메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 26, Issue 4, 2006, Pages 683-704

Legal positivism: Still descriptive and morally neutral

(1)  Marmor, Andrei a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 33845695477     PISSN: 01436503     EISSN: 14643820     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1093/ojls/gqi028     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (59)

References (62)
  • 1
    • 33845691811 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Often the same philosophers make both types of claims. Prominent examples of the first type of normative positivism were suggested by Ronald Dworkin, Jeremy Waldron, Tom Campbell, and Neil MacCormick; the second type of claim has been put forward by Dworkin, Waldron, Michael Moore, Stephen Perry, Gerald Postema, and others. References to these works will be mentioned in appropriate places below.
  • 3
    • 0004220262 scopus 로고
    • See (Oxford, 1st edn)
    • See The Concept of Law (Oxford, 1st edn, 1961) at 205-06.
    • (1961) The Concept of Law , pp. 205-206
  • 4
    • 3843108473 scopus 로고
    • 'A Moralistic Case for A-Moralistic Law'
    • If I understand MacCormick correctly, this is one of the main arguments he also makes in However, at points MacCormick seems also to endorse a version of the argument of type 3
    • If I understand MacCormick correctly, this is one of the main arguments he also makes in 'A Moralistic Case for A-Moralistic Law', 20 Valparaiso L Rev. 1 (1985). However, at points MacCormick seems also to endorse a version of the argument of type 3.
    • (1985) Valparaiso L Rev. , vol.20 , pp. 1
  • 5
    • 33845685617 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • One may wonder how this view differs from Ethical Legal Positivism. I will try to explain this in section 3
    • One may wonder how this view differs from Ethical Legal Positivism. I will try to explain this in section 3.
  • 7
    • 33845706793 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Arguably, there are single-purpose instruments that can only be used for one particular purpose, that may be either good or bad, or perhaps neither. No pure example comes to my mind, however, an in any case, it is clear that the law is not such a case. And of course we should also bear in mind that instruments can be used for purposes other than those for which they were created.
  • 8
    • 33845709697 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • One way to understand Thomist Natural Law is that it claims that the law essentially promotes the common good, and therefore the law is essentially good. (See Aquinas, Summa Theologica, Article 2, concl.) Still, there is an ambiguity here about what this 'essential' predicate denotes. As I explain below, something can be necessarily valuable instrumentally. If this is a plausible interpretation of Aquinas' thesis, it is not at odds with legal positivism.
  • 9
    • 0003516637 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It may be thought that Kelsen is a notable exception. The Basic Norm is not a social rule, Kelsen claimed, but a theoretical presupposition. But this is not quite accurate, since Kelsen acknowledges that what the Basic Norm in any give society is, depends on actual practice or, its 'efficacy', as Kelsen calls it. (e.g.)
    • It may be thought that Kelsen is a notable exception. The Basic Norm is not a social rule, Kelsen claimed, but a theoretical presupposition. But this is not quite accurate, since Kelsen acknowledges that what the Basic Norm in any give society is, depends on actual practice or, its 'efficacy', as Kelsen calls it. (e.g. General Theory of Law and State at 118).
    • General Theory of Law and State , pp. 118
  • 10
    • 9944254486 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Thus even if the idea of the Basic Norm is a presupposition, what the Basic Norm in any given society at any given time is, is a matter of social practice. (I have elaborated on this in my entry on Pure Theory of law, Also, it is not entirely clear whether Joseph Raz subscribes to this idea about social rules. As far as I know, he has not explicitly endorsed it anywhere. His sources thesis, however, is certainly compatible with it
    • Thus even if the idea of the Basic Norm is a presupposition, what the Basic Norm in any given society at any given time is, is a matter of social practice. (I have elaborated on this in my entry on Pure Theory of law, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/lawphil-theory) Also, it is not entirely clear whether Joseph Raz subscribes to this idea about social rules. As far as I know, he has not explicitly endorsed it anywhere. His sources thesis, however, is certainly compatible with it.
    • The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
  • 11
    • 31144474957 scopus 로고
    • See, for example, (Oxford, rev ed)
    • See, for example, Raz, Ethics in the Public Domain (Oxford, rev ed 1994) at 195.
    • (1994) Ethics in the Public Domain , pp. 195
    • Raz1
  • 14
    • 0040223979 scopus 로고
    • 'The Concept of Law Revisited'
    • For a critique of understanding the rules of recognition as conventions, see, for example
    • For a critique of understanding the rules of recognition as conventions, see, for example, L. Green, 'The Concept of Law Revisited', 94 Michigan L Rev. 1687 (1994).
