메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 156, Issue 2, 2007, Pages 395-452

Causing, aiding, and the superfluity of accomplice liability

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 39349112382     PISSN: 00419907     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: None     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (46)

References (185)
  • 1
    • 85081478961 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., WAYNE R. LAFAVE & AUSTIN W. SCOTT, JR., CRIMINAL. LAW 579-80 (2d ed. 1986).
    • See, e.g., WAYNE R. LAFAVE & AUSTIN W. SCOTT, JR., CRIMINAL. LAW 579-80 (2d ed. 1986).
  • 2
    • 85081490598 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MODEL PENAL CODE § 2.02 (1985).
    • MODEL PENAL CODE § 2.02 (1985).
  • 3
    • 85081491567 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This paper is the tenth in a series of papers on causation, both its metaphysics and its relevance to responsibility. The predecessor papers are: Heidi M. Hurd & Michael S. Moore, Negligence in the Air, 3 THEORETICAL INQUIRIES L. 333 (2002);
    • This paper is the tenth in a series of papers on causation, both its metaphysics and its relevance to responsibility. The predecessor papers are: Heidi M. Hurd & Michael S. Moore, Negligence in the Air, 3 THEORETICAL INQUIRIES L. 333 (2002);
  • 4
    • 85081480634 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Michael S. Moore, Causal Relata, in 13 ANNUAL REVIEW OF LAW AND ETHICS: PHILOSOPHIA PRACTICA UNIVERSALIS 589 (B. Sharon Byrd & Jan C. Joerden eds., 2005);
    • Michael S. Moore, Causal Relata, in 13 ANNUAL REVIEW OF LAW AND ETHICS: PHILOSOPHIA PRACTICA UNIVERSALIS 589 (B. Sharon Byrd & Jan C. Joerden eds., 2005);
  • 6
    • 0039598792 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Michael S. Moore, Causation and Responsibility, SOC. PHIL. & POL'Y, Summer 1999, at 1;
    • Michael S. Moore, Causation and Responsibility, SOC. PHIL. & POL'Y, Summer 1999, at 1;
  • 7
    • 85081490114 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Michael S. Moore, The Destruction of the World Trade Center and the Law on Event-Identity, in AGENCY AND ACTION 259 (John Hyman & Helen Steward eds., 2004);
    • Michael S. Moore, The Destruction of the World Trade Center and the Law on Event-Identity, in AGENCY AND ACTION 259 (John Hyman & Helen Steward eds., 2004);
  • 8
    • 84855873497 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For What Must We Pay? Causation and Counterfactual Baselines, 40
    • Michael Moore, For What Must We Pay? Causation and Counterfactual Baselines, 40 SAN DIEGO L. REV. 1181 (2003)
    • (2003) SAN DIEGO L. REV , vol.1181
    • Moore, M.1
  • 10
    • 0040870052 scopus 로고
    • The Independent Moral Significance of Wrongdoing, 5
    • Michael Moore, The Independent Moral Significance of Wrongdoing, 5 J. CONTEMP. LEGAL ISSUES 237 (1994);
    • (1994) J. CONTEMP. LEGAL ISSUES , vol.237
    • Moore, M.1
  • 11
    • 0041906861 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Metaphysics of Causal Intervention, 88
    • Michael S. Moore, The Metaphysics of Causal Intervention, 88 CAL, L. REV. 827 (2000);
    • (2000) CAL, L. REV , vol.827
    • Moore, M.S.1
  • 12
    • 36549088721 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and Michael S. Moore, Patrolling the Borders of Consequentialist Justifications: The Scope of Agent-Relative Restrictions, 27 LAW & PHIL. (forthcoming 2008)
    • and Michael S. Moore, Patrolling the Borders of Consequentialist Justifications: The Scope of Agent-Relative Restrictions, 27 LAW & PHIL. (forthcoming 2008)
  • 13
    • 85081477866 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [hereinafter Moore, Patrolling the Borders]. These papers together form the bulk of my forthcoming book, Causation and Responsibility, to be published by Oxford University Press in 2008.
    • [hereinafter Moore, Patrolling the Borders]. These papers together form the bulk of my forthcoming book, Causation and Responsibility, to be published by Oxford University Press in 2008.
  • 14
    • 85081486563 scopus 로고
    • Parties to Crime, 89
    • E.g
    • E.g., Rollin M. Perkins, Parties to Crime, 89 U. PA. L. REV. 581, 584 (1941).
    • (1941) U. PA. L. REV , vol.581 , pp. 584
    • Perkins, R.M.1
  • 15
    • 85081475690 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I argue for this at some length in MICHAEL S. MOORE, ACT AND CRIME: THE PHILOSOPHY OF ACTION AND ITS IMPLICATIONS FOR CRIMINAL LAW 189-238 (1993).
    • I argue for this at some length in MICHAEL S. MOORE, ACT AND CRIME: THE PHILOSOPHY OF ACTION AND ITS IMPLICATIONS FOR CRIMINAL LAW 189-238 (1993).
  • 16
    • 85081481954 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Glanville Williams, The Problem of Reckless Attempts, 1983 CRIM. L. REV. 365, 366 (discussing the absence of causal requirements in conduct crimes and providing the example of rape).
    • See, e.g., Glanville Williams, The Problem of Reckless Attempts, 1983 CRIM. L. REV. 365, 366 (discussing the absence of causal requirements in "conduct crimes" and providing the example of rape).
  • 17
    • 85081477807 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For other examples, see the discussion and citations in MOORE, supra note 5, at 209-10, 214-25
    • For other examples, see the discussion and citations in MOORE, supra note 5, at 209-10, 214-25.
  • 18
    • 85081479381 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See generally MOORE, supra note 5, at 60-77
    • See generally MOORE, supra note 5, at 60-77.
  • 19
    • 33947585669 scopus 로고
    • See, e.g, U.S
    • See, e.g, Pinkerton v. United States, 328 U.S. 640 (1946).
