메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 28, Issue 4, 2008, Pages 709-734

Debunking the idea of parliamentary sovereignty: The controlling factor of legality in the British constitution

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 57949108431     PISSN: 01436503     EISSN: 14643820     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1093/ojls/gqn019     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (31)

References (185)
  • 1
    • 33845671429 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Sovereignty of Parliament, Form or Substance?
    • For a helpful overview of these debates, see, J Jowell and D Oliver eds, 6th edn OUP, Oxford
    • For a helpful overview of these debates, see A Bradley, 'The Sovereignty of Parliament, Form or Substance?' in J Jowell and D Oliver (eds), The Changing Constitution (6th edn OUP, Oxford 2007).
    • (2007) The Changing Constitution
    • Bradley, A.1
  • 5
    • 57949102686 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid, ch 6.
    • Ibid, ch 6.
  • 6
    • 57949115652 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Jackson v Her Majesty's Attorney-General [2005] UKHL 56.
    • Jackson v Her Majesty's Attorney-General [2005] UKHL 56.
  • 7
    • 57949105596 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In making this argument, I will draw upon Ronald Dworkin's sustained critique of Hart's work.
    • In making this argument, I will draw upon Ronald Dworkin's sustained critique of Hart's work.
  • 8
    • 57949111858 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Taking Rights Seriously (Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts 1977), Law's Empire (Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts 1986)
    • See, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts
    • See R Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously (Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts 1977), Law's Empire (Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts 1986), Justice in Robes, (Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts 2006).
    • (2006) Justice in Robes
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 9
    • 57949094204 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I endorse what I take to be Dworkin's reading of Hart on this point: that, on the best reading of The Concept of Law (both the original edition and the postscript), Hart is committed to a conventionalist understanding of the rule of recognition. This is to say that there must be moral reasons to count the convergent attitudes of officials as being partly determinative of what we count as law. For a meticulously argued defence of a non-conventional reading of Hart,
    • I endorse what I take to be Dworkin's reading of Hart on this point: that, on the best reading of The Concept of Law (both the original edition and the postscript), Hart is committed to a conventionalist understanding of the rule of recognition. This is to say that there must be moral reasons to count the convergent attitudes of officials as being partly determinative of what we count as law. For a meticulously argued defence of a non-conventional reading of Hart,
  • 11
    • 57949111309 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See further n 126
    • See further (n 126).
  • 12
    • 57949096639 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Above n 6, 107
    • Above (n 6) [107].
  • 13
    • 57949108219 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Above (n 2) 3
    • Above (n 2) 3.
  • 14
    • 57949104550 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid 19.
  • 15
    • 57949088210 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid 27.
  • 16
    • 57949088799 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It should be stressed that I am not setting out to present Dicey's theory as either a structural or empirical claim, but rather to use his arguments as a gateway into these different types of theories. Indeed, in line with the general argument in this article, it is my view that Dicey can only be understood as making the normative claim that it is right and proper that Parliament should possess an all-embracing legislative authority. This position, I think, represents a particular conception of legality and not of sovereignty
    • It should be stressed that I am not setting out to present Dicey's theory as either a structural or empirical claim, but rather to use his arguments as a gateway into these different types of theories. Indeed, in line with the general argument in this article, it is my view that Dicey can only be understood as making the normative claim that it is right and proper that Parliament should possess an all-embracing legislative authority. This position, I think, represents a particular conception of legality and not of sovereignty.
  • 17
    • 57949105404 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See section 4 below
    • See section 4 below.
  • 18
    • 0040852654 scopus 로고
    • See, for instance, R Filmer, JP Sommerville ed, CUP, Cambridge
    • See, for instance, R Filmer, JP Sommerville (ed.), Patriarcha and Other Writings (CUP, Cambridge 1991).
    • (1991) Patriarcha and Other Writings
  • 19
    • 57949112021 scopus 로고
    • See T Hobbes, CB Macpherson ed, Penguin Books, London
    • See T Hobbes, CB Macpherson (ed.), Leviathon (Penguin Books, London 1986).
    • (1986) Leviathon
  • 20
    • 57949096638 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Above (n 3), Lecture vi.
    • Above (n 3), Lecture vi.
  • 21
    • 57949101318 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Above (n 4) 50
    • Above (n 4) 50.
  • 22
    • 57949095578 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Above (n 2) 3
    • Above (n 2) 3.
  • 23
    • 57949090270 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid 3.
  • 24
    • 57949106775 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, for instance, R v Secretary of State for the Home Department, ex p. Simms [2000] 2 AC 115, at 131. Even the most progressive constitutional theorists seem to accept this position.
    • See, for instance, R v Secretary of State for the Home Department, ex p. Simms [2000] 2 AC 115, at 131. Even the most progressive constitutional theorists seem to accept this position.
