메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 4, Issue 2, 2006, Pages

What does a verdict do? A speech act analysis of giving a verdict

Author keywords

Evidence; Fact finding; Legal proof; Sincerity; Speech act; Truth; Truthfulness; Verdict

Indexed keywords


EID: 33751316794     PISSN: 15544567     EISSN: 15544567     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.2202/1554-4567.1042     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (6)

References (141)
  • 1
    • 0010750182 scopus 로고
    • 'Definition and Theory in Jurisprudence'
    • reprinted in his Essays in Jurisprudence and Philosophy (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983), essay 1
    • H. L. A. Hart, 'Definition and Theory in Jurisprudence' (1954) 70 LQR 37, reprinted in his Essays in Jurisprudence and Philosophy (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983), essay 1;
    • (1954) LQR , vol.70 , pp. 37
    • Hart, H.L.A.1
  • 2
    • 33751341475 scopus 로고
    • 'Analytical Jurisprudence in Mid-Twentieth Century: A Reply to Professor Bodenheimer'
    • see also his 'Analytical Jurisprudence in Mid-Twentieth Century: A Reply to Professor Bodenheimer' (1957) 105 University of Pennsylvania Law Review 953,
    • (1957) University of Pennsylvania Law Review , vol.105 , pp. 953
  • 3
    • 34547360988 scopus 로고
    • 'The Ascription of Responsibility and Rights'
    • and his earlier work, in A.G.N. Flew (ed), (Oxford: Blackwell, 1951) (originally published in 49 Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 171)
    • and his earlier work, 'The Ascription of Responsibility and Rights' in A.G.N. Flew (ed), Essays on Logic and Language (Oxford: Blackwell, 1951) 145-166 (originally published in (1948) 49 Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 171).
    • (1948) Essays on Logic and Language , pp. 145-166
  • 4
    • 33751326711 scopus 로고
    • 'Definition in Jurisprudence'
    • On the surrounding controversy
    • On the surrounding controversy, see P.M.S. Hacker, 'Definition in Jurisprudence' (1969) 77 The Philosophical Quarterly 343;
    • (1969) The Philosophical Quarterly , vol.77 , pp. 343
    • Hacker, P.M.S.1
  • 5
    • 0042422881 scopus 로고
    • 'Hart on Action and Responsibility'
    • George Pitcher, 'Hart on Action and Responsibility' (1960) 69 The Philosophical Review 226;
    • (1960) The Philosophical Review , vol.69 , pp. 226
    • Pitcher, G.1
  • 6
    • 84922804092 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'The Ascription of Actions'
    • unpublished but available at
    • J. R. Lucas, 'The Ascription of Actions', unpublished but available at http://users.ox.ac.uk/~jrlucas/ascript.html;
    • Lucas, J.R.1
  • 9
    • 0003811485 scopus 로고
    • Hart himself famously came to doubt his own arguments: (Oxford: Clarendon Press)
    • Hart himself famously came to doubt his own arguments: Essays in Jurisprudence and Philosophy (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983) 2.
    • (1983) Essays in Jurisprudence and Philosophy , pp. 2
  • 10
    • 33751337684 scopus 로고
    • 'Basic Concepts of the Law of Evidence'
    • These propositions of fact are sometimes called 'material': 527 at
    • These propositions of fact are sometimes called 'material': J.L. Montrose, 'Basic Concepts of the Law of Evidence' (1954) 70 LQR 527 at 536-7.
    • (1954) LQR , vol.70 , pp. 536-537
    • Montrose, J.L.1
  • 12
    • 33645556673 scopus 로고
    • The present distinction is discussed by (Calcutta: Thacker, Spink & Co) where he contrasts 'facts in issue' with 'relevant facts'
    • The present distinction is discussed by James Fitzjames Stephen, The Indian Evidence Act - with an Introduction on the Principles of Judicial Evidence (Calcutta: Thacker, Spink & Co, 1872) 9-10 where he contrasts 'facts in issue' with 'relevant facts'.
    • (1872) The Indian Evidence Act - With an Introduction on the Principles of Judicial Evidence , pp. 9-10
    • Stephen, J.F.1
  • 13
    • 0003305744 scopus 로고
    • 'A Plea for Excuses'
    • With regard to the ability of a study of language use in casting light on norms governing the practice within which the language is used, compare Austin's famous description of his project as one of 'using a sharpened awareness of words to sharpen our perception of.. the phenomena'. He thought 'linguistic phenomenology' was a better way of describing his methodology than 'ordinary language philosophy': in J.O. Urmson and G.J. Warnock (eds), (Oxford: OUP) 3rd ed) ch 8 at
    • With regard to the ability of a study of language use in casting light on norms governing the practice within which the language is used, compare Austin's famous description of his project as one of 'using a sharpened awareness of words to sharpen our perception of.. the phenomena'. He thought 'linguistic phenomenology' was a better way of describing his methodology than 'ordinary language philosophy': J L Austin 'A Plea for Excuses' in J.O. Urmson and G.J. Warnock (eds), J L Austin, Philosophical Papers (Oxford: OUP, 1979, 3rd ed) ch 8 at 182.
    • (1979) J L Austin, Philosophical Papers , pp. 182
    • Austin, J.L.1
  • 14
    • 61149206124 scopus 로고
    • However, 'linguistic phenomenology' may not be an apt label for Austin's work on speech acts. According to (NY: Peter Lang) Austin's speech act writings 'are not attempts to carefully delineate distinctions marked by ordinary language in order to throw light on relevant phenomena. Rather they are attempts to understand how language, itself, functions.'
    • However, 'linguistic phenomenology' may not be an apt label for Austin's work on speech acts. According to Joseph J. DiGiovanna, Linguistic Phenomenology - Philosophical Method in J L Austin (NY: Peter Lang, 1988) 191, Austin's speech act writings 'are not attempts to carefully delineate distinctions marked by ordinary language in order to throw light on relevant phenomena. Rather they are attempts to understand how language, itself, functions.'
