메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 34, Issue 4, 2008, Pages 601-625

The responsibilities of victory: Jus post bellum and the Just War

(1)  Bellamy, Alex J a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 51349115514     PISSN: 02602105     EISSN: 14699044     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1017/S026021050800819X     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (70)

References (137)
  • 1
    • 51349102303 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Inter alia Brian Orend, 'Justice after War'
    • Inter alia Brian Orend, 'Justice after War', Ethics and International Affairs, 16:1 (2002):
    • (2002) Ethics and International Affairs , vol.16 , pp. 1
  • 2
    • 85055303569 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Just and Unjust Occupations
    • Winter
    • Michael Walzer, 'Just and Unjust Occupations', Dissent, Winter 2004,
    • (2004) Dissent
    • Walzer, M.1
  • 3
    • 84937383727 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Jus Post Bellum: The Importance of War Crimes Trials
    • Davida E. Kellogg, 'Jus Post Bellum: The Importance of War Crimes Trials', Parameters, 32:3 (2002), pp. 87-99,
    • (2002) Parameters , vol.32 , Issue.3 , pp. 87-99
    • Kellogg, D.E.1
  • 4
    • 70949102118 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Jus Post Bellum: The Moral Responsibilities if Victors in War
    • Louis V. Iasiello, 'Jus Post Bellum: The Moral Responsibilities if Victors in War', Naval War College Review, 57:3/4 (2004),
    • (2004) Naval War College Review , vol.57 , pp. 3-4
    • Iasiello, L.V.1
  • 9
    • 51349113112 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Especially Noah Feldman, What We Owe Iraq: War and the Ethics of Nation Building (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2006) and forthcoming special section of Ethics and International Affairs.
    • Especially Noah Feldman, What We Owe Iraq: War and the Ethics of Nation Building (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2006) and forthcoming special section of Ethics and International Affairs.
  • 10
    • 51349167891 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For instance. Carsten Stahn. 'Jus ad bellum Jus in bello . . . Jus post bellum: Towards a Tripartite Conception of Armed Conflict', Florence Agora Papers, 2005.
    • For instance. Carsten Stahn. 'Jus ad bellum Jus in bello . . . Jus post bellum: Towards a Tripartite Conception of Armed Conflict', Florence Agora Papers, 2005.
  • 11
    • 0004010604 scopus 로고
    • trans. H. Bettenson London: Penguin
    • Augustine, The City of God, trans. H. Bettenson (London: Penguin, 1972), p. 866;
    • (1972) The City of God , pp. 866
    • Augustine1
  • 12
    • 51349116214 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and see Brian Orend, 'Justice after War', Ethics and International Affairs, 16:1 (2002), p. 43.
    • and see Brian Orend, 'Justice after War', Ethics and International Affairs, 16:1 (2002), p. 43.
  • 13
    • 79954697924 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Was the War in Iraq a Humanitarian Intervention?
    • Kenneth Roth, 'Was the War in Iraq a Humanitarian Intervention?'. Journal of Military Ethics, 5:2 (2006).
    • (2006) Journal of Military Ethics , vol.5 , pp. 2
    • Roth, K.1
  • 14
    • 33645072445 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • One of the few voices of scepticism about jus post bellum aired to date is Nicholas Rengger, 'The Judgment of War: On the Idea of Legitimate Force in World Politics', Review of International Studies, 31:5 (2005), p.
    • One of the few voices of scepticism about jus post bellum aired to date is Nicholas Rengger, 'The Judgment of War: On the Idea of Legitimate Force in World Politics', Review of International Studies, 31:5 (2005), p.
  • 15
    • 51349159407 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Immanuel Kant, Perpetual Peace: A Philosophical Essay (1795) trans. M. Campbell Smith (London: Simon Sonnenschein & Co., 1903), p. 131.
    • Immanuel Kant, Perpetual Peace: A Philosophical Essay (1795) trans. M. Campbell Smith (London: Simon Sonnenschein & Co., 1903), p. 131.
