-
1
-
-
0004240210
-
-
Indianapolis, IN: Hackett
-
W. D. Ross, The Right and the Good (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett, 1988), 21-22.
-
(1988)
The Right and the Good
, pp. 21-22
-
-
Ross, W.D.1
-
2
-
-
0002653987
-
Does Moral Philosophy Rest on a Mistake? in Prichard
-
Oxford: Clarendon Press
-
H. A. Prichard, "Does Moral Philosophy Rest on a Mistake?" in Prichard, Moral Obligation (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1957), 16.
-
(1957)
Moral Obligation
, pp. 16
-
-
Prichard, H.A.1
-
3
-
-
0004048289
-
-
The method of reflective equilibrium, as initially described by John Rawls, calls for one to consider intuitively plausible general theories that come close to systematizing one's moral judgments about particular situations, and then to adjust both one's moral judgments about particular situations and one's moral theories to bring them into harmony with each other. See, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
-
The method of reflective equilibrium, as initially described by John Rawls, calls for one to consider intuitively plausible general theories that come close to systematizing one's moral judgments about particular situations, and then to adjust both one's moral judgments about particular situations and one's moral theories to bring them into harmony with each other. See John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971), 48-49.
-
(1971)
A Theory of Justice
, pp. 48-49
-
-
Rawls, J.1
-
4
-
-
37349008138
-
The Problem of the Criterion and Coherence Methods in Ethics
-
The method is now often understood in a broader sense, to include any process of weighing conflicting beliefs against each other and renouncing the less plausible beliefs in order to restore coherence to one's belief system. For a defense of the method, see
-
The method is now often understood in a broader sense, to include any process of weighing conflicting beliefs against each other and renouncing the less plausible beliefs in order to restore coherence to one's belief system. For a defense of the method, see Michael DePaul, "The Problem of the Criterion and Coherence Methods in Ethics," Canadian Journal of Philosophy 18 (1988): 67-86.
-
(1988)
Canadian Journal of Philosophy
, vol.18
, pp. 67-86
-
-
DePaul, M.1
-
5
-
-
0004264902
-
-
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
G. E. Moore, Principia Ethica (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1903);
-
(1903)
Principia Ethica
-
-
Moore, G.E.1
-
8
-
-
37349040663
-
-
See my Ethical Intuitionism (New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2005).
-
See my Ethical Intuitionism (New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2005).
-
-
-
-
9
-
-
37349096249
-
-
See, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press
-
See Robert Audi, The Good in the Right (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2004), 33-36, 48-49.
-
(2004)
The Good in the Right
, vol.33-36
, pp. 48-49
-
-
Audi, R.1
-
11
-
-
34948831656
-
A Theory of the A Priori
-
ed, Cambridge, MA: Blackwell
-
George Bealer, "A Theory of the A Priori," in James Tomberlin, ed., Philosophical Perspectives 13: Epistemology (Cambridge, MA: Blackwell, 1999), 30-31.
-
(1999)
Philosophical Perspectives 13: Epistemology
, pp. 30-31
-
-
Bealer, G.1
-
12
-
-
37349125894
-
-
The comprehension axiom states that for any well-formed predicate, there exists a set containing all and only the things to which that predicate applies. This leads to a contradiction when the well-formed predicate is not a member of itself is introduced.
-
The comprehension axiom states that for any well-formed predicate, there exists a set containing all and only the things to which that predicate applies. This leads to a contradiction when the well-formed predicate "is not a member of itself" is introduced.
-
-
-
-
13
-
-
37349015159
-
-
Some philosophers argue that one's understanding of the natures of abstract objects - for example, the nature of knowledge, or of value - must lead one to have generally reliable intuitions about the properties of and relationships among these abstract objects. See Bealer, A Theory of the A Priori, and my Ethical Intuitionism, 122-27, for discussion.