    • (1988) Linguistic Phenomenology - Philosophical Method in J L Austin , pp. 191
    • DiGiovanna, J.J.1
  • 15
    • 0001717367 scopus 로고
    • 'Performative Utterances'
    • His principal works in this area are in J.O. Urmson and G.J. Warnock (eds), (Oxford: OUP, 3rd ed.) ch 10
    • His principal works in this area are 'Performative Utterances' in Austin (1979), n 6 above, ch 10,
    • (1979) J L. Austin, Philosophical Paper
  • 16
    • 33751339169 scopus 로고
    • J.O. Urmson, and Marina Sbisà (eds), (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2nd ed)
    • and J.O. Urmson, and Marina Sbisà (eds), How to Do Things with Words (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1975, 2nd ed).
    • (1975) How to Do Things With Words
  • 18
    • 0001547494 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'A Taxonomy of Illocutionary Acts'
    • see also in K. Gunderson (ed), (Minneapolis: Univ of Minnesota Press) reprinted in John R. Searle, Expression and Meaning - Studies in the Theory of Speech Acts (Cambridge: CUP, 1979), ch 1
    • see also John R. Searle, 'A Taxonomy of Illocutionary Acts' in K. Gunderson (ed), Language, Mind, and Knowledge (Minneapolis: Univ of Minnesota Press, 1975), reprinted in John R. Searle, Expression and Meaning - Studies in the Theory of Speech Acts (Cambridge: CUP, 1979), ch 1.
    • (1975) Language, Mind, and Knowledge
    • Searle, J.R.1
  • 19
    • 0003693620 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A concise and accessible introduction to his theory can be found in (New York: Basic Books) ch 6
    • A concise and accessible introduction to his theory can be found in John R. Searle, Mind, Language and Society - Philosophy in The Real World (New York: Basic Books, 1998) ch 6.
    • (1998) Mind, Language and Society - Philosophy in The Real World
    • Searle, J.R.1
  • 20
    • 33751338206 scopus 로고
    • 'Speech Acts and the Law'
    • in Roger Shuy'and Anna Shukal (eds), (Washington D.C.: Georgetown University Press)
    • Michael Hancher, 'Speech Acts and the Law' in Roger Shuy'and Anna Shukal (eds), Language Use and the Uses of Language (Washington D.C.: Georgetown University Press, 1980) 245.
    • (1980) Language Use and the Uses of Language , pp. 245
    • Hancher, M.1
  • 21
    • 0010196149 scopus 로고
    • There is in fact a significant body of legal literature applying speech act theories to law generally, although, to be fair to Hancher, many were written after his piece: see eg (London: Stevens & Sons, 2nd ed), ch 8 (entitled 'Legal Performatives')
    • There is in fact a significant body of legal literature applying speech act theories to law generally, although, to be fair to Hancher, many were written after his piece: see eg Karl Olivecrona, Law as Fact (London: Stevens & Sons, 2nd ed, 1971) ch 8 (entitled 'Legal Performatives')
    • (1971) Law As Fact
    • Olivecrona, K.1
  • 22
    • 0043079537 scopus 로고
    • 'Legal Language and Reality'
    • and his in Ralph A. Newman (ed), (Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill) especially at 174 et seq
    • and his 'Legal Language and Reality' in Ralph A. Newman (ed), Essays in Jurisprudence in Honor of Roscoe Pound (Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1962) 151-191, especially at 174 et seq;
    • (1962) Essays in Jurisprudence in Honor of Roscoe Pound , pp. 151-191
  • 23
    • 33751339977 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Rights, Performatives, and Promises in Karl Olivecrona's Legal Theory'
    • Martin P. Golding, 'Rights, Performatives, and Promises in Karl Olivecrona's Legal Theory' (2005) 18 Ratio Juris 16;
    • (2005) Ratio Juris , vol.18 , pp. 16
    • Golding, M.P.1
  • 25
    • 84928838556 scopus 로고
    • 'Prolegomena to a Speech Act Approach to Hearsay Evidence'
    • and 'Prolegomena to a Speech Act Approach to Hearsay Evidence' (1988) 1 International Journal for the Semiotics of Law 263;
    • (1988) International Journal for the Semiotics of Law , vol.1 , pp. 263
  • 26
    • 84983947859 scopus 로고
    • 'Philosophy of Law and the Theory of Speech Acts'
    • Paul Amselek, 'Philosophy of Law and the Theory of Speech Acts' (1988) 1 Ratio Juris 187;
    • (1988) Ratio Juris , vol.1 , pp. 187
    • Amselek, P.1
  • 27
    • 84925925536 scopus 로고
    • 'Language in the Legal Process'
    • especially 457-461
    • Brenda Danet, 'Language in the Legal Process' (1980) 14 Law & Society Review 445 especially 457-461.
    • (1980) Law & Society Review , vol.14 , pp. 445
    • Danet, B.1
  • 28
    • 33751345005 scopus 로고
    • 'Performative Utterances'
    • The hearsay doctrine has also been subjected to speech-act analysis: eg, in J.O. Urmson and G.J. Warnock (eds) (Oxford: OUP, 3rd ed.) ch 10
    • The hearsay doctrine has also been subjected to speech-act analysis: eg, Austin (1975), n 7 above, 13;
    • (1975) J L Austin, Philosophical Papers , pp. 13
    • Austin, J.L.1
  • 29
    • 33751351017 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Hearsay: A Speech Act Analysis'
    • available at and Language and the Law, forthcoming, ch 3 of which deals with 'Legal Hearsay and Speech Acts' (I thank Professor Shane for the references)
    • Sanford Schane, 'Hearsay: A Speech Act Analysis', available at http://www.lawandlanguage.com/ and Language and the Law, forthcoming, ch 3 of which deals with
    • Schane, S.1
  • 30
    • 33751332906 scopus 로고
    • 'The Scope of the Hearsay Rule'
    • (Austin and Searle are mentioned)
    • and Stephen Guest, 'The Scope of the Hearsay Rule' (1985) 101 MLR 385 (Austin and Searle are mentioned);
    • (1985) MLR , vol.101 , pp. 385
    • Guest, S.1
  • 31
    • 33751345761 scopus 로고
    • 'Post-Modern Hearsay Reform: The Importance of Complexity'
    • Christopher B. Mueller, 'Post-Modern Hearsay Reform: The Importance of Complexity' (1992) 76 Minnesota Law Review 367, Part IV,
    • (1992) Minnesota Law Review , vol.76 , Issue.PART IV , pp. 367
    • Mueller, C.B.1
  • 32
    • 33751318629 scopus 로고
    • 'Incoming Drug Calls and Performative Words: They're Not Just Talking About It, Baron Parke!'