  • 16
    • 51349157279 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is the most common position. See Orend, Justice After War, Michael Walzer, Just and Unjust War: A Mora! Argument with Historical Illustrations New York: Basic Books, 1977, p. 119 though more recently Walzer advocated a more maximalist position, see Michael Walzer, Judging War, 2003, available at
    • This is the most common position. See Orend, 'Justice After War', Michael Walzer, Just and Unjust War: A Mora! Argument with Historical Illustrations (New York: Basic Books, 1977), p. 119 though more recently Walzer advocated a more maximalist position, see Michael Walzer. 'Judging War', 2003, available at: (www.boell.de/downloads/verfassung/michaelwalzer.pdf).
  • 17
    • 0036555381 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The idea of Just War as a tradition which contemporary thinkers draw upon as authority to validate contemporary arguments is set out most clearly by Nicholas Rengger, On the Just WatTradition in the Twenty-First Century, International Affairs. 78:2 2002, pp. 353 63
    • The idea of Just War as a tradition which contemporary thinkers draw upon as authority to validate contemporary arguments is set out most clearly by Nicholas Rengger, 'On the Just WatTradition in the Twenty-First Century'. International Affairs. 78:2 (2002), pp. 353 63
  • 18
    • 51349151348 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and developing in, inter alia, Alex J. Bellamy. Just Wars: From Cicero to Iraq (Cambridge: Polity Press. 2006).
    • and developing in, inter alia, Alex J. Bellamy. Just Wars: From Cicero to Iraq (Cambridge: Polity Press. 2006).
  • 20
    • 51349102754 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Orend argues that it may create a 'just cause'. Orend, 'Justice After War', p. 56.
    • Orend argues that it may create a 'just cause'. Orend, 'Justice After War', p. 56.
  • 21
    • 51349110699 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This idea was first put forward by Balthazar Ayala in the sixteenth century. See H. Duchhardt, War and International Law in Europe: Sixteenth to Eighteenth Centuries' in Philippe Contamine (ed, War and Competition Between States Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2000, p. 286
    • This idea was first put forward by Balthazar Ayala in the sixteenth century. See H. Duchhardt. 'War and International Law in Europe: Sixteenth to Eighteenth Centuries' in Philippe Contamine (ed.), War and Competition Between States (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2000), p. 286.
  • 22
    • 51349100498 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Writing in the early sixteenth century, Vitoria viewed war as a quasi-judicial activity properly resorted to in order to right a prior wrong in cases where there was no authoritative judge to adjudicate disputes. Francisco de Vitoria, 'On the Laws of War' in A. Pagden and J. Lawrence (eds), Vitoria: Political Writings (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), p. 303.
    • Writing in the early sixteenth century, Vitoria viewed war as a quasi-judicial activity properly resorted to in order to right a prior wrong in cases where there was no authoritative judge to adjudicate disputes. Francisco de Vitoria, 'On the Laws of War' in A. Pagden and J. Lawrence (eds), Vitoria: Political Writings (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), p. 303.
  • 25
    • 51349099541 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Benedict Kingsbury and Adam Roberts, introduction: Grotian Thought in International Relations', in Medley Bull, Benedict Kingsbury and Adam Roberts (eds): Hugo Grotius and International Relations (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992), p. 16.
    • Benedict Kingsbury and Adam Roberts, introduction: Grotian Thought in International Relations', in Medley Bull, Benedict Kingsbury and Adam Roberts (eds): Hugo Grotius and International Relations (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992), p. 16.
  • 26
    • 51349107131 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The distinction between Vattelian and Grotian conceptions of the law is borrowed from Jason Ralph. America and the International Criminal Court: An International Society Perspective (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007).
    • The distinction between Vattelian and Grotian conceptions of the law is borrowed from Jason Ralph. America and the International Criminal Court: An International Society Perspective (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007).