  • 25
    • 85010161492 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, for example, P Craig, 'Ultra Vires and the Foundations of Judicial Review' [1998] CLJ 63-90, 86
    • See, for example, P Craig, 'Ultra Vires and the Foundations of Judicial Review' [1998] CLJ 63-90, 86
  • 28
    • 57949086790 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • But cf J Jowell, 'Parliamentary Sovereignty under the New Constitutional Hypothesis', [2006] PL 562'80, 565'6.
    • But cf J Jowell, 'Parliamentary Sovereignty under the New Constitutional Hypothesis', [2006] PL 562'80, 565'6.
  • 30
    • 57949112761 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See also, P Craig, 'Sovereignty of the United Kingdom Parliament after Factortame' (1991) 11 YBEL 221-55.
    • See also, P Craig, 'Sovereignty of the United Kingdom Parliament after Factortame' (1991) 11 YBEL 221-55.
  • 31
    • 57949105960 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sovereignty-Revolution or
    • LQR 568-75
    • Cf HWR Wade, 'Sovereignty-Revolution or Evolution' (1996) 112 LQR 568-75.
    • (1996) Evolution , pp. 112
    • Wade, C.H.W.R.1
  • 32
    • 85012537938 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Of Fig Leaves and Fairy Tales: The Ultra Vires Doctrine, The Sovereignty of Parliament and Judicial Review
    • See, 55 CLJ 122-40, 133
    • See C Forsyth, 'Of Fig Leaves and Fairy Tales: The Ultra Vires Doctrine, The Sovereignty of Parliament and Judicial Review' (1996) 55 CLJ 122-40, 133.
    • (1996)
    • Forsyth, C.1
  • 33
    • 57949087917 scopus 로고
    • See, for instance, PL
    • See, for instance, Sir John Laws, 'Law and Democracy' [1995] PL 72-93, 84-7.
    • (1995) Law and Democracy , vol.72-93 , pp. 84-87
    • John Laws, S.1
  • 34
    • 57949089180 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a recent judicial endorsement of this view, see the opinions of, above n 6, 102] and [126, I discuss the philosophical significance of these judicial dicta in section 4
    • For a recent judicial endorsement of this view, see the opinions of Lord Steyn and Lord Hope in Jackson above (n 6) [102] and [126]. I discuss the philosophical significance of these judicial dicta in section 4.
    • Jackson
    • Steyn, L.1    Hope in, L.2
  • 35
    • 57949105791 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Austin allowed though for the possibility of non-legal constraints on the action of a sovereign.
    • Austin allowed though for the possibility of non-legal constraints on the action of a sovereign.
  • 36
    • 57949084544 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See (n 3) 215-6
    • See (n 3) 215-6.
  • 37
    • 0041694283 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a detailed discussion, see, Clarendon Press, Oxford, ch 2
    • For a detailed discussion, see N Stavropoulos, Objectivity in Law (Clarendon Press, Oxford 1996), ch 2.
    • (1996) Objectivity in Law
    • Stavropoulos, N.1
  • 38
    • 57949095754 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See R Dworkin, Justice in Robes above (n 7) 142-3 who offers this example. It should be stressed that this is not Dworkin's own view for which see R Dworkin, Freedom's Law (OUP, Oxford 1996) 'Introduction: The Moral Reading and the Majoritarian Premise'.
    • See R Dworkin, Justice in Robes above (n 7) 142-3 who offers this example. It should be stressed that this is not Dworkin's own view for which see R Dworkin, Freedom's Law (OUP, Oxford 1996) 'Introduction: The Moral Reading and the Majoritarian Premise'.
  • 39
    • 57949094203 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • One finds this type of argument in relation to the adjudication under the European Convention on Human Rights. Articles 8-12 of the Convention invite judges, firstly, to decide what the right is, and then to decide whether the state can legitimately interfere with that right. This analysis implies that the right has a prior fixed content before the court considers any legitimate reasons that the state may have for its decision or action
    • One finds this type of argument in relation to the adjudication under the European Convention on Human Rights. Articles 8-12 of the Convention invite judges, firstly, to decide what the right is, and then to decide whether the state can legitimately interfere with that right. This analysis implies that the right has a prior fixed content before the court considers any legitimate reasons that the state may have for its decision or action.
  • 42
    • 57949101148 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For the philosophical distinction between essential and accidental properties, see
    • For the philosophical distinction between essential and accidental properties, see http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/essential-accidental/
  • 43
    • 57949116191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It might be argued that Austin himself treats the existence of a sovereign as an accidental property of a state or constitution in so far as its existence is contingent on 'habits of obedience' by subjects towards a sovereign.
    • It might be argued that Austin himself treats the existence of a sovereign as an accidental property of a state or constitution in so far as its existence is contingent on 'habits of obedience' by subjects towards a sovereign.
