-
1
-
-
33845671429
-
The Sovereignty of Parliament, Form or Substance?
-
For a helpful overview of these debates, see, J Jowell and D Oliver eds, 6th edn OUP, Oxford
-
For a helpful overview of these debates, see A Bradley, 'The Sovereignty of Parliament, Form or Substance?' in J Jowell and D Oliver (eds), The Changing Constitution (6th edn OUP, Oxford 2007).
-
(2007)
The Changing Constitution
-
-
Bradley, A.1
-
5
-
-
57949102686
-
-
Ibid, ch 6.
-
Ibid, ch 6.
-
-
-
-
6
-
-
57949115652
-
-
Jackson v Her Majesty's Attorney-General [2005] UKHL 56.
-
Jackson v Her Majesty's Attorney-General [2005] UKHL 56.
-
-
-
-
7
-
-
57949105596
-
-
In making this argument, I will draw upon Ronald Dworkin's sustained critique of Hart's work.
-
In making this argument, I will draw upon Ronald Dworkin's sustained critique of Hart's work.
-
-
-
-
8
-
-
57949111858
-
Taking Rights Seriously (Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts 1977), Law's Empire (Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts 1986)
-
See, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts
-
See R Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously (Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts 1977), Law's Empire (Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts 1986), Justice in Robes, (Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts 2006).
-
(2006)
Justice in Robes
-
-
Dworkin, R.1
-
9
-
-
57949094204
-
-
I endorse what I take to be Dworkin's reading of Hart on this point: that, on the best reading of The Concept of Law (both the original edition and the postscript), Hart is committed to a conventionalist understanding of the rule of recognition. This is to say that there must be moral reasons to count the convergent attitudes of officials as being partly determinative of what we count as law. For a meticulously argued defence of a non-conventional reading of Hart,
-
I endorse what I take to be Dworkin's reading of Hart on this point: that, on the best reading of The Concept of Law (both the original edition and the postscript), Hart is committed to a conventionalist understanding of the rule of recognition. This is to say that there must be moral reasons to count the convergent attitudes of officials as being partly determinative of what we count as law. For a meticulously argued defence of a non-conventional reading of Hart,
-
-
-
-
10
-
-
34548494876
-
Is the Rule of Recognition Really a Conventional Rule
-
see, OJLS 373-402, Alas, this is a disagreement that I cannot even begin to do justice to within this article
-
see Julie Dickson, 'Is the Rule of Recognition Really a Conventional Rule' (2007) 27 OJLS 373-402. Dickson argues that there is a distinction - which, as a biographical matter, Hart accepted - between the existence conditions of the rule of recognition and any reasons that judges may have for following it. Alas, this is a disagreement that I cannot even begin to do justice to within this article.
-
(2007)
Dickson argues that there is a distinction - which, as a biographical matter, Hart accepted - between the existence conditions of the rule of recognition and any reasons that judges may have for following it
, vol.27
-
-
Dickson, J.1
-
11
-
-
57949111309
-
-
See further n 126
-
See further (n 126).
-
-
-
-
12
-
-
57949096639
-
-
Above n 6, 107
-
Above (n 6) [107].
-
-
-
-
13
-
-
57949108219
-
-
Above (n 2) 3
-
Above (n 2) 3.
-
-
-
-
14
-
-
57949104550
-
-
Ibid 19.
-
-
-
-
15
-
-
57949088210
-
-
Ibid 27.
-
-
-
-
16
-
-
57949088799
-
-
It should be stressed that I am not setting out to present Dicey's theory as either a structural or empirical claim, but rather to use his arguments as a gateway into these different types of theories. Indeed, in line with the general argument in this article, it is my view that Dicey can only be understood as making the normative claim that it is right and proper that Parliament should possess an all-embracing legislative authority. This position, I think, represents a particular conception of legality and not of sovereignty
-
It should be stressed that I am not setting out to present Dicey's theory as either a structural or empirical claim, but rather to use his arguments as a gateway into these different types of theories. Indeed, in line with the general argument in this article, it is my view that Dicey can only be understood as making the normative claim that it is right and proper that Parliament should possess an all-embracing legislative authority. This position, I think, represents a particular conception of legality and not of sovereignty.
-
-
-
-
17
-
-
57949105404
-
-
See section 4 below
-
See section 4 below.
-
-
-
-
18
-
-
0040852654
-
-
See, for instance, R Filmer, JP Sommerville ed, CUP, Cambridge
-
See, for instance, R Filmer, JP Sommerville (ed.), Patriarcha and Other Writings (CUP, Cambridge 1991).
-
(1991)
Patriarcha and Other Writings
-
-
-
19
-
-
57949112021
-
-
See T Hobbes, CB Macpherson ed, Penguin Books, London
-
See T Hobbes, CB Macpherson (ed.), Leviathon (Penguin Books, London 1986).
-
(1986)
Leviathon
-
-
-
20
-
-
57949096638
-
-
Above (n 3), Lecture vi.
-
Above (n 3), Lecture vi.
-
-
-
-
21
-
-
57949101318
-
-
Above (n 4) 50
-
Above (n 4) 50.
-
-
-
-
22
-
-
57949095578
-
-
Above (n 2) 3
-
Above (n 2) 3.
-
-
-
-
23
-
-
57949090270
-
-
Ibid 3.
