메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 16, Issue 2, 1999, Pages 1-51

Causation and responsibility

(1)  Moore, Michael S a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0039598792     PISSN: 02650525     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1017/s0265052500002387     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (27)

References (200)
  • 1
    • 0039233180 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Annotated Code of Maryland, Art. 27, Section 35A(2)
    • Annotated Code of Maryland, Art. 27, Section 35A(2).
  • 3
    • 24244434715 scopus 로고
    • New York: Banks Law Publishing Co.
    • Sir Frederick Pollock, Torts, 6th ed. (New York: Banks Law Publishing Co., 1901), 36.
    • (1901) Torts, 6th Ed. , pp. 36
    • Pollock, F.1
  • 4
    • 21844500590 scopus 로고
    • Criminal liability and the duty to aid the distressed
    • Such politics-based skepticism about metaphysics surfaced recently with regard to my use of the metaphysics of events to answer certain questions of criminal law. Compare Samuel Freeman, "Criminal Liability and the Duty to Aid the Distressed," University of Pennsylvania Law Review 142 (1994): 1455-56, with Michael S. Moore, "More on Act and Crime," University of Pennsylvania Law Review 142 (1994): 1750-59.
    • (1994) University of Pennsylvania Law Review , vol.142 , pp. 1455-1456
    • Freeman, S.1
  • 5
    • 21844487903 scopus 로고
    • More on act and crime
    • Such politics-based skepticism about metaphysics surfaced recently with regard to my use of the metaphysics of events to answer certain questions of criminal law. Compare Samuel Freeman, "Criminal Liability and the Duty to Aid the Distressed," University of Pennsylvania Law Review 142 (1994): 1455-56, with Michael S. Moore, "More on Act and Crime," University of Pennsylvania Law Review 142 (1994): 1750-59.
    • (1994) University of Pennsylvania Law Review , vol.142 , pp. 1750-1759
    • Moore, M.S.1
  • 6
    • 0345569990 scopus 로고
    • The semantics of judging
    • On purposive interpretation of legal texts, see Michael S. Moore, "The Semantics of Judging," Southern California Law Review 54 (1981): 279-81; and Moore, "A Natural Law Theory of Interpretation," Southern California Law Review 58 (1985): 383-88.
    • (1981) Southern California Law Review , vol.54 , pp. 279-281
    • Moore, M.S.1
  • 7
    • 0039233113 scopus 로고
    • A natural law theory of interpretation
    • On purposive interpretation of legal texts, see Michael S. Moore, "The Semantics of Judging," Southern California Law Review 54 (1981): 279-81; and Moore, "A Natural Law Theory of Interpretation," Southern California Law Review 58 (1985): 383-88.
    • (1985) Southern California Law Review , vol.58 , pp. 383-388
    • Moore1
  • 8
    • 0041011693 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the criminal-law meaning of "malice" in the law of homicide, see Moore, "Natural Law Theory," 332-36.
    • Natural Law Theory , pp. 332-336
    • Moore1
  • 9
    • 0000670301 scopus 로고
    • Some thoughts on risk distribution and the law of torts
    • A late expression of this view of tort law is to be found in Guido Calabresi, "Some Thoughts on Risk Distribution and the Law of Torts," Yale Law Journal 70 (1961): 499-553.
    • (1961) Yale Law Journal , vol.70 , pp. 499-553
    • Calabresi, G.1
  • 10
  • 11
    • 0011538305 scopus 로고
    • A theory of strict liability
    • I thus put aside those who interpret Coase to be a causal skeptic. (See, e.g., Richard Epstein, "A Theory of Strict Liability," Journal of Legal Studies 2 [1973]: 164-65, for an interpretation of Coase according to which the Coasean insight was that we cannot say what is the cause of what.) Coase made a much better point than this "interactive effects" interpretation gives him credit for: it is that causation does not matter for the efficient allocation of resources.
    • (1973) Journal of Legal Studies , vol.2 , pp. 164-165
    • Epstein, R.1
  • 12
    • 0038166120 scopus 로고
    • Concerning cause and the law of torts: An essay for Harry Kalven, Jr.
    • See, e.g., Guido Calabresi, "Concerning Cause and the Law of Torts: An Essay for Harry Kalven, Jr.," University of Chicago Law Review 43 (1975): 69-108; Steven Shavell, "An Analysis of Causation and the Scope of Liability in the Law of Torts," Journal of Legal Studies 9 (1980): 463-503; and William Landes and Richard Posner, "Causation in Tort Law: An Economic Approach," Journal of Legal Studies 12 (1983): 109-34.
    • (1975) University of Chicago Law Review , vol.43 , pp. 69-108
    • Calabresi, G.1
  • 13
    • 0002775690 scopus 로고
    • An analysis of causation and the scope of liability in the law of torts
    • See, e.g., Guido Calabresi, "Concerning Cause and the Law of Torts: An Essay for Harry Kalven, Jr.," University of Chicago Law Review 43 (1975): 69-108; Steven Shavell, "An Analysis of Causation and the Scope of Liability in the Law of Torts," Journal of Legal Studies 9 (1980): 463-503; and William Landes and Richard Posner, "Causation in Tort Law: An Economic Approach," Journal of Legal Studies 12 (1983): 109-34.
    • (1980) Journal of Legal Studies , vol.9 , pp. 463-503
    • Shavell, S.1
  • 14
    • 0039233105 scopus 로고
    • Causation in tort law: An economic approach
    • See, e.g., Guido Calabresi, "Concerning Cause and the Law of Torts: An Essay for Harry Kalven, Jr.," University of Chicago Law Review 43 (1975): 69-108; Steven Shavell, "An Analysis of Causation and the Scope of Liability in the Law of Torts," Journal of Legal Studies 9 (1980): 463-503; and William Landes and Richard Posner, "Causation in Tort Law: An Economic Approach," Journal of Legal Studies 12 (1983): 109-34.
    • (1983) Journal of Legal Studies , vol.12 , pp. 109-134
    • Landes, W.1    Posner, R.2
  • 15
    • 0011601654 scopus 로고
    • Actual causation versus probabilistic linkage: The bane of economic analysis
    • For a good discussion of the economists' misuse of "cause" to name an increase in conditional probability, see Richard Wright, "Actual Causation versus Probabilistic Linkage: The Bane of Economic Analysis," Journal of Legal Studies 14 (1985): 435-56; and Wright, "The Efficiency Theory of Causation and Responsibility: Unscientific Formalism and False Semantics," Chicago-Kent Law Review 63 (1987): 553-78.
    • (1985) Journal of Legal Studies , vol.14 , pp. 435-456
    • Wright, R.1
  • 16
    • 0039233109 scopus 로고
    • The efficiency theory of causation and responsibility: Unscientific formalism and false semantics
    • For a good discussion of the economists' misuse of "cause" to name an increase in conditional probability, see Richard Wright, "Actual Causation versus Probabilistic Linkage: The Bane of Economic Analysis," Journal of Legal Studies 14 (1985): 435-56; and Wright, "The Efficiency Theory of Causation and Responsibility: Unscientific Formalism and False Semantics," Chicago-Kent Law Review 63 (1987): 553-78.