    • and 'Incoming Drug Calls and Performative Words: They're Not Just Talking About It, Baron Parke!' (1995) 16 Mississippi College Law Review 117;
    • (1995) Mississippi College Law Review , vol.16 , pp. 117
  • 33
    • 33751321826 scopus 로고
    • 'Hearsay and Informal Reasoning'
    • (offering a Gricean analysis of the hearsay doctrine)
    • Craig R. Callen, 'Hearsay and Informal Reasoning' (1994) 47 Vanderbilt Law Review 43 (offering a Gricean analysis of the hearsay doctrine).
    • (1994) Vanderbilt Law Review , vol.47 , pp. 43
    • Callen, C.R.1
  • 34
    • 33751343841 scopus 로고
    • (London: Steven & Sons, 2nd ed, 1971) ch 8 (entitled 'Legal Performatives')
    • Olivecrona (1962), n 9 above, 174.
    • (1962) Law As Fact , pp. 174
    • Olivecrona, K.1
  • 35
    • 33751338206 scopus 로고
    • 'Speech Acts and the Law'
    • It is... obvious that for the structure and details of his theory Austin was heavily indebted to concepts and practices of the English common law. In fact, it can be objected that as a general theory of language Austin's theory suffers from just this partiality; that for a general theory it is too much in the thrall of the law.' in Roger Shuy and Anna Shukal (eds), (Washington D.C.: Georgetown University Press)
    • Hancher, n 9 above, 245: 'It is... obvious that for the structure and details of his theory Austin was heavily indebted to concepts and practices of the English common law. In fact, it can be objected that as a general theory of language Austin's theory suffers from just this partiality; that for a general theory it is too much in the thrall of the law.'
    • (1980) Language Use and the Uses of Langusges , pp. 245
    • Hancher, H.1
  • 36
    • 27844577843 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • According to (Oxford: OUP) 'Herbert's legal input to seminars with Austin almost certainly contributed to the latter's development of his famous "speech act" theory'
    • According to Nicola Lacey, A Life of H L A Hart - The Nightmare and the Noble Dream (Oxford: OUP, 2004) 145, 'Herbert's legal input to seminars with Austin almost certainly contributed to the latter's development of his famous "speech act" theory'.
    • (2004) A Life of H L A Hart - The Nightmare and the Noble Dream , pp. 145
    • Lacey, N.1
  • 37
    • 33751341234 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Similarly, in his review of Lacey's book 329, quoted the observation by Tony Honoré (made in Oxford Magazine 232 (2004), 10) that Austin's 'theory of speech-acts owed more to Hart than Hart owed to him'
    • Similarly, John Gardner, in his review of Lacey's book (2005) 121 LQR 329, 332 quoted the observation by Tony Honoré (made in Oxford Magazine 232 (2004), 10) that Austin's 'theory of speech-acts owed more to Hart than Hart owed to him'.
    • (2005) LQR , vol.121 , pp. 332
    • Gardner, J.1
  • 38
    • 33751345005 scopus 로고
    • 'Performative Utterances'
    • Austin has on at least one occasion explicitly acknowledged Hart's influence in J.P.O. Urmson and G.J. Warnock (eds), (Oxford: OUP, 1979, 3rd ed) ch 10
    • Austin has on at least one occasion explicitly acknowledged Hart's influence (Austin (1975), 50 n 7 above, 7),
    • (1975) J L Austin, Philosophical Papers , pp. 7
    • Austin, J.L.1
  • 39
    • 0007554725 scopus 로고
    • 'Definition and Theory in Jurisprudence'
    • a compliment repaid by (1954) reprinted in his Essays in Jurisprudence and Philosophy (Oxford: Clarendon Press)
    • a compliment repaid by Hart (1983), n 1 above, 2.
    • (1983) LQR , vol.70 , pp. 2
    • Hart, H.L.A.1
  • 40
    • 0010750182 scopus 로고
    • 'Definition and Theory in Jurisprudence'
    • a compliment repaid by (1954) reprinted in his Essays in Jurisprudence and Philosophy (Oxford: Clarendon Press)
    • In an article published a few years after his inaugural lecture (Hart (1957), n 1 above, 962),
    • (1957) LQR , vol.70 , pp. 962
    • Hart, H.L.A.1
  • 41
    • 33751347524 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hart drew attention to the relevance and importance of 'speech-act' theory in legal analysis. However, 329, noted that while 'Hart once held out high hopes for the jurisprudential significance of Austin's thinking' and while his 'philosophical debt to Austin is patent' in Hart's early works, it is 'less clear... how much of the same influence works its way into either Causation in the Law or The Concept of Law.'
    • Hart drew attention to the relevance and importance of 'speech-act' theory in legal analysis. However, Gardner, (2005) 121 LQR 329, 330-1, noted that while 'Hart once held out high hopes for the jurisprudential significance of Austin's thinking' and while his 'philosophical debt to Austin is patent' in Hart's early works, it is 'less clear... how much of the same influence works its way into either Causation in the Law or The Concept of Law.'
    • (2005) LQR , vol.121 , pp. 330-331
    • Gardner, J.1
  • 42
    • 33751311474 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • '(In)Felicitous Speech Acts in Kafka's The Trial'
    • available online at
    • J. Hillis Miller, '(In)Felicitous Speech Acts in Kafka's The Trial', (2000) 4 Tympanum - A Journal of Comparative Literary Studies, available online at http://www.usc.edu/dept/complit/tympanum/4/miller.html.