-
Some philosophers argue that one's understanding of the natures of abstract objects - for example, the nature of knowledge, or of value - must lead one to have generally reliable intuitions about the properties of and relationships among these abstract objects. See Bealer, "A Theory of the A Priori," and my Ethical Intuitionism, 122-27, for discussion.
-
-
-
-
14
-
-
0003560902
-
-
2d ed, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
Peter Singer, Practical Ethics, 2d ed. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), 232.
-
(1993)
Practical Ethics
, pp. 232
-
-
Singer, P.1
-
15
-
-
0004192384
-
-
New York: Oxford University Press, Unger does not, however, argue for a general rejection of intuition. Rather, he believes that through philosophical reasoning, we can correct the distorting influences on our intuitions
-
Peter Unger, Living High and Letting Die: Our Illusion of Innocence (New York: Oxford University Press, 1996), 101-2. Unger does not, however, argue for a general rejection of intuition. Rather, he believes that through philosophical reasoning, we can correct the distorting influences on our intuitions.
-
(1996)
Living High and Letting Die: Our Illusion of Innocence
, pp. 101-102
-
-
Unger, P.1
-
16
-
-
37349011788
-
-
Although Singer does not describe the moral premises he favors as ethical intuitions, I think that is in fact what they are. See the discussion in my essay Singer's Unstable Metaethics, in Jeffrey Schaler, ed, Singer Under Fire Chicago, IL: Open Court, forthcoming
-
Although Singer does not describe the moral premises he favors as "ethical intuitions," I think that is in fact what they are. See the discussion in my essay "Singer's Unstable Metaethics," in Jeffrey Schaler, ed., Singer Under Fire (Chicago, IL: Open Court, forthcoming).
-
-
-
-
17
-
-
37349017202
-
-
In this example, you see a child in danger of drowning in a shallow pond. Even though it will mean getting your clothes muddy and missing the lecture you were on your way to give, you clearly have a strong obligation to pull the child out of the pond. Singer thinks this is comparable to your obligation to donate money to save Third World children from malnutrition and disease (Singer, Practical Ethics, 229-46).
-
In this example, you see a child in danger of drowning in a shallow pond. Even though it will mean getting your clothes muddy and missing the lecture you were on your way to give, you clearly have a strong obligation to pull the child out of the pond. Singer thinks this is comparable to your obligation to donate money to save Third World children from malnutrition and disease (Singer, Practical Ethics, 229-46).
-
-
-
-
18
-
-
37349026528
-
-
The reasoning is roughly as follows: Imagine that you have already donated most of your income to charity organizations working to relieve world poverty. Now, while walking past a shallow pond on your way to a philosophy lecture, you see a small child drowning. You could pull the child out, but doing so would get your clothes muddy and make you miss your lecture. Even so, it would be seriously wrong not to pull the child out. But, as Singer and Unger would argue, failure to save the drowning child in this circumstance is morally comparable to failure to save another starving child by sending money to UNICEF. Thus, even when you have already given away most of your money, you are still obligated to give more Unger, Living High and Letting Die, 60-61, 135-39
-
The reasoning is roughly as follows: Imagine that you have already donated most of your income to charity organizations working to relieve world poverty. Now, while walking past a shallow pond on your way to a philosophy lecture, you see a small child drowning. You could pull the child out, but doing so would get your clothes muddy and make you miss your lecture. Even so, it would be seriously wrong not to pull the child out. But, as Singer and Unger would argue, failure to save the drowning child in this circumstance is morally comparable to failure to save another starving child by sending money to UNICEF. Thus, even when you have already given away most of your money, you are still obligated to give more (Unger, Living High and Letting Die, 60-61, 135-39).
-
-
-
-
19
-
-
37349097982
-
-
Furthermore, since Singer rejects the moral significance of the distinction between killing and letting die, he holds that allowing people in the Third World to die is comparable to murder (Singer, Practical Ethics, 222-29).
-
Furthermore, since Singer rejects the moral significance of the distinction between killing and letting die, he holds that allowing people in the Third World to die is comparable to murder (Singer, Practical Ethics, 222-29).