    • (1987) Chicago-Kent Law Review , vol.63 , pp. 553-578
    • Wright1
  • 18
  • 22
    • 0001777781 scopus 로고
    • Probabilistic causality
    • Contrast the simple, conditional probability analysis used by economists (supra note 10) with the more complicated probability analysis of causation by philosophers. See, e.g., Wesley Salmon, "Probabilistic Causality," Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 61 (1980): 50-74. No philosopher would propose a simple increase in the conditional probability of an event E by the existence of an event C as an analysis of causation, for that completely fails to distinguish epiphenomena, accidental correlations, and preempted conditions, on the one hand, from true causal relations, on the other. Yet from the point of view of an incentive-based system that eschews any attempt to analyze a pre-legal notion of causation, such an increase in conditional probability may be an appropriate trigger for legal liability.
    • (1980) Pacific Philosophical Quarterly , vol.61 , pp. 50-74
    • Salmon, W.1
  • 23
    • 0041011640 scopus 로고
    • The necessary myth of objective causation judgments in liberal political theory
    • Mark Kelman, "The Necessary Myth of Objective Causation Judgments in Liberal Political Theory," Chicago-Kent Law Review 63 (1987): 579-637.
    • (1987) Chicago-Kent Law Review , vol.63 , pp. 579-637
    • Kelman, M.1
  • 24
    • 0041011642 scopus 로고
    • Ruminations on cause-in-fact
    • Wex Malone, "Ruminations on Cause-in-Fact," Stanford Law Review 9 (1956): 60-99.
    • (1956) Stanford Law Review , vol.9 , pp. 60-99
    • Malone, W.1
  • 27
    • 0039233104 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ryan v. New York Central R.R., 35 N.Y. 210, 91 Am. Dec. 49 (1866). (Railroad liable only for the first house that its negligently emitted sparks ignite, not for each subsequent house that first house, in turn, ignites.)
    • Ryan v. New York Central R.R., 35 N.Y. 210, 91 Am. Dec. 49 (1866). (Railroad liable only for the first house that its negligently emitted sparks ignite, not for each subsequent house that first house, in turn, ignites.)
  • 28
    • 0003877887 scopus 로고
    • New York: Matthew-Bender
    • See Joshua Dressler, Understanding Criminal Law, 2d ed. (New York: Matthew-Bender, 1995): 466-67. (A death occurring more than a year and a day from the act of a defendant conclusively presumed not to be the effect of that act.)
    • (1995) Understanding Criminal Law, 2d Ed. , pp. 466-467
    • Dressler, J.1
  • 29
    • 0039233107 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 21
    • See Green, Rationale (supra note 21). On this test, one asks whether the harm that happened was an instance of the type of harm whose risk made the defendant's action negligent to perform; this is not a causal inquiry, but rather a culpability inquiry.
    • Rationale
    • Green1
  • 30
    • 0039233108 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • American Law Institute, Model Penal Code, section 2.03
    • American Law Institute, Model Penal Code, section 2.03.
  • 31
    • 0002042993 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (supra note 12), ch. 8
    • On foreseeability, see Moore, Placing Blame (supra note 12), ch. 8. The test purports to ask a single question: Was the harm that happened foreseeable to the defendant as he acted?
    • Placing Blame
    • Moore1
  • 32
    • 0039824972 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 20
    • Edgarton "Legal Cause" (supra note 20). ("Proximate cause" is the label put on the conclusion of balancing social and individual interests on a case-by-case basis.)
    • Legal Cause
    • Edgarton1
  • 33
    • 0004258937 scopus 로고
    • London: Methuen
    • P. F. Strawson, Individuals (London: Methuen, 1959). Ordinary-language philosophy (e.g., at Oxford University from 1945 to 1965) went further than I go in the text. Such ordinary-language philosophers as Gilbert Ryle, Ludwig Wittgenstein, and J. L. Austin thought that the only metaphysics one can do is the descriptive metaphysics described in the text. For a critique, see Michael Moore, "The Interpretive Turn: A Turn for the Worse?" Stanford Law Review 41 (1989): 927-34.
    • (1959) Individuals
    • Strawson, P.F.1
  • 34
    • 84926958480 scopus 로고
    • The interpretive turn: A turn for the worse?
    • P. F. Strawson, Individuals (London: Methuen, 1959). Ordinary-language philosophy (e.g., at Oxford University from 1945 to 1965) went further than I go in the text. Such ordinary-language philosophers as Gilbert Ryle, Ludwig Wittgenstein, and J. L. Austin thought that the only metaphysics one can do is the descriptive metaphysics described in the text. For a critique, see Michael Moore, "The Interpretive Turn: A Turn for the Worse?" Stanford Law Review 41 (1989): 927-34.
    • (1989) Stanford Law Review , vol.41 , pp. 927-934
    • Moore, M.1
  • 35
    • 0040417526 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kramer Service, Inc. v. Wilkins, 184 Miss. 483, 186 So. 625 (1939)
    • See, e.g., Kramer Service, Inc. v. Wilkins, 184 Miss. 483, 186 So. 625 (1939).
  • 36
    • 0040417525 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Although invariant succession is admissable as good evidence of causation.
  • 37
    • 85047316500 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • The example is David Armstrong's in his argument that accidentally true generalizations must be distinguished from true causal laws. See Armstrong, What Is a Law of Nature? (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1983).
    • (1983) What Is a Law of Nature?
    • Armstrong1
  • 38
    • 0039233084 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 17
    • For discussions of the epiphenomena problem, see Salmon, "Probabilistic Causality" (supra note 17); David Lewis, "Causation," Journal of Philosophy 70 (1973): 556-67; and Jaegwon Kim, "Epiphenomenal and Supervenient Causation," in Midwest Studies in Philosophy IX: Causation and Causal Theories, ed. Peter French, Theodore Vehling, and Howard Wettstein (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1984).
    • Probabilistic Causality
    • Salmon1
  • 39
    • 0001122210 scopus 로고
    • Causation
    • For discussions of the epiphenomena problem, see Salmon, "Probabilistic Causality" (supra note 17); David Lewis, "Causation," Journal of Philosophy 70 (1973): 556-67; and Jaegwon Kim, "Epiphenomenal and Supervenient Causation," in Midwest Studies in Philosophy IX: Causation and Causal Theories, ed. Peter French, Theodore Vehling, and Howard Wettstein (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1984).
    • (1973) Journal of Philosophy , vol.70 , pp. 556-567
    • Lewis, D.1
  • 40
    • 84985348714 scopus 로고
    • Epiphenomenal and supervenient causation
    • ed. Peter French, Theodore Vehling, and Howard Wettstein Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press
    • For discussions of the epiphenomena problem, see Salmon, "Probabilistic Causality" (supra note 17); David Lewis, "Causation," Journal of Philosophy 70 (1973): 556-67; and Jaegwon Kim, "Epiphenomenal and Supervenient Causation," in Midwest Studies in Philosophy IX: Causation and Causal Theories, ed. Peter French, Theodore Vehling, and Howard Wettstein (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1984).
    • (1984) Midwest Studies in Philosophy IX: Causation and Causal Theories
    • Jaegwon, K.1
  • 41
    • 84908913220 scopus 로고
    • Causality in everyday life and in recent science
    • For a discussion of how law, morals, common sense, and science all converge to distinguish correlation from causation, see Moritz Schlick, "Causality in Everyday Life and in Recent Science," University of California Publications in Philosophy 15 (1932): 99-125.
    • (1932) University of California Publications in Philosophy , vol.15 , pp. 99-125
    • Schlick, M.1
  • 42
    • 0041011632 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is the dominant test for cause-in-fact in both torts and criminal law in America. See, e.g., New York Central R.R. v. Grimstad, 264 F.2d 334 (2d Cir. 1920); and American Law Institute, Model Penal Code, section 2.03(1)
    • This is the dominant test for cause-in-fact in both torts and criminal law in America. See, e.g., New York Central R.R. v. Grimstad, 264 F.2d 334 (2d Cir. 1920); and American Law Institute, Model Penal Code, section 2.03(1).
