메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 9, Issue 1, 2007, Pages

How should egalitarians cope with market risks?

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 38049168921     PISSN: None     EISSN: 15653404     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.2202/1565-3404.1175     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (65)

References (81)
  • 2
    • 38049143276 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Elizabeth Warren, The Growing Threat to Middle-Class Families, 69 BROOK. L. REV. 401 (2003).
    • Elizabeth Warren, The Growing Threat to Middle-Class Families, 69 BROOK. L. REV. 401 (2003).
  • 3
    • 38049133556 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • JOHN RAWLS, A THEORY OF JUSTICE 74-77 (rev. ed. 1999).
    • JOHN RAWLS, A THEORY OF JUSTICE 74-77 (rev. ed. 1999).
  • 4
    • 38049109429 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Other interests may justify rules for criminal trials that result in deviations from this standard of justice. For example, our interest in constraining arbitrary state power may justify the exclusionary rule for illegally seized evidence, even though this reduces the probability of the guilty being convicted
    • Other interests may justify rules for criminal trials that result in deviations from this standard of justice. For example, our interest in constraining arbitrary state power may justify the exclusionary rule for illegally seized evidence, even though this reduces the probability of the guilty being convicted.
  • 5
    • 38149016341 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Time and space constraints prevent me from replying in any detail to the contribution by Richard Epstein in this Richard A. Epstein, Decentralized Responses to Good Fortune and Bad. Luck, 9 THEORETICAL INQUIRIES L. 309 2008
    • Time and space constraints prevent me from replying in any detail to the contribution by Richard Epstein in this volume. Richard A. Epstein, Decentralized Responses to Good Fortune and Bad. Luck, 9 THEORETICAL INQUIRIES L. 309 (2008).
  • 6
    • 38049149744 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I would, however, like to point to two large-scale disagreements between Epstein and egalitarians today, who, as Daniel Markovits has also noted, seek to reconcile egalitarianism. with widespread reliance on private property and market mechanisms. The first has to do with Epstein's characterization of egalitarian programs as wedded, to government intervention in an already defined system of markets and a supposedly pre-political initial distribution of property rights in persons and things. From an egalitarian point of view, property rights are artificial, all the way down. A primary role of the state in a market egalitarian system is to define a system of artificial property rights that realizes the freedom and equality, which is to say, the personal independence, of each individual in it, to the extent possible. What Epstein disparagingly calls tax and transfer programs, such as social security and universal health insurance, and interference with the market, such as
    • I would, however, like to point to two large-scale disagreements between Epstein and egalitarians today, who, as Daniel Markovits has also noted, seek to reconcile egalitarianism. with widespread reliance on private property and market mechanisms. The first has to do with Epstein's characterization of egalitarian programs as wedded, to government intervention in an already defined system of markets and a supposedly pre-political initial distribution of property rights in persons and things. From an egalitarian point of view, property rights are artificial, all the way down. A primary role of the state in a market egalitarian system is to define a system of artificial property rights that realizes the freedom and equality - which is to say, the personal independence - of each individual in it, to the extent possible. What Epstein disparagingly calls tax and transfer programs, such as social security and universal health insurance, and interference with the market, such as minimum wages, are construed, from the point of view of what Rawls has called, a property-owning democracy, as simply another form of artificial property right, added to others, such as patents, copyrights, and rights to the broadcast spectrum, that are obviously artificial. For more on these points, see Elizabeth Anderson, Ethical Assumptions of Economic Theory: Some Lessons from the History of Credit and Bankruptcy, 7 ETHICAL THEORY & MORAL PRAC. 347 (2004) and my blog posts on political economy, Postings of Elizabeth Anderson to Left2Right, http://www-personal.umich.edu/ %7Eeandersn/blogpoliticaleconomy.html. The second major disagreement between Epstein and egalitarians concerns the role of charity in a system for the satisfaction of individual needs. Epstein regards a system of poor relief that relies on private charity as benign. In practice, however, widespread reliance on private charity leads not to a system of free individuals, but to large-scale patron-client relations closer in spirit to Latin American latifundia, which are structured so as to lock the poor into permanent relations of personal dependence on the rich. Personal dependence of adults on specific others who may withhold their charity at will leads to relations of personal subjection, which are, like feudalism, incompatible with a free society. That is why property rights should be defined so as to avoid any adult's need to rely on the arbitrary good will of others, and why individuals enjoy greater freedom under an impersonal egalitarian system of property rights than under a libertarian or classical liberal system.