    • (1946) United States , vol.328 , pp. 640
    • Pinkerton, V.1
  • 20
    • 85081481811 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Joshua Dressier considers but rejects the vicarious basis for accomplice liability. Joshua Dressier, Reassessing the Theoretical Underpinnings of Accomplice Liability: New Solutions to an Old Problem, 37 HASTINGS L.J. 91, 109-11 (1985).
    • Joshua Dressier considers but rejects the vicarious basis for accomplice liability. Joshua Dressier, Reassessing the Theoretical Underpinnings of Accomplice Liability: New Solutions to an Old Problem, 37 HASTINGS L.J. 91, 109-11 (1985).
  • 21
    • 85081491770 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Richard Buxton, Complicity and the Law Commission, 1973 CRIM. L. REV. 223, 223-30;
    • See, e.g., Richard Buxton, Complicity and the Law Commission, 1973 CRIM. L. REV. 223, 223-30;
  • 22
    • 85081489521 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Richard Buxton, Complicity in the Criminal Code, 85 L.Q. REV. 252, 265-73 (1969);
    • Richard Buxton, Complicity in the Criminal Code, 85 L.Q. REV. 252, 265-73 (1969);
  • 23
    • 85081483098 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • J.R. Spencer, Trying To Help Another Person Commit a Crime, in CRIMINAL LAW: ESSAYS IN HONOUR OFJ.C. SMITH 148, 148 (Peter Smith ed., 1987);
    • J.R. Spencer, Trying To Help Another Person Commit a Crime, in CRIMINAL LAW: ESSAYS IN HONOUR OFJ.C. SMITH 148, 148 (Peter Smith ed., 1987);
  • 24
    • 26444585656 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Daniel Yeager, Helping, Doing, and the Grammar of Complicity, 15 CRIM. JUST. ETHICS 25, 30-33 (1996). Recently, Christopher Kutz seems to have joined the view that accomplice liability is a form of inchoate liability.
    • Daniel Yeager, Helping, Doing, and the Grammar of Complicity, 15 CRIM. JUST. ETHICS 25, 30-33 (1996). Recently, Christopher Kutz seems to have joined the view that accomplice liability is a form of inchoate liability.
  • 25
    • 34548790844 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Christopher Kutz, Causeless Complicity, 1 CRIM. L. & PHIL. 289, 301-03 (2007).
    • See Christopher Kutz, Causeless Complicity, 1 CRIM. L. & PHIL. 289, 301-03 (2007).
  • 26
    • 85081476580 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g, K.J.M. SMITH, A MODERN TREATISE ON THE LAW OF CRIMINAL COMPLICITY 124-27 (1991);
    • See, e.g, K.J.M. SMITH, A MODERN TREATISE ON THE LAW OF CRIMINAL COMPLICITY 124-27 (1991);
  • 27
    • 84927454283 scopus 로고
    • Imputed Criminal Liability, 93
    • Paul H. Robinson, Imputed Criminal Liability, 93 YALE L.J. 609, 613-14 (1984);
    • (1984) YALE L.J , vol.609 , pp. 613-614
    • Robinson, P.H.1
  • 28
    • 77952424958 scopus 로고
    • Criminal Responsibility for the Acts of Another, 43
    • Francis Bowes Sayre, Criminal Responsibility for the Acts of Another, 43 HARV. L. REV. 689, 702 (1930).
    • (1930) HARV. L. REV , vol.689 , pp. 702
    • Bowes Sayre, F.1
  • 29
    • 85081489773 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Pinkerton doctrine, 328 U.S. at 646-47, is a federal doctrine, but it is followed in a minority of American states.
    • The Pinkerton doctrine, 328 U.S. at 646-47, is a federal doctrine, but it is followed in a minority of American states.
  • 30
    • 85081485133 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., People v. Luparello, 231 Cal. Rptr. 832, 846-51 (Cal. Ct. App. 1986).
    • See, e.g., People v. Luparello, 231 Cal. Rptr. 832, 846-51 (Cal. Ct. App. 1986).
  • 31
    • 85081487664 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is the suggestion of Smith, Robinson, and Sayre, supra note 11
    • This is the suggestion of Smith, Robinson, and Sayre, supra note 11.
  • 32
    • 85081489519 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This view is held by Dressier, supra note 9, at 102-03, and CHRISTOPHER KUTZ, COMPLICITY: ETHICS AND LAW FOR A COLLECTIVE AGE 220-27 2000
    • This view is held by Dressier, supra note 9, at 102-03, and CHRISTOPHER KUTZ, COMPLICITY: ETHICS AND LAW FOR A COLLECTIVE AGE 220-27 (2000).
  • 33
    • 85081478631 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • So. 722 (Ala. 1894).
    • So. 722 (Ala. 1894).
  • 34
    • 85081491797 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 738
    • Id. at 738.
  • 35
    • 84954985316 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note 15, at, Kutz has recently come to a somewhat more nuanced view of causation
    • KUTZ, supra note 15, at 217. Kutz has recently come to a somewhat more nuanced view of causation.
    • supra , pp. 217
    • KUTZ1
  • 36
    • 85081486150 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Kutz, supra note 10, at 290 (Causation may be present, I argue, and causal relations feature in the justification of accomplice liability overall, but causation is not necessary to complicity.).
    • See Kutz, supra note 10, at 290 ("Causation may be present, I argue, and causal relations feature in the justification of accomplice liability overall, but causation is not necessary to complicity.").
  • 37
    • 85081490702 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • KUTZ, supra note 15, at 215;
    • KUTZ, supra note 15, at 215;
  • 38
    • 85081476258 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also Dressler, supra note 9, at 99;
    • see also Dressler, supra note 9, at 99;
  • 39
    • 85081481552 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Yeager, supra note 10, at 29
    • Yeager, supra note 10, at 29.
  • 40
    • 85081478749 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Moore, Causation and Counterfactual Baselines, supra note 3
    • Moore, Causation and Counterfactual Baselines, supra note 3.
  • 41
    • 85081485464 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The substitivity of identicals is often called Leibniz's Law. For an introduction, see MICHAEL MOORE, PLACING BLAME: A GENERAL THEORY OF THE CRIMINAL LAW 372 (1997).