  • 43
    • 0040417523 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 2
    • See Moore, Act and Crime (supra note 2), 267-76.
    • Act and Crime , pp. 267-276
    • Moore1
  • 45
    • 0004156082 scopus 로고
    • Princeton: Princeton University Press
    • For a discussion of these pragmatic features in various contexts, see Joel Feinberg, Doing and Deserving (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1970).
    • (1970) Doing and Deserving
    • Feinberg, J.1
  • 46
    • 0040416095 scopus 로고
    • Legal cause in actions of tort
    • Jeremiah Smith, "Legal Cause in Actions of Tort," Harvard Law Review 25 (1911-12): 104.
    • (1911) Harvard Law Review , vol.25 , pp. 104
    • Smith, J.1
  • 47
    • 0040417522 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Parsons v. State, 81 Ala. 577, 597, 5 So. 854, 866-67 (1887)
    • Parsons v. State, 81 Ala. 577, 597, 5 So. 854, 866-67 (1887).
  • 48
    • 84928216342 scopus 로고
    • Causation in tort law
    • The best contemporary legal discussion of these cases is to be found in Richard Wright, "Causation in Tort Law," California Law Review 73 (1985): 1775-98. Overdetermination cases are to be distinguished from garden-variety multiple cause cases. In the latter, no one event or state is sufficient to produce the harm, because more than one event is individually necessary to produce the harm. Such sets of individually necessary, only jointly sufficient conditions, are very frequent and may well be the most frequent kind of case. Wright mentions (in ibid., 1793) a kind of case intermediate between regular multiple cause cases and the overdetermination variety. If there are three fires, no one of which is sufficient, but any two of which are sufficient, to burn the plaintiff's structure, then no fire is individually necessary to produce the harm. Although I do not separately treat these, we should consider these too to be overdetermination cases.
    • (1985) California Law Review , vol.73 , pp. 1775-1798
    • Wright, R.1
  • 49
    • 84907467921 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The best contemporary legal discussion of these cases is to be found in Richard Wright, "Causation in Tort Law," California Law Review 73 (1985): 1775-98. Overdetermination cases are to be distinguished from garden-variety multiple cause cases. In the latter, no one event or state is sufficient to produce the harm, because more than one event is individually necessary to produce the harm. Such sets of individually necessary, only jointly sufficient conditions, are very frequent and may well be the most frequent kind of case. Wright mentions (in ibid., 1793) a kind of case intermediate between regular multiple cause cases and the overdetermination variety. If there are three fires, no one of which is sufficient, but any two of which are sufficient, to burn the plaintiff's structure, then no fire is individually necessary to produce the harm. Although I do not separately treat these, we should consider these too to be overdetermination cases.
    • California Law Review , pp. 1793
  • 50
    • 0039824970 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See ibid
    • See ibid.
  • 51
    • 0040417516 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • These are the facts of Anderson v. Minneapolis St. Paul & S. St. Marie R.R. Co., 146 Minn. 430, 179 NW 45 (1920); and Kingston v. Chicago and N.W. Ry., 191 Wis. 610, 211 N.W. 913 (1927)
    • These are the facts of Anderson v. Minneapolis St. Paul & S. St. Marie R.R. Co., 146 Minn. 430, 179 NW 45 (1920); and Kingston v. Chicago and N.W. Ry., 191 Wis. 610, 211 N.W. 913 (1927).
  • 52
    • 0040417507 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. City of Piqua v. Morris, 98 Ohio St. 42, 120 N.E. 300 (1918) (negligent maintenance of drainage wickets held not a cause of plaintiff's injury from overflowing reservoir, because the flood would have overflowed the reservoir even if the wickets were not clogged)
    • Cf. City of Piqua v. Morris, 98 Ohio St. 42, 120 N.E. 300 (1918) (negligent maintenance of drainage wickets held not a cause of plaintiff's injury from overflowing reservoir, because the flood would have overflowed the reservoir even if the wickets were not clogged).
  • 54
    • 0039233103 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cook v. Minneapolis, St. Paul and S. St. Marie Ry., 98 Wis. 624, 74 N.W. 561 (1898)
    • Cook v. Minneapolis, St. Paul and S. St. Marie Ry., 98 Wis. 624, 74 N.W. 561 (1898).
  • 55
    • 0345105262 scopus 로고
    • New York: Pocket Books
    • Agatha Christie, Murder on the Orient Express (New York: Pocket Books, 1960). See also People v. Lewis, 124 Cal. 551, 57 P. 470 (1899) (initial gunshot and later knife wound both caused victim's death, because "drop by drop his life current welled out from both wounds and at the very instant of death the gunshot wound was contributing to the event").
    • (1960) Murder on the Orient Express
    • Christie, A.1
  • 57
    • 0039233087 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • People v. Dlugash, 41 N.Y. 2d 725, 363 N.E.2d 1155, 395 N.Y.S.2d 419 (1977)
    • People v. Dlugash, 41 N.Y. 2d 725, 363 N.E.2d 1155, 395 N.Y.S.2d 419 (1977).
  • 58
    • 0040417521 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Corey v. Havener, 182 Mass. 250, 65 N. E. 69 (1902)
    • Corey v. Havener, 182 Mass. 250, 65 N. E. 69 (1902).
  • 60
    • 0039233092 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The less seriously punished treason statute in force in England during the Second World War. See Rex. v. Stean, [1947] K.B. 997, 32 Crim. App. Rep. 61, 1947-1 All Eng. L. Rep. 813
    • The less seriously punished treason statute in force in England during the Second World War. See Rex. v. Stean, [1947] K.B. 997, 32 Crim. App. Rep. 61, 1947-1 All Eng. L. Rep. 813.
  • 61
    • 0039233094 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rex. v. Stean
    • Rex. v. Stean.
  • 63
    • 0039233085 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 40
    • This is Richard Wright's conclusion. See Wright, "Causation in Tort Law" (supra note 40), 1802.
    • Causation in Tort Law , pp. 1802
    • Wright1
  • 64
    • 0039233085 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is Wright's conclusion on a slightly varied version of the hypothetical, in ibid. See also J. L. Mackie, The Cement of the Universe (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1980), 45-46.
    • Causation in Tort Law
    • Wright1
  • 65
    • 0004037962 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • This is Wright's conclusion on a slightly varied version of the hypothetical, in ibid. See also J. L. Mackie, The Cement of the Universe (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1980), 45-46.
    • (1980) The Cement of the Universe , pp. 45-46
    • Mackie, J.L.1
  • 67
    • 0041011633 scopus 로고
    • Causal apportionment in the law of torts: An economic approach
    • On the idea of causal apportionment, see Mario Rizzo and Frank Arnold, "Causal Apportionment in the Law of Torts: An Economic Approach," Columbia Law Review 80 (1980): 1399-1429; Kaye and Aickn, "A Comment on Causal Apportionment," Journal of Legal Studies 13 (1984): 191-208; and Mario Rizzo and Frank Arnold, "Causal Apportionment: Reply to the Critics," Journal of Legal Studies 20 (1986): 219-26. In his essay in this volume, Alvin Goldman nicely sets out how our obligations to vote - even when our individual vote is not a necessary condition for the election's outcome - can be explained on like grounds (of causal contribution to the outcome for which one's vote was not a necessary condition). See Goldman, "Why Citizens Should Vote: A Causal Responsibility Approach."