  • 7
    • 38049172212 scopus 로고
    • On the Currency of Egalitarian Justice, 99
    • Gerald A. Cohen, On the Currency of Egalitarian Justice, 99 ETHICS 906, 908, 932 (1989).
    • (1989) ETHICS , vol.906 , Issue.908 , pp. 932
    • Cohen, G.A.1
  • 8
    • 38049172214 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See THOMAS M. SCANLON, WHAT WE OWE TO EACH OTHER 248-49 (1998)
    • See THOMAS M. SCANLON, WHAT WE OWE TO EACH OTHER 248-49 (1998)
  • 9
    • 38049164814 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (distinguishing attributive responsibility from substantive responsibility) and SUSAN L. HURLEY, JUSTICE, LUCK, AND KNOWLEDGE 191-95 (2003) (distinguishing attributive responsibility from prudential responsibility).
    • (distinguishing attributive responsibility from substantive responsibility) and SUSAN L. HURLEY, JUSTICE, LUCK, AND KNOWLEDGE 191-95 (2003) (distinguishing attributive responsibility from prudential responsibility).
  • 10
    • 38049140210 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • My distinction between RCLE and DCLE owes much to Hurley. See also Mathias Risse & Michael Blake, Two Models of Equality and Responsibility (Aug. 23, 2006) (unpublished manuscript), available at http://ksghome.harvard.eduTmrisse/Papers/Papers%20%20Philosophy/ Two%20Models%20III.pdf (distinguishing Rawls's treatment of responsibility from that of luck egalitarianism).
    • My distinction between RCLE and DCLE owes much to Hurley. See also Mathias Risse & Michael Blake, Two Models of Equality and Responsibility (Aug. 23, 2006) (unpublished manuscript), available at http://ksghome.harvard.eduTmrisse/Papers/Papers%20%20Philosophy/ Two%20Models%20III.pdf (distinguishing Rawls's treatment of responsibility from that of luck egalitarianism).
  • 11
    • 38049167392 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Leading advocates of RCLE include Ronald Dworkin, What is Equality? Part 2: Equality of Resources, 10 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 283 (1981)
    • Leading advocates of RCLE include Ronald Dworkin, What is Equality? Part 2: Equality of Resources, 10 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 283 (1981)
  • 12
    • 38049140211 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and ERIC RAKOWSKI, EQUAL JUSTICE (1991).
    • and ERIC RAKOWSKI, EQUAL JUSTICE (1991).
  • 13
    • 0001322125 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Leading advocates of DCLE include Richard J. Arneson, Luck Egalitarianism and Prioritarianism, 110 ETHICS 339 (2000)
    • Leading advocates of DCLE include Richard J. Arneson, Luck Egalitarianism and Prioritarianism, 110 ETHICS 339 (2000)
  • 14
    • 38049159422 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and JOHN E. ROEMER, A Pragmatic Theory of Responsibility for the Egalitarian Planner, in EGALITARIAN PERSPECTIVES. 179 (1994).
    • and JOHN E. ROEMER, A Pragmatic Theory of Responsibility for the Egalitarian Planner, in EGALITARIAN PERSPECTIVES. 179 (1994).
  • 15
    • 38049133555 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Although Arneson calls his view responsibility-catering prioritarianism, it counts as desert-catering because it licenses inequalities that track differential prudential responsibility, holding degrees of attribution responsibility constant. While it upholds a prioritarian rather than an egalitarian baseline against which deviations must be justified, this does not disqualify it from the luck egalitarian family. Arneson, supra, at 341
    • Although Arneson calls his view "responsibility-catering prioritarianism," it counts as desert-catering because it licenses inequalities that track differential prudential responsibility, holding degrees of attribution responsibility constant. While it upholds a prioritarian rather than an egalitarian baseline against which deviations must be justified, this does not disqualify it from the luck egalitarian family. Arneson, supra, at 341.
  • 16
    • 38049104931 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dworkin, supra note 7, at 293-94
    • Dworkin, supra note 7, at 293-94.
  • 17
    • 0001073135 scopus 로고
    • The Use of Knowledge in Society, 35
    • Friedrich A. Hayek, The Use of Knowledge in Society, 35 AM. ECON. REV. 519 (1945).