    • The substitivity of identicals is often called "Leibniz's Law." For an introduction, see MICHAEL MOORE, PLACING BLAME: A GENERAL THEORY OF THE CRIMINAL LAW 372 (1997).
  • 42
    • 85081490729 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For the qualifications, see, at
    • For the qualifications, see Moore, Causal Relata, supra note 3, at 629-34.
    • Causal Relata, supra note , vol.3 , pp. 629-634
    • Moore1
  • 44
    • 85081492429 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • At least this is true so long as one does not stipulate (as did David Lewis and his followers) that counterfactuals that backtrack through time are deviant. For a hypothetical demonstrating this, see id. at 1227-37
    • At least this is true so long as one does not stipulate (as did David Lewis and his followers) that counterfactuals that "backtrack" through time are "deviant." For a hypothetical demonstrating this, see id. at 1227-37.
  • 46
    • 85081486430 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Counterfactualists argue this point mostly by a stipulated narrowing of the class of counterfactuals eligible to serve as sufficient conditions for causation. Thus, one response to (a) is the denial by counterfactualists that counterfactuals relating omissions are like ordinary counterfactuals relating events because the former but not the latter are about types, not particulars; to (b), the response is to stipulate that counter-factuals must be between distinct events; and to (c) and (d), the main response is to treat backtracking counterfactuals as deviant and not included in the class of counterfactuals relevant to causation. For a discussion of these responses, see Moore, Causation and Counterfactual Baselines, supra note 3, at 1238-57.
    • Counterfactualists argue this point mostly by a stipulated narrowing of the class of counterfactuals eligible to serve as sufficient conditions for causation. Thus, one response to (a) is the denial by counterfactualists that counterfactuals relating omissions are like ordinary counterfactuals relating events because the former but not the latter are about types, not particulars; to (b), the response is to stipulate that counter-factuals must be between "distinct events"; and to (c) and (d), the main response is to treat "backtracking" counterfactuals as deviant and not included in the class of counterfactuals relevant to causation. For a discussion of these responses, see Moore, Causation and Counterfactual Baselines, supra note 3, at 1238-57.
  • 47
    • 85081483340 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • discussing this attention in detail
    • See id. (discussing this attention in detail).
    • See id
  • 49
    • 85081483980 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Model Penal Code's failure to cover cases of concurrent causation is acknowledged at MODEL PENAL CODE § 2.03 cmt. 2 (1985).
    • The Model Penal Code's failure to cover cases of concurrent causation is acknowledged at MODEL PENAL CODE § 2.03 cmt. 2 (1985).
  • 50
    • 85081484128 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See generally Wex S. Malone, Ruminations on Cause-in-Fact, 9 STAN. L. REV. 60 (1956). For the critical legal studies version of this view,
    • See generally Wex S. Malone, Ruminations on Cause-in-Fact, 9 STAN. L. REV. 60 (1956). For the critical legal studies version of this view,
  • 51
    • 85081478319 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see Mark Kelman, The Necessary Myth of Objective Causation Judgments in Liberal Political Theory, 63 CHI.-KENT L. REV. 579 (1987).
    • see Mark Kelman, The Necessary Myth of Objective Causation Judgments in Liberal Political Theory, 63 CHI.-KENT L. REV. 579 (1987).
  • 52
    • 85081486749 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • My early commentary on Kelman appeared in Michael S. Moore, Thomson's Preliminaries About Causation and Rights, 63 CHI.-KENT L. REV. 497, 501-06 (1987).
    • My early commentary on Kelman appeared in Michael S. Moore, Thomson's Preliminaries About Causation and Rights, 63 CHI.-KENT L. REV. 497, 501-06 (1987).
  • 53
    • 85081481402 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Both Restatements eschew but-for causation for the substantial factor test. RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS § 431 (1965);
    • Both Restatements eschew but-for causation for the "substantial factor" test. RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS § 431 (1965);
  • 54
    • 85081481046 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • RESTATEMENT OF TORTS § 431 (1934).
    • RESTATEMENT OF TORTS § 431 (1934).
  • 55
    • 85081489307 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I explore the case law establishing these conditions in Moore, note 3, at
    • I explore the case law establishing these conditions in Moore, The Metaphysics of Causal Intervention, supra note 3, at 832-52.
    • The Metaphysics of Causal Intervention, supra , pp. 832-852
  • 56
    • 85081477402 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 839-46.
    • See id. at 839-46.
  • 57
    • 84920186177 scopus 로고
    • Complicity, Cause and Blame: A Study in the Interpretation of Doctrine, 73
    • Sanford H. Radish, Complicity, Cause and Blame: A Study in the Interpretation of Doctrine, 73 CAL. L. REV. 323 (1985).
    • (1985) CAL. L. REV , vol.323
    • Radish, S.H.1
  • 58
    • 85081477438 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • BLONDIE, One Way or Another, on PARALLEL LINES (Chrysalis Records 1978).
    • BLONDIE, One Way or Another, on PARALLEL LINES (Chrysalis Records 1978).
  • 60
    • 85081483325 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The fit of libertarian metaphysics to the legal doctrines of intervening causation is in fact a rough one, as I examine in Moore, The Metaphysics of Causal Intervention, supra note 3, at 869-71. This is one argument more than I need here, so I shall ignore it.
    • The fit of libertarian metaphysics to the legal doctrines of intervening causation is in fact a rough one, as I examine in Moore, The Metaphysics of Causal Intervention, supra note 3, at 869-71. This is one argument more than I need here, so I shall ignore it.
  • 61
    • 85081479947 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kadish, supra note 34, at 360
    • Kadish, supra note 34, at 360.
  • 62
    • 85081479610 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 334-36
    • Id. at 334-36.
  • 63
    • 85081479473 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • H.L.A. HART & TONY HONORÉ, CAUSATION IN THE LAW 28-32 (2d ed. 1985).
    • H.L.A. HART & TONY HONORÉ, CAUSATION IN THE LAW 28-32 (2d ed. 1985).