    • (1980) Columbia Law Review , vol.80 , pp. 1399-1429
    • Rizzo, M.1    Arnold, F.2
  • 68
    • 0039231596 scopus 로고
    • A comment on causal apportionment
    • On the idea of causal apportionment, see Mario Rizzo and Frank Arnold, "Causal Apportionment in the Law of Torts: An Economic Approach," Columbia Law Review 80 (1980): 1399-1429; Kaye and Aickn, "A Comment on Causal Apportionment," Journal of Legal Studies 13 (1984): 191-208; and Mario Rizzo and Frank Arnold, "Causal Apportionment: Reply to the Critics," Journal of Legal Studies 20 (1986): 219-26. In his essay in this volume, Alvin Goldman nicely sets out how our obligations to vote - even when our individual vote is not a necessary condition for the election's outcome - can be explained on like grounds (of causal contribution to the outcome for which one's vote was not a necessary condition). See Goldman, "Why Citizens Should Vote: A Causal Responsibility Approach."
    • (1984) Journal of Legal Studies , vol.13 , pp. 191-208
    • Kaye1    Aickn2
  • 69
    • 0040416096 scopus 로고
    • Causal apportionment: Reply to the critics
    • On the idea of causal apportionment, see Mario Rizzo and Frank Arnold, "Causal Apportionment in the Law of Torts: An Economic Approach," Columbia Law Review 80 (1980): 1399-1429; Kaye and Aickn, "A Comment on Causal Apportionment," Journal of Legal Studies 13 (1984): 191-208; and Mario Rizzo and Frank Arnold, "Causal Apportionment: Reply to the Critics," Journal of Legal Studies 20 (1986): 219-26. In his essay in this volume, Alvin Goldman nicely sets out how our obligations to vote - even when our individual vote is not a necessary condition for the election's outcome - can be explained on like grounds (of causal contribution to the outcome for which one's vote was not a necessary condition). See Goldman, "Why Citizens Should Vote: A Causal Responsibility Approach."
    • (1986) Journal of Legal Studies , vol.20 , pp. 219-226
    • Rizzo, M.1    Arnold, F.2
  • 70
    • 0039233086 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the idea of causal apportionment, see Mario Rizzo and Frank Arnold, "Causal Apportionment in the Law of Torts: An Economic Approach," Columbia Law Review 80 (1980): 1399-1429; Kaye and Aickn, "A Comment on Causal Apportionment," Journal of Legal Studies 13 (1984): 191-208; and Mario Rizzo and Frank Arnold, "Causal Apportionment: Reply to the Critics," Journal of Legal Studies 20 (1986): 219-26. In his essay in this volume, Alvin Goldman nicely sets out how our obligations to vote - even when our individual vote is not a necessary condition for the election's outcome - can be explained on like grounds (of causal contribution to the outcome for which one's vote was not a necessary condition). See Goldman, "Why Citizens Should Vote: A Causal Responsibility Approach."
    • Why Citizens Should Vote: A Causal Responsibility Approach
    • Goldman1
  • 71
    • 0040417512 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In its original opinion creating comparative fault in California (Li v. Yellow Cab Co. of California, 532 P. 2d, 1226 [Cal. Sup. Ct. 1975]), the California Supreme Court held that one should apportion tort liability "in direct proportion to the extent of the parties' causal responsibility" (119 Cal. Rptr. 858 footnote 6a. [1975] [advance sheets only]). Prior to final publication, the court recognized its error, proportioning liability to degrees of fault, not to degrees of causation
    • In its original opinion creating comparative fault in California (Li v. Yellow Cab Co. of California, 532 P. 2d, 1226 [Cal. Sup. Ct. 1975]), the California Supreme Court held that one should apportion tort liability "in direct proportion to the extent of the parties' causal responsibility" (119 Cal. Rptr. 858 footnote 6a. [1975] [advance sheets only]). Prior to final publication, the court recognized its error, proportioning liability to degrees of fault, not to degrees of causation.
  • 73
    • 0041011634 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See ibid
    • See ibid.
  • 74
  • 75
    • 0346509867 scopus 로고
    • sections 431-35
    • Restatement of Torts, sections 431-35 (1934); Restatement (Second) of Torts, sections 431-33 (1965).
    • (1934) Restatement of Torts
  • 76
    • 0038260135 scopus 로고
    • sections 431-33
    • Restatement of Torts, sections 431-35 (1934); Restatement (Second) of Torts, sections 431-33 (1965).
    • (1965) Restatement (Second) of Torts
  • 77
    • 0040417513 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Regina v. Howe, [1987-1] All Eng. L. Rep. 771
    • Regina v. Howe, [1987-1] All Eng. L. Rep. 771.
  • 78
    • 0039233096 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Director of Public Prosecutions for Northern Ireland v. Lynch, [1975] A.C. 653
    • Director of Public Prosecutions for Northern Ireland v. Lynch, [1975] A.C. 653.
  • 79
    • 0039233102 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Regina v. Howe
    • Regina v. Howe.
  • 80
    • 0040417519 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Abbott v. The Queen, [1976-3] All Eng. L. Rep. 140
    • Abbott v. The Queen, [1976-3] All Eng. L. Rep. 140.
  • 81
    • 0041010200 scopus 로고
    • Torture and the balance of evils
    • See Michael Moore, "Torture and the Balance of Evils," Israel Law Review 23 (1989): 280-344; revised and reprinted as chapter 17 of Moore, Placing Blame (supra note 12).
    • (1989) Israel Law Review , vol.23 , pp. 280-344
    • Moore, M.1
  • 82
    • 0002042993 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • revised and reprinted as chapter 17 of supra note 12
    • See Michael Moore, "Torture and the Balance of Evils," Israel Law Review 23 (1989): 280-344; revised and reprinted as chapter 17 of Moore, Placing Blame (supra note 12).
    • Placing Blame
    • Moore1
  • 89
    • 0039233095 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • These are the facts of Regina v. Faulkner, 13 Cox C.C. 550 (Ireland, Court of Crown Cases Reserved, 1877)
    • These are the facts of Regina v. Faulkner, 13 Cox C.C. 550 (Ireland, Court of Crown Cases Reserved, 1877).
  • 90
    • 0038260135 scopus 로고
    • section 431, comment a
    • See the Restatement (Second) of Torts, section 431, comment a (1965), which proclaims that in law, "cause" is used "in the popular sense, in which there always lurks the idea of responsibility, rather than in the so-called 'philosophic sense' which includes every one of the great number of events without which any happening would not have occurred."
    • (1965) Restatement (Second) of Torts
  • 91
    • 0039233099 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 38
    • See, e.g., Smith, "Legal Cause" (supra note 38), 109. The sine qua non test, or necessary-condition test, is discussed in the text accompanying note 34 supra.
    • Legal Cause , pp. 109
    • Smith1
  • 92
    • 0041011635 scopus 로고
    • Maxims of the law
    • Bacon, London: Assigns of I. Moore
    • Sir Francis Bacon, "Maxims of the Law," in Bacon, The Elements of the Common Law of England (London: Assigns of I. Moore, 1630), 1.