    • (1994) Michigan L Rev. , vol.94 , pp. 1687
    • Green, L.1
  • 15
    • 0038413610 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For my own defence of the exclusive version of legal positivism, see (Oxford) ch 3
    • For my own defence of the exclusive version of legal positivism, see Positive Law and Objective Values (Oxford, 2001) ch 3.
    • (2001) Positive Law and Objective Values
  • 16
    • 3843097695 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Legal Positivism: 5 1/2 Myths'
    • See, for example
    • See, for example, J. Gardner, 'Legal Positivism: 5 1/2 Myths', American Journal of Jurisprudence, 46 (2001), 199.
    • (2001) American Journal of Jurisprudence , vol.46 , pp. 199
    • Gardner, J.1
  • 17
    • 33845686531 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Why necessarily? The idea would have to be that a form of regime or de-facto authority that is completely wicked and promotes absolutely nothing of value, could not be recognized as a legal order, would simply not function as law, so to speak. I am not sure about this argument, and I certainly do not wish to defend it here. I tend to think that this is contingently true as a rough generalization, but not necessarily.
  • 19
    • 33845693773 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • With the exception, perhaps, of John Austin
    • With the exception, perhaps, of John Austin.
  • 20
    • 33845692953 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Unless, of course, by 'reference to morality' one means a reliance on moral judgments and evaluations.
  • 21
    • 33845707988 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Not necessarily, though. Even when the law is clear, it may be the case that judges are not under a legal duty to apply it to the particular case at hand; they may still have the legal power to change the law.
  • 22
    • 0003529325 scopus 로고
    • (Oxford) denies that it is accurate to ascribe this view to Thomist Natural Law. But the position is not unfamiliar, and adherents persist
    • John Finnis Natural Law & Natural Rights (Oxford, 1980) denies that it is accurate to ascribe this view to Thomist Natural Law. But the position is not unfamiliar, and adherents persist.
    • (1980) Natural Law & Natural Rights
    • Finnis, J.1
  • 25
    • 0038413610 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a more detailed account of how Dworkin sees the essential moral element in determining the legal validity of principles, see my
    • For a more detailed account of how Dworkin sees the essential moral element in determining the legal validity of principles, see my Positive Law and Objective Values, at pp. 81-88.
    • Positive Law and Objective Values , pp. 81-88
  • 26
  • 27
    • 0004220262 scopus 로고
    • See, for example, (Oxford, 1st edn)
    • See, for example, The Concept of Law (Oxford, 1st edn, 1961) at 205-06,
    • (1961) The Concept of Law , pp. 205-206
  • 29
    • 33845699036 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'A Moralistic Case for A-Moralistic Law'
    • Note that we assume that P is a set of descriptive propositions. At points, one may get the impression that actually makes this mistake of inferring that P from the thesis that it is morally good if everybody believes that P. But it is not always clear that he takes P to consist of descriptive propositions. In other words, one can interpret MacCormick as advancing a form of Ethical Positivism
    • Note that we assume that P is a set of descriptive propositions. At points, one may get the impression that MacCormick ('A Moralistic Case for A-Moralistic Law') actually makes this mistake of inferring that P from the thesis that it is morally good if everybody believes that P. But it is not always clear that he takes P to consist of descriptive propositions. In other words, one can interpret MacCormick as advancing a form of Ethical Positivism.
    • MacCormick1
  • 30
    • 0003883951 scopus 로고
    • See (Oxford) Furthermore, Postema argues (at p. 331), it is not entirely clear that Bentham was sufficiently aware of the distinction between an account of law as it is and his arguments about how to make law more useful or beneficial
    • See G. Postema, Bentham and the Common Law Tradition (Oxford, 1986). Furthermore, Postema argues (at p. 331), it is not entirely clear that Bentham was sufficiently aware of the distinction between an account of law as it is and his arguments about how to make law more useful or beneficial.
    • (1986) Bentham and the Common Law Tradition
    • Postema, G.1
  • 31
    • 33845704704 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • These kind of concerns have resurfaced recently with the collapse of the Berlin Wall and the decision to prosecute former East-German guards who had 'shot to kill' escapees to the West, allegedly following the legal orders of the regime at the time.
  • 32
    • 0004220262 scopus 로고
    • See above, See, for example, (Oxford, 1st edn)
    • See above, n 21.