-
-
-
-
24
-
-
57949106775
-
-
See, for instance, R v Secretary of State for the Home Department, ex p. Simms [2000] 2 AC 115, at 131. Even the most progressive constitutional theorists seem to accept this position.
-
See, for instance, R v Secretary of State for the Home Department, ex p. Simms [2000] 2 AC 115, at 131. Even the most progressive constitutional theorists seem to accept this position.
-
-
-
-
25
-
-
85010161492
-
-
See, for example, P Craig, 'Ultra Vires and the Foundations of Judicial Review' [1998] CLJ 63-90, 86
-
See, for example, P Craig, 'Ultra Vires and the Foundations of Judicial Review' [1998] CLJ 63-90, 86
-
-
-
-
28
-
-
57949086790
-
-
But cf J Jowell, 'Parliamentary Sovereignty under the New Constitutional Hypothesis', [2006] PL 562'80, 565'6.
-
But cf J Jowell, 'Parliamentary Sovereignty under the New Constitutional Hypothesis', [2006] PL 562'80, 565'6.
-
-
-
-
30
-
-
57949112761
-
-
See also, P Craig, 'Sovereignty of the United Kingdom Parliament after Factortame' (1991) 11 YBEL 221-55.
-
See also, P Craig, 'Sovereignty of the United Kingdom Parliament after Factortame' (1991) 11 YBEL 221-55.
-
-
-
-
31
-
-
57949105960
-
Sovereignty-Revolution or
-
LQR 568-75
-
Cf HWR Wade, 'Sovereignty-Revolution or Evolution' (1996) 112 LQR 568-75.
-
(1996)
Evolution
, pp. 112
-
-
Wade, C.H.W.R.1
-
32
-
-
85012537938
-
Of Fig Leaves and Fairy Tales: The Ultra Vires Doctrine, The Sovereignty of Parliament and Judicial Review
-
See, 55 CLJ 122-40, 133
-
See C Forsyth, 'Of Fig Leaves and Fairy Tales: The Ultra Vires Doctrine, The Sovereignty of Parliament and Judicial Review' (1996) 55 CLJ 122-40, 133.
-
(1996)
-
-
Forsyth, C.1
-
33
-
-
57949087917
-
-
See, for instance, PL
-
See, for instance, Sir John Laws, 'Law and Democracy' [1995] PL 72-93, 84-7.
-
(1995)
Law and Democracy
, vol.72-93
, pp. 84-87
-
-
John Laws, S.1
-
34
-
-
57949089180
-
-
For a recent judicial endorsement of this view, see the opinions of, above n 6, 102] and [126, I discuss the philosophical significance of these judicial dicta in section 4
-
For a recent judicial endorsement of this view, see the opinions of Lord Steyn and Lord Hope in Jackson above (n 6) [102] and [126]. I discuss the philosophical significance of these judicial dicta in section 4.
-
Jackson
-
-
Steyn, L.1
Hope in, L.2
-
35
-
-
57949105791
-
-
Austin allowed though for the possibility of non-legal constraints on the action of a sovereign.
-
Austin allowed though for the possibility of non-legal constraints on the action of a sovereign.
-
-
-
-
36
-
-
57949084544
-
-
See (n 3) 215-6
-
See (n 3) 215-6.
-
-
-
-
37
-
-
0041694283
-
-
For a detailed discussion, see, Clarendon Press, Oxford, ch 2
-
For a detailed discussion, see N Stavropoulos, Objectivity in Law (Clarendon Press, Oxford 1996), ch 2.
-
(1996)
Objectivity in Law
-
-
Stavropoulos, N.1
-
38
-
-
57949095754
-
-
See R Dworkin, Justice in Robes above (n 7) 142-3 who offers this example. It should be stressed that this is not Dworkin's own view for which see R Dworkin, Freedom's Law (OUP, Oxford 1996) 'Introduction: The Moral Reading and the Majoritarian Premise'.
-
See R Dworkin, Justice in Robes above (n 7) 142-3 who offers this example. It should be stressed that this is not Dworkin's own view for which see R Dworkin, Freedom's Law (OUP, Oxford 1996) 'Introduction: The Moral Reading and the Majoritarian Premise'.
-
-
-
-
39
-
-
57949094203
-
-
One finds this type of argument in relation to the adjudication under the European Convention on Human Rights. Articles 8-12 of the Convention invite judges, firstly, to decide what the right is, and then to decide whether the state can legitimately interfere with that right. This analysis implies that the right has a prior fixed content before the court considers any legitimate reasons that the state may have for its decision or action
-
One finds this type of argument in relation to the adjudication under the European Convention on Human Rights. Articles 8-12 of the Convention invite judges, firstly, to decide what the right is, and then to decide whether the state can legitimately interfere with that right. This analysis implies that the right has a prior fixed content before the court considers any legitimate reasons that the state may have for its decision or action.
-
-
-
-
42
-
-
57949101148
-
-
For the philosophical distinction between essential and accidental properties, see
-
For the philosophical distinction between essential and accidental properties, see http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/essential-accidental/
-
-
-
-
43
-
-
57949116191
-
-
It might be argued that Austin himself treats the existence of a sovereign as an accidental property of a state or constitution in so far as its existence is contingent on 'habits of obedience' by subjects towards a sovereign.
-
It might be argued that Austin himself treats the existence of a sovereign as an accidental property of a state or constitution in so far as its existence is contingent on 'habits of obedience' by subjects towards a sovereign.