  • 27
    • 84923989648 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The relationship between law and morality and the nature of the Just War tradition forms one of the most profound debates in contemporary just war thinking. Many ethicists argue that 'Just War' thinking should be divorced from legal concerns (and privileged) on account of its historical authority and concern with justice. See, for instance, Oliver O'Donovan, The Just War Revisited Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 2003
    • The relationship between law and morality and the nature of the Just War tradition forms one of the most profound debates in contemporary just war thinking. Many ethicists argue that 'Just War' thinking should be divorced from legal concerns (and privileged) on account of its historical authority and concern with justice. See, for instance, Oliver O'Donovan, The Just War Revisited (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 2003)
  • 29
    • 33847105336 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Some lawyers, however, argue that law, not ethics, is the normative currency in relation to war, on the grounds that it is legal concerns rather than ethical concerns that animate decision-makers. See, London: Atlantic Books, Following Ian Clark, however, I argue that judgments about the legitimacy of war and peace comprise elements of both a legal and ethical nature, a point that I will elaborate on later
    • Some lawyers, however, argue that law, not ethics, is the normative currency in relation to war, on the grounds that it is legal concerns rather than ethical concerns that animate decision-makers. See Michael Byers, War Law: Understanding Internationa! Law and Armed Conflict (London: Atlantic Books, 2005). Following Ian Clark, however, I argue that judgments about the legitimacy of war and peace comprise elements of both a legal and ethical nature - a point that I will elaborate on later.
    • (2005) War Law: Understanding Internationa! Law and Armed Conflict
    • Byers, M.1
  • 31
    • 0007208632 scopus 로고
    • trans. F. W. Kelsev Washington, DC: Carnegie Council
    • Hugo Grotius, De Jure Belli ac Pacis Libri Tres, trans. F. W. Kelsev (Washington, DC: Carnegie Council, 1925). p. 172.
    • (1925) De Jure Belli ac Pacis Libri Tres , pp. 172
    • Grotius, H.1
  • 35
  • 36
  • 37
  • 38
    • 51349113531 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As Orend puts it, therefore, jus post bellum permits the just victor to (1) roll back the aggression. (2) punish the wrongdoers in the shape of war crimes trials and reparations and (3) require some form of demobilisation and/or political rehabilitation. Orend, 'Justice After War', p. 47.
    • As Orend puts it, therefore, jus post bellum permits the just victor to (1) roll back the aggression. (2) punish the wrongdoers in the shape of war crimes trials and reparations and (3) require some form of demobilisation and/or political rehabilitation. Orend, 'Justice After War', p. 47.
  • 39
    • 27744534672 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Paradox of the International Law of Military Occupation: Sovereignty and the Reformation of Iraq
    • See
    • See Conor McCarthy. 'The Paradox of the International Law of Military Occupation: Sovereignty and the Reformation of Iraq'. Journal of Conflict and Security Law 10:1 (2005), pp. 49-51.
    • (2005) Journal of Conflict and Security Law , vol.10 , Issue.1 , pp. 49-51
    • McCarthy, C.1
  • 41
    • 51349149710 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Article 43 of the Hague Regulations (1907).
    • Article 43 of the Hague Regulations (1907).
  • 42
    • 27844535440 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Legislation and Maintenance of Public Order and Civil Life by Occupying Powers
    • Otherwise, the occupying allies would have been expected to uphold Nazi racial discrimination laws. See
    • Otherwise, the occupying allies would have been expected to uphold Nazi racial discrimination laws. See Marco Sassoli, 'Legislation and Maintenance of Public Order and Civil Life by Occupying Powers', European Journal of International Law, 16:4 (2005), pp. 665-7
    • (2005) European Journal of International Law , vol.16 , Issue.4 , pp. 665-667
    • Sassoli, M.1
  • 43
  • 44
    • 51349144205 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Citing Liddell Hart, Walzer argues that '[t]hc object in war is a better peace', continuing 'better within the confines of the argument for justice, means more secure than the status quo ante bellum. less vulnerable to territorial expansion, safer for ordinary men and women and for their domestic self-determination'. Walzer. Just and Unjust Wars, pp. 122-3.
    • Citing Liddell Hart, Walzer argues that '[t]hc object in war is a better peace', continuing 'better within the confines of the argument for justice, means more secure than the status quo ante bellum. less vulnerable to territorial expansion, safer for ordinary men and women and for their domestic self-determination'. Walzer. Just and Unjust Wars, pp. 122-3.
  • 45
    • 84888230419 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • as Orend puts it, 'one ought not to want the literal restoration of the status quo ante bellum because that situation was precisely what led to armed conflict in the first place'. Brian Orend, 'Jus Post Bellum'
    • Or, as Orend puts it, 'one ought not to want the literal restoration of the status quo ante bellum because that situation was precisely what led to armed conflict in the first place'. Brian Orend, 'Jus Post Bellum', Journal of Social Philosophy, 31:1 (2000). p. 122.
