메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 9, Issue 1, 2007, Pages

Lucky in your judge

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 38049112720     PISSN: None     EISSN: 15653404     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.2202/1565-3404.1173     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (24)

References (82)
  • 1
    • 38049149752 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Sanford Kadish, The Criminal Law and the Luck of the Draw, 84 J. CRIM. L. & CRIMINOLOGY 679 (1994);
    • See Sanford Kadish, The Criminal Law and the Luck of the Draw, 84 J. CRIM. L. & CRIMINOLOGY 679 (1994);
  • 2
    • 38049107616 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Benjamin Zipursky, Two Dimensions of Responsibility in Crime, Tort, and Moral Luck, 9 THEORETICAL INQUIRIES L. 97 (2008).
    • Benjamin Zipursky, Two Dimensions of Responsibility in Crime, Tort, and Moral Luck, 9 THEORETICAL INQUIRIES L. 97 (2008).
  • 3
    • 38049112022 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Jeremy Waldron, Moments of Carelessness and Massive Loss, in PHILOSOPHICAL FOUNDATIONS OF TORT LAW 387 (David Owen ed., 1996).
    • See Jeremy Waldron, Moments of Carelessness and Massive Loss, in PHILOSOPHICAL FOUNDATIONS OF TORT LAW 387 (David Owen ed., 1996).
  • 4
    • 38049102455 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A. Bell, Twelve Men and True! Bah Humbug, 147 NEW L.J. 1857 (1997).
    • A. Bell, Twelve Men and True! Bah Humbug, 147 NEW L.J. 1857 (1997).
  • 5
    • 38049159425 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The odd thing is, however, that trial by ordeal was supposed to eliminate the element of luck surrounding any human attempt to infer a conclusion from circumstantial evidence, by substituting for that sort of judgment the infallible - albeit inscrutable -judgment of God. See JOHN H. LANGBEIN, TORTURE AND THE LAW OF PROOF 5-8 (1976).
    • The odd thing is, however, that trial by ordeal was supposed to eliminate the element of luck surrounding any human attempt to infer a conclusion from circumstantial evidence, by substituting for that sort of judgment the infallible - albeit inscrutable -judgment of God. See JOHN H. LANGBEIN, TORTURE AND THE LAW OF PROOF 5-8 (1976).
  • 6
    • 38049159427 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See J.C. Smith & D.J. Birch, Case and Comment - R. v. Ponting, 1985 CRIM. L. REV. 318 on the refusal of an English jury to convict civil servant Clive Ponting for a clear violation of the Official Secrets Act despite being ordered directly by the judge to convict him.
    • See J.C. Smith & D.J. Birch, Case and Comment - R. v. Ponting, 1985 CRIM. L. REV. 318 on the refusal of an English jury to convict civil servant Clive Ponting for a clear violation of the Official Secrets Act despite being ordered directly by the judge to convict him.
  • 7
    • 84855509382 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Jury Nullification: A Selective, Annotated Bibliography, 39
    • See also
    • See also Teresa Conaway, Carol Mutz & Joann Ross, Jury Nullification: A Selective, Annotated Bibliography, 39 VAL. U. L. REV. 393 (2004).
    • (2004) VAL. U. L. REV , vol.393
    • Conaway, T.1    Mutz, C.2    Ross, J.3
  • 8
    • 38049159426 scopus 로고
    • U.S. 668
    • Strickland v. Washington, 466 U.S. 668, 694-95 (1984).
    • (1984) Washington , vol.466 , pp. 694-695
    • Strickland1
  • 9
    • 0043128534 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Myth of the Nullifying Jury, 93
    • See the arguments in
    • See the arguments in Nancy Marder, The Myth of the Nullifying Jury, 93 NW. U. L. REV. 877 (1999)
    • (1999) NW. U. L. REV , vol.877
    • Marder, N.1
  • 10
    • 0030540786 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rethinking Jury Nullification, 82
    • and in Andrew D. Leipold, Rethinking Jury Nullification, 82 VA. L. REV. 253, 312-24 (1996).
    • (1996) VA. L. REV , vol.253 , pp. 312-324
    • in Andrew, D.1    Leipold2
  • 11
    • 38049172220 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • William Glaberson, In Tiny Courts of New York, Abuses of Law and Power, N.Y. TIMES, Sept. 25, 2006, at Al.
    • William Glaberson, In Tiny Courts of New York, Abuses of Law and Power, N.Y. TIMES, Sept. 25, 2006, at Al.