-
-
-
-
44
-
-
57949110557
-
-
Hart seemed to express some sympathy with this approach, which derives from 'ordinary language' philosophy. For instance, he endorses the view of JL Austin, that, we are using a sharpened awareness of words to sharpen our perception of the phenomena, See
-
Hart seemed to express some sympathy with this approach, which derives from 'ordinary language' philosophy. For instance, he endorses the view of JL Austin, that '...we are using a sharpened awareness of words to sharpen our perception of the phenomena.' See Hart (n 4) 14
-
, vol.14
, Issue.4
-
-
Hart1
-
46
-
-
57949112760
-
-
See
-
See Hart, (n 4) 246-8.
-
, vol.246 -8
, Issue.4
-
-
Hart1
-
51
-
-
57949110292
-
-
See Hart, (n 4), chs 2-4.
-
See Hart, (n 4), chs 2-4.
-
-
-
-
55
-
-
34547109892
-
Adjudication and the Law
-
See, 27 OJLS 311-26, 312
-
See T Endicott, 'Adjudication and the Law' (2007) 27 OJLS 311-26, 312.
-
(2007)
-
-
Endicott, T.1
-
56
-
-
57949094029
-
-
Above (n 4) 90
-
Above (n 4) 90.
-
-
-
-
57
-
-
57949091913
-
-
Ibid 117.
-
-
-
-
58
-
-
57949098265
-
-
Ibid 111-2.
-
-
-
-
59
-
-
33845695477
-
-
For a recent defence of this position, see A Marmor, 'Legal Positivism: Still Descriptive and Morally Neutral' (2006) 26 OJLS 683-704.
-
For a recent defence of this position, see A Marmor, 'Legal Positivism: Still Descriptive and Morally Neutral' (2006) 26 OJLS 683-704.
-
-
-
-
60
-
-
57949088420
-
-
Above (n 4) 111-2
-
Above (n 4) 111-2.
-
-
-
-
61
-
-
57949112950
-
Hart and the Principles of Legality' (unpublished) delivered in The Legacy of H.L.A
-
See, Cambridge, July 27-28
-
See J Waldron, 'Hart and the Principles of Legality' (unpublished) delivered in The Legacy of H.L.A. Hart Conference, Cambridge, July 27-28, 2007.
-
(2007)
Hart Conference
-
-
Waldron, J.1
-
62
-
-
57949100775
-
-
Hart anticipates possible confusion between these two different views where he warns that 'It is important to distinguish [the] subordination of one criterion to another from derivation, since some spurious support for the view that all law is essentially ... the product of legislation, has been gained from confusion of these two ideas...' (n 4) 101.
-
Hart anticipates possible confusion between these two different views where he warns that 'It is important to distinguish [the] subordination of one criterion to another from derivation, since some spurious support for the view that all law is essentially ... the product of legislation, has been gained from confusion of these two ideas...' (n 4) 101.
-
-
-
-
63
-
-
57949102684
-
-
Hence, Austin's theory is often described in terms of the rule of men rather than the rule of law. See R Cotterrell, The Politics of Jurisprudence: A Critical Introduction to Legal Philosophy (2nd edn, LexisNexis Butterworths, London 2003) 70.
-
Hence, Austin's theory is often described in terms of the rule of men rather than the rule of law. See R Cotterrell, The Politics of Jurisprudence: A Critical Introduction to Legal Philosophy (2nd edn, LexisNexis Butterworths, London 2003) 70.
-
-
-
-
64
-
-
57949093131
-
-
See also R Bellamy (ed.), The Rule of Law and the Separation of Powers (Ashgate Publishing, Aldershot, Hampshire 2005) 'Introduction: the Rule of Law as the Rule of Persons'.
-
See also R Bellamy (ed.), The Rule of Law and the Separation of Powers (Ashgate Publishing, Aldershot, Hampshire 2005) 'Introduction: the Rule of Law as the Rule of Persons'.
-
-
-
-
65
-
-
57949109974
-
-
See Hart (n 4) 148 and 151.
-
See Hart (n 4) 148 and 151.
-
-
-
-
66
-
-
1642600610
-
-
For a recent defence of Hart's account of Parliamentary sovereignty, see, Clarendon Press, Oxford, especially chs 2 and 10
-
For a recent defence of Hart's account of Parliamentary sovereignty, see J Goldsworthy, The Sovereignty of Parliament: History and Philosophy (Clarendon Press, Oxford 1999), especially chs 2 and 10.
-
(1999)
The Sovereignty of Parliament: History and Philosophy
-
-
Goldsworthy, J.1
-
67
-
-
57949113272
-
-
Above (n 4) 247
-
Above (n 4) 247.
-
-
-
-
68
-
-
0000580092
-
Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals
-
See also, 598-629
-
See also Hart, 'Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals', (1958) 71 Harvard Law Review 598-629.
-
(1958)
Harvard Law Review
, vol.71
-
-
Hart1
-
69
-
-
57949112020
-
-
In the posthumously published postscript to The Concept of Law, Hart endorses so-called 'soft' positivism according to which it is acceptable for moral norms to be incorporated by reference into the ultimate rule of recognition. Above (n 4) 250-4
-
In the posthumously published postscript to The Concept of Law, Hart endorses so-called 'soft' positivism according to which it is acceptable for moral norms to be incorporated by reference into the ultimate rule of recognition. Above (n 4) 250-4.