  • 64
    • 85081492525 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The nineteenth century's last wrongdoer rule is an example of such an avowedly fictionalist approach to intervening causation. See Lawrence S. Eldredge, Culpable Intervention as Superseding Cause, 86 U. PA. L. REV. 121, 124 (1937). On this rule, the law only need punish the (temporally) last wrongdoer in some complicated chain of causation leading to some legally prohibited result. Such last wrongdoer thus cuts off all earlier wrongdoers from liability for that harm.
    • The nineteenth century's "last wrongdoer" rule is an example of such an avowedly fictionalist approach to intervening causation. See Lawrence S. Eldredge, Culpable Intervention as Superseding Cause, 86 U. PA. L. REV. 121, 124 (1937). On this rule, the law only need punish the (temporally) last wrongdoer in some complicated chain of causation leading to some legally prohibited result. Such "last wrongdoer" thus cuts off all earlier wrongdoers from liability for that harm.
  • 66
    • 85081475392 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 124-25;
    • Id. at 124-25;
  • 67
    • 85081482702 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also Clifford v. Atl. Cotton Mills, 15 N.E. 84, 87 (Mass. 1888) (Holmes, J.) (describing the last wrongdoer rule as no more than a general tendency of courts).
    • see also Clifford v. Atl. Cotton Mills, 15 N.E. 84, 87 (Mass. 1888) (Holmes, J.) (describing the "last wrongdoer" rule as no more than a "general tendency" of courts).
  • 68
    • 85081487126 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., CAL. PENAL CODE § 664 (West 1999).
    • See, e.g., CAL. PENAL CODE § 664 (West 1999).
  • 69
    • 74049118413 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note 40, at, Sanford Kadish and John Gardner have also explicitly endorsed this kind of causal dualism
    • HART & HONORÉ, supra note 40, at 6. Sanford Kadish and John Gardner have also explicitly endorsed this kind of causal dualism.
    • supra , pp. 6
    • HART1    HONORÉ2
  • 70
    • 85081482572 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kadish, supra note 34, at 334;
    • Kadish, supra note 34, at 334;
  • 71
    • 34247367701 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • John Gardner, Complicity and Causality, 1 CRIM. L. & PHIL. 127, 134 (2007).
    • John Gardner, Complicity and Causality, 1 CRIM. L. & PHIL. 127, 134 (2007).
  • 72
    • 85081483648 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • HART & HONORÉ, supra note 40, at 186
    • HART & HONORÉ, supra note 40, at 186.
  • 73
    • 85081489643 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 388
    • Id. at 388.
  • 74
    • 85081475865 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 195
    • Id. at 195.
  • 75
    • 84928216942 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Antony Flew, Psychiatry, Law and Responsibility, 35 PHIL. Q. 425, 430 (1985)
    • Antony Flew, Psychiatry, Law and Responsibility, 35 PHIL. Q. 425, 430 (1985)
  • 76
    • 85081488266 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (reviewing MICHAEL S. MOORE, LAW AND PSYCHIATRY: RETHINKING THE RELATIONSHIP (1984)).
    • (reviewing MICHAEL S. MOORE, LAW AND PSYCHIATRY: RETHINKING THE RELATIONSHIP (1984)).
  • 77
    • 85081490969 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is not to be confused with statements of comparative causation, as in, Factor X was sixty percent the cause, factor Y forty percent the cause of harm Z, Some of us think such scalar statements of degrees of causal contribution make perfectly good sense. See Moore, The Metaphysics of Causal Intervention, supra note 3, at 874 & n.229
    • This is not to be confused with statements of comparative causation, as in, "Factor X was sixty percent the cause, factor Y forty percent the cause of harm Z," Some of us think such scalar statements of degrees of causal contribution make perfectly good sense. See Moore, The Metaphysics of Causal Intervention, supra note 3, at 874 & n.229.
  • 78
    • 85081476418 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For real world examples (Sheldon Glueck and Norval Morris) and an analysis of why this is truly metaphysical gibberish, see Michael S. Moore, Causation and the Excuses, 73 CAL. L. REV. 1091, 1114-19 (1985).
    • For real world examples (Sheldon Glueck and Norval Morris) and an analysis of why this is truly metaphysical gibberish, see Michael S. Moore, Causation and the Excuses, 73 CAL. L. REV. 1091, 1114-19 (1985).
  • 80
    • 85081492717 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 111
    • Id. at 111.
  • 81
    • 85081482878 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See MOORE, supra note 5, at 230-31
    • See MOORE, supra note 5, at 230-31.
  • 82
    • 85081488242 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Thus, for example, the Model Penal Code eschews the biblical thou shalt not kill for one shall not cause[] the death of another human being. MODEL PENAL CODE § 210.1 (1) (1985).
    • Thus, for example, the Model Penal Code eschews the biblical "thou shalt not kill" for one shall not "cause[] the death of another human being." MODEL PENAL CODE § 210.1 (1) (1985).
  • 83
    • 85081479310 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dir. of Pub. Prosecutions for N. Ir. v. Lynch, [1975] A.C. 653, 659 (H.L.) (appeal taken from NICA (Crim)).
    • Dir. of Pub. Prosecutions for N. Ir. v. Lynch, [1975] A.C. 653, 659 (H.L.) (appeal taken from NICA (Crim)).
  • 84
    • 85081487073 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The House of Lords recognized as much by refusing the duress defense on roughly these facts (though involving stabbing instead of snooting) in Abbott v. The Queen, (1976) 3 All. E.R. 140, 142, 148 (P.C.) (appeal taken from Trin. & Tobago Ct. App.).
    • The House of Lords recognized as much by refusing the duress defense on roughly these facts (though involving stabbing instead of snooting) in Abbott v. The Queen, (1976) 3 All. E.R. 140, 142, 148 (P.C.) (appeal taken from Trin. & Tobago Ct. App.).
  • 85
    • 85081481951 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is argued for more extensively in Moore, Patrolling the Borders, supra note 3 manuscript at 36-37
    • This is argued for more extensively in Moore, Patrolling the Borders, supra note 3 (manuscript at 36-37).