    • (1630) The Elements of the Common Law of England , pp. 1
    • Bacon, F.1
  • 93
    • 0040417510 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Berry v. Borough of Sugar Notch, 191 Pa. 345, 43 Atl. 240 (1899). For another coincidence case, see Denny v. N.Y. Central R.R., 13 Gray (Mass.) 481 (1859) (railroad's negligence in delaying at one section of track, and its subsequent arrival at a flood plain just when a flood sweeps down and destroys goods on the train, held not to be a cause of the damage to the goods)
    • Berry v. Borough of Sugar Notch, 191 Pa. 345, 43 Atl. 240 (1899). For another coincidence case, see Denny v. N.Y. Central R.R., 13 Gray (Mass.) 481 (1859) (railroad's negligence in delaying at one section of track, and its subsequent arrival at a flood plain just when a flood sweeps down and destroys goods on the train, held not to be a cause of the damage to the goods).
  • 94
    • 0039824972 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Bird v. St. Paul F. and Minneapolis Ins. Co., 224 N.Y. 47, 120 N.E. 86 (1918) ("There is no use in arguing that distance ought not to count, if life and experience tell us that it does"); and supra note 20
    • Cf. Bird v. St. Paul F. and Minneapolis Ins. Co., 224 N.Y. 47, 120 N.E. 86 (1918) ("There is no use in arguing that distance ought not to count, if life and experience tell us that it does"); and Edgarton, "Legal Cause" (supra note 20), 369-70.
    • Legal Cause , pp. 369-370
    • Edgarton1
  • 95
    • 0040417506 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • People v. Botkin, 132 Cal. 231, 64 Pac. 286 (1901)
    • People v. Botkin, 132 Cal. 231, 64 Pac. 286 (1901).
  • 96
    • 0041010196 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A refinement may be necessary here. If the causal relation is transmitted over many events that are of the same type, then the diminishment of causation often seems to be less. See, e.g., Scott v. Shepherd, 96 All Eng. L. Rep. 525 (K.B. 1773) (liability for causing injury to plaintiff by explosion of a lighted squib that was thrown into a crowded marketplace by defendant, and then rethrown by each subsequent possessor of it so as to rid himself of the danger). The analogy here is to a long row of dominos; the falling of each is plausibly individuated as one event, but their ability to transmit causal force seems unrelated to the number of such events. A colorful example offered by Alfred Mele is a variation of People v. Botkin (supra note 80): Would it matter if the poisoned candy was sent from California to Delaware by Pony Express (with numerous handoffs) rather than by train
    • A refinement may be necessary here. If the causal relation is transmitted over many events that are of the same type, then the diminishment of causation often seems to be less. See, e.g., Scott v. Shepherd, 96 All Eng. L. Rep. 525 (K.B. 1773) (liability for causing injury to plaintiff by explosion of a lighted squib that was thrown into a crowded marketplace by defendant, and then rethrown by each subsequent possessor of it so as to rid himself of the danger). The analogy here is to a long row of dominos; the falling of each is plausibly individuated as one event, but their ability to transmit causal force seems unrelated to the number of such events. A colorful example offered by Alfred Mele is a variation of People v. Botkin (supra note 80): Would it matter if the poisoned candy was sent from California to Delaware by Pony Express (with numerous handoffs) rather than by train?
  • 97
    • 0040417505 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This line is much more difficult to draw than is recognized in any of the legal literature, yet it is a necessary line to draw in that preemption intervening causes do not have to meet the criteria below articulated for an intervening cause.
  • 98
    • 0003532976 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 47
    • Hart and Honoré, Causation in the Law (supra note 47). Although the clarity and the nonlegal analogues of the idea of an intervening cause were new with Hart and Honoré, they built on a solid body of case law. This case law is detailed in Charles Carpenter, "Workable Rules for Determining Proximate Cause," California Law Review 20 (1932): 229-59, 396-419, 471-539. Hart and Honoré's detailing of the case law is in Causation in the Law, 133-85, 325-62.
    • Causation in the Law
    • Hart1    Honoré2
  • 99
    • 0039231604 scopus 로고
    • Workable rules for determining proximate cause
    • Hart and Honoré, Causation in the Law (supra note 47). Although the clarity and the nonlegal analogues of the idea of an intervening cause were new with Hart and Honoré, they built on a solid body of case law. This case law is detailed in Charles Carpenter, "Workable Rules for Determining Proximate Cause," California Law Review 20 (1932): 229-59, 396-419, 471-539. Hart and Honoré's detailing of the case law is in Causation in the Law, 133-85, 325-62.
    • (1932) California Law Review , vol.20 , pp. 229-259
    • Carpenter, C.1
  • 100
    • 0003532976 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hart and Honoré, Causation in the Law (supra note 47). Although the clarity and the nonlegal analogues of the idea of an intervening cause were new with Hart and Honoré, they built on a solid body of case law. This case law is detailed in Charles Carpenter, "Workable Rules for Determining Proximate Cause," California Law Review 20 (1932): 229-59, 396-419, 471-539. Hart and Honoré's detailing of the case law is in Causation in the Law, 133-85, 325-62.
    • Causation in the Law , pp. 133-185
    • Hart1    Honoré2
  • 101
    • 0039233083 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Watson v. Kentucky and Indiana Bridge and Ry. Co., 137 Ky. 619, 126 S.W. 146 (1910)
    • Watson v. Kentucky and Indiana Bridge and Ry. Co., 137 Ky. 619, 126 S.W. 146 (1910).
  • 103
    • 0041011628 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • These are roughly the facts of Kimble v. Mackintosh Hemphill Co., 359 Pa. 461, 59 A.2d 68 (1948)
    • These are roughly the facts of Kimble v. Mackintosh Hemphill Co., 359 Pa. 461, 59 A.2d 68 (1948).
  • 107
    • 0039823586 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • E.g., State v. Scates, 50 N.C. 409 (1858) (defendant who burned child not liable for the child's death if an intervening blow on the head by a third party killed the dying child)
    • E.g., State v. Scates, 50 N.C. 409 (1858) (defendant who burned child not liable for the child's death if an intervening blow on the head by a third party killed the dying child).
  • 108
    • 0003532976 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • In the original edition of their book, Hart and Honoré simply except such situations from the normal rule about intentional intervening agents. See H. L. A. Hart and A. M. Honoré, Causation in the Law (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1959). As Joel Feinberg noted, these were ad hoc, unexplained, and seemingly unlimited as exceptions. See Feinberg, "Causing Voluntary Actions," in Feinberg, Doing and Deserving (supra note 37). In the second edition of Causation in the Law (supra note 47), chapters VII and XIII now deal extensively with the provision of opportunities and the giving of reasons as "non-central" kinds of causings.
    • (1959) Causation in the Law
    • Hart, H.L.A.1    Honoré, A.M.2
  • 109
    • 0009125779 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Causing voluntary actions
    • Feinberg, supra note 37
    • In the original edition of their book, Hart and Honoré simply except such situations from the normal rule about intentional intervening agents. See H. L. A. Hart and A. M. Honoré, Causation in the Law (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1959). As Joel Feinberg noted, these were ad hoc, unexplained, and seemingly unlimited as exceptions. See Feinberg, "Causing Voluntary Actions," in Feinberg, Doing and Deserving (supra note 37). In the second edition of Causation in the Law (supra note 47), chapters VII and XIII now deal extensively with the provision of opportunities and the giving of reasons as "non-central" kinds of causings.