  • 12
    • 38049163518 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 15
    • 38049097209 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Id.: An unfamiliarity with basic legal principles is remarkably common in what are known as the justice courts, legacies of the Colonial era that survive in more than 1,000 New York towns and villages. For generations, justices have hailed them as 'poor man's courts,' where ordinary people can get simple justice with little formality or expense.
    • See Id.: "An unfamiliarity with basic legal principles is remarkably common in what are known as the justice courts, legacies of the Colonial era that survive in more than 1,000 New York towns and villages. For generations, justices have hailed them as 'poor man's courts,' where ordinary people can get simple justice with little formality or expense."
  • 16
    • 38049112021 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I am grateful to Chaim Gans, Complaining About Being Unlucky with Your Judge (Jan. 5, 2007) (comment prepared for the conference on Moral and Legal Luck, the Hebrew University of Jerusalem and Tel Aviv University, on file with Theoretical Inquiries in Law), for insisting on this point.
    • I am grateful to Chaim Gans, Complaining About Being Unlucky with Your Judge (Jan. 5, 2007) (comment prepared for the conference on Moral and Legal Luck, the Hebrew University of Jerusalem and Tel Aviv University, on file with Theoretical Inquiries in Law), for insisting on this point.
  • 17
    • 38049167394 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • FA. HAYEK, THE CONSTITUTION OF LIBERTY 142, 153 (1960).
    • FA. HAYEK, THE CONSTITUTION OF LIBERTY 142, 153 (1960).
  • 18
    • 38049131425 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Gans, supra note 13, has suggested that an unpredictable outcome is a matter of moral concern only if it is unjust. I do not accept this. In a community whose members disagree about justice, the importance of my being able to predict what will happen to me as a result of the operation of the law should not vary from one perspective to another, depending on the observer's views about justice.
    • Gans, supra note 13, has suggested that an unpredictable outcome is a matter of moral concern only if it is unjust. I do not accept this. In a community whose members disagree about justice, the importance of my being able to predict what will happen to me as a result of the operation of the law should not vary from one perspective to another, depending on the observer's views about justice.
  • 19
    • 38049128343 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • However, JOEL FEINBERG, Noncomparative Justice, in RIGHTS, JUSTICE AND THE BOUNDS OF LIBERTY: ESSAYS IN SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY 265, 285-86 (1980) argues that noncomparative injustice tends to be more serious than comparative injustice.
    • However, JOEL FEINBERG, Noncomparative Justice, in RIGHTS, JUSTICE AND THE BOUNDS OF LIBERTY: ESSAYS IN SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY 265, 285-86 (1980) argues that noncomparative injustice tends to be more serious than comparative injustice.
  • 20
    • 38049147587 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Gans, supra note 13, argues that the principle of treating like cases alike can form the basis of a moral complaint about a person's treatment only when that person's treatment is unjust. This seems plausible, but it may gain some of its plausibility from an implicit assumption that it is clear to all concerned what is just and what is unjust. As I suggested earlier, supra note 15, treating like cases alike may have an importance of its own in a community in which people (especially officials) are in disagreement about what justice requires. In such a community, like cases' being treated differently might be a matter of concern to us quite independently of our judgments about the justice or the injustice of the treatment of either or both of the cases. I take it that this is the implication of Ronald Dworkin's argument concerning the (relative) independence of justice and integrity as virtues of a legal system. See RONALD DWORKIN, LAW'S E
    • Gans, supra note 13, argues that the principle of treating like cases alike can form the basis of a moral complaint about a person's treatment only when that person's treatment is unjust. This seems plausible, but it may gain some of its plausibility from an implicit assumption that it is clear to all concerned what is just and what is unjust. As I suggested earlier, supra note 15, treating like cases alike may have an importance of its own in a community in which people (especially officials) are in disagreement about what justice requires. In such a community, like cases' being treated differently might be a matter of concern to us quite independently of our judgments about the justice or the injustice of the treatment of either or both of the cases. I take it that this is the implication of Ronald Dworkin's argument concerning the (relative) independence of justice and integrity as virtues of a legal system. See RONALD DWORKIN, LAW'S EMPIRE 166 (1986).