  • 86
    • 85081486567 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, for example, Kimble v. Mackintosh Hemphill Co., 59 A.2d 68, 71 (Pa. 1948), where the defendant successfully argued that extreme winds were an intervening cause.
    • See, for example, Kimble v. Mackintosh Hemphill Co., 59 A.2d 68, 71 (Pa. 1948), where the defendant successfully argued that extreme winds were an intervening cause.
  • 87
    • 85081485906 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The hypothetical slightly alters the facts of Abbott, [1976] 3 All. E.R. at 141.
    • The hypothetical slightly alters the facts of Abbott, [1976] 3 All. E.R. at 141.
  • 88
    • 85081478613 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note 34, at, a recent paper, John Gardner does not see this problem as distinct from the general semantics of causatives just discussed
    • Kadish, supra note 34, at 372-85. In a recent paper, John Gardner does not see this problem as distinct from the general semantics of causatives just discussed.
    • supra , pp. 372-385
    • Kadish1
  • 89
    • 85081491501 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Gardner, supra note 43, at 135-36. Gardner's mistake here is due to his bloated notion of proxyability. Gardner mistakenly assumes all (or most) criminal prohibitions utilizing the causative verbs of English create nonproxyabile crimes. As we will see shortly, this is not Kadish's notion, which is much narrower and thus much more interesting.
    • See Gardner, supra note 43, at 135-36. Gardner's mistake here is due to his bloated notion of "proxyability." Gardner mistakenly assumes all (or most) criminal prohibitions utilizing the causative verbs of English create "nonproxyabile crimes." As we will see shortly, this is not Kadish's notion, which is much narrower and thus much more interesting.
  • 90
    • 85081491809 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Radish, supra note 34, at 373
    • Radish, supra note 34, at 373.
  • 91
    • 85081475898 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • footnotes omitted
    • Id. (footnotes omitted).
  • 92
    • 85081483152 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The explicit definition in some states, such as North Carolina, provides that only penetration by the defendant's penis constitutes rape. N.C. GEN. STAT. §§ 14-27.1-14-27.10 (2005).
    • The explicit definition in some states, such as North Carolina, provides that only penetration by the defendant's penis constitutes rape. N.C. GEN. STAT. §§ 14-27.1-14-27.10 (2005).
  • 93
    • 85081491989 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dusenbery v. Commonwealth, 263 S.E.2d 392 (Va. 1980).
    • Dusenbery v. Commonwealth, 263 S.E.2d 392 (Va. 1980).
  • 94
    • 85081479875 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 393
    • Id. at 393.
  • 95
    • 85081479678 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS § 431 (1965);
    • RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS § 431 (1965);
  • 96
    • 85081491364 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • RESTATEMENT OF TORTS § 431 (1934).
    • RESTATEMENT OF TORTS § 431 (1934).
  • 97
    • 85081490924 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This causation as primitive except for scalarity approach was adopted by the American Law Institute from Jeremiah Smith, Legal Cause in Actions of Tort (pts. 1-3, 25 HARV. L. REV. 102, 223, 303 1911-1912, Cause-as-primitive is a respectable view within the contemporary philosophy of science
    • This "causation as primitive except for scalarity" approach was adopted by the American Law Institute from Jeremiah Smith, Legal Cause in Actions of Tort (pts. 1-3), 25 HARV. L. REV. 102, 223, 303 (1911-1912). Cause-as-primitive is a respectable view within the contemporary philosophy of science.
  • 98
    • 85081488302 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See generally D.M. ARMSTRONG, WHAT IS A LAW OF NATURE? (1983);
    • See generally D.M. ARMSTRONG, WHAT IS A LAW OF NATURE? (1983);
  • 99
    • 85081489480 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MICHAEL TOOLEY, CAUSATION: A REALIST APPROACH (1987).
    • MICHAEL TOOLEY, CAUSATION: A REALIST APPROACH (1987).
  • 100
    • 85081488331 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS § 431;
    • RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS § 431;
  • 101
    • 85081486064 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • RESTATEMENT OF TORTS § 431.
    • RESTATEMENT OF TORTS § 431.
  • 102
    • 85081488500 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g, Perkins, supra note 4, at 594
    • See, e.g., Perkins, supra note 4, at 594.
  • 103
    • 85081485572 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a summary, see Kadish, supra note 34, at 369-72
    • For a summary, see Kadish, supra note 34, at 369-72.
  • 104
    • 85081479071 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 105
    • 85081476655 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 106
    • 85081486119 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • E.g, AGATHA CHRISTIE, MURDER ON THE ORIENT EXPRESS (1960). For a real-Hfe, if scaled-down, version with only two wounders,
    • E.g, AGATHA CHRISTIE, MURDER ON THE ORIENT EXPRESS (1960). For a real-Hfe, if scaled-down, version with only two wounders,
  • 107
    • 85081479662 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see People v. Lewis, 57 P. 470 (Cal. 1899).
    • see People v. Lewis, 57 P. 470 (Cal. 1899).
  • 108
    • 85081487336 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Wilcox v. Jeffery, (1951) 1 All E.R. 464 (K.B.).
    • Wilcox v. Jeffery, (1951) 1 All E.R. 464 (K.B.).
  • 109
    • 85081484553 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 466
    • Id. at 466.
  • 111
    • 85081485797 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • State ex. rel. Martin v. Tally, 15 So. 722 (Ala. 1894);
    • State ex. rel. Martin v. Tally, 15 So. 722 (Ala. 1894);
  • 112
    • 84963456897 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • notes 16-18 and ac-companying text
    • see supra notes 16-18 and ac-companying text.
    • see supra
  • 113
    • 84888494968 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • text accompanying notes 26-27
    • See supra text accompanying notes 26-27.