    • (1945) AM. ECON. REV , vol.519
    • Hayek, F.A.1
  • 18
    • 38049124737 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • FRIEDRICH A. HAYEK, THE CONSTITUTION OF LIBERTY 93 (1960).
    • FRIEDRICH A. HAYEK, THE CONSTITUTION OF LIBERTY 93 (1960).
  • 19
    • 38049152131 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ROEMER, supra note 8
    • ROEMER, supra note 8.
  • 20
    • 38049154723 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • HAYEK, supra note 11, at 96
    • HAYEK, supra note 11, at 96.
  • 21
    • 38049163511 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 2 FRIEDRICH A. HAYEK, LAW, LEGISLATION, AND LIBERTY: THE MIRAGE OF SOCIAL JUSTICE 125 (1976).
    • 2 FRIEDRICH A. HAYEK, LAW, LEGISLATION, AND LIBERTY: THE MIRAGE OF SOCIAL JUSTICE 125 (1976).
  • 22
    • 38049140208 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • HAYEK, supra note 11, at 95-97
    • HAYEK, supra note 11, at 95-97.
  • 23
    • 38049149747 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Roemer's group-based standards of desert avoid invading individual privacy at the cost of making stigmatizing judgments about racial, ethnic, gender, and religious groups
    • DCLE must choose between invading privacy and reinforcing group stigma, version of DCLE, which assesses responsibility at the individual, level, would reduce group stigmatization at the cost of privacy
    • DCLE must choose between invading privacy and reinforcing group stigma. Roemer's group-based standards of desert avoid invading individual privacy at the cost of making stigmatizing judgments about racial, ethnic, gender, and religious groups. Arneson's version of DCLE, which assesses responsibility at the individual, level, would reduce group stigmatization at the cost of privacy.
    • Arneson's
  • 24
    • 38049117041 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Arneson, supra note 8
    • Arneson, supra note 8,
  • 25
    • 0043189249 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and Richard J. Arneson, Egalitarian Justice Versus the Right to Privacy?, 17 SOC. PHIL. & POL'Y 91 (2000).
    • and Richard J. Arneson, Egalitarian Justice Versus the Right to Privacy?, 17 SOC. PHIL. & POL'Y 91 (2000).
  • 26
    • 38049180172 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Richard J. Arneson, Luck and Equality, 75 PROC. ARISTOTELIAN SOC'Y (SUPP.) 73 (2001).
    • Richard J. Arneson, Luck and Equality, 75 PROC. ARISTOTELIAN SOC'Y (SUPP.) 73 (2001).
  • 27
    • 1842795953 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Gerald A. Cohen, Facts and Principles, 31 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 211, 244 (2003) advances the same objection.
    • Gerald A. Cohen, Facts and Principles, 31 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 211, 244 (2003) advances the same objection.
  • 28
    • 38049163512 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • STEPHEN DARWALL, THE SECOND- PERSON STANDPOINT (2006) provides the definitive account of the second-person status of judgments of justice and moral lightness.
    • STEPHEN DARWALL, THE SECOND- PERSON STANDPOINT (2006) provides the definitive account of the second-person status of judgments of justice and moral lightness.
  • 29
    • 38049176145 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The act in question may be simply deliberative or procedural - for instance, to weigh A's interests in deciding what to do.
    • The act in question may be simply deliberative or procedural - for instance, to weigh A's interests in deciding what to do.
  • 30
    • 38049136118 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The notion of substantive responsibility in this claim is the stronger sense that could justify complaints against B for failure, not the weaker sense in which B has no complaints against anyone else for failure. Assignments of weak, substantive responsibility for an outcome do not presuppose that the responsible parties have the power to achieve it. Each adult in a free society is weakly responsible for choosing a suitable spouse, in that they have no one to blame but themselves if they choose poorly. Yet they may not have the power to choose well
    • The notion of substantive responsibility in this claim is the stronger sense that could justify complaints against B for failure, not the weaker sense in which B has no complaints against anyone else for failure. Assignments of weak, substantive responsibility for an outcome do not presuppose that the responsible parties have the power to achieve it. Each adult in a free society is weakly responsible for choosing a suitable spouse, in that they have no one to blame but themselves if they choose poorly. Yet they may not have the power to choose well.