    • (2000) Journal of Social Philosophy , vol.31 , Issue.1 , pp. 122
    • Or1
  • 50
    • 84923989648 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This type of argument gathered momentum after September 11. Thus, for instance. Oliver O'Donovan argued that the legalism predominant in jus ad bellum be replaced by a 'praxis of judgment' that would permit war to end or prevent grave injustice regardless of its legal status, granting the Just War tradition a 'natural law rather than positive law orientation, More pointedly. Elshtain called for a revived Augustinian account of the just war. permitting punishment (by war) of wrongdoers and perceiving the question of just cause in more or less objective terms. Oliver O'Donovan. The Just War Revisited Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003, p. 23
    • This type of argument gathered momentum after September 11. Thus, for instance. Oliver O'Donovan argued that the legalism predominant in jus ad bellum be replaced by a 'praxis of judgment' that would permit war to end or prevent grave injustice regardless of its legal status, granting the Just War tradition a 'natural law rather than positive law orientation'. More pointedly. Elshtain called for a revived Augustinian account of the just war. permitting punishment (by war) of wrongdoers and perceiving the question of just cause in more or less objective terms. Oliver O'Donovan. The Just War Revisited (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003), p. 23,
  • 53
    • 34547700169 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the latter see
    • On the latter see Byers, War Law, p. 2.
    • War Law , pp. 2
    • Byers1
  • 54
    • 51349102752 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Accredited to the Russian delegate F. F. de Martens at the 1899 Hague peace conference, the Martens clause stipulates that: 'Until a more complete code of the laws of war is issued, the High Contracting parties [to the 1899 Hague Convention] declare that in cases not included in the Regulations adopted by them, populations and belligerents remain under the protection of the principles of international law, as they result from the usages established between civilized nations, from the laws of humanity, and the requirements of public conscience'. Cited in Theodore Meron, 'The Martens Clause, Principles of Humanity, and Dictates of Public Conscience', American Journal of International Law, 94:1 (2000). p. 79.
    • Accredited to the Russian delegate F. F. de Martens at the 1899 Hague peace conference, the Martens clause stipulates that: 'Until a more complete code of the laws of war is issued, the High Contracting parties [to the 1899 Hague Convention] declare that in cases not included in the Regulations adopted by them, populations and belligerents remain under the protection of the principles of international law, as they result from the usages established between civilized nations, from the laws of humanity, and the requirements of public conscience'. Cited in Theodore Meron, 'The Martens Clause, Principles of Humanity, and Dictates of Public Conscience', American Journal of International Law, 94:1 (2000). p. 79.
  • 58
    • 51349089330 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It is worth noting that neither Bass, Walzer nor Orend specifically refer to the laws of occupation in their discussion of how occupations be conducted
    • It is worth noting that neither Bass, Walzer nor Orend specifically refer to the laws of occupation in their discussion of how occupations be conducted.
  • 59
    • 84920874387 scopus 로고
    • War Crimes by Enemy Nationals Administering Justice in Occupied Territory
    • See
    • See Alwyn V. Freeman, 'War Crimes by Enemy Nationals Administering Justice in Occupied Territory', American Journal of International Law, 41:3 (1947). p. 581.
    • (1947) American Journal of International Law , vol.41 , Issue.3 , pp. 581
    • Freeman, A.V.1
  • 60
    • 51349108021 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It is worth noting that proposals for a maximalist position, which would have required occupiers to make life pleasant, were levelled by both the victims of occupation in the Second World War and humanitarian agencies but were rejected
    • Best, Law and War, p. 117. It is worth noting that proposals for a maximalist position, which would have required occupiers to make life pleasant, were levelled by both the victims of occupation in the Second World War and humanitarian agencies but were rejected.
    • Law and War , pp. 117
    • Best1
  • 62
    • 27644495672 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • They span forty pages of the UK Ministry of Defence, Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • They span forty pages of the UK Ministry of Defence. The Manual of the Law of Armed Conflict (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005), pp. 215-55.