-
-
-
-
70
-
-
57949087717
-
-
This is to be contrasted with so-called 'hard' positivism, which does not allow for any recourse to morality in identifying the law. See, for instance, J Raz, The Authority of Law, Essays on Law and Morality Clarendon Press, Oxford 1979
-
This is to be contrasted with so-called 'hard' positivism, which does not allow for any recourse to morality in identifying the law. See, for instance, J Raz, The Authority of Law, Essays on Law and Morality (Clarendon Press, Oxford 1979).
-
-
-
-
71
-
-
57949102685
-
-
Indeed, this is a claim made by a number of eminent constitutional theorists. See section 3 below.
-
Indeed, this is a claim made by a number of eminent constitutional theorists. See section 3 below.
-
-
-
-
72
-
-
57949095407
-
-
42 MLR 1-21
-
(1979) 42 MLR 1-21.
-
-
-
-
73
-
-
57949100436
-
-
Ibid 16.
-
-
-
-
74
-
-
57949113640
-
-
Ibid.
-
-
-
-
75
-
-
57949114316
-
-
Above (n 52) 19
-
Above (n 52) 19.
-
-
-
-
77
-
-
85203999849
-
-
For a similar reading of Griffith, see, Hart Publishing, Oxford
-
For a similar reading of Griffith, see A Tomkins, Our Republican Constitution (Hart Publishing, Oxford 2005) 37-9.
-
(2005)
Our Republican Constitution
, pp. 37-39
-
-
Tomkins, A.1
-
78
-
-
57949106956
-
-
Cf T Poole, 'Tilting at Windmills? Truth and Illusion in The Political Constitution' (2007) 70 MLR 250 77, 253 and, especially, at 274-7.
-
Cf T Poole, 'Tilting at Windmills? Truth and Illusion in "The Political Constitution"' (2007) 70 MLR 250 77, 253 and, especially, at 274-7.
-
-
-
-
80
-
-
57949093304
-
-
See S Sedley, The Sound of Silence: Constitutional Law without a Constitution' (1994) 110 LQR 270-91
-
See S Sedley, The Sound of Silence: Constitutional Law without a Constitution' (1994) 110 LQR 270-91
-
-
-
-
81
-
-
0001289944
-
Human Rights: A Twenty-First Century Agenda
-
'Human Rights: A Twenty-First Century Agenda' [1995] PL 386-400, 389,
-
(1995)
, vol.PL 386-400
, pp. 389
-
-
-
82
-
-
57949107669
-
-
and 'The Common Law and the Constitution', in Lord Nolan of Brasted and Sir Stephen Sedley (eds), The Making and Remaking of the British Constitution (Blackstone Press, London 1997) 26.
-
and 'The Common Law and the Constitution', in Lord Nolan of Brasted and Sir Stephen Sedley (eds), The Making and Remaking of the British Constitution (Blackstone Press, London 1997) 26.
-
-
-
-
83
-
-
57949099427
-
-
See J Griffith 'The Common Law and the Political Constitution', (2001) 117 LQR 42-67.
-
See J Griffith 'The Common Law and the Political Constitution', (2001) 117 LQR 42-67.
-
-
-
-
84
-
-
57949083635
-
-
Commentators sometimes refer to Griffith as a 'functionalist'. There is some disagreement though as to whether such a label implies a 'descriptive' or 'prescriptive' approach, or both. See M Loughlin, 'The Functionalist Style in Public Law' (2005) 55 University of Toronto Law Journal 361-403, 368.
-
Commentators sometimes refer to Griffith as a 'functionalist'. There is some disagreement though as to whether such a label implies a 'descriptive' or 'prescriptive' approach, or both. See M Loughlin, 'The Functionalist Style in Public Law' (2005) 55 University of Toronto Law Journal 361-403, 368.
-
-
-
-
85
-
-
57949111857
-
-
Cf. A Tomkins, (n 54) 39.
-
, vol.39
, Issue.54
-
-
Tomkins, C.A.1
-
86
-
-
57949099951
-
-
Above n 6
-
Above (n 6).
-
-
-
-
87
-
-
57949090838
-
-
Ibid.
-
-
-
-
88
-
-
57949100954
-
-
See, particular, Lord Hope [124, Lord Bingham [36, Lord Nicholls [63] and the
-
See, in particular, Lord Hope [124], Lord Bingham [36], Lord Nicholls [63] and the Court of Appeal [2005] QB 579 [97].
-
(2005)
Court of Appeal
, vol.QB 579
, pp. 97
-
-
-
89
-
-
57949103122
-
-
Ibid [25].
-
-
-
-
90
-
-
57949096267
-
-
Ibid [24].
-
-
-
-
91
-
-
57949116031
-
-
Ibid.
-
-
-
-
92
-
-
57949108408
-
-
Ibid [32].
-
-
-
-
93
-
-
57949104222
-
-
Ibid.
-
-
-
-
95
-
-
57949099598
-
-
Ibid [59]. Lord Carswell explicitly agrees with Lord Nicholl's reading at [175].
-
Ibid [59]. Lord Carswell explicitly agrees with Lord Nicholl's reading at [175].
-
-
-
-
96
-
-
57949084169
-
-
Ibid [61].
-
-
-
-
97
-
-
57949085802
-
-
Ibid [79].