    • Doing and Deserving
    • Feinberg1
  • 110
    • 0040416100 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (supra note 47), chapters VII and XIII now deal extensively with the provision of opportunities and the giving of reasons as "non-central" kinds of causings
    • In the original edition of their book, Hart and Honoré simply except such situations from the normal rule about intentional intervening agents. See H. L. A. Hart and A. M. Honoré, Causation in the Law (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1959). As Joel Feinberg noted, these were ad hoc, unexplained, and seemingly unlimited as exceptions. See Feinberg, "Causing Voluntary Actions," in Feinberg, Doing and Deserving (supra note 37). In the second edition of Causation in the Law (supra note 47), chapters VII and XIII now deal extensively with the provision of opportunities and the giving of reasons as "non-central" kinds of causings.
    • Second Edition of Causation in the Law
  • 111
    • 0039824953 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Richardson v. Ham, 44 Cal.2d 772, 285 P.2d 269 (1955)
    • Richardson v. Ham, 44 Cal.2d 772, 285 P.2d 269 (1955).
  • 112
    • 0040416098 scopus 로고
    • A theory of complicity
    • R. Gavison, ed., Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • Particularly clear and systematic about this is Sanford Kadish, "A Theory of Complicity," in R. Gavison, ed., Issues in Contemporary Legal Philosophy: The Influence of H. L. A. Hart (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1987); and Kadish, "Causation and Complicity: A Study in the Interpretation of Doctrine," California Law Review 73 (1985): 323-410; reprinted in Kadish, Blame and Punishment (New York: MacMillan, 1987).
    • (1987) Issues in Contemporary Legal Philosophy: The Influence of H. L. A. Hart
    • Kadish, S.1
  • 113
    • 84920186177 scopus 로고
    • Causation and complicity: A study in the interpretation of doctrine
    • Particularly clear and systematic about this is Sanford Kadish, "A Theory of Complicity," in R. Gavison, ed., Issues in Contemporary Legal Philosophy: The Influence of H. L. A. Hart (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1987); and Kadish, "Causation and Complicity: A Study in the Interpretation of Doctrine," California Law Review 73 (1985): 323-410; reprinted in Kadish, Blame and Punishment (New York: MacMillan, 1987).
    • (1985) California Law Review , vol.73 , pp. 323-410
    • Kadish1
  • 114
    • 33749103244 scopus 로고
    • New York: MacMillan
    • Particularly clear and systematic about this is Sanford Kadish, "A Theory of Complicity," in R. Gavison, ed., Issues in Contemporary Legal Philosophy: The Influence of H. L. A. Hart (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1987); and Kadish, "Causation and Complicity: A Study in the Interpretation of Doctrine," California Law Review 73 (1985): 323-410; reprinted in Kadish, Blame and Punishment (New York: MacMillan, 1987).
    • (1987) Blame and Punishment
    • Kadish1
  • 115
    • 0039233082 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See the two essays by Kadish cited in note 93 supra
    • See the two essays by Kadish cited in note 93 supra.
  • 117
    • 0041010199 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • State ex. rel. Att'y Gen'l v. Tally, 102 Ala. 25, 15 So. 722 (1894)
    • State ex. rel. Att'y Gen'l v. Tally, 102 Ala. 25, 15 So. 722 (1894).
  • 118
    • 0041010197 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hines v. Garrett, 131 Va. 125, 108 S.E. 690 (1921)
    • Hines v. Garrett, 131 Va. 125, 108 S.E. 690 (1921).
  • 119
    • 0039823585 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Richardson v. Ham (supra note 92)
    • Richardson v. Ham (supra note 92).
  • 120
    • 0040416099 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See the two essays by Kadish cited in note 93 supra
    • See the two essays by Kadish cited in note 93 supra.
  • 121
    • 0040417523 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 2
    • Michael Moore, Act and Crime (supra note 2), 28-29; Moore, "More on Act and Crime," University of Pennsylvania Law Review 142 (1994): 1788.
    • Act and Crime , pp. 28-29
    • Moore, M.1
  • 122
    • 21844487903 scopus 로고
    • More on act and crime
    • Michael Moore, Act and Crime (supra note 2), 28-29; Moore, "More on Act and Crime," University of Pennsylvania Law Review 142 (1994): 1788.
    • (1994) University of Pennsylvania Law Review , vol.142 , pp. 1788
    • Moore1
  • 124
    • 84937306212 scopus 로고
    • On the moral irrelevance of bodily movements
    • See, e.g., George Fletcher, "On the Moral Irrelevance of Bodily Movements," University of Pennsylvania Law Review 142 (1994): 1443-53.
    • (1994) University of Pennsylvania Law Review , vol.142 , pp. 1443-1453
    • Fletcher, G.1
  • 125
    • 0039231601 scopus 로고
    • The proximate consequences of an act
    • This is Joseph Beale's apparent view, in Beale, "The Proximate Consequences of an Act," Harvard Law Review 33 (1920): 637.
    • (1920) Harvard Law Review , vol.33 , pp. 637
    • Beale1
  • 126
    • 0039152178 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 9
    • See Epstein, "A Theory of Strict Liability" (supra note 9), 192; and Eric Mack, "Bad Samaritanism and the Causation of Harm," Philosophy and Public Affairs 9 (1980): 240-41, 242-43.
    • A Theory of Strict Liability , pp. 192
    • Epstein1
  • 127
    • 0008396630 scopus 로고
    • Bad samaritanism and the causation of harm
    • See Epstein, "A Theory of Strict Liability" (supra note 9), 192; and Eric Mack, "Bad Samaritanism and the Causation of Harm," Philosophy and Public Affairs 9 (1980): 240-41, 242-43.
    • (1980) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.9 , pp. 240-241
    • Mack, E.1
  • 128
    • 0039231592 scopus 로고
    • Columbus, OH: Ohio State University Press, The hypothetical is based on the facts of Larrimore v. American National Insurance Co., 184 Okla. 614, 89 P.2d 340 (1939)
    • This is the famous hypothetical used by Robert Keeton, Legal Cause in the Law of Torts (Columbus, OH: Ohio State University Press, 1963), 3. The hypothetical is based on the facts of Larrimore v. American National Insurance Co., 184 Okla. 614, 89 P.2d 340 (1939).
    • (1963) Legal Cause in the Law of Torts , pp. 3
    • Keeton, R.1
  • 129
    • 0040417523 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (supra note 2), ch. 11
    • For a defense of the view that there is only one act here, although there are many different descriptions of it, see Moore, Act and Crime (supra note 2), ch. 11.
    • Act and Crime
    • Moore1
  • 130
    • 0041010191 scopus 로고
    • Foreseeing harm opaquely
    • John Gardner, Jeremy Horder, and Stephen Shute, eds., Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • For a discussion of Leibniz's principle in a legal context, see Michael Moore, "Foreseeing Harm Opaquely," in John Gardner, Jeremy Horder, and Stephen Shute, eds., Action and Value in Criminal Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1993).
    • (1993) Action and Value in Criminal Law
    • Moore, M.1
  • 131
    • 0039231602 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 18
    • This is what Mark Kelman does, albeit with an imperfect grasp of just what extensionality is. See Kelman, "Necessary Myth" (supra note 18), 604-6.
    • Necessary Myth , pp. 604-606
    • Kelman1
  • 132
    • 0039231599 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 107
    • For a discussion of this reference-shifting strategy, see Moore, "Foreseeing Harm" (supra note 107).
    • Foreseeing Harm
    • Moore1
  • 133
    • 0004264817 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill
    • For an excellent discussion of the difference between facts and events, see Jonathan Bennett, Events and Their Names (Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1988).
    • (1988) Events and Their Names
    • Bennett, J.1
  • 134
    • 0007042374 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Blackwell
    • See Keith Campbell, Abstract Particulars (Cambridge, MA: Blackwell, 1990). It is not uncontroversial whether facts are tropes, or whether they consist instead of a complex of substance-particulars and universals. See "Introduction," in P. H. Mellor and Alex Oliver, eds., Properties (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997), 18-20.