    • (2005) The Manual of the Law of Armed Conflict , pp. 215-255
  • 63
    • 51349100930 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Manual
    • The following discussion draws extensively on MoD, in-text references refer to paragraphs in the manual
    • The following discussion draws extensively on MoD, Manual. Unless otherwise stated, the following in-text references refer to paragraphs in the manual.
    • Unless otherwise stated, the following
  • 69
    • 51349122135 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A shift that Morgenthau used to explain the deterioration of the power of international law to constrain behaviour. Hans J. Morgenthau, The Twilight of International Morality, Ethics. 58:2 1948
    • A shift that Morgenthau used to explain the deterioration of the power of international law to constrain behaviour. Hans J. Morgenthau, 'The Twilight of International Morality', Ethics. 58:2 (1948).
  • 72
    • 29244474466 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Human Security Centre University of British Columbia, New York: Oxford University Press
    • Human Security Centre (University of British Columbia), Human Security Report 2005: War and Peace in the Twenty-First Century (New York: Oxford University Press, 2005), p. 23.
    • (2005) Human Security Report 2005: War and Peace in the Twenty-First Century , pp. 23
  • 73
    • 84937331216 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Spectator Sport Warfare
    • Colin Mclnnes, 'Spectator Sport Warfare', Contemporary Security Policy, 20:3 (1999), p. 152.
    • (1999) Contemporary Security Policy , vol.20 , Issue.3 , pp. 152
    • Mclnnes, C.1
  • 74
    • 3242740976 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Human Security Centre
    • Human Security Centre, Human Security Report, p. 23.
    • Human Security Report , pp. 23
  • 75
    • 84921848852 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Allen Buchanan. Justice, Legitimacy, and Self-Determination: Moral Foundations for International Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press. 2004). 'The idea that norm breaking behaviourincurs costs (political, military and economic) is a mainstay of constructivism.
    • See Allen Buchanan. Justice, Legitimacy, and Self-Determination: Moral Foundations for International Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press. 2004). 'The idea that norm breaking behaviourincurs costs (political, military and economic) is a mainstay of constructivism.
  • 77
    • 51349089766 scopus 로고
    • When the Shooting Stops: Missing Elements in Just War Theory
    • See, 26 October, The idea of the 'presumption against war' is described as a 'distortion' of classical just war thinking by James Turner Johnson
    • See Michael J. Schuck, 'When the Shooting Stops: Missing Elements in Just War Theory', The Christian Century. 26 October 1994. The idea of the 'presumption against war' is described as a 'distortion' of classical just war thinking by James Turner Johnson.
    • (1994) The Christian Century
    • Schuck, M.J.1
  • 79
    • 84937383727 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Jus Post Bellum: The Importance of War Crimes Trials
    • Davida E. Kellogg, 'Jus Post Bellum: The Importance of War Crimes Trials'. Parameters, 32:3 (2002), pp. 87-99.
    • (2002) Parameters , vol.32 , Issue.3 , pp. 87-99
    • Kellogg, D.E.1
  • 81
    • 51349132873 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Though Churchill, of course, famously argued that the Nazis be summarily shot in the aftermath of the Second World War
    • Though Churchill, of course, famously argued that the Nazis be summarily shot in the aftermath of the Second World War.
  • 86
    • 0011132662 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the Hazards of Foreign Travel for Dictators and other International Criminals
    • On Pinochet see
    • On Pinochet see Marc Weiler, 'On the Hazards of Foreign Travel for Dictators and other International Criminals'. International Affairs, 75:3 (1999), pp. 599-617.
    • (1999) International Affairs , vol.75 , Issue.3 , pp. 599-617
    • Weiler, M.1
  • 87
    • 51349100499 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In Bosnia, Rwanda and elsewhere. See, inter alia, on impunity Richard J. Goldstone, For Humanity: Reflections of a War Crimes Investigator (New Haven: Yale University Press, 2000),
    • In Bosnia, Rwanda and elsewhere. See, inter alia, on impunity Richard J. Goldstone, For Humanity: Reflections of a War Crimes Investigator (New Haven: Yale University Press, 2000),
  • 88
    • 51349124981 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • on Bosnia Jan-Willem Honig. Srebrenica: Record of a War Crime (London: Penguin. 1988),
    • on Bosnia Jan-Willem Honig. Srebrenica: Record of a War Crime (London: Penguin. 1988),
  • 89
    • 51349132085 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and on Rwanda Linda Melvern, A People Betrayed: The Role of the West in Rwanda's Genocide (London: Zed Books, 2000).