    • See supra
  • 114
    • 85081491389 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Cook v. Minneapolis, St. Paul & Sault Ste. Marie Ry. Co., 74 N.W. 561 (Wis. 1898) (concurrent overdetermination);
    • See Cook v. Minneapolis, St. Paul & Sault Ste. Marie Ry. Co., 74 N.W. 561 (Wis. 1898) (concurrent overdetermination);
  • 115
    • 85081478556 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • City of Piqua v. Morris, 120 N.E. 300 (Ohio 1918) (asymmetrical overdetermination);
    • City of Piqua v. Morris, 120 N.E. 300 (Ohio 1918) (asymmetrical overdetermination);
  • 116
    • 85081488741 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dillon v. Twin State Gas & Elec. Co., 163 A. 111 (N.H. 1932) (preemptive overdetermination).
    • Dillon v. Twin State Gas & Elec. Co., 163 A. 111 (N.H. 1932) (preemptive overdetermination).
  • 118
    • 85081482407 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Compare the differing views discussed in Causation and Counterfactual Baselines, id. at 1266-67,
    • Compare the differing views discussed in Causation and Counterfactual Baselines, id. at 1266-67,
  • 119
    • 85081484322 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • with Moore, Patrolling the Borders, supra note 3
    • with Moore, Patrolling the Borders, supra note 3.
  • 120
    • 85081484105 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The discussion that follows summarizes Moore, Causal Relata, supra note 3, at 614-25
    • The discussion that follows summarizes Moore, Causal Relata, supra note 3, at 614-25.
  • 121
    • 85081483006 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • One needn't agree with the example to agree with the point being illustrated. If to your sense of how things are, dyings are just not-survivings, then transpose the example. And if your view is that surviving and dying are both positive events or states of affairs, then (given the contradictory or at least contrary relation between them) your positive events are at the same time negative events-that is, you seem committed to there being negative events, negative states of affairs, and negative properties.
    • One needn't agree with the example to agree with the point being illustrated. If to your sense of how things are, dyings are just not-survivings, then transpose the example. And if your view is that surviving and dying are both positive events or states of affairs, then (given the contradictory or at least contrary relation between them) your "positive" events are at the same time "negative" events-that is, you seem committed to there being negative events, negative states of affairs, and negative properties.
  • 122
    • 85081487585 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For more details, see, at
    • For more details, see Moore, Causal Relata, supra note 3, at 617-18.
    • Causal Relata, supra note , vol.3 , pp. 617-618
    • Moore1
  • 123
    • 85081477232 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a description of the rape that occurred in New Bedford, see Lynn S. Chancer, New Bedford, Massachusetts, March 6, 1983- March 22, 1984: The Before and After of a Group Rape, 1 GENDER & SOC'Y 239, 244-46 (1987). For a fictionalized account, see THE ACCUSED (Paramount Pictures 1988).
    • For a description of the rape that occurred in New Bedford, see Lynn S. Chancer, New Bedford, Massachusetts, March 6, 1983- March 22, 1984: The "Before and After" of a Group Rape, 1 GENDER & SOC'Y 239, 244-46 (1987). For a fictionalized account, see THE ACCUSED (Paramount Pictures 1988).
  • 124
    • 85081489950 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MOORE, supra note 5, at 278 n.42.
    • MOORE, supra note 5, at 278 n.42.
  • 126
    • 85081482912 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Most of my article Patrolling the Borders, supra note 3, deals with the doing/allowing distinction.
    • Most of my article Patrolling the Borders, supra note 3, deals with the doing/allowing distinction.
  • 127
    • 85081482172 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. (manuscript at 44).
    • See id. (manuscript at 44).
  • 128
    • 85081487789 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Most famous is Regina v. Dudley Stephens, (1884) 14 Q.B.D. 273,
    • Most famous is Regina v. Dudley Stephens, (1884) 14 Q.B.D. 273,
  • 129
    • 85081477747 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • where the defendants killed a cabin boy who was about to die of natural causes anyway. I discuss the run of acceleration cases in Moore, Patrolling the Borders, supra note 3 (manuscript at 44-48).
    • where the defendants killed a cabin boy who was about to die of natural causes anyway. I discuss the run of acceleration cases in Moore, Patrolling the Borders, supra note 3 (manuscript at 44-48).
  • 130
    • 85081490891 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Moore, Patrolling the Borders, supra note 3 (manuscript at 43-44) for a description of such interrogation techniques and an analysis of whether torture can be justified in the war on terror.
    • See Moore, Patrolling the Borders, supra note 3 (manuscript at 43-44) for a description of such interrogation techniques and an analysis of whether torture can be justified in the "war on terror."
  • 131
    • 85081477278 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. (manuscript at 43).
    • See id. (manuscript at 43).
  • 133
    • 85081486196 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ireland v. United Kingdom, 25 Eur. Ct. H.R. (ser. A) at 67 (1976).
    • Ireland v. United Kingdom, 25 Eur. Ct. H.R. (ser. A) at 67 (1976).
  • 134
    • 85081483308 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sister Diana Ortiz acknowledged this in her Keynote Address to the conference at the City University of New York Graduate Center, Torture After 9/11: The Legal and Ethical Implications of Torture in the New Age of Terrorism Oct. 24, 2003
    • Sister Diana Ortiz acknowledged this in her Keynote Address to the conference at the City University of New York Graduate Center, Torture After 9/11: The Legal and Ethical Implications of Torture in the New Age of Terrorism (Oct. 24, 2003).
  • 135
    • 85081478625 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For those unfamiliar with the notation, P(E/C) means the probability of E given C, whereas P(E) means the probability of E.
    • For those unfamiliar with the notation, P(E/C) means "the probability of E given C," whereas P(E) means "the probability of E."
  • 136
    • 85081482789 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For an excellent summary of the different interpretations of probability, see DONALD GILLIES, PHILOSOPHICAL THEORIES OF PROBABILITY 1-13 (2000).
    • For an excellent summary of the different interpretations of probability, see DONALD GILLIES, PHILOSOPHICAL THEORIES OF PROBABILITY 1-13 (2000).
  • 137
    • 85081475529 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • An epiphenomenal fork is created when a single cause produces two distinct effects that have no causal relationship between themselves. To return to an earlier example, see supra text accompanying notes 25-26, at time t1 I run in the morning with my dog; this causes (at t2) my foot to become sore. My running with my dog also causes at t3 my dog to get tired. If I only run with my dog, he only gets tired when he runs with me, and my feet only get tired when I run, then my dog being tired at t3 raises the probability of my feet being tired at t2
    • 2.