  • 21
    • 38049131422 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sometimes, however, we worry about failures of equal protection as between citizens of different states in a federal system. A worry of this kind is expressed by Ronald Dworkin, contemplating the prospect that, if abortion decision-making is decentralized in the United States (made no longer a mater of federal law), fetuses might be treated as constitutional persons in some states but not in others. See RONALD DWORKIN, LIFE'S DOMINION: AN ARGUMENT ABOUT ABORTION, EUTHANASIA, AND INDIVIDUAL FREEDOM 113-14 (1993).
    • Sometimes, however, we worry about failures of "equal protection" as between citizens of different states in a federal system. A worry of this kind is expressed by Ronald Dworkin, contemplating the prospect that, if abortion decision-making is decentralized in the United States (made no longer a mater of federal law), fetuses might be treated as constitutional persons in some states but not in others. See RONALD DWORKIN, LIFE'S DOMINION: AN ARGUMENT ABOUT ABORTION, EUTHANASIA, AND INDIVIDUAL FREEDOM 113-14 (1993).
  • 22
    • 38049122650 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Gans, supra note 13, argues that a positivist need not accept that all law ought to be a matter of contingency. Gans claims that a positivist, like anyone else, will wish for good law; he will not relish the prospect of a purely happenstance relation between the demands of law and the demands of morality. This is certainly true. However, even if he values a coincidence of law and morality, the positivist will still acknowledge that whether or not a moral truth is embodied in law depends necessarily on the contingency of the enactment of a law with a given content. And he may well say that this is a good thing: we are better off with legal requirements dependent on a contingency like clear enactment than we are in a situation where the existence of a law has a necessary connection with morality, but people disagree about what morality requires or what the appropriate necessary connection is
    • Gans, supra note 13, argues that a positivist need not accept that all law ought to be a matter of contingency. Gans claims that a positivist, like anyone else, will wish for good law; he will not relish the prospect of a purely happenstance relation between the demands of law and the demands of morality. This is certainly true. However, even if he values a coincidence of law and morality, the positivist will still acknowledge that whether or not a moral truth is embodied in law depends necessarily on the contingency of the enactment of a law with a given content. And he may well say that this is a good thing: we are better off with legal requirements dependent on a contingency like clear enactment than we are in a situation where the existence of a law has a necessary connection with morality, but people disagree about what morality requires or what the appropriate necessary connection is.
  • 23
    • 38049136121 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • JEREMY WALDRON, LAW AND DISAGREEMENT (1999).
    • JEREMY WALDRON, LAW AND DISAGREEMENT (1999).
  • 24
    • 38049137875 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It is possible to make law-by-voting look even more arbitrary than this. Among students of public choice, Kenneth Arrow, A Difficulty in the Concept of Social Welfare, 58 J. POL. ECON. 328 (1950) is commonly taken to have shown that neither majority-decision nor any other method of aggregation can guarantee that a coherent group preference can be constructed rationally out of a variety of coherent individual preferences. Under certain conditions, the aggregation method may yield the result that the group prefers option X to option Y, Y to Z, and Z to X, leaving it completely arbitrary where in this cycle we take the view of the majority to rest.
    • It is possible to make law-by-voting look even more arbitrary than this. Among students of "public choice," Kenneth Arrow, A Difficulty in the Concept of Social Welfare, 58 J. POL. ECON. 328 (1950) is commonly taken to have shown that neither majority-decision nor any other method of aggregation can guarantee that a coherent group preference can be constructed rationally out of a variety of coherent individual preferences. Under certain conditions, the aggregation method may yield the result that the group "prefers" option X to option Y, Y to Z, and Z to X, leaving it completely arbitrary where in this cycle we take "the view of the majority" to rest.
  • 25
    • 38049117043 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • THOMAS HOBBES, ON THE CITIZEN 124 (Richard Tuck & Michael Silverthorne eds., Cambridge Univ. Press 1998) (1642) (ch. X, para. 13).
    • THOMAS HOBBES, ON THE CITIZEN 124 (Richard Tuck & Michael Silverthorne eds., Cambridge Univ. Press 1998) (1642) (ch. X, para. 13).
  • 26
    • 38049106847 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Once again, I disagree with Chaim Gans's suggestion, supra note 13, that these phenomena can only be a matter of moral concern to the extent that at any given time, the law in force at that time is unjust. Constancy is valued morally in a way that is independent of concerns about justice and valued particularly in a society whose members are well-known to be divided about justice.
    • Once again, I disagree with Chaim Gans's suggestion, supra note 13, that these phenomena can only be a matter of moral concern to the extent that at any given time, the law in force at that time is unjust. Constancy is valued morally in a way that is independent of concerns about justice and valued particularly in a society whose members are well-known to be divided about justice.