    • and on Rwanda Linda Melvern, A People Betrayed: The Role of the West in Rwanda's Genocide (London: Zed Books, 2000).
  • 90
    • 51349152500 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Most notably Richard Goldstone, For Humanity: Reflections of a War Crimes Investigator (New Haven: Yale University Press, 2000).
    • Most notably Richard Goldstone, For Humanity: Reflections of a War Crimes Investigator (New Haven: Yale University Press, 2000).
  • 93
    • 51349090226 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Emphasis added, Kellogg, 'Jus Post Bellum', p. 88.
    • Emphasis added, Kellogg, 'Jus Post Bellum', p. 88.
  • 97
    • 51349100018 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., p. 396.
    • Bass1
  • 98
    • 70949102118 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Jus Post Bellum: The Moral Responsibilities if Victors in War
    • Louis V. Iasiello, 'Jus Post Bellum: The Moral Responsibilities if Victors in War', Naval War College Review, 57:3/4 (2004), p. 48.
    • (2004) Naval War College Review , vol.57 , Issue.3-4 , pp. 48
    • Iasiello, L.V.1
  • 101
    • 84923408249 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The importance of intentions (as opposed to motives or outcomes) in adducing the morality of humanitarian intervention is outlined in Alex J. Bellamy, 'Motives, Outcomes, Intentions and the Legitimacy of Humanitarian Intervention', Journal of Military Ethics, 3:3 (2004),
    • The importance of intentions (as opposed to motives or outcomes) in adducing the morality of humanitarian intervention is outlined in Alex J. Bellamy, 'Motives, Outcomes, Intentions and the Legitimacy of Humanitarian Intervention', Journal of Military Ethics, 3:3 (2004),
  • 102
    • 84994331157 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Eight Principles of Humanitarian Intervention
    • and Fernando Tesón. 'Eight Principles of Humanitarian Intervention', Journal of Military Ethics, 5:2 (2006).
    • (2006) Journal of Military Ethics , vol.5 , pp. 2
    • Tesón, F.1
  • 103
    • 0003868779 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press., Wheeler differs from Bellamy and Tesón in arguing that outcomes are important in and of themselves, whereas Bellamy and Tesón suggest that they are important because the degree of investment and preparation for the peace is indicative of an actor's intentions
    • Nicholas J. Wheeler, Saving Strangers: Humanitarian Intervention in International Society (Oxford: Oxford University Press. 2000). Wheeler differs from Bellamy and Tesón in arguing that outcomes are important in and of themselves, whereas Bellamy and Tesón suggest that they are important because the degree of investment and preparation for the peace is indicative of an actor's intentions.
    • (2000) Saving Strangers: Humanitarian Intervention in International Society
    • Wheeler, N.J.1
  • 104
    • 0004284229 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • International Commission on Intervention and State Sovereignty, Ottawa: ICISS
    • International Commission on Intervention and State Sovereignty. The Responsibility to Protect (Ottawa: ICISS, 2002).
    • (2002) The Responsibility to Protect
  • 106
    • 51349087877 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A norm encapsulated in Article 23 of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights. As Brad Roth points out, the 'will of the people' is a particularly indeterminate phrase that democracies and non-democracies alike can, and do, point to in order to legitimate sovereign rule. The norm does, however, prohibit two types of government: rule by ethnic minorities (e.g. white Rhodesia and apartheid South Africa) and rule by foreign occupiers. See Brad R. Roth, Government Illegitimacy in International Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000), pp. 37-41.
    • A norm encapsulated in Article 23 of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights. As Brad Roth points out, the 'will of the people' is a particularly indeterminate phrase that democracies and non-democracies alike can, and do, point to in order to legitimate sovereign rule. The norm does, however, prohibit two types of government: rule by ethnic minorities (e.g. white Rhodesia and apartheid South Africa) and rule by foreign occupiers. See Brad R. Roth, Government Illegitimacy in International Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000), pp. 37-41.