    • (2000) Tympanum - A Journal of Comparative Literary Studies , vol.4
    • Hillis Miller, J.1
  • 45
    • 33751345760 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'How Performatives Work'
    • I should mention a debate into which we need not go. For some, a performative is also a statement; for others, a statement is a performative of some other kind. On the first view, I make a statement when I say'I promise to do x', whereas on the second, to utter that sentence is not to make a statement but to perform the different speech act of giving a promise; in the that very utterance, I make a promise rather than make a statement that I am making a promise. The two views seem equally plausible. See Searle's attempt at reconciliation in in Daniel Vanderveken and Susumu Kubo (eds), (Amsterdam: John Benjamins Publishing Co)
    • I should mention a debate into which we need not go. For some, a performative is also a statement; for others, a statement is a performative of some other kind. On the first view, I make a statement when I say'I promise to do x', whereas on the second, to utter that sentence is not to make a statement but to perform the different speech act of giving a promise; in the that very utterance, I make a promise rather than make a statement that I am making a promise. The two views seem equally plausible. See Searle's attempt at reconciliation in John R. Searle, 'How Performatives Work' in Daniel Vanderveken and Susumu Kubo (eds), Essay in Speech Act Theory (Amsterdam: John Benjamins Publishing Co, 2001).
    • (2001) Essay in Speech Act Theory
    • Searle, J.R.1
  • 47
    • 0001717367 scopus 로고
    • 'Performative Utterances'
    • See 'the bit where we take it all back': in J.O. Ormson and G.J. Warnock (eds) (Oxford: OUP, 1979, 3rd ed) ch 10 241
    • See 'the bit where we take it all back': Austin (1979), n 7 above, 241, and 246-251;
    • (1979) J L Austin, Philosophical Papers , pp. 246-251
    • Austin, J.L.1
  • 48
  • 50
    • 0004058502 scopus 로고
    • In a transcript recorded by (London: Martin Robertson) we see a long exchange between the court and the defendant before the right words were elicited from the latter. A part of the exchange reads: Magistrate: Do you plead guilty or not guilty? Defendant: Yes, I did it. Magistrate: No, I'm asking you whether you plead guilty or not guilty. You must use either the words "not guilty" or "guilty"
    • In a transcript recorded by Pat Carlen, Magistrates'Justice (London: Martin Robertson, 1976) 110-11, we see a long exchange between the court and the defendant before the right words were elicited from the latter. A part of the exchange reads: Magistrate: Do you plead guilty or not guilty? Defendant: Yes, I did it. Magistrate: No, I'm asking you whether you plead guilty or not guilty. You must use either the words "not guilty" or "guilty."
    • (1976) Magistrates'Justice , pp. 110-111
    • Carlen, P.1
  • 51
    • 0001856113 scopus 로고
    • 'Intention and Convention in Speech Acts'
    • Acknowledging as much: 439, '[T]he fact that the word "guilty" is pronounced by the foreman of the jury in court at the proper moment constitutes his utterance as the act of bringing in a verdict; and that this is so is certainly a matter of the conventional procedures of the law'
    • Acknowledging as much: P.F. Strawson, 'Intention and Convention in Speech Acts' (1964) 73 The Philosophical Review 439, 443: '[T]he fact that the word "guilty" is pronounced by the foreman of the jury in court at the proper moment constitutes his utterance as the act of bringing in a verdict; and that this is so is certainly a matter of the conventional procedures of the law.'
    • (1964) The Philosophical Review , vol.73 , pp. 443
    • Strawson, P.F.1
  • 55
    • 0003430658 scopus 로고
    • This question is addressed by Oxford: Clarendon Press)
    • This question is addressed by L. Jonathan Cohen, An Essay on Belief and Acceptance Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992) 117-125.
    • (1992) An Essay on Belief and Acceptance , pp. 117-125
    • Cohen, L.J.1
  • 56
    • 33751331108 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A good collection of essays on the relation between the two concepts can be found in Pascal Engel (ed), (Dordrecht: Kluwer)
    • A good collection of essays on the relation between the two concepts can be found in Pascal Engel (ed), Believing and Accepting (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 2001).
    • (2001) Believing and Accepting
  • 57
    • 82855178458 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Speech Acts and Pragmatics'
    • Speech act belongs to the theory of language use (pragmatics), which is different from, although related to, the theory of linguistic meaning (semantics). For the distinction and relation between them, see in Michael Devitt and Richard Hanley (eds), (Malden, Mass: Blackwell)
    • Speech act belongs to the theory of language use (pragmatics), which is different from, although related to, the theory of linguistic meaning (semantics). For the distinction and relation between them, see Kent Bach, 'Speech Acts and Pragmatics' in Michael Devitt and Richard Hanley (eds), Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Language (Malden, Mass: Blackwell, 2006).
    • (2006) Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Language
    • Bach, K.1
  • 59
    • 0040475564 scopus 로고
    • 'Austin on Locutionary and Illocutionary Acts'
    • Searle disputes Austin's locutionary-illocutionary or meaning-force distinction. As Searle sees it, the real distinction lies between the propositional content of an utterance and its force: in
    • Searle disputes Austin's locutionary-illocutionary or meaning-force distinction. As Searle sees it, the real distinction lies between the propositional content of an utterance and its force: John R. Searle, 'Austin on Locutionary and Illocutionary Acts' in (1968) 77 The Philosophical Review 405.
    • (1968) The Philosophical Review , vol.77 , pp. 405
    • Searle, J.R.1
  • 60
    • 0040475564 scopus 로고
    • 'Austin on Locutionary and Illocutionary Acts'
    • eg above, (discussion of the distinction between 'statement-act' and 'statement-object')
    • eg Searle, n 29 above, 422 (discussion of the distinction between 'statement-act' and 'statement-object')
    • (1968) The Philosophical Review , vol.77 , pp. 422
    • Searle, J.R.1
  • 70
    • 33751341233 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • My point, elaborated later, is that a conviction itself expresses criticism of the person's conduct. It is not unusual for the judge to explicitly chastise a person after his conviction in order to bring home the condemnation which is already implicit in the act of convicting him.
