented by further structural conditions, can do the job without help from historical constraints on desire-acquisition (M. Slote, ‘Understanding Free Will,’ Journal of Philosophy78 [1980] 136–51; J.M. Fischer and M. Ravizza, Responsibility and Control [Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 1998]; A. Mele, Autonomous Agents [Oxford: Oxford University Press 1995]). I take up the first objection in ‘Hierarchical Motivation and Freedom of the Will,’ Pacific Philosophical Quarterly62 (1981) and the second in ‘Doing and Time: Psychological Structure vs Personal History in Compatibilist Theories of Autonomy,’ forthcoming.
    • (1977) Journal of Philosophy , vol.75 , pp. 254-368
    • Watson, G.1
  • 5
    • 0004141126 scopus 로고
    • Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, Cited Evidently, this idea was espoused only by the later Stoics of the imperial period. On the relevant differences within the Stoic tradition, see Julia Annas, The Morality of Happiness (Oxford: Oxford University Press 1993), 174–5,307; also Martha Nussbaum, The Therapy of Desire (Princeton: Princeton University Press 1994), 11, 339, 353, 361, 363, 395. Moreover, it seems that not even Seneca, an important later Stoic, consistently downgraded the importance of worldly misfortune. Nussbaum cites a rather different sentiment from the one the text: ‘There is no time for playing around…. You who have promised to bring help to the shipwrecked, the imprisoned, the needy, to those whose heads are under the poised axe. Where are you deflecting your attention? What are you doing?’ (317) She cites several other passages from Seneca which further mitigate the awfulness of the sentiment quoted the text (325, 342
    • Williams, B., 1993. Shame and Necessity 115Berkeley, CA: University of California Press. Cited in Evidently, this idea was espoused only by the later Stoics of the imperial period. On the relevant differences within the Stoic tradition, see Julia Annas, The Morality of Happiness (Oxford: Oxford University Press 1993), 174–5,307; also Martha Nussbaum, The Therapy of Desire (Princeton: Princeton University Press 1994), 11, 339, 353, 361, 363, 395. Moreover, it seems that not even Seneca, an important later Stoic, consistently downgraded the importance of worldly misfortune. Nussbaum cites a rather different sentiment from the one in the text: ‘There is no time for playing around…. You who have promised to bring help to the shipwrecked, the imprisoned, the needy, to those whose heads are under the poised axe. Where are you deflecting your attention? What are you doing?’ (317) She cites several other passages from Seneca which further mitigate the awfulness of the sentiment quoted in the text (325, 342).
    • (1993) Shame and Necessity , pp. 115
    • Williams, B.1
  • 6
    • 0001649911 scopus 로고
    • Three Concepts of Free Action
    • Supplementary Volume at 124, emphasis added
    • Frankfurt. 1975. “ ‘Three Concepts of Free Action,’ ”. In Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 113–25. Supplementary Volume at 124, emphasis added
    • (1975) Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society , pp. 113-125
    • Frankfurt1
  • 7
    • 85063699853 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • fact, I have posed the Stoic thesis Frankfurts own language, for the distinction between is one of the cornerstones of his theory. He famously insists that ‘the principle of alternate possibilities,’ which is associated with the first (‘Alternate Possibilities and Moral Responsibility’) is not a condition for moral responsibility, which involves only the second (‘Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person’
    • In fact, I have posed the Stoic thesis in Frankfurt's own language, for the distinction between freedom of action acting freely is one of the cornerstones of his theory. He famously insists that ‘the principle of alternate possibilities,’ which is associated with the first (‘Alternate Possibilities and Moral Responsibility’) is not a condition for moral responsibility, which involves only the second (‘Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person’).