  • 31
    • 38049149746 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hayek argues that if no agent is attributively responsible for some distributive outcome, then the outcome is not unjust. HAYEK, supra note 14, at 67-70. Hence, since aggregate market outcomes are not intended or chosen by anyone, the concept of justice is not applicable to market distributions. Hayek errs. The relevant concept of responsibility here is substantive, not attributive. If the state were able to satisfy some valid claim, of distributive justice that the unregulated market fails to meet, then, although no agent is attributively responsible for market distributions, the state may still coherently be held substantively responsible for correcting it.
    • Hayek argues that if no agent is attributively responsible for some distributive outcome, then the outcome is not unjust. HAYEK, supra note 14, at 67-70. Hence, since aggregate market outcomes are not intended or chosen by anyone, the concept of justice is not applicable to market distributions. Hayek errs. The relevant concept of responsibility here is substantive, not attributive. If the state were able to satisfy some valid claim, of distributive justice that the unregulated market fails to meet, then, although no agent is attributively responsible for market distributions, the state may still coherently be held substantively responsible for correcting it.
  • 32
    • 38049119016 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This epistemic objection applies better to Arneson's individualized inner worth conception of desert than to Roemer's group-stereotype conception of desert, which is pragmatic rather than metaphysical. My objection from authority applies to both Arneson's and Roemer's versions of desert-catering
    • This epistemic objection applies better to Arneson's individualized "inner worth" conception of desert than to Roemer's group-stereotype conception of desert, which is pragmatic rather than metaphysical. My objection from authority applies to both Arneson's and Roemer's versions of desert-catering.
  • 33
    • 38049114503 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • HAYEK, supra note 11, at 99, allows that desert-catering principles may be implemented at the enterprise level. His argument, like mine, is directed against desert-catering principles for the basic structure of society.
    • HAYEK, supra note 11, at 99, allows that desert-catering principles may be implemented at the enterprise level. His argument, like mine, is directed against desert-catering principles for the basic structure of society.
  • 34
    • 38049097205 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Individually allocating constraints based on need are indispensable to an egalitarian society. However, the scope of directly need-based allocations is mainly confined to publicly provided or subsidized in-kind goods, such as education, health care, disaster relief, and the public transportation/ communication infrastructure. Other needs can be largely provided through the market. To ensure that everyone's market-provided needs are met, a range-constraining rule providing an income floor should be sufficient.
    • Individually allocating constraints based on need are indispensable to an egalitarian society. However, the scope of directly need-based allocations is mainly confined to publicly provided or subsidized in-kind goods, such as education, health care, disaster relief, and the public transportation/ communication infrastructure. Other needs can be largely provided through the market. To ensure that everyone's market-provided needs are met, a range-constraining rule providing an income floor should be sufficient.
  • 35
    • 0032647108 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • What is the Point of Equality?, 109
    • Elizabeth S. Anderson, What is the Point of Equality?, 109 ETHICS 287, 296-97, 322-23, 287-337 (1999).
    • (1999) ETHICS , vol.287 , Issue.296-297
    • Anderson, E.S.1
  • 36
    • 38049122647 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Seana V. Shiffrin, Egalitarianism, Choice-Sensitivity, and Accommodation, in REASON AND VALUE 270 (Jay Wallace et al. eds., 2004) objects to RCI's refusal to accommodate certain choices on grounds of liberty more than equality.
    • Seana V. Shiffrin, Egalitarianism, Choice-Sensitivity, and Accommodation, in REASON AND VALUE 270 (Jay Wallace et al. eds., 2004) objects to RCI's refusal to accommodate certain choices on grounds of liberty more than equality.
  • 37
    • 38049168205 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • RAKOWSKI, supra note 7, at 73-90
    • RAKOWSKI, supra note 7, at 73-90.
  • 38
    • 38049109426 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dworkin, supra note 7, at 294
    • Dworkin, supra note 7, at 294.
  • 39
    • 38049097206 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 295
    • Id. at 295.
  • 40
    • 38049155134 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Despite its notoriously steep tax rates, Sweden boasts 5 of the richest 525 people in the world. Forbes.com, The World's Richest People (Aug. 23, 2006), http://www.forbes.com/lists/2006/10/Residence_14.html. One can progress very far in an egalitarian distributive program without significantly threatening the freedom to pursue risk-loving, fortune-seeking conceptions of the good.