  • 72
    • 85187365952 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Introduction: Towards A Normative Theory of the Criminal Trial'
    • in Antony Duff et al (eds), (Oxford: Hart)
    • Antony Duff, Lindsay Farmer, Sandra Marshall and Victor Tadras, 'Introduction: Towards A Normative Theory of the Criminal Trial' in Antony Duff et al (eds), The Trial on Trial - Truth and Due Process (Oxford: Hart, 2004).
    • (2004) The Trial on Trial - Truth and Due Process
    • Duff, A.1    Farmer, L.2    Marshall, S.3    Tadras, V.4
  • 73
    • 0039393210 scopus 로고
    • See generally (Englewood Cliffs, New Jersey: Prentice Hall) ch 6
    • See generally Martin P. Golding, Philosophy of Law (Englewood Cliffs, New Jersey: Prentice Hall, 1975) ch 6;
    • (1975) Philosophy of Law
    • Golding, M.P.1
  • 77
    • 84900110947 scopus 로고
    • 'Speech Acts, Legal Institutions, and Real Laws'
    • in Neil MacCormick and Peter Birks (eds), (Oxford: Clarendon Press)
    • Neil MacCormick and Zenon Bankowski, 'Speech Acts, Legal Institutions, and Real Laws' in Neil MacCormick and Peter Birks (eds), The Legal Mind - Essays for Tony Honore (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986) 128-129;
    • (1986) The Legal Mind - Essays for Tony Honore , pp. 128-129
    • MacCormick, N.1    Bankowski, Z.2
  • 78
    • 84928447007 scopus 로고
    • 'Liability and Individualized Evidence'
    • 199
    • Judith Jarvis Thomson, 'Liability and Individualized Evidence' (1986) 49 Law and Contemporary Problems 199, 213.
    • (1986) Law and Contemporary Problems , vol.49 , pp. 213
    • Thomson, J.J.1
  • 79
    • 33751324998 scopus 로고
    • (London: Stevens & Sons, 2nd ed) ch 8 (entitled 'Legal Performatives')
    • Olivecrona (1971), n 9 above, 209.
    • (1971) Law As Fact , pp. 209
    • Olivecrona, K.1
  • 80
    • 0004287704 scopus 로고
    • See also (Berkeley: niversity of California press) [T]he legal does not say: 'If a certain individual has committed murder, then a punishment ought to be imposed upon him.' The legal rule says: 'If the authorized court in a proper determined by the legal order has ascertained, with the force of law,that a certain individual has committed a murder, then the court ought to impose a punishment upon that individual.' In juristic thinking the ascertainment of the fact by the competent authority replaces the fact itself that in nonjuristic thinking is the condition for the coercive act
    • See also Hans Kelsen, Pure Theory of Law (Berkeley: niversity of California press, 1967) 240: [T]he legal does not say: 'If a certain individual has committed murder, then a punishment ought to be imposed upon him.' The legal rule says: 'If the authorized court in a proper determined by the legal order has ascertained, with the force of law,that a certain individual has committed a murder, then the court ought to impose a punishment upon that individual.' In juristic thinking the ascertainment of the fact by the competent authority replaces the fact itself that in nonjuristic thinking is the condition for the coercive act.
    • (1967) Pure Theory of Law , pp. 240
    • Kelsen, H.1
  • 81
    • 33751333857 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Note, however, that in finding guilt of liability, the court is not thereby committed to imposing punishment or awarding damages. A verdict is, for this reason, not a speech act of the nature of a 'commissive.'
  • 82
    • 33751321825 scopus 로고
    • 'The Jury and Reality'
    • cf in Patrick Nerhot (ed), (Dordrecht: Kluwer) (the trial serves the purpose of 'certifying' truth)
    • cf Zenon Bankowski, 'The Jury and Reality' in Patrick Nerhot (ed), Law, Interpretation and Reality (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1990) 236 (the trial serves the purpose of 'certifying' truth).,
    • (1990) Law, Interpretation and Reality , pp. 236
    • Bankowski, Z.1
  • 84
    • 33751345760 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'How Performatives Work'
    • in Daniel Vanderveken and Susumu Kubo (eds), (Amstersdam: John Benjamins Publishing Co)
    • Searle (2001), n 16, above, 99-100.
    • (2001) Essays in Speech Act Theory , pp. 99-100
    • Searle, J.R.1
  • 85
    • 0001547494 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'A Taxonomy of Illocutionary Acts'
    • The concept of institutional fact is clearly illustrated by above, in K. Gunderson (ed), (Minneapolis: Univ of Minnesota Press), 'it is only given the institution of money that I now have a five dollar bill in my hand
    • The concept of institutional fact is clearly illustrated by Searle (1969), n 8 above, 51: 'it is only given the institution of money that I now have a five dollar bill in my hand.
    • (1969) Language, Mind, and Knowledge , pp. 51
    • Searle, J.R.1
  • 86
    • 33751347756 scopus 로고
    • 'The Instituting of Brute Facts'
    • Take away the institution and all I have is a piece of paper with various gray and green markings.' There is much valuable discussion of institutional facts in the context of a trial (eg)
    • Take away the institution and all I have is a piece of paper with various gray and green markings.' There is much valuable discussion of institutional facts in the context of a trial (eg Bert van Roermund, 'The Instituting of Brute Facts' (1991) 4 International Journal for the Semiotics of Law 279)
    • (1991) International Journal for the Semiotics of Law , vol.4 , pp. 279
    • van Roermund, B.1
  • 88
    • 33751326710 scopus 로고
    • See the useful discussion in (London: Stevens & Sons, 2nd ed) ch 8 (entitled 'Legal Performatives')
    • See the useful discussion in Olivecrona, n 9 above, 200-202.
    • (1971) Law As Fact , pp. 200-202
    • Olivecrona, K.1
  • 90
    • 0003305744 scopus 로고
    • 'A Plea for Excuses'
    • The ambiguity of the illocutionary force of a verdict was also noted by in J.O. Urmson and G.J. Warnock (eds), (Oxford: OUP, 3rd ed) ch 8 and 141-142
    • The ambiguity of the illocutionary force of a verdict was also noted by Austin (1979), n 7 above, 249-250 and 141-142.