    • (1990) Abstract Particulars
    • Campbell, K.1
  • 135
    • 0039823584 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Introduction
    • P. H. Mellor and Alex Oliver, eds., Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • See Keith Campbell, Abstract Particulars (Cambridge, MA: Blackwell, 1990). It is not uncontroversial whether facts are tropes, or whether they consist instead of a complex of substance-particulars and universals. See "Introduction," in P. H. Mellor and Alex Oliver, eds., Properties (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997), 18-20.
    • (1997) Properties , pp. 18-20
  • 136
    • 0039231598 scopus 로고
    • Tropes
    • These two kinds of commitments to tropes are distinguished in Chris Daly, "Tropes," Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 94 (1994): 253-61; rewritten and reprinted in Mellor and Oliver, eds., Properties (supra note 111).
    • (1994) Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society , vol.94 , pp. 253-261
    • Daly, C.1
  • 137
    • 0006017601 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • rewritten and reprinted in supra note 111
    • These two kinds of commitments to tropes are distinguished in Chris Daly, "Tropes," Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 94 (1994): 253-61; rewritten and reprinted in Mellor and Oliver, eds., Properties (supra note 111).
    • Properties
    • Mellor1    Oliver2
  • 139
    • 0037806580 scopus 로고
    • London: Routledge
    • Jennifer Hornsby, Actions (London: Routledge, 1980), 76 n. 1.
    • (1980) Actions , pp. 76
    • Hornsby, J.1
  • 140
    • 0039231600 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • These are the facts of Foster v. Preston Mill Co., 44 Wash.2d 440, 268 P.2d 645 (1954)
    • These are the facts of Foster v. Preston Mill Co., 44 Wash.2d 440, 268 P.2d 645 (1954).
  • 142
    • 0039824972 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 20
    • All of these cases are detailed in Edgarton, "Legal Cause" (supra note 20), 356-60.
    • Legal Cause , pp. 356-360
    • Edgarton1
  • 144
    • 0041010195 scopus 로고
    • Moral reality
    • Michael Moore, "Moral Reality," Wisconsin Law Review 1982,1061-1156; Moore, "Moral Reality Revisited," Michigan Law Review 90 (1992): 2424-2533.
    • (1982) Wisconsin Law Review , pp. 1061-1156
    • Moore, M.1
  • 145
    • 0041010194 scopus 로고
    • Moral reality revisited
    • Michael Moore, "Moral Reality," Wisconsin Law Review 1982,1061-1156; Moore, "Moral Reality Revisited," Michigan Law Review 90 (1992): 2424-2533.
    • (1992) Michigan Law Review , vol.90 , pp. 2424-2533
    • Moore1
  • 146
    • 0039231603 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See the text accompanying note 117 supra
    • See the text accompanying note 117 supra.
  • 147
    • 0039824972 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 20
    • Skeptics about causation have perceived this, leading them to invoke these cases regularly. See Edgarton, "Legal Cause" (supra note 20), 346-47 ("D's act stands in the same logical relation to the result, whether the other actor is a wrongdoer, an innocent person, or a thunderstorm"); Shavell, "An Analysis of Causation and the Scope of Liability in the Law of Torts" (supra note 10), 495; and Landes and Posner, "Causation in Tort Law: An Economic Approach" (supra note 10), 110.
    • Legal Cause , pp. 346-347
    • Edgarton1
  • 148
    • 0039823570 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 10
    • Skeptics about causation have perceived this, leading them to invoke these cases regularly. See Edgarton, "Legal Cause" (supra note 20), 346-47 ("D's act stands in the same logical relation to the result, whether the other actor is a wrongdoer, an innocent person, or a thunderstorm"); Shavell, "An Analysis of Causation and the Scope of Liability in the Law of Torts" (supra note 10), 495; and Landes and Posner, "Causation in Tort Law: An Economic Approach" (supra note 10), 110.
    • An Analysis of Causation and the Scope of Liability in the Law of Torts , pp. 495
    • Shavell1
  • 149
    • 0039233085 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 10
    • Skeptics about causation have perceived this, leading them to invoke these cases regularly. See Edgarton, "Legal Cause" (supra note 20), 346-47 ("D's act stands in the same logical relation to the result, whether the other actor is a wrongdoer, an innocent person, or a thunderstorm"); Shavell, "An Analysis of Causation and the Scope of Liability in the Law of Torts" (supra note 10), 495; and Landes and Posner, "Causation in Tort Law: An Economic Approach" (supra note 10), 110.
    • Causation in Tort Law: An Economic Approach , pp. 110
    • Landes1    Posner2
  • 150
    • 0040417523 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (supra note 2), ch. 8
    • I explore the lesser (but not nonexistent) causal requirement for attempt liability in Moore, Act and Crime (supra note 2), ch. 8.
    • Act and Crime
    • Moore1
  • 154
    • 0040417523 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 2
    • This latter point is argued more extensively in Moore, Act and Crime (supra note 2), 31-34.
    • Act and Crime , pp. 31-34
    • Moore1
  • 155
    • 0040416097 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See note 91 and the accompanying text
    • See note 91 and the accompanying text.
  • 156
    • 0003532976 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 47
    • Hart and Honoré, Causation in the Law (supra note 47), 186: The main feature that unifies "inducing wrongful acts" and "occasioning harm" is that these two types of "causal connection" (to use the expression in the wide sense commonly found in legal writings) are not negatived by the factors that negative the simpler type of causal connection . . . for both . . . may be traced through an intervening voluntary action and the second form may also be traced through an intervening coincidence.
    • Causation in the Law , pp. 186
    • Hart1    Honoré2
  • 158
    • 0041010189 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 84
    • Watson (supra note 84).
    • Watson
  • 159
    • 0041010193 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is a variation of the facts in Central of Georgia Ry. Co. v. Price, 106 Ga. 176, 32 S.E. 77 (1898)
    • This is a variation of the facts in Central of Georgia Ry. Co. v. Price, 106 Ga. 176, 32 S.E. 77 (1898).
  • 160
    • 0004264817 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 110
    • The argument is pressed by Kadish in the essays cited in note 93 supra; Bennett, Events and Their Names (supra note 110); Donald Davidson, Actions and Events (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1980); and Judith Jarvis Thomson, Acts and Other Events (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1977). Such a view is adopted in Dusenberry v. Commonwealth, 220 Va. 770, 263 S.E.2d 392 (1980) (no rape by a defendant who inserted the penis of another into the victim).
    • Events and Their Names
    • Bennett1
  • 161
    • 0003835482 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • The argument is pressed by Kadish in the essays cited in note 93 supra; Bennett, Events and Their Names (supra note 110); Donald Davidson, Actions and Events (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1980); and Judith Jarvis Thomson, Acts and Other Events (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1977). Such a view is adopted in Dusenberry v. Commonwealth, 220 Va. 770, 263 S.E.2d 392 (1980) (no rape by a defendant who inserted the penis of another into the victim).
    • (1980) Actions and Events
    • Davidson, D.1
  • 162
    • 0004276916 scopus 로고
    • Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, Such a view is adopted in Dusenberry v. Commonwealth, 220 Va. 770, 263 S.E.2d 392 (1980) (no rape by a defendant who inserted the penis of another into the victim)
    • The argument is pressed by Kadish in the essays cited in note 93 supra; Bennett, Events and Their Names (supra note 110); Donald Davidson, Actions and Events (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1980); and Judith Jarvis Thomson, Acts and Other Events (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1977). Such a view is adopted in Dusenberry v. Commonwealth, 220 Va. 770, 263 S.E.2d 392 (1980) (no rape by a defendant who inserted the penis of another into the victim).