-
-
-
-
21
-
-
37349028616
-
-
J. Patrick Gray reports a total of 1,045 societies practicing at least occasional polygamy, compared with 186 exclusively monogamous societies; see Gray, Ethnographic Atlas Codebook, World Cultures 10 (1998): 90.
-
J. Patrick Gray reports a total of 1,045 societies practicing at least occasional polygamy, compared with 186 exclusively monogamous societies; see Gray, "Ethnographic Atlas Codebook," World Cultures 10 (1998): 90.
-
-
-
-
22
-
-
33746134363
-
-
Sharon Street makes these remarks regarding the biases supposedly generated by natural selection; see Street, A Darwinian Dilemma for Realist Theories of Value, Philosophical Studies 127 2006, 124. Her ultimate conclusion favors some form of subjectivism
-
Sharon Street makes these remarks regarding the biases supposedly generated by natural selection; see Street, "A Darwinian Dilemma for Realist Theories of Value," Philosophical Studies 127 (2006): 124. Her ultimate conclusion favors some form of subjectivism.
-
-
-
-
23
-
-
37349036114
-
-
d, see Michael Ruse, Amherst, NY: Prometheus
-
On (d), see Michael Ruse, Taking Darwin Seriously (Amherst, NY: Prometheus, 1998), 145-47.
-
(1998)
Taking Darwin Seriously
, pp. 145-147
-
-
On1
-
24
-
-
0004149207
-
-
e, see Richard Dawkins, Oxford: Oxford University Press, chap. 9
-
On (e), see Richard Dawkins, The Selfish Gene (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999), chap. 9.
-
(1999)
The Selfish Gene
-
-
On1
-
25
-
-
84909358155
-
The Emotional Dog and Its Rational Tail: A Social Intuitionist Approach to Moral Judgment
-
Jonathan Haidt has studied attitudes toward harmless, consensual incest, as well as other victimless alleged wrongs; see
-
Jonathan Haidt has studied attitudes toward harmless, consensual incest, as well as other victimless alleged wrongs; see Haidt, "The Emotional Dog and Its Rational Tail: A Social Intuitionist Approach to Moral Judgment," Psychological Review 108 (2001): 814-34.
-
(2001)
Psychological Review
, vol.108
, pp. 814-834
-
-
Haidt1
-
26
-
-
37349105282
-
-
Ruse, Taking Darwin Seriously, 252-54; Street, A Darwinian Dilemma.
-
Ruse, Taking Darwin Seriously, 252-54; Street, "A Darwinian Dilemma."
-
-
-
-
27
-
-
84921385773
-
-
Oxford: Oxford University Press
-
Walter Sinnott-Armstrong, Moral Skepticisms (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006), 195-204.
-
(2006)
Moral Skepticisms
, pp. 195-204
-
-
Sinnott-Armstrong, W.1
-
28
-
-
37349055018
-
-
Ted Bundy killed dozens of young women across the United States during the 1970s, becoming one of history's most notorious serial murderers.
-
Ted Bundy killed dozens of young women across the United States during the 1970s, becoming one of history's most notorious serial murderers.
-
-
-
-
29
-
-
0003498229
-
-
According to the coherence theory of justification, a belief is justified, if at all, by virtue of the way it fits together with the rest of one's belief system. This fitting together is usually understood as a matter of supporting and being supported by other beliefs, being explainable in terms of one's other beliefs, and so on. See, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
-
According to the coherence theory of justification, a belief is justified, if at all, by virtue of the way it fits together with the rest of one's belief system. This "fitting together" is usually understood as a matter of supporting and being supported by other beliefs, being explainable in terms of one's other beliefs, and so on. See Laurence BonJour, The Structure of Empirical Knowledge (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1985), 93-101.