-
-
-
-
98
-
-
57949105074
-
-
Similarly see Lord Rodger at [139].
-
Similarly see Lord Rodger at [139].
-
-
-
-
99
-
-
57949088209
-
-
Ibid [102].
-
-
-
-
100
-
-
57949094693
-
-
Ibid [120].
-
-
-
-
101
-
-
57949117376
-
-
Ibid [159].
-
-
-
-
105
-
-
57949096636
-
-
Above (n 49) 236
-
Above (n 49) 236.
-
-
-
-
106
-
-
57949107668
-
-
Ibid 240.
-
-
-
-
107
-
-
57949094575
-
Is Parliament Sovereign? Recent Challenges to the Doctrine of Parliamentary Sovereignty
-
See also
-
See also J Goldsworthy, 'Is Parliament Sovereign? Recent Challenges to the Doctrine of Parliamentary Sovereignty' (2005) 3 New Zealand Journal of Public and International Law 7-37, 7.
-
(2005)
New Zealand Journal of Public and International Law
, vol.3
-
-
Goldsworthy, J.1
-
108
-
-
57949114553
-
-
This is particularly so in relation to the dictum of Lord Hope (n 70) who seems to suggest in characteristically Austinian fashion that the limits on sovereignty are extra-legal rather than legal limits
-
This is particularly so in relation to the dictum of Lord Hope (n 70) who seems to suggest in characteristically Austinian fashion that the limits on sovereignty are extra-legal rather than legal limits.
-
-
-
-
109
-
-
57949101497
-
-
Distinguishing this case from Pickin v. British Railways Board [1974] AC 765.
-
Distinguishing this case from Pickin v. British Railways Board [1974] AC 765.
-
-
-
-
110
-
-
57949109063
-
-
n 6, 25] and [110
-
Jackson (n 6) [25] and [110].
-
Jackson
-
-
-
111
-
-
57949106306
-
-
Ibid [102] and [159].
-
Ibid [102] and [159].
-
-
-
-
112
-
-
57949094853
-
-
Ibid [120].
-
-
-
-
113
-
-
0002388111
-
-
Wade 'The Basis of Legal Sovereignty' (1955) 13 CLJ 172-97.
-
Wade 'The Basis of Legal Sovereignty' (1955) 13 CLJ 172-97.
-
-
-
-
114
-
-
0040642168
-
-
See generally, OUP, Oxford
-
See generally, T Allan, Law, Liberty and Justice, the Legal Foundations of British Constitutionalism (OUP, Oxford 1993)
-
(1993)
Law, Liberty and Justice, the Legal Foundations of British Constitutionalism
-
-
Allan, T.1
-
117
-
-
57949115233
-
Competing Models of Judicial Review
-
For an excellent discussion of the similarities, on this point, between Wade and Laws, see, C Forsyth ed, Hart Publishing, Oxford and Portland, Oregon
-
For an excellent discussion of the similarities, on this point, between Wade and Laws, see P Craig, 'Competing Models of Judicial Review' in C Forsyth (ed) Judicial Review and the Constitution (Hart Publishing, Oxford and Portland, Oregon 2000).
-
(2000)
Judicial Review and the Constitution
-
-
Craig, P.1
-
118
-
-
57949084912
-
-
This reflects the classical 'social contract' position whereby citizens give their tacit consent to the authority of the state only under certain conditions, say, of liberty and equality. See, for instance, J Locke, Peter Laslett ed, Two Treatises of Government CUP, Cambridge 2003
-
This reflects the classical 'social contract' position whereby citizens give their tacit consent to the authority of the state only under certain conditions, say, of liberty and equality. See, for instance, J Locke, Peter Laslett ed.), Two Treatises of Government (CUP, Cambridge 2003).
-
-
-
-
119
-
-
57949102334
-
-
This type of approach is found in theories of civic republicanism. See, for instance, Tomkins n 56
-
This type of approach is found in theories of civic republicanism. See, for instance, Tomkins (n 56).
-
-
-
-
120
-
-
57949107667
-
-
See also Lord Woolf CJ in the Court of Appeal in Jackson who includes attitudes of 'the populace' in the calculation, (n 62).
-
See also Lord Woolf CJ in the Court of Appeal in Jackson who includes attitudes of 'the populace' in the calculation, (n 62).
-
-
-
-
121
-
-
57949092428
-
-
See Hart, n 4 148
-
See Hart, (n 4) 148.
-
-
-
-
122
-
-
57949114154
-
-
Ibid 117.
-
-
-
-
123
-
-
57949112949
-
-
See Jackson, (n 6) [81].
-
See Jackson, (n 6) [81].
-
-
-
-
124
-
-
57949089352
-
-
This applies, a fortiori, to Griffith for whom the identity of the ultimate lawmaker does not even require acceptance by officials: Parliament is whatever it happens to be. See (n 52) 16
-
This applies, a fortiori, to Griffith for whom the identity of the ultimate lawmaker does not even require acceptance by officials: Parliament is whatever it happens to be. See (n 52) 16.
-
-
-
-
125
-
-
57949086973
-
-
To use Dworkin's two dimensions of interpretation, this reasoning neither 'fits' nor 'justifies' the fact that Parliament possesses legislative powers in the British constitution. See R Dworkin, Law's Empire, (n 7) 139.