  • 138
    • 85081476234 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For background information on the idea that causes raise the probability of their effects, see Christopher Hitchcock, Probabilistic Causation, in STANFORD ENCYCLOPEDIA OF PHILOSOPHY (Edward N. Zalta ed., Summer 2007), http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2007/entries/causation- probalistic/.
    • For background information on the idea that causes raise the probability of their effects, see Christopher Hitchcock, Probabilistic Causation, in STANFORD ENCYCLOPEDIA OF PHILOSOPHY (Edward N. Zalta ed., Summer 2007), http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2007/entries/causation- probalistic/.
  • 139
    • 85081485249 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • § 6.2 for an explanation of theories that reach a contrary conclusion -that
    • See id. § 6.2 for an explanation of theories that reach a contrary conclusion -that A did not cause V's death.
    • A did not cause V's death
  • 140
    • 85081491154 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A hard way case is where there are two causal routes possible to some result, one route being easier than another in the sense that success is much more probable with the easier route. For example, I could hit a birdie in golf with a direct shot to the hole; or once in a great while I could make the birdie by hitting a tree in just such a way that the ball ricochets into the hole. Making the birdie the hard way is to hit the tree. Hitting the tree admittedly caused me to make the birdie but hitting the tree also lowered the probability of the birdie compared to a direct shot. For a number of such counterexamples, see Wesley C. Salmon, Probabilistic Causality, 61 PAC. PHIL. Q. 50, 68-70 (1980).
    • A "hard way" case is where there are two causal routes possible to some result, one route being easier than another in the sense that success is much more probable with the easier route. For example, I could hit a birdie in golf with a direct shot to the hole; or once in a great while I could make the birdie by hitting a tree in just such a way that the ball ricochets into the hole. Making the birdie the "hard way" is to hit the tree. Hitting the tree admittedly caused me to make the birdie but hitting the tree also lowered the probability of the birdie compared to a direct shot. For a number of such counterexamples, see Wesley C. Salmon, Probabilistic Causality, 61 PAC. PHIL. Q. 50, 68-70 (1980).
  • 141
    • 85081490935 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The example is discussed in Germund Hesslow, Two Notes on the Probabilistic Approach to Causality, 43 PHIL. SCI. 290, 291 (1976).
    • The example is discussed in Germund Hesslow, Two Notes on the Probabilistic Approach to Causality, 43 PHIL. SCI. 290, 291 (1976).
  • 142
    • 85081482676 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See the summary in Hitchcock, supra note 98
    • See the summary in Hitchcock, supra note 98.
  • 144
    • 85081481596 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The leading case on the tort of lost chance is Herskovits v. Group Health Cooperative of Puget Sound, 664 P.2d 474 (Wash. 1983). Eric Johnson nicely shows how many putatively cause-based liability cases in criminal law are in reality lost chance cases (because of laxity in the proof deemed sufficient for causation).
    • The leading case on the tort of "lost chance" is Herskovits v. Group Health Cooperative of Puget Sound, 664 P.2d 474 (Wash. 1983). Eric Johnson nicely shows how many putatively cause-based liability cases in criminal law are in reality lost chance cases (because of laxity in the proof deemed sufficient for causation).
  • 145
    • 31144475403 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Criminal Liability for Loss of a Chance, 91
    • Eric A. Johnson, Criminal Liability for Loss of a Chance, 91 IOWA L. REV. 59, 69-76 (2005).
    • (2005) IOWA L. REV , vol.59 , pp. 69-76
    • Johnson, E.A.1
  • 146
    • 85081479684 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • E.g, State ex rel. Martin v. Tally, 15 So. 722 (Ala. 1894).
    • E.g, State ex rel. Martin v. Tally, 15 So. 722 (Ala. 1894).
  • 147
    • 85081490952 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • An instance of the latter kind is Hyam v. Director of Public Prosecutions, 1975] A.C. 55, 78-79 (H.L, appeal taken from Eng, in which the court determed that Mrs. Hyam did not intend to kill Mr. Booth, but she did intend to create a serious risk of death in order to scare Mrs. Booth
    • An instance of the latter kind is Hyam v. Director of Public Prosecutions, [1975] A.C. 55, 78-79 (H.L.) (appeal taken from Eng.), in which the court determed that Mrs. Hyam did not intend to kill Mr. Booth, but she did intend to create a serious risk of death (in order to scare Mrs. Booth).
  • 148
    • 0030530625 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Deontology of Negligence, 76
    • There is considerable debate here. For arguments supporting the idea that risk is not in itself harm, see
    • There is considerable debate here. For arguments supporting the idea that risk is not in itself harm, see Heidi M. Hurd, The Deontology of Negligence, 76 B.U. L. REV. 249, 262-65 (1996);
    • (1996) B.U. L. REV , vol.249 , pp. 262-265
    • Hurd, H.M.1
  • 149
    • 85081487363 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Stephen R. Perry, Risk, Harm, and Responsibility, in PHILOSOPHICAL FOUNDATIONS OF TORT LAW 321, 330-39 (David G. Owen ed., 1995). For an exploration of the idea that exposing someone to a risk is itself to harm her,
    • Stephen R. Perry, Risk, Harm, and Responsibility, in PHILOSOPHICAL FOUNDATIONS OF TORT LAW 321, 330-39 (David G. Owen ed., 1995). For an exploration of the idea that exposing someone to a risk is itself to harm her,
  • 150
    • 0038548470 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Is Risk a Harm?, 151
    • see
    • see Claire Finkelstein, Is Risk a Harm?, 151 U. PA. L. REV. 963 (2003).
    • (2003) U. PA. L. REV , vol.963
    • Finkelstein, C.1
  • 152
    • 85081480519 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 15 So. at
    • Tally, 15 So. at 738-39.
    • Tally , pp. 738-739
  • 153
    • 85081481819 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 739
    • Id. at 739.