    • (1979) J L Austin, Philosophical Papers , pp. 249-250
    • Austin, J.L.1
  • 93
    • 0001547494 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'A Taxonomy of Illocutionary Acts'
    • cf in K. Gunderson (ed), (Minneapolis: Univ of Minnesota Press), 'One cannot, for example, greet or christen insincerely, but one can state or promise insincerely'
    • cf Searle (1969), n 8 above, 65: 'One cannot, for example, greet or christen insincerely, but one can state or promise insincerely.'
    • (1969) Language, Mind, and Knowledge , pp. 65
    • Searle, J.R.1
  • 94
    • 0003305744 scopus 로고
    • 'A Plea for Excuses'
    • Austin long ago recognised this multi-dimensionality: in J.O. Urmson and G.J. Warnock (eds), (Oxford: OUP, 1979, 3rd ed) ch 8 There is a class of performatives which I call verdictives: for example, when we say 'I find the accused guilty' or merely' guilty'.... When we say 'guilty', this is happy in a way if we sincerely think on the evidence that he did it. But, of course, the whole point of the procedure in a way is to be correct... [W]e may have a 'bad' verdict: it may either be unjustified (jury) or even incorrect (umpire). So here we have a very unhappy situation. But still it is not infelicitous in any of our senses: it is not void (if the umpire says 'out', the batsman is out; the umpire's decision is final) and not insincere
    • Austin long ago recognised this multi-dimensionality: Austin (1975), n 7 above, 42-3: There is a class of performatives which I call verdictives: for example, when we say 'I find the accused guilty' or merely 'guilty' .... When we say 'guilty', this is happy in a way if we sincerely think on the evidence that he did it. But, of course, the whole point of the procedure in a way is to be correct... [W]e may have a 'bad' verdict: it may either be unjustified (jury) or even incorrect (umpire). So here we have a very unhappy situation. But still it is not infelicitous in any of our senses: it is not void (if the umpire says 'out', the batsman is out; the umpire's decision is final) and not insincere.
    • (1975) J L Austin, Philosophical Papers , pp. 42-43
    • Austin, J.L.1
  • 95
    • 0003305744 scopus 로고
    • 'A Plea for Excuses'
    • See also in J.O. Urmson and G.J. Warnock (eds), (Oxford: OUP, 1979, 3rd ed) ch 8 There is a class of performatives which I call verdictives: for example, when we say 'I find the accused guilty' or merely' guilty'.... When we say 'guilty', this is happy in a way if we sincerely think on the evidence that he did it. But, of course, the whole point of the procedure in a way is to be correct... [W]e may have a 'bad' verdict: it may either be unjustified (jury) or even incorrect (umpire). So here we have a very unhappy situation. But still it is not infelicitous in any of our senses: it is not void (if the umpire says 'out', the batsman is out; the umpire's decision is final) and not insincere
    • See also ibid at 249-250.
    • (1975) J L Austin, Philosophical Papers , pp. 249-250
    • Austin, J.L.1
  • 97
    • 0038259964 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Of course, the trial is neither wholly nor straightforwardly a process of discovery. Trial deliberation is undoubtedly highly complex. For a sophisticated and illuminating account of 'the intellectual operations the jury must perform on the trial's linguistic practices' (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press)
    • Of course, the trial is neither wholly nor straightforwardly a process of discovery. Trial deliberation is undoubtedly highly complex. For a sophisticated and illuminating account of 'the intellectual operations the jury must perform on the trial's linguistic practices' (Robert P. Burns, A Theory of the Trial (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1999) 185),
    • (1999) A Theory of the Trial , pp. 185
    • Burns, R.P.1
  • 98
    • 0038259964 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press) ch. VII. My essay is written from what Burns calls the 'Received View of the Trial'
    • see ibid, ch. VII. My essay is written from what Burns calls the 'Received View of the Trial'.
    • (1999) A Theory of the Trial , pp. 185
    • Burns, R.P.1
  • 99
    • 0003547949 scopus 로고
    • (Berkeley, Los Angeles: University of California Press)
    • Hanna Fenichel Pitkin, Wittgenstein and Justice (Berkeley, Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1972) 262-3.
    • (1972) Wittgenstein and Justice , pp. 262-263
    • Pitkin, H.F.1
  • 100
    • 33751329894 scopus 로고
    • The 'Popi M'
    • The 'Popi M' [1983] 2 Lloyd's Rep 235.
    • (1983) Lloyd's Rep 235 , vol.2
  • 101
    • 0003522414 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Oxford: Clarendon) 'A failure to find a person "guilty" is not the same as a finding of "innocence." When a presumption of innocence has not been overcome by sufficient evidence of guilt, all we know is that there is inadequate evidence to conclude that he is guilty'
    • Randy E. Barnett, The Structure of Liberty - Justice and the Rule of Law (Oxford: Clarendon, 1998) 206: 'A failure to find a person "guilty" is not the same as a finding of "innocence." When a presumption of innocence has not been overcome by sufficient evidence of guilt, all we know is that there is inadequate evidence to conclude that he is guilty'.
    • (1998) The Structure of Liberty - Justice and the Rule of Law , pp. 206
    • Barnett, R.E.1
  • 102
    • 85187365952 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Introduction: Towards A Normative Theory of the Criminal Trial'
    • Similarly, in Anthony Duff et al (eds), (Oxford: Hart), 'surely "not guilty" cannot amount to an assertion of the defendant's innocence, but must rather be read as asserting that he has not been proved to be guilty'
    • Similarly, Duff, Farmer, Marshall and Tadros, n 41 above, 19: 'surely "not guilty" cannot amount to an assertion of the defendant's innocence, but must rather be read as asserting that he has not been proved to be guilty.'
    • (2004) The Trial on Trial - Truth and Due Process , pp. 19
    • Duff, A.1    Farmer, L.2    Marshall, S.3    Tadros, V.4
  • 103
    • 33751320042 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • R (Mullen) v Home Secretary
    • As put it in [43]; [2003] QB 993, 1007, the 'criminal law system.... does not provide for proof of innocence'. This is not true in some jurisdictions. In California, the defendant may, following acquittal, petition for a finding that he is 'factually innocent': see section 851.8 of the California Penal Code
    • As Schiemann LJ put it in R (Mullen) v Home Secretary [2002] EWCA Civ 1882 at [43]; [2003] QB 993, 1007, the 'criminal law system.... does not provide for proof of innocence'. This is not true in some jurisdictions. In California, the defendant may, following acquittal, petition for a finding that he is 'factually innocent': see section 851.8 of the California Penal Code.