  • 107
    • 51349096672 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, inter alia, W. Michael Reisman, 'Stopping Wars and Making Peace: Reflections on the Ideology of Conflict Termination in Contemporary World Polities', Tulane Journal of International and Comparative Law 6:5 (1998).
    • See, inter alia, W. Michael Reisman, 'Stopping Wars and Making Peace: Reflections on the Ideology of Conflict Termination in Contemporary World Polities', Tulane Journal of International and Comparative Law 6:5 (1998).
  • 112
    • 51349091645 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Creation and Funding of the UN Peacebuilding Commission
    • See, November
    • See Richard Ponzio, 'The Creation and Funding of the UN Peacebuilding Commission', Saferworld, November 2005.
    • (2005) Saferworld
    • Ponzio, R.1
  • 113
    • 51349109825 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Though in practice, that responsibility can be subcontracted to regional organisations and coalitions of the willing, as the Security Council has done in relation to Afghanistan and Iraq
    • Though in practice, that responsibility can be subcontracted to regional organisations and coalitions of the willing, as the Security Council has done in relation to Afghanistan and Iraq.
  • 114
    • 51349087383 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In relation to Iraq, in Resolution 1483. the Security Council felt the need to endorse and authorise the allied transitional authority - and just as significantly, the US felt the need to request such endorsement.
    • In relation to Iraq, in Resolution 1483. the Security Council felt the need to endorse and authorise the allied transitional authority - and just as significantly, the US felt the need to request such endorsement.
  • 115
    • 51349113111 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The basic propositions come from Eyal Benvenisti, 'The Security Council and the Law on Occupation: Resolution 1483 in Historical Perspective', Israel Defence Forces Law Review, 19:1 (2003), pp. 23-7. Benvenisti actually identifies four problems, but the second ('lack of neutrality') and fourth 'avoidance' amount to much the same thing the idea that despite the Nuremberg court's insistence otherwise the Hague regulations did not become customary law principally because they were never actually practised.
    • The basic propositions come from Eyal Benvenisti, 'The Security Council and the Law on Occupation: Resolution 1483 in Historical Perspective', Israel Defence Forces Law Review, 19:1 (2003), pp. 23-7. Benvenisti actually identifies four problems, but the second ('lack of neutrality') and fourth 'avoidance' amount to much the same thing the idea that despite the Nuremberg court's insistence otherwise the Hague regulations did not become customary law principally because they were never actually practised.
  • 118
    • 51349085203 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As McDougal and Feliciano put it, 'occupants did in fact intervene in and subject to regulation practically every aspect of life in a modern state which legitimate sovereigns themselves are wont to regulate'. McDougal and Feliciano. Law and Minimum World Public Order. p. 747.
    • As McDougal and Feliciano put it, 'occupants did in fact intervene in and subject to regulation practically every aspect of life in a modern state which legitimate sovereigns themselves are wont to regulate'. McDougal and Feliciano. Law and Minimum World Public Order. p. 747.
  • 120
    • 51349111482 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For this argument to carry the weight that Benvenisti gives it would require a conception of legitimacy that gave overriding weight to legal legitimacy, which for reasons I discussed earlier this essay refuses to do
    • For this argument to carry the weight that Benvenisti gives it would require a conception of legitimacy that gave overriding weight to legal legitimacy, which for reasons I discussed earlier this essay refuses to do.
  • 122
    • 51349124979 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The connection between the Great Powers' interest in legitimating colonial rule and international law governing occupation and legitimate combatancy in discussed in detail by Karma Nablusi, Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • The connection between the Great Powers' interest in legitimating colonial rule and international law governing occupation and legitimate combatancy in discussed in detail by Karma Nablusi, Traditions of War: Occupation, Resistance and the Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002).
    • (2002) Traditions of War: Occupation, Resistance and the Law
  • 124
    • 51349146727 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • William Shawcross, for instance, argued that 'Saddam should have been removed in 1991', William Shawcross. 'After Iraq: America and Europe', 2003 Harkness Lecture. King's College London. 27 March 2003.