    • (1961) The Concept of Law , pp. 205-206
  • 33
    • 3843070366 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Normative (or Ethical) Positivism'
    • See in J. Coleman (ed.), (Oxford)
    • See J. Waldron, 'Normative (or Ethical) Positivism' in J. Coleman (ed.), Hart's Postscript (Oxford, 2001) at 429.
    • (2001) Hart's Postscript , pp. 429
    • Waldron, J.1
  • 34
    • 33845709518 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Hart's Methodological Positivism'
    • See also 323ff. See in J. Coleman (ed.), (Oxford)
    • See also S. Perry 'Hart's Methodological Positivism', ibid. at 311, 323ff.
    • (2001) Hart's Postscript , pp. 311
    • Perry, S.1
  • 35
    • 33845688409 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Even in this case, however, much would depend on the exact content of the claim. As I have earlier indicated, legal positivism is compatible with the thesis that law is necessarily good.
  • 36
    • 33845699606 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hart himself made it quite clear that such functional values are not necessarily moral or normative in the relevant sense, in his reply to Fuller's thesis about the rule of law virtues. See his
    • Hart himself made it quite clear that such functional values are not necessarily moral or normative in the relevant sense, in his reply to Fuller's thesis about the rule of law virtues. See his Essays in Jurisprudence and Philosophy, at 349-50.
    • Essays in Jurisprudence and Philosophy , pp. 349-350
  • 37
    • 4143153716 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'The Rule of Law and its Limits'
    • By this I do not mean to endorse Hart's view that the virtues of the rule of law are purely functional. In fact I have criticized this view in my
    • By this I do not mean to endorse Hart's view that the virtues of the rule of law are purely functional. In fact I have criticized this view in my 'The Rule of Law and its Limits', 23 Law and Philosophy 1 (2003).
    • (2003) Law and Philosophy , vol.23 , pp. 1
  • 41
    • 33845715716 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This should not be confused with a very different type of argument: Raz has argued that the law necessarily claims to be a legitimate authority, and therefore it must meet certain conditions to be the kind of thing that can make such a claim. (Ethics in the Public Domain, ch 9). Raz's argument is not an attempt to derive an is from ought.
  • 42
    • 0038413610 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Since I find the argument structurally invalid, I did not go into the details of its concrete suggestion to view the ideal of protected expectations as central to the legitimacy of law, and its possible connection with an analysis of social conventions. In my I have tried to explain why both of these aspects of Dworkin's suggestion are seriously misguided
    • Since I find the argument structurally invalid, I did not go into the details of its concrete suggestion to view the ideal of protected expectations as central to the legitimacy of law, and its possible connection with an analysis of social conventions. In my Positive Law and Objective Values, 47-48, I have tried to explain why both of these aspects of Dworkin's suggestion are seriously misguided.
    • Positive Law and Objective Values , pp. 47-48
  • 43
    • 26044477858 scopus 로고
    • P. A. Bulloch and J. Raz (eds) (Oxford, 2nd edn)
    • Hart, The Concept of Law, P. A. Bulloch and J. Raz (eds) (Oxford, 2nd edn, 1994) at 240.
    • (1994) The Concept of Law , pp. 240
    • Hart1
  • 44
    • 0009445978 scopus 로고
    • 'Interpretation and Methodology in Legal Theory'
    • in A Marmor (ed.), (Oxford)
    • S. Perry, 'Interpretation and Methodology in Legal Theory' in A Marmor (ed.), Law and Interpretation (Oxford, 1995), 97 at 123.
    • (1995) Law and Interpretation , vol.97 , pp. 123
    • Perry, S.1
  • 45
  • 46
    • 33845711177 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I do not mean to deny that in certain contexts an expression of the form 'x is useful' is meant as a normative endorsement or positive appraisal. I only need to deny, as I do, that this is necessarily the case.
  • 47
    • 33845716753 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Although she does not focus on Perry's arguments, Julie Dickson has advanced a very similar line of reasoning against this methodological challenge in her Evaluation and Legal Theory (Hart Publishing, 2001).
  • 49
    • 3843070366 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Normative (or Ethical) Positivism'
    • 'Normative (or Ethical) Positivism' at 420.
  • 50
    • 3843070366 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Normative (or Ethical) Positivism'
    • Ibid.