  • 44
    • 57949110557 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hart seemed to express some sympathy with this approach, which derives from 'ordinary language' philosophy. For instance, he endorses the view of JL Austin, that, we are using a sharpened awareness of words to sharpen our perception of the phenomena, See
    • Hart seemed to express some sympathy with this approach, which derives from 'ordinary language' philosophy. For instance, he endorses the view of JL Austin, that '...we are using a sharpened awareness of words to sharpen our perception of the phenomena.' See Hart (n 4) 14
    • , vol.14 , Issue.4
    • Hart1
  • 46
    • 57949112760 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See
    • See Hart, (n 4) 246-8.
    • , vol.246 -8 , Issue.4
    • Hart1
  • 51
    • 57949110292 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Hart, (n 4), chs 2-4.
    • See Hart, (n 4), chs 2-4.
  • 55
    • 34547109892 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Adjudication and the Law
    • See, 27 OJLS 311-26, 312
    • See T Endicott, 'Adjudication and the Law' (2007) 27 OJLS 311-26, 312.
    • (2007)
    • Endicott, T.1
  • 56
    • 57949094029 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Above (n 4) 90
    • Above (n 4) 90.
  • 57
    • 57949091913 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid 117.
  • 58
    • 57949098265 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid 111-2.
  • 59
    • 33845695477 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a recent defence of this position, see A Marmor, 'Legal Positivism: Still Descriptive and Morally Neutral' (2006) 26 OJLS 683-704.
    • For a recent defence of this position, see A Marmor, 'Legal Positivism: Still Descriptive and Morally Neutral' (2006) 26 OJLS 683-704.
  • 60
    • 57949088420 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Above (n 4) 111-2
    • Above (n 4) 111-2.
  • 61
    • 57949112950 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hart and the Principles of Legality' (unpublished) delivered in The Legacy of H.L.A
    • See, Cambridge, July 27-28
    • See J Waldron, 'Hart and the Principles of Legality' (unpublished) delivered in The Legacy of H.L.A. Hart Conference, Cambridge, July 27-28, 2007.
    • (2007) Hart Conference
    • Waldron, J.1
  • 62
    • 57949100775 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hart anticipates possible confusion between these two different views where he warns that 'It is important to distinguish [the] subordination of one criterion to another from derivation, since some spurious support for the view that all law is essentially ... the product of legislation, has been gained from confusion of these two ideas...' (n 4) 101.
    • Hart anticipates possible confusion between these two different views where he warns that 'It is important to distinguish [the] subordination of one criterion to another from derivation, since some spurious support for the view that all law is essentially ... the product of legislation, has been gained from confusion of these two ideas...' (n 4) 101.
  • 63
    • 57949102684 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hence, Austin's theory is often described in terms of the rule of men rather than the rule of law. See R Cotterrell, The Politics of Jurisprudence: A Critical Introduction to Legal Philosophy (2nd edn, LexisNexis Butterworths, London 2003) 70.
    • Hence, Austin's theory is often described in terms of the rule of men rather than the rule of law. See R Cotterrell, The Politics of Jurisprudence: A Critical Introduction to Legal Philosophy (2nd edn, LexisNexis Butterworths, London 2003) 70.
  • 64
    • 57949093131 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See also R Bellamy (ed.), The Rule of Law and the Separation of Powers (Ashgate Publishing, Aldershot, Hampshire 2005) 'Introduction: the Rule of Law as the Rule of Persons'.
    • See also R Bellamy (ed.), The Rule of Law and the Separation of Powers (Ashgate Publishing, Aldershot, Hampshire 2005) 'Introduction: the Rule of Law as the Rule of Persons'.
  • 65
    • 57949109974 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Hart (n 4) 148 and 151.
    • See Hart (n 4) 148 and 151.
  • 66
    • 1642600610 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a recent defence of Hart's account of Parliamentary sovereignty, see, Clarendon Press, Oxford, especially chs 2 and 10
    • For a recent defence of Hart's account of Parliamentary sovereignty, see J Goldsworthy, The Sovereignty of Parliament: History and Philosophy (Clarendon Press, Oxford 1999), especially chs 2 and 10.
    • (1999) The Sovereignty of Parliament: History and Philosophy
    • Goldsworthy, J.1
  • 67
    • 57949113272 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Above (n 4) 247
    • Above (n 4) 247.
  • 68
    • 0000580092 scopus 로고
    • Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals
    • See also, 598-629
    • See also Hart, 'Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals', (1958) 71 Harvard Law Review 598-629.
    • (1958) Harvard Law Review , vol.71
    • Hart1
  • 69
    • 57949112020 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In the posthumously published postscript to The Concept of Law, Hart endorses so-called 'soft' positivism according to which it is acceptable for moral norms to be incorporated by reference into the ultimate rule of recognition. Above (n 4) 250-4
    • In the posthumously published postscript to The Concept of Law, Hart endorses so-called 'soft' positivism according to which it is acceptable for moral norms to be incorporated by reference into the ultimate rule of recognition. Above (n 4) 250-4.