-
(1985)
The Structure of Empirical Knowledge
, pp. 93-101
-
-
BonJour, L.1
-
30
-
-
37349060995
-
-
The probability of as many as two of the six witnesses picking the same incorrect license plate number by chance (assuming random selection from six-digit alphanumeric sequences) is about one in 145 million. This kind of argument is advanced by BonJour, The Structure of Empirical Knowledge, 147-48
-
The probability of as many as two of the six witnesses picking the same incorrect license plate number by chance (assuming random selection from six-digit alphanumeric sequences) is about one in 145 million. This kind of argument is advanced by BonJour, The Structure of Empirical Knowledge, 147-48,
-
-
-
-
32
-
-
34547518955
-
-
See Erik Olsson, Against Coherence (Oxford: Clarendon, 2005), for an extended discussion of the conditions under which coherence produces confirmation. Note that the argument requires that the witnesses be more reliable than chance, but not that they be more than 50 percent reliable. Note also that I do not hereby embrace a coherence theory of justification, since I do not claim that coherence is either necessary or sufficient for justification; I claim only that coherence can ratchet up the level of justification that intuitions start with.
-
See Erik Olsson, Against Coherence (Oxford: Clarendon, 2005), for an extended discussion of the conditions under which coherence produces confirmation. Note that the argument requires that the witnesses be more reliable than chance, but not that they be more than 50 percent reliable. Note also that I do not hereby embrace a coherence theory of justification, since I do not claim that coherence is either necessary or sufficient for justification; I claim only that coherence can ratchet up the level of justification that intuitions start with.
-
-
-
-
33
-
-
0003942296
-
-
See, 2d ed, Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, for the distinction between rebutting and undercutting defeaters
-
See John Pollock and Joseph Cruz, Contemporary Theories of Knowledge, 2d ed. (Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 1999), 195-96, for the distinction between rebutting and undercutting defeaters.
-
(1999)
Contemporary Theories of Knowledge
, pp. 195-196
-
-
Pollock, J.1
Cruz, J.2
-
36
-
-
0004206765
-
-
See, respectively, Oxford: Blackwell
-
See, respectively, Jonathan Dancy, Moral Reasons (Oxford: Blackwell, 1993);
-
(1993)
Moral Reasons
-
-
Dancy, J.1
-
39
-
-
84902743640
-
The Problem of Abortion and the Doctrine of the Double Effect
-
In this example, one must choose between allowing a runaway trolley to run over and kill five people, and flipping a switch to send the trolley onto another track, where it will run over and kill one person. See
-
In this example, one must choose between allowing a runaway trolley to run over and kill five people, and flipping a switch to send the trolley onto another track, where it will run over and kill one person. See Philippa Foot, "The Problem of Abortion and the Doctrine of the Double Effect," Oxford Review 5 (1967): 5-15.
-
(1967)
Oxford Review
, vol.5
, pp. 5-15
-
-
Foot, P.1
-
40
-
-
37349109973
-
-
DePaul expresses doubt on this score in The Problem of the Criterion and Coherence Methods in Ethics.
-
DePaul expresses doubt on this score in "The Problem of the Criterion and Coherence Methods in Ethics."
-
-
-
-
41
-
-
84910472031
-
Abortion and Infanticide
-
Michael Tooley employs the latter principle in his defense of abortion and infanticide; see
-
Michael Tooley employs the latter principle in his defense of abortion and infanticide; see Tooley, "Abortion and Infanticide," Philosophy and Public Affairs 2 (1972): 37-65.
-
(1972)
Philosophy and Public Affairs
, vol.2
, pp. 37-65
-
-
Tooley1
-
42
-
-
37349120349
-
-
Axiological additivity principles claim that value can be added along some dimension, for example, that the value of a pair of people's lives is equal to the value of the first person's life plus the value of the second person's life; or that the value of some event is equal to the value of the first half of the event plus the value of the second half of the event
-
Axiological additivity principles claim that value can be added along some dimension - for example, that the value of a pair of people's lives is equal to the value of the first person's life plus the value of the second person's life; or that the value of some event is equal to the value of the first half of the event plus the value of the second half of the event.