    • Despite its notoriously steep tax rates, Sweden boasts 5 of the richest 525 people in the world. Forbes.com, The World's Richest People (Aug. 23, 2006), http://www.forbes.com/lists/2006/10/Residence_14.html. One can progress very far in an egalitarian distributive program without significantly threatening the freedom to pursue risk-loving, fortune-seeking conceptions of the good.
  • 41
    • 0040746485 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Egalitarianism, Option Luck, and Responsibility, 111
    • Kasper Lippert-Rasmussen, Egalitarianism, Option Luck, and Responsibility, 111 ETHICS 548 (2001).
    • (2001) ETHICS , vol.548
    • Lippert-Rasmussen, K.1
  • 42
    • 0035602285 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Egalitarian Opportunities
    • Marc Fleurbaey, Egalitarian Opportunities, 20 LAW & PHIL. 499, 517-20 (2001).
    • (2001) LAW & PHIL , vol.20
    • Fleurbaey, M.1
  • 43
    • 84912124405 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Marc Fleurbaey, Equal Opportunity or Equal Social Outcome?, 11 ECON. & PHIL. 25, 40-41 (1995);
    • Marc Fleurbaey, Equal Opportunity or Equal Social Outcome?, 11 ECON. & PHIL. 25, 40-41 (1995);
  • 44
    • 38049109427 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Lippert-Rasmussen, supra note 32, at 557-62
    • Lippert-Rasmussen, supra note 32, at 557-62.
  • 45
    • 0043025551 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Marc Fleurbaey, Equality of Resources Revisited, 113 ETHICS 82, 83 (2002) observes that luck egalitarians including Dworkin, Roemer, Cohen, and Arneson (in his earlier equality of opportunity theory, which he has since recanted) allow choice to legitimize catastrophic outcomes for individuals.
    • Marc Fleurbaey, Equality of Resources Revisited, 113 ETHICS 82, 83 (2002) observes that luck egalitarians including Dworkin, Roemer, Cohen, and Arneson (in his earlier equality of opportunity theory, which he has since recanted) allow choice to legitimize catastrophic outcomes for individuals.
  • 47
    • 38049109428 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See also HAYEK, supra note 11, at 259;
    • See also HAYEK, supra note 11, at 259;
  • 48
    • 38049186286 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • HAYEK, supra note 14, at 55
    • HAYEK, supra note 14, at 55.
  • 49
    • 38149049309 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As Daniel Markovits proposes in this issue. Daniel. Markovits, Luck Egalitarianism and Political Solidarity, 9 THEORETICAL INQUIRIES L. 271 (2008).
    • As Daniel Markovits proposes in this issue. Daniel. Markovits, Luck Egalitarianism and Political Solidarity, 9 THEORETICAL INQUIRIES L. 271 (2008).
  • 50
    • 38049143274 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Lippert-Rasmussen, supra note 32, at 557-62
    • Lippert-Rasmussen, supra note 32, at 557-62.
  • 51
    • 38049176147 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Markovits, supra note 37, at 297-303
    • Markovits, supra note 37, at 297-303.
  • 52
    • 38049102451 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. passim
    • Id. passim.
  • 53
    • 38049167391 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SCANLON, supra note 6, at 258
    • SCANLON, supra note 6, at 258.
  • 54
    • 38049186285 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 258-63 (arguing that such standing may be lost even in the absence of a voluntary assumption of risk, if the injuring party has taken sufficient precautions to prevent and limit injury to others, and has provided reasonable opportunities to avoid the injury, although these opportunities were unknown to the injured party).
    • Id. at 258-63 (arguing that such standing may be lost even in the absence of a voluntary assumption of risk, if the injuring party has taken sufficient precautions to prevent and limit injury to others, and has provided reasonable opportunities to avoid the injury, although these opportunities were unknown to the injured party).
  • 55
    • 38049159420 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As Markovits acknowledges. Markovits, supra note 37, at 302-03.
    • As Markovits acknowledges. Markovits, supra note 37, at 302-03.
  • 56
    • 38049119017 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 286-87
    • Id. at 286-87.
  • 57
    • 38049137871 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is the starting point of the equality of what? debates, including the works cited supra notes 5, 7, and 8
    • This is the starting point of the "equality of what?" debates, including the works cited supra notes 5, 7, and 8.
  • 58
    • 38049172211 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Anderson, supra note 26
    • See Anderson, supra note 26.