  • 27
    • 38049140214 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • LON FULLER, THE MORALITY OF LAW 80 (rev. ed. 1964).
    • LON FULLER, THE MORALITY OF LAW 80 (rev. ed. 1964).
  • 28
    • 38049176151 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 10 § 44, at 232 (James Madison) (George W
    • McLellan eds, Liberty Fund
    • THE FEDERALIST NO. 10 § 44, at 232 (James Madison) (George W. Carey & James McLellan eds., Liberty Fund 2001).
    • (2001) Carey & James
    • THE FEDERALIST, N.O.1
  • 29
    • 38049131423 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Ronald Dworkin, What is Equality? Part 2: Equality of Resources, 10 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 283 (1981);
    • See, e.g., Ronald Dworkin, What is Equality? Part 2: Equality of Resources, 10 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 283 (1981);
  • 30
    • 38049180173 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ERIC RAKOWSKI, EQUAL JUSTICE (1991);
    • ERIC RAKOWSKI, EQUAL JUSTICE (1991);
  • 31
    • 38049168921 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Elizabeth Anderson, How Should Egalitarians Cope with Market Risks?, 9 THEORETICAL INQUIRIES L. 239 (2008).
    • Elizabeth Anderson, How Should Egalitarians Cope with Market Risks?, 9 THEORETICAL INQUIRIES L. 239 (2008).
  • 32
    • 38049157730 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See text accompanying supra note 13
    • See text accompanying supra note 13.
  • 33
    • 38049114505 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For the separability thesis, see H.L.A. HART, THE CONCEPT OF LAW 185-86 (rev. ed. 1994).
    • For the separability thesis, see H.L.A. HART, THE CONCEPT OF LAW 185-86 (rev. ed. 1994).
  • 35
    • 38049117042 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • DWORKIN, supra note 17, at 1
    • DWORKIN, supra note 17, at 1.
  • 36
    • 38049104934 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See also supra note 19
    • See also supra note 19.
  • 37
    • 38049172215 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • JOHN LOCKE, TWO TREATISES OF GOVERNMENT 350-51 (Peter Laslett ed., Cambridge Univ. Press 1988) (1689) (II, §§ 124-25).
    • JOHN LOCKE, TWO TREATISES OF GOVERNMENT 350-51 (Peter Laslett ed., Cambridge Univ. Press 1988) (1689) (II, §§ 124-25).
  • 38
    • 38049164818 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Locke suggests that thirdly, there also exists the good, or bad luck of getting someone to help enforce whatever natural law judgment is applied. Id. at 351 (II, § 126).
    • Locke suggests that thirdly, there also exists the good, or bad luck of getting someone to help enforce whatever natural law judgment is applied. Id. at 351 (II, § 126).
  • 39
    • 38049176152 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • JOHN RAWLS, POLITICAL LIBERALISM 54-58 (rev. ed. 1996).
    • JOHN RAWLS, POLITICAL LIBERALISM 54-58 (rev. ed. 1996).
  • 40
    • 38049164816 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For an argument that the burdens of judgment apply as much to reasoning on the matters of justice that natural law addresses as to reasoning on the issue of what makes life worth living, see WALDRON, supra note 20, at 151-52
    • For an argument that the burdens of judgment apply as much to reasoning on the matters of justice that natural law addresses as to reasoning on the issue of what makes life worth living, see WALDRON, supra note 20, at 151-52.
  • 41
    • 38049157729 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See also the discussion of Lockean legislation in JEREMY WALDRON, THE DIGNITY OF LEGISLATION 63-91 (1999).
    • See also the discussion of Lockean legislation in JEREMY WALDRON, THE DIGNITY OF LEGISLATION 63-91 (1999).
  • 42
    • 38049147588 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • RAWLS, supra note 32, at 58
    • RAWLS, supra note 32, at 58.
  • 43
    • 84868079593 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note 31, at, II, §§ 136-37
    • LOCKE, supra note 31, at 358-60 (II, §§ 136-37).
    • supra , pp. 358-360
    • LOCKE1
  • 45
    • 38049163517 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • JOHN CHIPMAN GRAY, THE NATURE AND SOURCES OF LAW 102 (rev. ed. 1948) (citing Benjamin Hoadley, Sermon Preached Before the King (1717)).