    • (2002) EWCA Civ , pp. 1882
    • Schiemann, L.J.1
  • 104
    • 33751337683 scopus 로고
    • McNicol v H M Advocate
    • In 151, the High Court of Justiciary explained that the 'not proven' verdict 'gives a jury, who have some lingering doubts as to the guilt of an accused and who are certainly on the evidence not prepared to say that he is innocent, the chance to find the charge against him not proven'
    • In McNicol v H M Advocate (1964) SLT 151, 152, the High Court of Justiciary explained that the 'not proven' verdict 'gives a jury, who have some lingering doubts as to the guilt of an accused and who are certainly on the evidence not prepared to say that he is innocent, the chance to find the charge against him not proven.'
    • (1964) SLT , pp. 152
  • 105
    • 0037630446 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Is the Criminal Process about Truth?: A German Perspective'
    • 157 at ('In systems relying on professional judges to find the facts... the court must invariably explain in writing how it arrived at its verdict, and the court must relate the outcome of the case to the evidence presented')
    • Thomas Weigend, 'Is the Criminal Process about Truth?: A German Perspective' (2003) 26 Harvard Journal of Law & Public Policy 157 at 166-7 ('In systems relying on professional judges to find the facts... the court must invariably explain in writing how it arrived at its verdict, and the court must relate the outcome of the case to the evidence presented').
    • (2003) Harvard Journal of Law & Public Policy , vol.26 , pp. 166-167
    • Weigend, T.1
  • 106
    • 33751306893 scopus 로고
    • R v Fergus
    • eg, in 313, the Court of Appeal, in quashing a conviction, made it a point to announce that 'the conviction was not only unsafe and unsatisfactory. but that [the defendant] was wholly innocent'
    • eg, in R v Fergus (1994) 98 Cr App R 313, 325, the Court of Appeal, in quashing a conviction, made it a point to announce that 'the conviction was not only unsafe and unsatisfactory. but that [the defendant] was wholly innocent.'
    • (1994) Cr App R , vol.98 , pp. 325
  • 107
    • 33751331360 scopus 로고
    • 221, para 30
    • (1993) 17 EHRR 221, 235, para 30.
    • (1993) EHRR , vol.17 , pp. 235
  • 108
    • 33751324731 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It is very doubtful that the presumption of innocence is, in fact, as expansive as the rhetoric supporting it suggests. (Cambridge: CUP) has forcefully argued that the presumption has an extremely narrow application within the legal process
    • It is very doubtful that the presumption of innocence is, in fact, as expansive as the rhetoric supporting it suggests. Larry Laudan, Truth, Error, and Criminal Law (Cambridge: CUP, 2006) 93-6, has forcefully argued that the presumption has an extremely narrow application within the legal process.
    • (2006) Truth, Error, and Criminal Law , pp. 93-96
    • Laudan, L.1
  • 109
    • 33751339424 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [2005] 1 AC 1
    • [2004] UKHL 18, [2005] 1 AC 1.
    • (2004) UKHL , pp. 18
  • 110
    • 33751316184 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Guilt and Innocence in the Criminal Justice System: A Comment on R (Mullen) v Secretary of State for the Home Department'
    • For criticisms of this case, see
    • For criticisms of this case, see Richard Nobles and David Schiff, 'Guilt and Innocence in the Criminal Justice System: A Comment on R (Mullen) v Secretary of State for the Home Department' (2006) 69 MLR 80.
    • (2006) MLR , vol.69 , pp. 80
    • Nobles, R.1    Schiff, D.2
  • 111
    • 0033269213 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Law, Fact and Legal Language'
    • On which see eg 461, 'in judicial proceedings we are in some circumstances compelled to accept false statements if they follow e.g. from irrebuttable presumptions'
    • On which see eg Lech Morawski, 'Law, Fact and Legal Language' (1999) 18 Law and Philosophy 461, 465-6: 'in judicial proceedings we are in some circumstances compelled to accept false statements if they follow e.g. from irrebuttable presumptions.'
    • (1999) Law and Philosophy , vol.18 , pp. 465-466
    • Morawski, L.1
  • 113
  • 114
    • 33751315940 scopus 로고
    • 'Principles for Legal Procedure'
    • Three major complications are identified by 33, [J]udicial decision making is not a simple application of rules and principles to facts. First, finding facts is not a straight-forward descriptive process. Facts must be classified for the application of rules and do not come neatly labeled. Second, many so-called factual questions are matters of evaluation. Determining whether someone was negligent, reasonable, or insane requires judgment and evaluation. Third, even when the facts are clear, it is not always clear what the rules and principles imply
    • Three major complications are identified by Michael D. Bayles, 'Principles for Legal Procedure' (1986) 5 Law and Philosophy 33, 40: [J]udicial decision making is not a simple application of rules and principles to facts. First, finding facts is not a straight-forward descriptive process. Facts must be classified for the application of rules and do not come neatly labeled. Second, many so-called factual questions are matters of evaluation. Determining whether someone was negligent, reasonable, or insane requires judgment and evaluation. Third, even when the facts are clear, it is not always clear what the rules and principles imply.
    • (1986) Law and Philosophy , vol.5 , pp. 40
    • Bayles, M.D.1
  • 116
    • 26144448227 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the evaluative and normative nature of fact-finding, see (Dorchecht: Kluwer) ch 4 ('Ascription of Normative Consequences to Facts)
    • On the evaluative and normative nature of fact-finding, see Bert van Roermund, Law, Narrative and Reality - An Essay in Intercepting Politics (Dorchecht: Kluwer, 1997) ch 4 ('Ascription of Normative Consequences to Facts);
    • (1997) Law, Narrative and Reality - An Essay in Intercepting Politics
    • van Roermund, B.1
  • 117
    • 33751344515 scopus 로고
    • 'The Element of Valuation'
    • nd ed) ch 8
    • Olivecrona, n 9 above, 212-215 ('The Element of Valuation');
    • (1971) Law As Fact , pp. 212-215
    • Olivecrona, K.1
  • 118
    • 0033269213 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Law, Fact and Legal Language'
    • and on the related difficulty of drawing a bright line between facts and legal norms
    • and on the related difficulty of drawing a bright line between facts and legal norms: Morawski, n 69 above.