-
-
-
-
43
-
-
37349102272
-
-
This is a special case of the availability heuristic, discussed in Amos Tversky and Daniel Kahneman, Availability: A Heuristic for Judging Frequency and Probability, in Daniel Kahneman, Paul Slovic, and Amos Tversky, eds, Judgment under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982, 163-78
-
This is a special case of the "availability heuristic," discussed in Amos Tversky and Daniel Kahneman, "Availability: A Heuristic for Judging Frequency and Probability," in Daniel Kahneman, Paul Slovic, and Amos Tversky, eds., Judgment under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982), 163-78.
-
-
-
-
44
-
-
37349078970
-
-
David Lewis discusses this kind of case in Causation, in Lewis, Philosophical Papers, 2 (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1986), 159-214.
-
David Lewis discusses this kind of case in "Causation," in Lewis, Philosophical Papers, vol. 2 (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1986), 159-214.
-
-
-
-
45
-
-
22544472841
-
-
Stuart Rachels, Counterexamples to the Transitivity of Better Than, Australasian Journal of Philosophy 76 (1998): 71-83. Rachels takes his series of cases to provide a counter-example to the transitivity principle. I take it, instead, to illustrate certain biases in our evaluations of the cases.
-
Stuart Rachels, "Counterexamples to the Transitivity of Better Than," Australasian Journal of Philosophy 76 (1998): 71-83. Rachels takes his series of cases to provide a counter-example to the transitivity principle. I take it, instead, to illustrate certain biases in our evaluations of the cases.
-
-
-
-
46
-
-
33749445850
-
-
See my Non-Egalitarianism, Philosophical Studies 114 (2003): 147-71, for an argument against welfare egalitarianism based mainly on formal intuitions.
-
See my "Non-Egalitarianism," Philosophical Studies 114 (2003): 147-71, for an argument against welfare egalitarianism based mainly on formal intuitions.
-
-
-
-
47
-
-
37349072048
-
-
See Derek Parfit, Reasons and Persons (Oxford: Clarendon, 1987), 419-30, for an argument (though Parfit does not endorse the argument) based mainly on formal intuitions for the repugnant conclusion that, for any world of very happy people, some world with a much larger population of people with lives barely worth living would be better.
-
See Derek Parfit, Reasons and Persons (Oxford: Clarendon, 1987), 419-30, for an argument (though Parfit does not endorse the argument) based mainly on formal intuitions for "the repugnant conclusion" that, for any world of very happy people, some world with a much larger population of people with lives barely worth living would be better.
-
-
-
-
48
-
-
0004192384
-
-
See also, for an argument that our intuitions about sacrificing individuals to produce greater benefit violate the principle of independence of irrelevant alternatives
-
See also Unger, Living High and Letting Die, 88-94, for an argument that our intuitions about sacrificing individuals to produce greater benefit violate the principle of independence of irrelevant alternatives.
-
Living High and Letting Die
, pp. 88-94
-
-
Unger1
-
50
-
-
0004269702
-
-
See, New York: Oxford University Press
-
See Gilbert Harman, The Nature of Morality (New York: Oxford University Press, 1977), 94-95.
-
(1977)
The Nature of Morality
, pp. 94-95
-
-
Harman, G.1
-
51
-
-
37349059918
-
-
However, I argue in Ethical Intuitionism (176-79) that even demands for consistency and coherence are problematic for ethical antirealists.
-
However, I argue in Ethical Intuitionism (176-79) that even demands for consistency and coherence are problematic for ethical antirealists.
-
-
-
-
52
-
-
37349013879
-
-
I discuss the issue in greater detail in my A Paradox for Moderate Deontology (unpublished manuscript).
-
I discuss the issue in greater detail in my "A Paradox for Moderate Deontology" (unpublished manuscript).
-
-
-
|