    • JOHN CHIPMAN GRAY, THE NATURE AND SOURCES OF LAW 102 (rev. ed. 1948) (citing Benjamin Hoadley, Sermon Preached Before the King (1717)).
  • 46
    • 38049149751 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See JEROME FRANK, LAW AND THE MODERN MIND 47 (1930) (defining law as [a]ctual specific decisions, and guess as to actual specific future decisions ).
    • See JEROME FRANK, LAW AND THE MODERN MIND 47 (1930) (defining law as "[a]ctual specific decisions, and guess as to actual specific future decisions" ).
  • 47
    • 38049149750 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 104
    • Id. at 104.
  • 48
    • 38049104936 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 105-06
    • Id. at 105-06.
  • 49
    • 0039631961 scopus 로고
    • Transcendental Nonsense and the Functional Approach, 35
    • Felix Cohen, Transcendental Nonsense and the Functional Approach, 35 COLUM. L. REV. 809, 843 (1935).
    • (1935) COLUM. L. REV , vol.809 , pp. 843
    • Cohen, F.1
  • 50
    • 0001272681 scopus 로고
    • Form and Substance in Private Law Adjudication, 89
    • Duncan Kennedy, Form and Substance in Private Law Adjudication, 89 HARV. L. REV. 1685, 1776 (1976).
    • (1976) HARV. L. REV , vol.1685 , pp. 1776
    • Kennedy, D.1
  • 51
    • 38049117047 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1775
    • Id. at 1775.
  • 52
    • 84936031667 scopus 로고
    • The Player and the Cards: Nihilism and Legal Theory, 94
    • Joseph Singer, The Player and the Cards: Nihilism and Legal Theory, 94 YALE L.J. 1, 10 (1984).
    • (1984) YALE L.J , vol.1 , pp. 10
    • Singer, J.1
  • 53
    • 38049124741 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 11
    • Id. at 11.
  • 54
    • 38049140213 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 23
    • Id. at 23.
  • 55
    • 38049109431 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., JOHN MORTIMER, Rumpole and the Judge's Elbow, in RUMPOLE'S LAST CASE AND OTHER STORIES 23 (1987).
    • See, e.g., JOHN MORTIMER, Rumpole and the Judge's Elbow, in RUMPOLE'S LAST CASE AND OTHER STORIES 23 (1987).
  • 56
    • 38049172219 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • FRANK, supra note 38, at 11-12
    • FRANK, supra note 38, at 11-12
  • 57
    • 38049114504 scopus 로고
    • What is Never in the Record, But Always in the Case, 8
    • citing
    • (citing Willard McEwen, What is Never in the Record, But Always in the Case, 8 ILL. L. REV. 594, 596 (1914)).
    • (1914) ILL. L. REV , vol.594 , pp. 596
    • McEwen, W.1
  • 58
    • 38049163516 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. BMW of North America Inc. v. Gore, 517 U.S. 559 (1996).
    • Cf. BMW of North America Inc. v. Gore, 517 U.S. 559 (1996).
  • 59
    • 33746366172 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 598 (Scalia, J., dissenting). For comment, see Jenny Miao Jiang, Whimsical Punishment: The Vice of Federal Intervention, Constitutionalization, and Substantive Due Process in Punitive Damages Law, 94 CAL. L. REV. 793 (2006);
    • See id. at 598 (Scalia, J., dissenting). For comment, see Jenny Miao Jiang, Whimsical Punishment: The Vice of Federal Intervention, Constitutionalization, and Substantive Due Process in Punitive Damages Law, 94 CAL. L. REV. 793 (2006);
  • 60
    • 33748950618 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Due Process and Punitive Damages: The Error of Federal Excessiveness Jurisprudence, 79
    • A. Benjamin Spencer, Due Process and Punitive Damages: The Error of Federal Excessiveness Jurisprudence, 79 S. CAL. L. REV. 1085 (2006).
    • (2006) S. CAL. L. REV , vol.1085
    • Benjamin Spencer, A.1
  • 61
    • 38049163515 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I am assuming these are not just crisscrossing platitudes (to use the language of Justice Scalia in BMW of North America Inc., 517 U.S. at 606).
    • I am assuming these are not just "crisscrossing platitudes" (to use the language of Justice Scalia in BMW of North America Inc., 517 U.S. at 606).
  • 62
    • 38049133557 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • DWORKIN, supra note 17 (especially at 238-75).
    • DWORKIN, supra note 17 (especially at 238-75).