-
To use Dworkin's two dimensions of interpretation, this reasoning neither 'fits' nor 'justifies' the fact that Parliament possesses legislative powers in the British constitution. See R Dworkin, Law's Empire, (n 7) 139.
-
-
-
-
126
-
-
57949108035
-
-
See Jackson, (n 6) [157]. This principle, I think, justifies the view expressed by different judges that the point of the 1911 Act was to restrict the power of the House of Lords.
-
See Jackson, (n 6) [157]. This principle, I think, justifies the view expressed by different judges that the point of the 1911 Act was to restrict the power of the House of Lords.
-
-
-
-
127
-
-
57949084001
-
It would be odd then if these principles played no part in the way that judges define the concept of Parliament
-
The principles of democracy and checks and balances are, of course, precisely the types of principles that have historically motivated political debates about the reform of Parliament. See, Lord Wakeham Cmnd 4534, 2000
-
The principles of democracy and checks and balances are, of course, precisely the types of principles that have historically motivated political debates about the reform of Parliament. See, for instance, Report of the Royal Commission on the Reform of the House of Lords (Chair: Lord Wakeham) Cmnd 4534, 2000). It would be odd then if these principles played no part in the way that judges define the concept of Parliament.
-
Report of the Royal Commission on the Reform of the House of Lords (Chair
-
-
for instance1
-
128
-
-
57949114315
-
-
I certainly do not mean to imply that there cannot be law unless there is democracy. If it were plausible to suppose that Freemasons and Knights of the Realm (or whomever) do in fact exercise legislative power in British legal practice, then it may be that we could justify that power according to, say, the principle of protected expectations or certainty if most people in fact obeyed their edicts
-
I certainly do not mean to imply that there cannot be law unless there is democracy. If it were plausible to suppose that Freemasons and Knights of the Realm (or whomever) do in fact exercise legislative power in British legal practice, then it may be that we could justify that power according to, say, the principle of protected expectations or certainty if most people in fact obeyed their edicts.
-
-
-
-
129
-
-
57949098067
-
-
See Hart, n 4 151
-
See Hart, (n 4) 151.
-
-
-
-
130
-
-
57949107478
-
-
For an insightful discussion of the legal and constitutional implications of this type of development in Britain, see R Dworkin, A Bill of Rights for Britain Chatto & Windus, London 1990
-
For an insightful discussion of the legal and constitutional implications of this type of development in Britain, see R Dworkin, A Bill of Rights for Britain (Chatto & Windus, London 1990).
-
-
-
-
131
-
-
57949102682
-
-
Baroness Hale plays with these types of ideas but she does so, it is suggested, without recognising that there are certain principled limits to the ways in which Parliament qua Parliament can redefine itself. See Jackson, n 6 [163].
-
Baroness Hale plays with these types of ideas but she does so, it is suggested, without recognising that there are certain principled limits to the ways in which Parliament qua Parliament can redefine itself. See Jackson, n 6) [163].
-
-
-
-
133
-
-
57949099597
-
-
and Law's Empire (n 7) ch 4.
-
and Law's Empire (n 7) ch 4.
-
-
-
-
134
-
-
57949102950
-
-
See Jackson, (n 6) [67]-[69] and [171].
-
See Jackson, (n 6) [67]-[69] and [171].
-
-
-
-
135
-
-
57949104892
-
-
Under the rule in Pepper v Hart [1993] AC 593.
-
Under the rule in Pepper v Hart [1993] AC 593.
-
-
-
-
136
-
-
57949109973
-
-
See Jackson, (n 6) [65], [97] and [98].
-
See Jackson, (n 6) [65], [97] and [98].
-
-
-
-
137
-
-
57949101793
-
-
See Hart, (n 4) 123, 147-54 and 251.
-
See Hart, (n 4) 123, 147-54 and 251.
-
-
-
-
138
-
-
57949099594
-
-
See, generally, chs 1 and 2
-
See, generally, R Dworkin, Justice in Robes (n 7), chs 1 and 2.
-
Justice in Robes
, Issue.7
-
-
Dworkin, R.1
-
139
-
-
57949103855
-
-
See J Griffith, 'The Brave New World of Sir John Laws', (2000) 63 MLR 159-76.
-
See J Griffith, 'The Brave New World of Sir John Laws', (2000) 63 MLR 159-76.
-
-
-
-
140
-
-
57949104221
-
-
Again, this is the position of so-called 'soft' or 'inclusive' positivists. See (n 50).
-
Again, this is the position of so-called 'soft' or 'inclusive' positivists. See (n 50).
-
-
-
-
142
-
-
57949097152
-
-
Dworkin helpfully expresses these differences in reasoning in terms of 'concurrent' and 'conventional' morality. As he says, 'A community displays a concurrent morality when its members are agreed in asserting the same, or much the same, normative rule, but they do not count the fact of that agreement as an essential part of their grounds for asserting that rule. It displays a conventional morality when they do'. Ibid 53.
-
Dworkin helpfully expresses these differences in reasoning in terms of 'concurrent' and 'conventional' morality. As he says, 'A community displays a concurrent morality when its members are agreed in asserting the same, or much the same, normative rule, but they do not count the fact of that agreement as an essential part of their grounds for asserting that rule. It displays a conventional morality when they do'. Ibid 53.
-
-
-
-
143
-
-
57949090656
-
-
See, for example, Forsyth, (n 22).
-
See, for example, Forsyth, (n 22).