    • Freedom of action acting freelynot
  • 9
    • 0003613516 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press, I am not the first to take Frankfurts theory to be committed to the Stoic idea that a free will can flourish the inner citadel. fact, a recent collection of essays on hierarchical motivation theories has precisely this title. (See J. Christman,].) Annette Baier also writes that developing her own views she has ‘departed from both Spinoza and Frankfurt… rejecting the thoroughgoing fatalism which collapses the actual into the necessary, and the normatively demanded into the one thing possible, at all levels of reflectiveness’ (Baier, ‘Comments on Frankfurt,’ Synthese53 (1982), 288–289), a decidedly late Stoic reading of both of them
    • 1989. The Inner Citadel: Essays on Individual Autonomy Oxford: Oxford University Press. I am not the first to take Frankfurt's theory to be committed to the Stoic idea that a free will can flourish in the inner citadel. In fact, a recent collection of essays on hierarchical motivation theories has precisely this title. (See J. Christman,].) Annette Baier also writes that in developing her own views she has ‘departed from both Spinoza and Frankfurt… in rejecting the thoroughgoing fatalism which collapses the actual into the necessary, and the normatively demanded into the one thing possible, at all levels of reflectiveness’ (Baier, ‘Comments on Frankfurt,’ Synthese53 (1982), 288–289), a decidedly late Stoic reading of both of them.
    • (1989) The Inner Citadel: Essays on Individual Autonomy
  • 10
    • 0009204690 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press, Whether hierarchical motivation theories should incorporate some kind of historical condition is a large and vexed issue which is too complex to tackle here. (For some of the relevant literature, see note 4.) Suffice it to say that Frankfurt has hitherto been reluctant to take this step for reasons which are not entirely clear. He may share the suspicion of some philosophers (R. Double,], 56–61) that it is harder, perhaps even impossible, to defend a compatibilist version of a hierarchical motivation theory which makes a serious concession to history. However, other philosophers argue that this is not a good reason to resist history, because compatibilism has the resources to tame it. (See, for example, Mele, 158–9.) However that may be, Frankfurt should not resist the version of the restricted PAP defended the text, because it is an historical condition a very weak sense which falls far short of any of the historical constraints on preference-acquisition which he rejects. Like his unsupplemented hierarchical theory, it places the principal emphasis on what an agent who has been manipulated the past does now at time t+1 to deal with it and why he strives for wholehearted identification now. I clarify the dispute between structuralists and historicists about autonomy and what it would take to resolve it ‘Doing and Time.’
    • 1991. The Non-Reality of Free Will Oxford: Oxford University Press. Whether hierarchical motivation theories should incorporate some kind of historical condition is a large and vexed issue which is too complex to tackle here. (For some of the relevant literature, see note 4.) Suffice it to say that Frankfurt has hitherto been reluctant to take this step for reasons which are not entirely clear. He may share the suspicion of some philosophers (R. Double,], 56–61) that it is harder, perhaps even impossible, to defend a compatibilist version of a hierarchical motivation theory which makes a serious concession to history. However, other philosophers argue that this is not a good reason to resist history, because compatibilism has the resources to tame it. (See, for example, Mele, 158–9.) However that may be, Frankfurt should not resist the version of the restricted PAP defended in the text, because it is an historical condition in a very weak sense which falls far short of any of the historical constraints on preference-acquisition which he rejects. Like his unsupplemented hierarchical theory, it places the principal emphasis on what an agent who has been manipulated in the past does now at time t+1 to deal with it and why he strives for wholehearted identification now. I clarify the dispute between structuralists and historicists about autonomy and what it would take to resolve it in ‘Doing and Time.’
    • (1991) The Non-Reality of Free Will
  • 12
    • 85063703633 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Fischers condition is quite acceptable, with whatever qualifications are necessary to deal with unintentional action, which, is, action proper. If I unintentionally shoot you, mistaking you for a deer the underbrush, I have shot you, not merely made some movements. Thus, some pro-attitude or volition will enter into the causal provenance of my action even though specification of its content will not make essential reference to ‘my shooting you’ but rather (say) to ‘my shooting the deer making that rumpus the underbrush.’