  • 154
    • 85081485434 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g, Perkins, supra note 4, at 618
    • See, e.g., Perkins, supra note 4, at 618.
  • 155
    • 85081483894 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See MODEL PENAL CODE § 5.01(3) (1985) (making liable for attempt one who aid[s] another to commit a crime that would establish his complicity under section 2.06 if the crime were committed by such other person).
    • See MODEL PENAL CODE § 5.01(3) (1985) (making liable for attempt one who "aid[s] another to commit a crime that would establish his complicity under section 2.06 if the crime were committed by such other person").
  • 156
    • 85081479357 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g, Perkins, supra note 4, at 600
    • See, e.g., Perkins, supra note 4, at 600.
  • 157
    • 85081475152 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MODEL PENAL CODE § 2.06 cmt. 6 (c).
    • MODEL PENAL CODE § 2.06 cmt. 6 (c).
  • 158
    • 85081477437 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Tally, 15 So. at 739.
    • Tally, 15 So. at 739.
  • 159
    • 85081483150 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See 2 DAVID R. LEWIS, Postscripts to Causation, in PHILOSOPHICAL PAPERS 172 (1986).
    • See 2 DAVID R. LEWIS, Postscripts to "Causation," in PHILOSOPHICAL PAPERS 172 (1986).
  • 160
    • 85081488260 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 176
    • Id. at 176.
  • 161
    • 85081474960 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 178
    • Id. at 178.
  • 162
    • 85081489112 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 163
    • 85081492568 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See note 98, § 3.2
    • See Hitchcock, supra note 98, § 3.2.
    • supra
    • Hitchcock1
  • 164
    • 85081486462 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Larkins v. Police, [1987] 2 N.Z.L.R. 282, 283-86 (H.C.).
    • See Larkins v. Police, [1987] 2 N.Z.L.R. 282, 283-86 (H.C.).
  • 165
    • 85081479723 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MODEL PENAL CODE § 2.06(3) (a) (ii).
    • MODEL PENAL CODE § 2.06(3) (a) (ii).
  • 166
    • 85081477272 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. § 5.01 (3).
    • Id. § 5.01 (3).
  • 167
    • 85081483326 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • People v. Rizzo, 158 N.E. 888, 889 (N.Y. 1927)
    • People v. Rizzo, 158 N.E. 888, 889 (N.Y. 1927)
  • 168
    • 85081479681 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (quoting Hyde v. United States, 225 U.S. 347, 388 (1911) (Holmes, J., dissenting)).
    • (quoting Hyde v. United States, 225 U.S. 347, 388 (1911) (Holmes, J., dissenting)).
  • 169
    • 85081487581 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Admittedly, it is difficult to discern any one policy intuition guiding the old common law defense of legal impossibility. The requirement that there be a near miss - a significant raising of objective chance - is the best sense I can make of the cases.
    • Admittedly, it is difficult to discern any one policy intuition guiding the old common law defense of "legal impossibility." The requirement that there be a "near miss" - a significant raising of objective chance - is the best sense I can make of the cases.
  • 170
    • 85081484555 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MODEL PENAL CODE § 5.01 (2).
    • MODEL PENAL CODE § 5.01 (2).
  • 171
    • 85081487378 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. § 5.05 (2).
    • See id. § 5.05 (2).
  • 172
    • 85081486362 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The mental action theorists saw this clearly. For a discussion, see MOORE, supra note 5, at 95-108
    • The "mental action" theorists saw this clearly. For a discussion, see MOORE, supra note 5, at 95-108.
  • 173
    • 85081488529 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • These are roughly the facts of Thacker v. Commonwealth, 114 S.E. 504, 505 (Va. 1922).
    • These are roughly the facts of Thacker v. Commonwealth, 114 S.E. 504, 505 (Va. 1922).
  • 174
    • 65849098499 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Michael Zimmerman, Taking Luck Seriously, 99 J. PHIL. 553, 554-55 (2002). Christopher Kutz plainly feels the tug toward aretaic theories in his inchoate interpretation of complicity.
    • Michael Zimmerman, Taking Luck Seriously, 99 J. PHIL. 553, 554-55 (2002). Christopher Kutz plainly feels the tug toward aretaic theories in his inchoate interpretation of complicity.
  • 175
    • 85081489606 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Kutz, supra note 10
    • See Kutz, supra note 10.
  • 176
    • 85081480182 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • But not as blameworthy, because she has done nothing wrong. In my lexicon, culpability is but one of two ingredients in overall blameworthiness, the other being wrongdoing. See Moore, The Independent Moral Significance of Wrongdoing, supra note 3, at 237-38.
    • But not as blameworthy, because she has done nothing wrong. In my lexicon, culpability is but one of two ingredients in overall blameworthiness, the other being wrongdoing. See Moore, The Independent Moral Significance of Wrongdoing, supra note 3, at 237-38.
  • 178
    • 85081488297 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 646
    • Id. at 646.
  • 179
    • 85081485925 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 651 (Rutledge, J., dissenting in part).
    • Id. at 651 (Rutledge, J., dissenting in part).
  • 180
    • 85081485944 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MODEL PENAL CODE § 2.06(3) & cmt. 6(a) (1985).
    • MODEL PENAL CODE § 2.06(3) & cmt. 6(a) (1985).
  • 181
    • 85081490910 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Joshua Dressler heads off in this direction, although with only two categories of accomplices, causal accomplices and noncausal accomplices, rather than four. Dressier, supra note 9, at 124-30
    • Joshua Dressler heads off in this direction, although with only two categories of accomplices, "causal accomplices" and "noncausal accomplices," rather than four. Dressier, supra note 9, at 124-30.
  • 183
    • 85081484549 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For development of this suggestion, see Moore, Causation and Responsibility, supra note 3, at 19, 41-43
    • For development of this suggestion, see Moore, Causation and Responsibility, supra note 3, at 19, 41-43.
  • 184
    • 85081485964 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Regina v. Richards, [1974] Q.B. 776.
    • Regina v. Richards, [1974] Q.B. 776.
  • 185
    • 85081482683 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 780
    • Id. at 780.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.