-
-
-
-
144
-
-
57949090268
-
See C Forsyth and M Elliott
-
The so-called 'modified' ultra vires theory seeks to preserve this basic intuition albeit that Parliament is said to have an abstract intention that judges give effect to the rule of law rather than concrete intentions as to particular principles of judicial review, PL
-
The so-called 'modified' ultra vires theory seeks to preserve this basic intuition albeit that Parliament is said to have an abstract intention that judges give effect to the rule of law rather than concrete intentions as to particular principles of judicial review. See C Forsyth and M Elliott, 'The Legitimacy of Judicial Review' [2003] PL 286-307.
-
(2003)
The Legitimacy of Judicial Review
, pp. 286-307
-
-
-
146
-
-
57949097156
-
-
P Craig, 'Utra Vires and the Foundations of Judicial Review', (n 20).
-
P Craig, 'Utra Vires and the Foundations of Judicial Review', (n 20).
-
-
-
-
149
-
-
57949115053
-
-
Ibis, I think, is clearly the meaning afforded to the term 'sovereignty' by a number of other leading constitutional theorists.
-
Ibis, I think, is clearly the meaning afforded to the term 'sovereignty' by a number of other leading constitutional theorists.
-
-
-
-
150
-
-
57949109796
-
-
See Sedley, n 57
-
See Sedley, (n 57)
-
-
-
-
151
-
-
57949113639
-
-
TRS Allan, n 86
-
TRS Allan, (n 86).
-
-
-
-
152
-
-
57949088207
-
-
UK lawyers commonly use phrases such as 'shared sovereignty' or 'pooled sovereignty' (among many other variations) when they refer to the relationship between the United Kingdom and the EU institutions. See, for example, Neil Walker, 'Late Sovereignty in the European Union', in Walker (ed.), Sovereignty in Transition (Hart Publishing, Oxford 2003) 10-18.
-
UK lawyers commonly use phrases such as 'shared sovereignty' or 'pooled sovereignty' (among many other variations) when they refer to the relationship between the United Kingdom and the EU institutions. See, for example, Neil Walker, 'Late Sovereignty in the European Union', in Walker (ed.), Sovereignty in Transition (Hart Publishing, Oxford 2003) 10-18.
-
-
-
-
153
-
-
57949110925
-
-
In the European context, just as in the context of the powers of institutions within a state, the word sovereignty, I think, seems to connote something like 'power' or perhaps more aptly 'competence, Other commentators have lately dispensed with the language of sovereignty and described the relationship between member states and the EU as one of 'legal pluralism, See N MacCormick, Questioning Sovereignty: Law, State, and Nation in the European Commonwealth OUP, Oxford 1999
-
In the European context, just as in the context of the powers of institutions within a state, the word sovereignty, I think, seems to connote something like 'power' or perhaps more aptly 'competence'. Other commentators have lately dispensed with the language of sovereignty and described the relationship between member states and the EU as one of 'legal pluralism'. See N MacCormick, Questioning Sovereignty: Law, State, and Nation in the European Commonwealth (OUP, Oxford 1999)
-
-
-
-
154
-
-
34147211700
-
The Idea of a European Constitution
-
27 OJLS 1-21, 14
-
P Eleftheriadis, 'The Idea of a European Constitution' (2007) 27 OJLS 1-21, 14.
-
(2007)
-
-
Eleftheriadis, P.1
-
155
-
-
57949094576
-
-
In the context of public international law too, there appears to be a movement away from the idea of absolute sovereign states towards the idea that there are certain normative conditions attached to the exercise of state power. See M Koskenniemi, From Apology to Utopia CUP, Cambridge 2005, ch 4
-
In the context of public international law too, there appears to be a movement away from the idea of absolute sovereign states towards the idea that there are certain normative conditions attached to the exercise of state power. See M Koskenniemi, From Apology to Utopia (CUP, Cambridge 2005), ch 4.
-
-
-
-
156
-
-
57949097717
-
-
As Jowell has recently put it, the allocation of political power depends on 'a moral claim to its exercise (or limitation)'. See Jowell, 'Parliamentary Sovereignty' (n 20) 565-6.
-
As Jowell has recently put it, the allocation of political power depends on 'a moral claim to its exercise (or limitation)'. See Jowell, 'Parliamentary Sovereignty' (n 20) 565-6.
-
-
-
-
157
-
-
57949092084
-
-
The most assiduous proponent of this type of theory is TRS Allan. See (n 86).
-
The most assiduous proponent of this type of theory is TRS Allan. See (n 86).
-
-
-
-
158
-
-
57949113442
-
-
See also Lord Woolf 'Droit Public - English Style' [1995] PL 57-71.
-
See also Lord Woolf 'Droit Public - English Style' [1995] PL 57-71.
-
-
-
-
159
-
-
57949085097
-
-
It might be argued though that the House of Lords has recognised the primacy of the principle of legality through its 'constitutional rights' jurisprudence. See generally Jowell n 20
-
It might be argued though that the House of Lords has recognised the primacy of the principle of legality through its 'constitutional rights' jurisprudence. See generally Jowell (n 20).
-
-
-
-
160
-
-
57949101792
-
-
n 6, 107, my emphasis
-
Jackson (n 6) [107] (my emphasis).
-
Jackson
-
-
-
162
-
-
57949105959
-
-
Jackson (n 6) [104].
-
Jackson (n 6) [104].