  • 70
    • 57949087717 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is to be contrasted with so-called 'hard' positivism, which does not allow for any recourse to morality in identifying the law. See, for instance, J Raz, The Authority of Law, Essays on Law and Morality Clarendon Press, Oxford 1979
    • This is to be contrasted with so-called 'hard' positivism, which does not allow for any recourse to morality in identifying the law. See, for instance, J Raz, The Authority of Law, Essays on Law and Morality (Clarendon Press, Oxford 1979).
  • 71
    • 57949102685 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Indeed, this is a claim made by a number of eminent constitutional theorists. See section 3 below.
    • Indeed, this is a claim made by a number of eminent constitutional theorists. See section 3 below.
  • 72
    • 57949095407 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 42 MLR 1-21
    • (1979) 42 MLR 1-21.
  • 73
    • 57949100436 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid 16.
  • 74
    • 57949113640 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid.
  • 75
    • 57949114316 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Above (n 52) 19
    • Above (n 52) 19.
  • 77
    • 85203999849 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a similar reading of Griffith, see, Hart Publishing, Oxford
    • For a similar reading of Griffith, see A Tomkins, Our Republican Constitution (Hart Publishing, Oxford 2005) 37-9.
    • (2005) Our Republican Constitution , pp. 37-39
    • Tomkins, A.1
  • 78
    • 57949106956 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf T Poole, 'Tilting at Windmills? Truth and Illusion in The Political Constitution' (2007) 70 MLR 250 77, 253 and, especially, at 274-7.
    • Cf T Poole, 'Tilting at Windmills? Truth and Illusion in "The Political Constitution"' (2007) 70 MLR 250 77, 253 and, especially, at 274-7.
  • 80
    • 57949093304 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See S Sedley, The Sound of Silence: Constitutional Law without a Constitution' (1994) 110 LQR 270-91
    • See S Sedley, The Sound of Silence: Constitutional Law without a Constitution' (1994) 110 LQR 270-91
  • 81
    • 0001289944 scopus 로고
    • Human Rights: A Twenty-First Century Agenda
    • 'Human Rights: A Twenty-First Century Agenda' [1995] PL 386-400, 389,
    • (1995) , vol.PL 386-400 , pp. 389
  • 82
    • 57949107669 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and 'The Common Law and the Constitution', in Lord Nolan of Brasted and Sir Stephen Sedley (eds), The Making and Remaking of the British Constitution (Blackstone Press, London 1997) 26.
    • and 'The Common Law and the Constitution', in Lord Nolan of Brasted and Sir Stephen Sedley (eds), The Making and Remaking of the British Constitution (Blackstone Press, London 1997) 26.
  • 83
    • 57949099427 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See J Griffith 'The Common Law and the Political Constitution', (2001) 117 LQR 42-67.
    • See J Griffith 'The Common Law and the Political Constitution', (2001) 117 LQR 42-67.
  • 84
    • 57949083635 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Commentators sometimes refer to Griffith as a 'functionalist'. There is some disagreement though as to whether such a label implies a 'descriptive' or 'prescriptive' approach, or both. See M Loughlin, 'The Functionalist Style in Public Law' (2005) 55 University of Toronto Law Journal 361-403, 368.
    • Commentators sometimes refer to Griffith as a 'functionalist'. There is some disagreement though as to whether such a label implies a 'descriptive' or 'prescriptive' approach, or both. See M Loughlin, 'The Functionalist Style in Public Law' (2005) 55 University of Toronto Law Journal 361-403, 368.
  • 85
    • 57949111857 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. A Tomkins, (n 54) 39.
    • , vol.39 , Issue.54
    • Tomkins, C.A.1
  • 86
    • 57949099951 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Above n 6
    • Above (n 6).
  • 87
    • 57949090838 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid.
  • 88
    • 57949100954 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, particular, Lord Hope [124, Lord Bingham [36, Lord Nicholls [63] and the
    • See, in particular, Lord Hope [124], Lord Bingham [36], Lord Nicholls [63] and the Court of Appeal [2005] QB 579 [97].
    • (2005) Court of Appeal , vol.QB 579 , pp. 97
  • 89
    • 57949103122 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid [25].
  • 90
    • 57949096267 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid [24].
  • 91
    • 57949116031 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid.
  • 92
    • 57949108408 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid [32].
  • 93
    • 57949104222 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid.
  • 95
    • 57949099598 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid [59]. Lord Carswell explicitly agrees with Lord Nicholl's reading at [175].
    • Ibid [59]. Lord Carswell explicitly agrees with Lord Nicholl's reading at [175].
  • 96
    • 57949084169 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid [61].
  • 97
    • 57949085802 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid [79].
  • 98
    • 57949105074 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Similarly see Lord Rodger at [139].
    • Similarly see Lord Rodger at [139].
  • 99
    • 57949088209 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid [102].