    • (1977) Acts and Other Events
    • Thomson, J.J.1
  • 163
    • 0040417523 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (supra note 2), ch. 8
    • I have argued this at some length in Moore, Act and Crime (supra note 2), ch. 8.
    • Act and Crime
    • Moore1
  • 164
    • 0002042993 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (supra note 12), ch. 13
    • See Moore, Placing Blame (supra note 12), ch. 13.
    • Placing Blame
    • Moore1
  • 165
    • 0039231593 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See the essays by Kadish cited in note 93 supra. Kadish persuasively argues that the accomplice who does not cause the legally prohibited state of affairs (because the acts of the principal constitute intervening causes) is like the lucky attemptor who does not cause the harm he attempts; both are quite culpable, yet neither can be held responsible for a harm he did not cause
    • See the essays by Kadish cited in note 93 supra. Kadish persuasively argues that the accomplice who does not cause the legally prohibited state of affairs (because the acts of the principal constitute intervening causes) is like the lucky attemptor who does not cause the harm he attempts; both are quite culpable, yet neither can be held responsible for a harm he did not cause.
  • 166
    • 0039823582 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dillon v. Twin State Gas and Electric Co., 85 N.H. 449, 163 A. 111 (1932)
    • Dillon v. Twin State Gas and Electric Co., 85 N.H. 449, 163 A. 111 (1932).
  • 171
    • 0041010192 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 103
    • Notably Beale, "Proximate Consequences" (supra note 103); and Epstein, "A Theory of Strict Liability" (supra note 9).
    • Proximate Consequences
    • Beale, N.1
  • 172
  • 174
    • 0004224908 scopus 로고
    • London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, chs. 3 and 4
    • I am unconcerned with whether the regularity theory sketched below was really believed by Hume. On this, see, e.g., Barry Stroud, Hume (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1977), chs. 3 and 4; and Galen Strawson, The Secret Connexion (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1989). The Humean theory is an interesting and an influential one even if it turns out that Hume never held it.
    • (1977) Hume
    • Stroud, B.1
  • 175
    • 0039823574 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • I am unconcerned with whether the regularity theory sketched below was really believed by Hume. On this, see, e.g., Barry Stroud, Hume (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1977), chs. 3 and 4; and Galen Strawson, The Secret Connexion (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1989). The Humean theory is an interesting and an influential one even if it turns out that Hume never held it.
    • (1989) The Secret Connexion
    • Strawson, G.1
  • 178
    • 0004037962 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 55
    • Mackie, Cement of the Universe (supra note 55); Wright, "Causation in Tort Law" (supra note 40), 1795.
    • Cement of the Universe
    • Mackie1
  • 179
    • 0039233085 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 40
    • Mackie, Cement of the Universe (supra note 55); Wright, "Causation in Tort Law" (supra note 40), 1795.
    • Causation in Tort Law , pp. 1795
  • 182
    • 0040416083 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 5
    • I discuss the paradigm-case argument in Moore, "The Semantics of Judging" (supra note 5), 281-92.
    • The Semantics of Judging , pp. 281-292
    • Moore1
  • 183
    • 0039823568 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is an interpretation of Hart and Honoré offered in the essays by Kadish cited in note 93 supra. Hart himself questioned this libertarian interpretation of intervening causation when one of Kadish's papers was initially presented in Jerusalem in 1984
    • This is an interpretation of Hart and Honoré offered in the essays by Kadish cited in note 93 supra. Hart himself questioned this libertarian interpretation of intervening causation when one of Kadish's papers was initially presented in Jerusalem in 1984.
  • 184
    • 0003835482 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 132
    • This is a rendering of Donald Davidson's "anomalous monism." See Davidson, Actions and Events (supra note 132).
    • Actions and Events
    • Davidson1
  • 187
    • 84880407097 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 32
    • The defining article on this theory is David Lewis's "Causation" (supra note 32).
    • Causation
    • Lewis, D.1
  • 188
    • 0039823575 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As Lewis makes clear in ibid
    • As Lewis makes clear in ibid.
  • 189
    • 0039233085 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 40
    • See the discussion in Wright, "Causation in Tort Law" (supra note 40), 1777-80.
    • Causation in Tort Law , pp. 1777-1780
    • Wright1
  • 190
    • 84880407097 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 32
    • Lewis, "Causation" (supra note 32), 204.
    • Causation , pp. 204
    • Lewis1
  • 192
    • 0002042993 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 12
    • See Moore, Placing Blame (supra note 12), 351.
    • Placing Blame , pp. 351
    • Moore1
  • 193
    • 0040417523 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 2
    • See Moore, Act and Crime (supra note 2), 268-69.
    • Act and Crime , pp. 268-269
    • Moore1
  • 194
    • 0039231587 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • Thus, it is standard to use the overdetermination cases, the asymmetry of the causal relation, the problems of epiphenomena and other mere correlations, and the selectivity of "the cause," as arguments testing the truth of various theories of causation, and not just the legal adequacy of such theories. See, e.g., Douglas Ehring, Causation and Persistence: A Theory of Causation (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997).
    • (1997) Causation and Persistence: A Theory of Causation
    • Ehring, D.1
  • 195
    • 0039231577 scopus 로고
    • Causation: Reductionism versus realism
    • This is Michael Tooley's suggestion, in his "Causation: Reductionism versus Realism," Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 50 (Supp. 1990): 215-36; and in Tooley, Causation: A Realist Approach (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1987).
    • (1990) Philosophy and Phenomenological Research , vol.50 , Issue.SUPPL. , pp. 215-236
    • Tooley, M.1
  • 196
    • 0004199132 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • This is Michael Tooley's suggestion, in his "Causation: Reductionism versus Realism," Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 50 (Supp. 1990): 215-36; and in Tooley, Causation: A Realist Approach (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1987).
    • (1987) Causation: A Realist Approach
    • Tooley1
  • 197
    • 0011179574 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • As it is in Elizabeth Anscombe, Causality and Determination (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1971); and C. J. Ducasse, "On the Nature and the Observability of the Causal Relation," Journal of Philosophy 23 (1926): 57-68.
    • (1971) Causality and Determination
    • Anscombe, E.1
  • 198
    • 0039823569 scopus 로고
    • On the nature and the observability of the causal relation
    • As it is in Elizabeth Anscombe, Causality and Determination (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1971); and C. J. Ducasse, "On the Nature and the Observability of the Causal Relation," Journal of Philosophy 23 (1926): 57-68.
    • (1926) Journal of Philosophy , vol.23 , pp. 57-68
    • Ducasse, C.J.1
  • 199
    • 0039231581 scopus 로고
    • Causation and the flow of energy
    • See, for example, David Fair, "Causation and the Flow of Energy," Erkenntnis 14 (1979): 219-50.
    • (1979) Erkenntnis , vol.14 , pp. 219-250
    • Fair, D.1
  • 200
    • 0040416034 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • These are the metaphors employed by the cause-as-force theorists in law, Joseph Beale (supra note 103), and Richard Epstein (supra note 9)
    • These are the metaphors employed by the cause-as-force theorists in law, Joseph Beale (supra note 103), and Richard Epstein (supra note 9).


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.