    • Fischer's condition is quite acceptable, with whatever qualifications are necessary to deal with unintentional action, which is action proper. If I unintentionally shoot you, mistaking you for a deer in the underbrush, I have shot you, not merely made some movements. Thus, some pro-attitude or volition will enter into the causal provenance of my action even though specification of its content will not make essential reference to ‘my shooting you’ but rather (say) to ‘my shooting the deer making that rumpus in the underbrush.’
  • 13
    • 85063702319 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I include this observation to allay a worry registered by an anonymous referee for the
    • Canadian Journal of Philosophy. I include this observation to allay a worry registered by an anonymous referee for the
    • Canadian Journal of Philosophy.
  • 14
    • 85063698196 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I pursue this theme greater detail ‘Tie Me Up, Tie Me Down: The Freedom and Unfreedom of Person-Parametric Decisions,’ forthcoming. See especially the case of ‘Pran.’
    • I pursue this theme in greater detail in ‘Tie Me Up, Tie Me Down: The Freedom and Unfreedom of Person-Parametric Decisions,’ forthcoming. See especially the case of ‘Pran.’
  • 15
    • 85063697619 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Alan Wertheimer defends an account of duress as justification his (Princeton: Princeton University Press 1987), 166–9
    • Coercion Alan Wertheimer defends an account of duress as justification in his (Princeton: Princeton University Press 1987), 166–9.
    • Coercion
  • 16
    • 85063698100 scopus 로고
    • Kill the welshing bastard or I'll break both your arms and legs… slowly.’) It is perfectly compatible with a first-order account that it require that P coerces Q in a responsibility-relieving way only if Q is morally permitted to comply with the terms of P's threat. This neither reduces the non-blameworthiness of coerced actions to justification nor departs from the main line of a first-order account of the distinctly excusing force of compliance to some harsh, credible threats. (I include this observation to allay the worries of an anonymous referee for the Canadian journal of Philosophy.) For appropriately detailed accounts of first-order theories of coercion, see R. Nozick, ‘Coercion
    • in, S., Morgenbesser, et al., eds
    • 1969. I emphasize that the sketch offered in the text is just that, merely a sketch. There are many complications in a purely first-order analysis of the excusing force of compliance with coercion which we cannot consider here. However, to blunt one immediate source of concern, I will note that such an account does not entail that harsh, credible threats always relieve the recipient of moral responsibility for complying. For example, I would have a hard time getting anyone to excuse my having killed a man who reneged on his debt to a loan shark by explaining that I did it solely because Sammy the Bull threatened me with serious harm if I did not comply. (Suppose he carefully explained to me something like: ‘Kill the welshing bastard or I'll break both your arms and legs… slowly.’) It is perfectly compatible with a first-order account that it require that P coerces Q in a responsibility-relieving way only if Q is morally permitted to comply with the terms of P's threat. This neither reduces the non-blameworthiness of coerced actions to justification nor departs from the main line of a first-order account of the distinctly excusing force of compliance to some harsh, credible threats. (I include this observation to allay the worries of an anonymous referee for the Canadian journal of Philosophy.) For appropriately detailed accounts of first-order theories of coercion, see R. Nozick, ‘Coercion,’ in S. Morgenbesser et al., eds., Philosophy, Science and Method (New York: St. Martin's J. Feinberg, Harm to Self (Oxford: Oxford University Press 1986); and D. Zimmerman, ‘Coercive Wage Offers,’ Philosophy and Public Affairs10 (1981) 121–45.