  • 59
    • 38049102449 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., LARRY S. TEMKIN, INEQUALITY (1993) (arguing that it is bad for some people to be worse off than others through no fault of their own)
    • See, e.g., LARRY S. TEMKIN, INEQUALITY (1993) (arguing that it is bad for some people to be worse off than others through no fault of their own)
  • 60
    • 38049115218 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and David Enoch, Luck Between Morality, Law, and Justice, 9 THEORETICAL INQUIRIES L. 23 (2008).
    • and David Enoch, Luck Between Morality, Law, and Justice, 9 THEORETICAL INQUIRIES L. 23 (2008).
  • 61
    • 84996218911 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The current discussion pertains to constraints on permissible outcomes, without regard to anyone's chances of attaining better or worse outcomes within the permissible range. I thus omit consideration of constraints pertaining to equality of opportunity, which have to do with each person's chances of attaining positions greater than the minimum acceptable. For my views on this question, see Elizabeth Anderson, Rethinking Equality of Opportunity, 2 THEORY & RES. EDUC. 99 (2004).
    • The current discussion pertains to constraints on permissible outcomes, without regard to anyone's chances of attaining better or worse outcomes within the permissible range. I thus omit consideration of constraints pertaining to equality of opportunity, which have to do with each person's chances of attaining positions greater than the minimum acceptable. For my views on this question, see Elizabeth Anderson, Rethinking Equality of Opportunity, 2 THEORY & RES. EDUC. 99 (2004).
  • 62
    • 38049133553 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See RAWLS, supra note 2, at 132-35 (arguing that if individuals are so motivated, then they will, choose the difference principle, which only permits inequalities to the extent that they maximize the prospects of the least advantaged).
    • See RAWLS, supra note 2, at 132-35 (arguing that if individuals are so motivated, then they will, choose the difference principle, which only permits inequalities to the extent that they maximize the prospects of the least advantaged).
  • 63
    • 38049154724 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See JEAN-JACQUES ROUSSEAU, THE SOCIAL CONTRACT 2.11 (G.D.H. Cole ed. & trans., J.M. Dent & Sons 1913) (1762) ([N]o citizen shall ever be wealthy enough to buy another, and none poor enough to be forced to sell himself.).
    • See JEAN-JACQUES ROUSSEAU, THE SOCIAL CONTRACT 2.11 (G.D.H. Cole ed. & trans., J.M. Dent & Sons 1913) (1762) ("[N]o citizen shall ever be wealthy enough to buy another, and none poor enough to be forced to sell himself.").
  • 64
    • 38049128340 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The ideal of equality is but one element in a comprehensive theory of justice. Other claims may arise that are based on non-egalitarian considerations, such as the obligations of humanity, individualistic contractualist considerations, and so forth
    • The ideal of equality is but one element in a comprehensive theory of justice. Other claims may arise that are based on non-egalitarian considerations, such as the obligations of humanity, individualistic contractualist considerations, and so forth.
  • 65
    • 38049168206 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Anderson, supra note 26;
    • Anderson, supra note 26;
  • 66
    • 38049182391 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MARIA H. MORALES, PERFECT EQUALITY: JOHN STUART MILL ON WELL-C ONSTITUTED COMMUNITIES (1996).
    • MARIA H. MORALES, PERFECT EQUALITY: JOHN STUART MILL ON WELL-C ONSTITUTED COMMUNITIES (1996).
  • 67
    • 38049176143 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • John Rawls, Kantian Constructivism in Moral Theory, 77 J. PHIL. 515, 546 (1980).
    • John Rawls, Kantian Constructivism in Moral Theory, 77 J. PHIL. 515, 546 (1980).
  • 68
    • 38049136119 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A society between equals... can only exist on the understanding that the interests of all are to be regarded equally and consulted. JOHN STUART MLL, UTILITARIANISM 40 (Oskar Piest ed., Bobbs-Merrill 1957) (1861).
    • A " society between equals... can only exist on the understanding that the interests of all are to be regarded equally" and "consulted." JOHN STUART MLL, UTILITARIANISM 40 (Oskar Piest ed., Bobbs-Merrill 1957) (1861).
  • 69
    • 38049167390 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Anderson, supra note 26
    • See Anderson, supra note 26
  • 70
    • 34248031305 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and Samuel Scheffler, Choice, Circumstance and the Value of Equality, 4 POL. PHIL. & ECON. 5 (2005).