  • 63
    • 38049102454 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 238-58
    • Id. at 238-58.
  • 64
    • 38049180175 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 235
    • Id. at 235.
  • 65
    • 38049122655 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • At the end of supra Part II
    • At the end of supra Part II.
  • 66
    • 38049117045 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Conversation with Ronald Dworkin, in New York (Fall 2006).
    • Conversation with Ronald Dworkin, in New York (Fall 2006).
  • 67
    • 38049097208 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I think one's response to this point will be connected to one's response to Chaim Gans's point about predictability and injustice, discussed briefly in supra note 15.
    • I think one's response to this point will be connected to one's response to Chaim Gans's point about predictability and injustice, discussed briefly in supra note 15.
  • 68
    • 0347893130 scopus 로고
    • Protestant Interpretation and Social Practices
    • Gerald Postema, "Protestant Interpretation" and Social Practices, 6 LAW & PHIL. 283 (1987).
    • (1987) LAW & PHIL , vol.6 , pp. 283
    • Postema, G.1
  • 69
    • 38049164819 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • IMMANUEL KANT, CRITIQUE OF JUDGMENT 135-38 (J.H. Bernard trans., Hafner Press 1951) (1790).
    • IMMANUEL KANT, CRITIQUE OF JUDGMENT 135-38 (J.H. Bernard trans., Hafner Press 1951) (1790).
  • 70
    • 38049137877 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Even what I have called the literary model might be inappropriate in some cases. Postema cites Dworkin's own example of a chain-novel. postema, supra note 58, at 311.
    • Even what I have called the literary model might be inappropriate in some cases. Postema cites Dworkin's own example of a chain-novel. postema, supra note 58, at 311.
  • 71
    • 38049154728 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See DWORKIN, supra note 17, at 206-15
    • See DWORKIN, supra note 17, at 206-15.
  • 72
    • 38049152132 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Fairness in the political sense defined m id. at 164-65.
    • "Fairness" in the political sense defined m id. at 164-65.
  • 73
    • 38049143278 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Postema, supra note 58, at 296-97 citations omited
    • Postema, supra note 58, at 296-97 (citations omited).
  • 74
    • 38049137879 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 75
    • 38049182395 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For the burdens of judgment, see supra note 32 and accompanying text.
    • For "the burdens of judgment," see supra note 32 and accompanying text.
  • 76
    • 38049104933 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • DWORKIN, supra note 17, at 239. See also id. at 412: I have not devised an algorithm for the courtroom. No electronic magician could design from my arguments a computer program that would supply a verdict everyone would accept once the facts of the case and the text of all past statutes and judicial decisions were put at the computer's disposal.
    • DWORKIN, supra note 17, at 239. See also id. at 412: "I have not devised an algorithm for the courtroom. No electronic magician could design from my arguments a computer program that would supply a verdict everyone would accept once the facts of the case and the text of all past statutes and judicial decisions were put at the computer's disposal."
  • 77
    • 38049122654 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 264
    • Id. at 264.
  • 78
    • 38049128341 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • To make the case tight (though fantastic, P has two cases at law: one case (as plaintiff) against S, before Heraclea, and one case (as defendant) against R, before Hercules. The problem is that in the case before Heraclea, P as defendant is being required to bear the burden of a standard that differs from the standard whose benefit he enjoys as plaintiff in the case bearing the same exact characteristics before Hercules
    • To make the case tight (though fantastic), P has two cases at law: one case (as plaintiff) against S, before Heraclea, and one case (as defendant) against R, before Hercules. The problem is that in the case before Heraclea, P as defendant is being required to bear the burden of a standard that differs from the standard whose benefit he enjoys as plaintiff in the case bearing the same exact characteristics before Hercules.
  • 79
    • 38049122652 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See JOSEPH RAZ, Authority, Law and Morality, in ETHICS IN THE PUBLIC DOMAIN: ESSAYS IN THE MORALITY OF LAW AND POLITICS 210, 215-20 (1994).
    • See JOSEPH RAZ, Authority, Law and Morality, in ETHICS IN THE PUBLIC DOMAIN: ESSAYS IN THE MORALITY OF LAW AND POLITICS 210, 215-20 (1994).
  • 80
    • 38049172217 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Postema, supra note 58, at 312
    • Postema, supra note 58, at 312.
  • 81
    • 38049140212 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 82
    • 38049104935 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 314
    • Id. at 314.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.