    • (1981) Philosophy, Science and Method (New York: St. Martin's J. Feinberg, Harm to Self (Oxford: Oxford University Press 1986); and D. Zimmerman, ‘Coercive Wage Offers,’ Philosophy and Public Affairs 10 , pp. 121-145
  • 17
    • 85063697765 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Frankfurt cites Dworkins ‘suggestive discussion of these issues’ (in ‘Coercion and Moral Responsibility,’ note 16), but doing so mistakenly runs together two different ideas: 1) not wanting to be a situation which one is forced to act on a certain first-order desire, and 2) having a second-order desire not to have a certain first-order desire. Dworkins account of acting unfreely makes reference only to 1), whereas Frankfurts central condition for non-autonomy also involves 2
    • Frankfurt cites Dworkin's ‘suggestive discussion of these issues’ (in ‘Coercion and Moral Responsibility,’ note 16), but in doing so mistakenly runs together two different ideas: 1) not wanting to be in a situation in which one is forced to act on a certain first-order desire, and 2) having a second-order desire not to have a certain first-order desire. Dworkin's account of acting unfreely makes reference only to 1), whereas Frankfurt's central condition for non-autonomy also involves 2).
  • 18
    • 85063697784 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I offer such an account ‘Coercive Wage Offers.’
    • I offer such an account in ‘Coercive Wage Offers.’
  • 19
    • 0003599888 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press, (and Freedom and Reason (Oxford: Oxford University Press 1963); A. Gewirth, Reason and Morality (Chicago: University of Chicago Press 1978
    • Hare, R. M., 1952. The Language of Morals Oxford: Oxford University Press. (and Freedom and Reason (Oxford: Oxford University Press 1963); A. Gewirth, Reason and Morality (Chicago: University of Chicago Press 1978)
    • (1952) The Language of Morals
    • Hare, R.M.1
  • 20
    • 0003599888 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press, (and Freedom and Reason (Oxford: Oxford University Press 1963); A. Gewirth, Reason and Morality (Chicago: University of Chicago Press 1978
    • Here, R. M., 1952. The Language of Morals Oxford: Oxford University Press. (and Freedom and Reason (Oxford: Oxford University Press 1963); A. Gewirth, Reason and Morality (Chicago: University of Chicago Press 1978)
    • (1952) The Language of Morals
    • Here, R.M.1
  • 21
    • 85063698109 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • To be sure, the Stoic vision of liberation from coercion is not thereby shown to be incoherent on its own; for that we also need at least the hierarchical theory of the unfreedom of coerced action. But they were made for each other; in fact, since the latter entails the former, the existence of the paradoxes also entails the incoherence of this aspect of Stoicism, a result to be applauded.
    • To be sure, the Stoic vision of liberation from coercion is not thereby shown to be incoherent on its own; for that we also need at least the hierarchical theory of the unfreedom of coerced action. But they were made for each other; in fact, since the latter entails the former, the existence of the paradoxes also entails the incoherence of this aspect of Stoicism, a result to be applauded.
  • 22
    • 85063705689 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Understanding Free Will’ is much-cited in the literature on autonomous agency, but not much of it is much-cited, for commentators only mention the brief last section in which Slote urges that hierarchical motivation theories must supplement their structural condition with a historical constraint on desire-acquisition. He may well be correct about this, but there is an unappreciated irony in his urging this course on Frankfurt
    • because an historical condition would enable Frankfurt to escape from the very Stoic encumbrances which Slote the bulk of his essay urges him to embrace!
    • Slote's ‘Understanding Free Will’ is much-cited in the literature on autonomous agency, but not much of it is much-cited, for commentators only mention the brief last section in which Slote urges that hierarchical motivation theories must supplement their structural condition with a historical constraint on desire-acquisition. He may well be correct about this, but there is an unappreciated irony in his urging this course on Frankfurt, because an historical condition would enable Frankfurt to escape from the very Stoic encumbrances which Slote in the bulk of his essay urges him to embrace!
    • Slote's ‘
  • 23
    • 85063700135 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • preparing this paper, I have been helped by comments from Ishtiyaque Haji, Martin Hollis, Alfred Mele, and two anonymous referees for the
    • Canadian journal of Philosophy. In preparing this paper, I have been helped by comments from Ishtiyaque Haji, Martin Hollis, Alfred Mele, and two anonymous referees for the
    • Canadian journal of Philosophy.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.