  • 100
    • 57949094693 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid [120].
  • 101
    • 57949117376 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid [159].
  • 105
    • 57949096636 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Above (n 49) 236
    • Above (n 49) 236.
  • 106
    • 57949107668 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid 240.
  • 107
    • 57949094575 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Is Parliament Sovereign? Recent Challenges to the Doctrine of Parliamentary Sovereignty
    • See also
    • See also J Goldsworthy, 'Is Parliament Sovereign? Recent Challenges to the Doctrine of Parliamentary Sovereignty' (2005) 3 New Zealand Journal of Public and International Law 7-37, 7.
    • (2005) New Zealand Journal of Public and International Law , vol.3
    • Goldsworthy, J.1
  • 108
    • 57949114553 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is particularly so in relation to the dictum of Lord Hope (n 70) who seems to suggest in characteristically Austinian fashion that the limits on sovereignty are extra-legal rather than legal limits
    • This is particularly so in relation to the dictum of Lord Hope (n 70) who seems to suggest in characteristically Austinian fashion that the limits on sovereignty are extra-legal rather than legal limits.
  • 109
    • 57949101497 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Distinguishing this case from Pickin v. British Railways Board [1974] AC 765.
    • Distinguishing this case from Pickin v. British Railways Board [1974] AC 765.
  • 110
    • 57949109063 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • n 6, 25] and [110
    • Jackson (n 6) [25] and [110].
    • Jackson
  • 111
    • 57949106306 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid [102] and [159].
    • Ibid [102] and [159].
  • 112
    • 57949094853 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid [120].
  • 113
    • 0002388111 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Wade 'The Basis of Legal Sovereignty' (1955) 13 CLJ 172-97.
    • Wade 'The Basis of Legal Sovereignty' (1955) 13 CLJ 172-97.
  • 117
    • 57949115233 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Competing Models of Judicial Review
    • For an excellent discussion of the similarities, on this point, between Wade and Laws, see, C Forsyth ed, Hart Publishing, Oxford and Portland, Oregon
    • For an excellent discussion of the similarities, on this point, between Wade and Laws, see P Craig, 'Competing Models of Judicial Review' in C Forsyth (ed) Judicial Review and the Constitution (Hart Publishing, Oxford and Portland, Oregon 2000).
    • (2000) Judicial Review and the Constitution
    • Craig, P.1
  • 118
    • 57949084912 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This reflects the classical 'social contract' position whereby citizens give their tacit consent to the authority of the state only under certain conditions, say, of liberty and equality. See, for instance, J Locke, Peter Laslett ed, Two Treatises of Government CUP, Cambridge 2003
    • This reflects the classical 'social contract' position whereby citizens give their tacit consent to the authority of the state only under certain conditions, say, of liberty and equality. See, for instance, J Locke, Peter Laslett ed.), Two Treatises of Government (CUP, Cambridge 2003).
  • 119
    • 57949102334 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This type of approach is found in theories of civic republicanism. See, for instance, Tomkins n 56
    • This type of approach is found in theories of civic republicanism. See, for instance, Tomkins (n 56).
  • 120
    • 57949107667 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See also Lord Woolf CJ in the Court of Appeal in Jackson who includes attitudes of 'the populace' in the calculation, (n 62).
    • See also Lord Woolf CJ in the Court of Appeal in Jackson who includes attitudes of 'the populace' in the calculation, (n 62).
  • 121
    • 57949092428 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Hart, n 4 148
    • See Hart, (n 4) 148.
  • 122
    • 57949114154 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid 117.
  • 123
    • 57949112949 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Jackson, (n 6) [81].
    • See Jackson, (n 6) [81].
  • 124
    • 57949089352 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This applies, a fortiori, to Griffith for whom the identity of the ultimate lawmaker does not even require acceptance by officials: Parliament is whatever it happens to be. See (n 52) 16
    • This applies, a fortiori, to Griffith for whom the identity of the ultimate lawmaker does not even require acceptance by officials: Parliament is whatever it happens to be. See (n 52) 16.
  • 125
    • 57949086973 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • To use Dworkin's two dimensions of interpretation, this reasoning neither 'fits' nor 'justifies' the fact that Parliament possesses legislative powers in the British constitution. See R Dworkin, Law's Empire, (n 7) 139.
    • To use Dworkin's two dimensions of interpretation, this reasoning neither 'fits' nor 'justifies' the fact that Parliament possesses legislative powers in the British constitution. See R Dworkin, Law's Empire, (n 7) 139.
  • 126
    • 57949108035 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Jackson, (n 6) [157]. This principle, I think, justifies the view expressed by different judges that the point of the 1911 Act was to restrict the power of the House of Lords.
    • See Jackson, (n 6) [157]. This principle, I think, justifies the view expressed by different judges that the point of the 1911 Act was to restrict the power of the House of Lords.