    • William Shawcross, for instance, argued that 'Saddam should have been removed in 1991', William Shawcross. 'After Iraq: America and Europe', 2003 Harkness Lecture. King's College London. 27 March 2003.
  • 125
    • 51349141970 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A common starting point for debate on intervention is the view that the prevailing normative order is based on just such a presumption. See, inter alia, Simon Chesterman, Just War or Just Peace? Humanitarian Intervention and International Law Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001
    • A common starting point for debate on intervention is the view that the prevailing normative order is based on just such a presumption. See, inter alia, Simon Chesterman, Just War or Just Peace? Humanitarian Intervention and International Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001),
  • 127
    • 84924139187 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Humanitarian Intervention: An Overview of the Ethical Issues
    • and Michael J. Smith, 'Humanitarian Intervention: An Overview of the Ethical Issues', Ethics and International Affairs, 12:1 (1998).
    • (1998) Ethics and International Affairs , vol.12 , pp. 1
    • Smith, M.J.1
  • 128
    • 0038428233 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Independent International Commission on Kosovo
    • The Independent International Commission on Kosovo found NATO's intervention to be 'illegal but legitimate' on precisely these grounds, Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • The Independent International Commission on Kosovo found NATO's intervention to be 'illegal but legitimate' on precisely these grounds. See Independent International Commission on Kosovo, Kosovo Report: Conflict, International Response, Lessons Learned (Oxford: Oxford University Press. 2000), p. 4.
    • (2000) Kosovo Report: Conflict, International Response, Lessons Learned , pp. 4
  • 129
    • 51349101908 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Other notable examples include Kenneth Roth, 'The Right Exit', New Statesman, 15 March 2004. Gareth Evans' International Crisis Group argued that any withdrawal should be gradual and only take place as the security situation improved. See International Crisis Group, 'Iraq: Insurgency and Sectarianism', 14 February 2006.
    • Other notable examples include Kenneth Roth, 'The Right Exit', New Statesman, 15 March 2004. Gareth Evans' International Crisis Group argued that any withdrawal should be gradual and only take place as the security situation improved. See International Crisis Group, 'Iraq: Insurgency and Sectarianism', 14 February 2006.
  • 130
    • 51349150023 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Unless one shares McMahon's view that a war that is initially unjust can later become just, a position that is inconsistent with the prevailing view of the Just War tradition and international law. In effect, war involves taking measures that are generally proscribed (i.e. killing people in peacetime is murder). Those measures are legitimate in war because warriors obtain a 'licence' to conduct them by virtue of the ¡us ad bellum. See Jeff McMahon, 'Just Causes for War', Ethics and International Affairs, 20:1 (2006).
    • Unless one shares McMahon's view that a war that is initially unjust can later become just, a position that is inconsistent with the prevailing view of the Just War tradition and international law. In effect, war involves taking measures that are generally proscribed (i.e. killing people in peacetime is murder). Those measures are legitimate in war because warriors obtain a 'licence' to conduct them by virtue of the ¡us ad bellum. See Jeff McMahon, 'Just Causes for War', Ethics and International Affairs, 20:1 (2006).
  • 131
    • 51349111017 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I deliberately mean to refer both to Walzer's 'supreme emergencies' and Wheeler's 'supreme humanitarian emergencies'.
    • I deliberately mean to refer both to Walzer's 'supreme emergencies' and Wheeler's 'supreme humanitarian emergencies'.
  • 134
    • 0040565376 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rethinking Humanitarian Intervention
    • Parekh, 'Rethinking Humanitarian Intervention'. International Political Science Review, 18:1 (1997). pp. 54-5.
    • (1997) International Political Science Review , vol.18 , Issue.1 , pp. 54-55
    • Parekh1
  • 135
    • 51349114831 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As happened in Iraq, where the US-created transitional authority received the blessing of the UN Security Council
    • As happened in Iraq, where the US-created transitional authority received the blessing of the UN Security Council.
  • 136
    • 0004284229 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A position put forward by the ICISS
    • A position put forward by the ICISS, Responsibility to Protect.
    • Responsibility to Protect
  • 137
    • 51349115298 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • And as noted above, international institutions have a special role to play in such cases
    • And as noted above, international institutions have a special role to play in such cases.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.