    • and Samuel Scheffler, Choice, Circumstance and the Value of Equality, 4 POL. PHIL. & ECON. 5 (2005).
  • 71
    • 38049136117 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ADAM SMITH, THE WEALTH OF NATIONS V.2.148 (Edwin Cannan ed., 5th ed. Methuen & Co. 1904) (1776) (By necessaries I understand not only the commodities which are indispensably necessary for the support of life, but what ever the customs of the country renders it indecent for creditable people, even the lowest order, to be without. A linen shirt, for example, is, strictly speaking, not a necessary of life.... But in the present times, through the greater part of Europe, a creditable day-laborer would be ashamed to appear in public without a linen shirt....).
    • ADAM SMITH, THE WEALTH OF NATIONS V.2.148 (Edwin Cannan ed., 5th ed. Methuen & Co. 1904) (1776) ("By necessaries I understand not only the commodities which are indispensably necessary for the support of life, but what ever the customs of the country renders it indecent for creditable people, even the lowest order, to be without. A linen shirt, for example, is, strictly speaking, not a necessary of life.... But in the present times, through the greater part of Europe, a creditable day-laborer would be ashamed to appear in public without a linen shirt....").
  • 72
    • 38049106844 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I borrow this conjecture from John Roemer, Prospects for Achieving Equality in Market Economies 12 (Sept. 30, 2006) (unpublished manuscript), available at http://www.stanford.edu/dept/EIS/equality_and_markets/ papers/Roemer.pdf.
    • I borrow this conjecture from John Roemer, Prospects for Achieving Equality in Market Economies 12 (Sept. 30, 2006) (unpublished manuscript), available at http://www.stanford.edu/dept/EIS/equality_and_markets/ papers/Roemer.pdf.
  • 73
    • 38049182392 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • RAWLS, supra note 2, at 197-200
    • RAWLS, supra note 2, at 197-200.
  • 74
    • 84934452882 scopus 로고
    • The Welfare State Versus the Relief of Poverty, 100
    • Brian Barry, The Welfare State Versus the Relief of Poverty, 100 ETHICS 503 (1990).
    • (1990) ETHICS , vol.503
    • Barry, B.1
  • 75
    • 38049167389 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Therese Bjorkholm has suggested that egalitarian policies in Sweden are sustained, by the motive of duty rather than solidarity. However, even in Sweden some sense of solidarity or common identity will, need to be cultivated between native Swedes and growing immigrant populations to facilitate the latter's integration into society, which is a prerequisite for their standing in full, relations of equality with respect to citizens of Swedish ancestry.
    • Therese Bjorkholm has suggested that egalitarian policies in Sweden are sustained, by the motive of duty rather than solidarity. However, even in Sweden some sense of solidarity or common identity will, need to be cultivated between native Swedes and growing immigrant populations to facilitate the latter's integration into society, which is a prerequisite for their standing in full, relations of equality with respect to citizens of Swedish ancestry.
  • 76
    • 38049112017 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Theoretically, egalitarians should be neutral between policies that prevent people in the middle from falling too far from their accustomed positions, and policies that ensure that others replace them in those positions. In practice, it is easier to maintain the former policies, since these can also take advantage of individualistic motives for social insurance, such as are represented in the contractualist argument for middle-range constraints
    • Theoretically, egalitarians should be neutral between policies that prevent people in the middle from falling too far from their accustomed positions, and policies that ensure that others replace them in those positions. In practice, it is easier to maintain the former policies, since these can also take advantage of individualistic motives for social insurance, such as are represented in the contractualist argument for middle-range constraints.
  • 77
    • 38049106845 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • RAWLS, supra note 2, at xiv-xv, 242
    • RAWLS, supra note 2, at xiv-xv, 242.
  • 78
    • 38049117039 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at xv
    • Id. at xv.
  • 79
    • 38049133554 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ROBERT NOZICK, ANARCHY, STATE, AND UTOPIA 160-64 (1974).
    • ROBERT NOZICK, ANARCHY, STATE, AND UTOPIA 160-64 (1974).
  • 80
    • 38049176144 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • HAYEK, supra note 14, at xii-xiii
    • HAYEK, supra note 14, at xii-xiii.
  • 81
    • 38049143275 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 100
    • Id. at 100.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.