  • 127
    • 57949084001 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It would be odd then if these principles played no part in the way that judges define the concept of Parliament
    • The principles of democracy and checks and balances are, of course, precisely the types of principles that have historically motivated political debates about the reform of Parliament. See, Lord Wakeham Cmnd 4534, 2000
    • The principles of democracy and checks and balances are, of course, precisely the types of principles that have historically motivated political debates about the reform of Parliament. See, for instance, Report of the Royal Commission on the Reform of the House of Lords (Chair: Lord Wakeham) Cmnd 4534, 2000). It would be odd then if these principles played no part in the way that judges define the concept of Parliament.
    • Report of the Royal Commission on the Reform of the House of Lords (Chair
    • for instance1
  • 128
    • 57949114315 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I certainly do not mean to imply that there cannot be law unless there is democracy. If it were plausible to suppose that Freemasons and Knights of the Realm (or whomever) do in fact exercise legislative power in British legal practice, then it may be that we could justify that power according to, say, the principle of protected expectations or certainty if most people in fact obeyed their edicts
    • I certainly do not mean to imply that there cannot be law unless there is democracy. If it were plausible to suppose that Freemasons and Knights of the Realm (or whomever) do in fact exercise legislative power in British legal practice, then it may be that we could justify that power according to, say, the principle of protected expectations or certainty if most people in fact obeyed their edicts.
  • 129
    • 57949098067 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Hart, n 4 151
    • See Hart, (n 4) 151.
  • 130
    • 57949107478 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For an insightful discussion of the legal and constitutional implications of this type of development in Britain, see R Dworkin, A Bill of Rights for Britain Chatto & Windus, London 1990
    • For an insightful discussion of the legal and constitutional implications of this type of development in Britain, see R Dworkin, A Bill of Rights for Britain (Chatto & Windus, London 1990).
  • 131
    • 57949102682 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Baroness Hale plays with these types of ideas but she does so, it is suggested, without recognising that there are certain principled limits to the ways in which Parliament qua Parliament can redefine itself. See Jackson, n 6 [163].
    • Baroness Hale plays with these types of ideas but she does so, it is suggested, without recognising that there are certain principled limits to the ways in which Parliament qua Parliament can redefine itself. See Jackson, n 6) [163].
  • 133
    • 57949099597 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and Law's Empire (n 7) ch 4.
    • and Law's Empire (n 7) ch 4.
  • 134
    • 57949102950 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Jackson, (n 6) [67]-[69] and [171].
    • See Jackson, (n 6) [67]-[69] and [171].
  • 135
    • 57949104892 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Under the rule in Pepper v Hart [1993] AC 593.
    • Under the rule in Pepper v Hart [1993] AC 593.
  • 136
    • 57949109973 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Jackson, (n 6) [65], [97] and [98].
    • See Jackson, (n 6) [65], [97] and [98].
  • 137
    • 57949101793 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Hart, (n 4) 123, 147-54 and 251.
    • See Hart, (n 4) 123, 147-54 and 251.
  • 138
    • 57949099594 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, generally, chs 1 and 2
    • See, generally, R Dworkin, Justice in Robes (n 7), chs 1 and 2.
    • Justice in Robes , Issue.7
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 139
    • 57949103855 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See J Griffith, 'The Brave New World of Sir John Laws', (2000) 63 MLR 159-76.
    • See J Griffith, 'The Brave New World of Sir John Laws', (2000) 63 MLR 159-76.
  • 140
    • 57949104221 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Again, this is the position of so-called 'soft' or 'inclusive' positivists. See (n 50).
    • Again, this is the position of so-called 'soft' or 'inclusive' positivists. See (n 50).
  • 142
    • 57949097152 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dworkin helpfully expresses these differences in reasoning in terms of 'concurrent' and 'conventional' morality. As he says, 'A community displays a concurrent morality when its members are agreed in asserting the same, or much the same, normative rule, but they do not count the fact of that agreement as an essential part of their grounds for asserting that rule. It displays a conventional morality when they do'. Ibid 53.
    • Dworkin helpfully expresses these differences in reasoning in terms of 'concurrent' and 'conventional' morality. As he says, 'A community displays a concurrent morality when its members are agreed in asserting the same, or much the same, normative rule, but they do not count the fact of that agreement as an essential part of their grounds for asserting that rule. It displays a conventional morality when they do'. Ibid 53.
  • 143
    • 57949090656 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, for example, Forsyth, (n 22).
    • See, for example, Forsyth, (n 22).
  • 144
    • 57949090268 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See C Forsyth and M Elliott
    • The so-called 'modified' ultra vires theory seeks to preserve this basic intuition albeit that Parliament is said to have an abstract intention that judges give effect to the rule of law rather than concrete intentions as to particular principles of judicial review, PL
    • The so-called 'modified' ultra vires theory seeks to preserve this basic intuition albeit that Parliament is said to have an abstract intention that judges give effect to the rule of law rather than concrete intentions as to particular principles of judicial review. See C Forsyth and M Elliott, 'The Legitimacy of Judicial Review' [2003] PL 286-307.