-
-
-
-
163
-
-
57949102492
-
-
See also similarly P Craig (n 106) 107-11 who suggests that sovereignty does not mean 'absolute' sovereignty; judges place a variety of different constraints on sovereign power through various different forms of statutory interpretation. Craig makes his argument in response to Allan's view that the idea of Parliamentary Sovereignty cannot permit of any limits to Parliament's power.
-
See also similarly P Craig (n 106) 107-11 who suggests that sovereignty does not mean 'absolute' sovereignty; judges place a variety of different constraints on sovereign power through various different forms of statutory interpretation. Craig makes his argument in response to Allan's view that the idea of Parliamentary Sovereignty cannot permit of any limits to Parliament's power.
-
-
-
-
165
-
-
57949099596
-
-
For detailed discussion on this question, see, for instance
-
For detailed discussion on this question, see, for instance, Goldsworthy (n 49) 250,
-
, vol.250
, Issue.49
-
-
Goldsworthy1
-
167
-
-
57949091912
-
-
Indeed, even if one were to adopt an Austinian or Hartian account of the power of law-makers, it would make no sense to speak in terms of legal limits on sovereignty. The Austinian sovereign is, by definition legally unlimited; and for Hart, the law-making powers of Parliament (or some other law-maker) are determined by a rule of recognition. In this respect, it is submitted that Allan (n 120) must be correct.
-
Indeed, even if one were to adopt an Austinian or Hartian account of the power of law-makers, it would make no sense to speak in terms of legal limits on sovereignty. The Austinian sovereign is, by definition legally unlimited; and for Hart, the law-making powers of Parliament (or some other law-maker) are determined by a rule of recognition. In this respect, it is submitted that Allan (n 120) must be correct.
-
-
-
-
168
-
-
57949086789
-
-
Jackson (n 6) [107].
-
Jackson (n 6) [107].
-
-
-
-
173
-
-
57949095232
-
-
See Hart (n 4) 91-7
-
See Hart (n 4) 91-7
-
-
-
-
175
-
-
57949105401
-
-
Hence, many judges require only that a document appear 'on the Parliamentary roll, See
-
Hence, many judges require only that a document appear 'on the Parliamentary roll'. See Lord Hope in Jackson (n 6) [112].
-
Hope in Jackson (n 6)
, vol.112
-
-
Lord1
-
176
-
-
57949115495
-
-
These conditions equate roughly to Hart's emphasis on consensus and the core meaning of words. See sections 1 and 2 above. Dworkin recasts Hart's 'descriptive' theory as an 'interpretive' morally engaged theory which he describes as 'conventionalism'. See Dworkin, Law's Empire (n 7) ch 4.
-
These conditions equate roughly to Hart's emphasis on consensus and the core meaning of words. See sections 1 and 2 above. Dworkin recasts Hart's 'descriptive' theory as an 'interpretive' morally engaged theory which he describes as 'conventionalism'. See Dworkin, Law's Empire (n 7) ch 4.
-
-
-
-
177
-
-
57949114552
-
-
According to this interpretation of British legal practice, there are moral reasons to count clear, well-known and widely accepted rules as the operative standards in the constitution. As I have explained (n 8), I endorse this reading of Hart.
-
According to this interpretation of British legal practice, there are moral reasons to count clear, well-known and widely accepted rules as the operative standards in the constitution. As I have explained (n 8), I endorse this reading of Hart.
-
-
-
-
178
-
-
57949110556
-
-
This is the position taken by so-called 'ethical' positivists. See T Campbell, Prescriptive Legal Positivism: Law, Rights and Democracy Routledge-Cavendish, 2004
-
This is the position taken by so-called 'ethical' positivists. See T Campbell, Prescriptive Legal Positivism: Law, Rights and Democracy (Routledge-Cavendish, 2004)
-
-
-
-
179
-
-
3843070366
-
Normative (or Ethical) Positivism
-
J Coleman ed, ch 12
-
J Waldron, 'Normative (or Ethical) Positivism' in J Coleman (ed), Hart's Postscript (n 33), ch 12.
-
Hart's Postscript
, Issue.33
-
-
Waldron, J.1
-
180
-
-
57949110926
-
-
This is a rough account of Dworkin's theory of law as integrity. See Dworkin, Law's Empire (n 7) ch 6
-
This is a rough account of Dworkin's theory of law as integrity. See Dworkin, Law's Empire (n 7) ch 6.
-
-
-
-
181
-
-
57949107311
-
-
A number of theorists have objected to an expansive definition of the concept of legality on the basis that it robs the concept of any independent value. See Raz, n 50 299
-
A number of theorists have objected to an expansive definition of the concept of legality on the basis that it robs the concept of any independent value. See Raz, (n 50) 299.
-
-
-
-
184
-
-
57949095230
-
-
Jackson (n 6) [107].
-
Jackson (n 6) [107].
-
-
-
-
185
-
-
57949083456
-
-
Other argue in support of some other value or values. Sir John Laws, for example, has placed the value of autonomy at the heart of his constitutional theory. See Sir John Laws 'The Constitution: Morals and Rights' [1996] PL 622-35.
-
Other argue in support of some other value or values. Sir John Laws, for example, has placed the value of autonomy at the heart of his constitutional theory. See Sir John Laws 'The Constitution: Morals and Rights' [1996] PL 622-35.
-
-
-
|