  • 51
    • 85008228042 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Hart's Concluding Scientific Postscript'
    • Michael Moore also makes a similar argument in At one point Waldron is unnecessarily too hard on himself: he thinks that this argument commits him to the view that 'in order to do positivist jurisprudence in the normative mode, one has to view law as a good thing' [p. 428] and he rightly wonders whether this is not too strong. But I do not see how he is committed to this strong view at all. All that the argument commits him to (as opposed to Dworkin's argument, perhaps), is to say that normative positivism must have some views about what would make law good, or bad, views that would explain why it is important to distinguish legal from other normative claims. This is not tantamount to viewing law as a good thing. Suppose that somebody thinks that law is actually a bad thing. That would give him a very good reason to strive to distinguish what law is from what it is not
    • Michael Moore also makes a similar argument in 'Hart's Concluding Scientific Postscript', 4 Legal Theory 301 (1998). At one point Waldron is unnecessarily too hard on himself: He thinks that this argument commits him to the view that 'in order to do positivist jurisprudence in the normative mode, one has to view law as a good thing' [p. 428] and he rightly wonders whether this is not too strong. But I do not see how he is committed to this strong view at all. All that the argument commits him to (as opposed to Dworkin's argument, perhaps), is to say that normative positivism must have some views about what would make law good, or bad, views that would explain why it is important to distinguish legal from other normative claims. This is not tantamount to viewing law as a good thing. Suppose that somebody thinks that law is actually a bad thing. That would give him a very good reason to strive to distinguish what law is from what it is not.
    • (1998) Legal Theory , vol.4 , pp. 301
  • 52
    • 0040428020 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, for example, (Oxford)
    • See, for example, J. Raz, Engaging Reason (Oxford, 1999) at 159.
    • (1999) Engaging Reason , pp. 159
    • Raz, J.1
  • 54
    • 3843070366 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Normative (or Ethical) Positivism'
    • A very similar point is made by
    • A very similar point is made by Waldron, 'Normative (or Ethical) Positivism' at 425-26.
    • Waldron1
  • 55
    • 0040428020 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, for example
    • See, for example, Raz, Engaging Reason at 157.
    • Engaging Reason , pp. 157
    • Raz1
  • 56
    • 0004294163 scopus 로고
    • Hart, actually, resisted this last conclusion, at least if it is understood in moral terms. Hart insisted that even 'when judges . . . make committed statements . . . it is not the case that they must necessarily believe that they are referring to a species of moral obligation'. (Oxford) I have some doubts about the point of this debate. If we assume, as seems plausible, that a reason for Ø-ing entails that Ø is valuable, or that Ø-ing will bring about something valuable, then committed participants must be taken to presume that the reasons for following the law are reasons that derive from some values the law promotes. I tend to think that it matters very little whether we classify these values as necessarily 'moral' or not. Morality has very fuzzy boundaries anyway
    • Hart, actually, resisted this last conclusion, at least if it is understood in moral terms. Hart insisted that even 'when judges . . . make committed statements . . . it is not the case that they must necessarily believe that they are referring to a species of moral obligation'. (Essays on Bentham (Oxford, 1982) at 161.) I have some doubts about the point of this debate. If we assume, as seems plausible, that a reason for Ø-ing entails that Ø is valuable, or that Ø-ing will bring about something valuable, then committed participants must be taken to presume that the reasons for following the law are reasons that derive from some values the law promotes. I tend to think that it matters very little whether we classify these values as necessarily 'moral' or not. Morality has very fuzzy boundaries anyway.
    • (1982) Essays on Bentham , pp. 161
  • 57
    • 33845693175 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Of course I could not understand Sarah's choice if I had no idea what thrillers and melodramas are, and what are the differences between them. But my understanding of Sarah's reasoning about such matters is simply not affected by my own views about the values of thrillers and melodramas, or such. My own evaluative preferences are simply not relevant here.
  • 58
    • 0009328199 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I have done that elsewhere; see my (Hart Publishing, revised 2nd edn)
    • I have done that elsewhere; see my Interpretation and Legal Theory (Hart Publishing, revised 2nd edn, 2005).
    • (2005) Interpretation and Legal Theory
  • 61
    • 33845710834 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'The Rule of Law and Its Limits'
    • See my and references there
    • See my 'The Rule of Law and Its Limits' at 5, and references there.
  • 62
    • 84972620169 scopus 로고
    • 'The Political Content of Legal Theory'
    • For a similar argument, claiming that law is not an essentially contested concept, see
    • For a similar argument, claiming that law is not an essentially contested concept, see L. Green, 'The Political Content of Legal Theory', 17 Philosophy and Social Sciences 1 (1987) at 16-20.
    • (1987) Philosophy and Social Sciences , vol.17 , Issue.1 , pp. 16-20
    • Green, L.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.