    • (2003) The Legitimacy of Judicial Review , pp. 286-307
  • 146
    • 57949097156 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • P Craig, 'Utra Vires and the Foundations of Judicial Review', (n 20).
    • P Craig, 'Utra Vires and the Foundations of Judicial Review', (n 20).
  • 149
    • 57949115053 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibis, I think, is clearly the meaning afforded to the term 'sovereignty' by a number of other leading constitutional theorists.
    • Ibis, I think, is clearly the meaning afforded to the term 'sovereignty' by a number of other leading constitutional theorists.
  • 150
    • 57949109796 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Sedley, n 57
    • See Sedley, (n 57)
  • 151
    • 57949113639 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • TRS Allan, n 86
    • TRS Allan, (n 86).
  • 152
    • 57949088207 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • UK lawyers commonly use phrases such as 'shared sovereignty' or 'pooled sovereignty' (among many other variations) when they refer to the relationship between the United Kingdom and the EU institutions. See, for example, Neil Walker, 'Late Sovereignty in the European Union', in Walker (ed.), Sovereignty in Transition (Hart Publishing, Oxford 2003) 10-18.
    • UK lawyers commonly use phrases such as 'shared sovereignty' or 'pooled sovereignty' (among many other variations) when they refer to the relationship between the United Kingdom and the EU institutions. See, for example, Neil Walker, 'Late Sovereignty in the European Union', in Walker (ed.), Sovereignty in Transition (Hart Publishing, Oxford 2003) 10-18.
  • 153
    • 57949110925 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In the European context, just as in the context of the powers of institutions within a state, the word sovereignty, I think, seems to connote something like 'power' or perhaps more aptly 'competence, Other commentators have lately dispensed with the language of sovereignty and described the relationship between member states and the EU as one of 'legal pluralism, See N MacCormick, Questioning Sovereignty: Law, State, and Nation in the European Commonwealth OUP, Oxford 1999
    • In the European context, just as in the context of the powers of institutions within a state, the word sovereignty, I think, seems to connote something like 'power' or perhaps more aptly 'competence'. Other commentators have lately dispensed with the language of sovereignty and described the relationship between member states and the EU as one of 'legal pluralism'. See N MacCormick, Questioning Sovereignty: Law, State, and Nation in the European Commonwealth (OUP, Oxford 1999)
  • 154
    • 34147211700 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Idea of a European Constitution
    • 27 OJLS 1-21, 14
    • P Eleftheriadis, 'The Idea of a European Constitution' (2007) 27 OJLS 1-21, 14.
    • (2007)
    • Eleftheriadis, P.1
  • 155
    • 57949094576 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In the context of public international law too, there appears to be a movement away from the idea of absolute sovereign states towards the idea that there are certain normative conditions attached to the exercise of state power. See M Koskenniemi, From Apology to Utopia CUP, Cambridge 2005, ch 4
    • In the context of public international law too, there appears to be a movement away from the idea of absolute sovereign states towards the idea that there are certain normative conditions attached to the exercise of state power. See M Koskenniemi, From Apology to Utopia (CUP, Cambridge 2005), ch 4.
  • 156
    • 57949097717 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As Jowell has recently put it, the allocation of political power depends on 'a moral claim to its exercise (or limitation)'. See Jowell, 'Parliamentary Sovereignty' (n 20) 565-6.
    • As Jowell has recently put it, the allocation of political power depends on 'a moral claim to its exercise (or limitation)'. See Jowell, 'Parliamentary Sovereignty' (n 20) 565-6.
  • 157
    • 57949092084 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The most assiduous proponent of this type of theory is TRS Allan. See (n 86).
    • The most assiduous proponent of this type of theory is TRS Allan. See (n 86).
  • 158
    • 57949113442 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See also Lord Woolf 'Droit Public - English Style' [1995] PL 57-71.
    • See also Lord Woolf 'Droit Public - English Style' [1995] PL 57-71.
  • 159
    • 57949085097 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It might be argued though that the House of Lords has recognised the primacy of the principle of legality through its 'constitutional rights' jurisprudence. See generally Jowell n 20
    • It might be argued though that the House of Lords has recognised the primacy of the principle of legality through its 'constitutional rights' jurisprudence. See generally Jowell (n 20).
  • 160
    • 57949101792 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • n 6, 107, my emphasis
    • Jackson (n 6) [107] (my emphasis).
    • Jackson
  • 162
    • 57949105959 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Jackson (n 6) [104].
    • Jackson (n 6) [104].
  • 163
    • 57949102492 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See also similarly P Craig (n 106) 107-11 who suggests that sovereignty does not mean 'absolute' sovereignty; judges place a variety of different constraints on sovereign power through various different forms of statutory interpretation. Craig makes his argument in response to Allan's view that the idea of Parliamentary Sovereignty cannot permit of any limits to Parliament's power.
    • See also similarly P Craig (n 106) 107-11 who suggests that sovereignty does not mean 'absolute' sovereignty; judges place a variety of different constraints on sovereign power through various different forms of statutory interpretation. Craig makes his argument in response to Allan's view that the idea of Parliamentary Sovereignty cannot permit of any limits to Parliament's power.
  • 165
    • 57949099596 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For detailed discussion on this question, see, for instance
    • For detailed discussion on this question, see, for instance, Goldsworthy (n 49) 250,
    • , vol.250 , Issue.49
    • Goldsworthy1
  • 167
    • 57949091912 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Indeed, even if one were to adopt an Austinian or Hartian account of the power of law-makers, it would make no sense to speak in terms of legal limits on sovereignty. The Austinian sovereign is, by definition legally unlimited; and for Hart, the law-making powers of Parliament (or some other law-maker) are determined by a rule of recognition. In this respect, it is submitted that Allan (n 120) must be correct.
    • Indeed, even if one were to adopt an Austinian or Hartian account of the power of law-makers, it would make no sense to speak in terms of legal limits on sovereignty. The Austinian sovereign is, by definition legally unlimited; and for Hart, the law-making powers of Parliament (or some other law-maker) are determined by a rule of recognition. In this respect, it is submitted that Allan (n 120) must be correct.
  • 168
    • 57949086789 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Jackson (n 6) [107].
    • Jackson (n 6) [107].
  • 173
    • 57949095232 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Hart (n 4) 91-7
    • See Hart (n 4) 91-7
  • 175
    • 57949105401 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hence, many judges require only that a document appear 'on the Parliamentary roll, See
    • Hence, many judges require only that a document appear 'on the Parliamentary roll'. See Lord Hope in Jackson (n 6) [112].
    • Hope in Jackson (n 6) , vol.112
    • Lord1
  • 176
    • 57949115495 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • These conditions equate roughly to Hart's emphasis on consensus and the core meaning of words. See sections 1 and 2 above. Dworkin recasts Hart's 'descriptive' theory as an 'interpretive' morally engaged theory which he describes as 'conventionalism'. See Dworkin, Law's Empire (n 7) ch 4.
    • These conditions equate roughly to Hart's emphasis on consensus and the core meaning of words. See sections 1 and 2 above. Dworkin recasts Hart's 'descriptive' theory as an 'interpretive' morally engaged theory which he describes as 'conventionalism'. See Dworkin, Law's Empire (n 7) ch 4.
  • 177
    • 57949114552 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • According to this interpretation of British legal practice, there are moral reasons to count clear, well-known and widely accepted rules as the operative standards in the constitution. As I have explained (n 8), I endorse this reading of Hart.
    • According to this interpretation of British legal practice, there are moral reasons to count clear, well-known and widely accepted rules as the operative standards in the constitution. As I have explained (n 8), I endorse this reading of Hart.
  • 178
    • 57949110556 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is the position taken by so-called 'ethical' positivists. See T Campbell, Prescriptive Legal Positivism: Law, Rights and Democracy Routledge-Cavendish, 2004
    • This is the position taken by so-called 'ethical' positivists. See T Campbell, Prescriptive Legal Positivism: Law, Rights and Democracy (Routledge-Cavendish, 2004)
  • 179
    • 3843070366 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Normative (or Ethical) Positivism
    • J Coleman ed, ch 12
    • J Waldron, 'Normative (or Ethical) Positivism' in J Coleman (ed), Hart's Postscript (n 33), ch 12.
    • Hart's Postscript , Issue.33
    • Waldron, J.1
  • 180
    • 57949110926 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is a rough account of Dworkin's theory of law as integrity. See Dworkin, Law's Empire (n 7) ch 6
    • This is a rough account of Dworkin's theory of law as integrity. See Dworkin, Law's Empire (n 7) ch 6.
  • 181
    • 57949107311 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A number of theorists have objected to an expansive definition of the concept of legality on the basis that it robs the concept of any independent value. See Raz, n 50 299
    • A number of theorists have objected to an expansive definition of the concept of legality on the basis that it robs the concept of any independent value. See Raz, (n 50) 299.
  • 184
    • 57949095230 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Jackson (n 6) [107].
    • Jackson (n 6) [107].
  • 185
    • 57949083456 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Other argue in support of some other value or values. Sir John Laws, for example, has placed the value of autonomy at the heart of his constitutional theory. See Sir John Laws 'The Constitution: Morals and Rights' [1996] PL 622-35.
    • Other argue in support of some other value or values. Sir John Laws, for example, has placed the value of autonomy at the heart of his constitutional theory. See Sir John Laws 'The Constitution: Morals and Rights' [1996] PL 622-35.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.