    • (1999) Law and Philosophy , vol.18 , pp. 465-466
    • Morawski, L.1
  • 119
    • 33751315205 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • At lower levels, a verdict asserts, if only by implication, facts on which the ascription operates.
  • 121
    • 33751347523 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • introduction to his forthcoming book
    • Sanford Schane, introduction to his forthcoming book, Language and the Law.
    • Language and the Law
    • Schane, S.1
  • 122
    • 85187365434 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "'More Than Just Illogical": Truth and Jury Nullification'
    • For a sophisticated argument against construing what the nullifying jury does as lying, see in Duff, Farmer, Marshall and Tadros (Oxford: Hart)
    • For a sophisticated argument against construing what the nullifying jury does as lying, see Matt Matravers, "'More Than Just Illogical": Truth and Jury Nullification' in Duff, Farmer, Marshall and Tadros (2004), n 41 above.
    • (2004) The Trial on Trial - Truth and Due Process
    • Matravers, M.1
  • 123
    • 0041161623 scopus 로고
    • On the condemnatory aspect of a conviction, see (Cambridge, CUP)
    • On the condemnatory aspect of a conviction, see Duff, n 41 above, 108.
    • (1986) Trials and Punishments , pp. 108
    • Duff, R.A.1
  • 124
    • 84921593506 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Tadros argues 'that imposing criminal responsibility expresses moral indignation about the fact that an individual has failed properly to be motivated by the interests of others' (Oxford: OUP)
    • Tadros argues 'that imposing criminal responsibility expresses moral indignation about the fact that an individual has failed properly to be motivated by the interests of others' (Victor Tadros, Criminal Responsibility (Oxford: OUP, 2005) 85;
    • (2005) Criminal Responsibility , pp. 85
    • Tadros, V.1
  • 127
    • 0010089297 scopus 로고
    • It is worth noting that moral expressivism, while certainly a respectable theory, is challenged by some philosophers. See eg, (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul) especially the claims made at and the discussion that follows
    • It is worth noting that moral expressivism, while certainly a respectable theory, is challenged by some philosophers. See eg, Julius Kovesi Moral Notions (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1967) especially the claims made at 148-9, and the discussion that follows;
    • (1967) Moral Notions , pp. 148-149
    • Kovesi, J.1
  • 128
    • 85044883505 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Moral Description: Overcoming Dichotomy in Social Research'
    • and see also the application of Kovesi's argument by 6
    • and see also the application of Kovesi's argument by James R. Doughney, 'Moral Description: Overcoming Dichotomy in Social Research' (2005) 2 International Journal of Mental Health and Addiction 6 at 9-10.
    • (2005) International Journal of Mental Health and Addiction , vol.2 , pp. 9-10
    • Doughney, J.R.1
  • 129
    • 33751332205 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Tellingly, 'condemn' is defined in the Oxford English Dictionary as synonymous with 'convict'.
  • 131
    • 84921593506 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also (Oxford: OUP) 'The label "criminal" is appropriate when certain moral attitudes are appropriate in response to the conduct prohibited, and this is to be distinguished from, for example, torts. The label "tortious" may make appropriate some reactive attitudes, but surely not the same kind as are made appropriate by the criminal law'
    • see also ibid at 80: 'The label "criminal" is appropriate when certain moral attitudes are appropriate in response to the conduct prohibited, and this is to be distinguished from, for example, torts. The label "tortious" may make appropriate some reactive attitudes, but surely not the same kind as are made appropriate by the criminal law.'
    • (2005) Criminal Responsibility , pp. 80
    • Tadros, V.1
  • 132
    • 33751321824 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • R v H [2003] UKHL 1, [2003] 1 All ER 497 is, strictly speaking, a logical decision. But for broader criticisms, see
    • R v H [2003] UKHL 1, [2003] 1 All ER 497 is, strictly speaking, a logical decision. But for broader criticisms, see A. J. Ashworth, [2003] Crim L R 817.
    • (2003) Crim L R 817
    • Ashworth, A.J.1
  • 133
    • 0040325981 scopus 로고
    • 'Noncomparative Justice'
    • The point is forcefully put by 297, When an innocent man is pronounced guilty, the record about him is falsified to the disadvantage of his reputation and to the detriment of the cause of truth. This is an injustice to him and remains so even if his sentence is suspended and no further hardship is imposed upon him. The injustice in this case consists precisely in the falsity of what is believed about the unjustly convicted man
    • The point is forcefully put by Joel Feinberg, 'Noncomparative Justice' (1974) 83 The Philosophical Review 297, 302: When an innocent man is pronounced guilty, the record about him is falsified to the disadvantage of his reputation and to the detriment of the cause of truth. This is an injustice to him and remains so even if his sentence is suspended and no further hardship is imposed upon him. The injustice in this case consists precisely in the falsity of what is believed about the unjustly convicted man.
    • (1974) The Philosophical Review , vol.83 , pp. 302
    • Feinberg, J.1
  • 134
    • 84934858934 scopus 로고
    • 'The Evidence or the Event? On Judicial Proof and the Acceptability of Verdicts'
    • Charles Nesson, 'The Evidence or the Event? On Judicial Proof and the Acceptability of Verdicts', (1985) 98 Harvard Law Review 1357.
    • (1985) Harvard Law Review , vol.98 , pp. 1357
    • Nesson, C.1
  • 135
    • 33751336772 scopus 로고
    • 'Rationality, Mythology, and the "Acceptability of Verdicts" Thesis'
    • Critical reactions to this piece include
    • Critical reactions to this piece include: Ronald J. Allen, 'Rationality, Mythology, and the "Acceptability of Verdicts" Thesis' (1986) 66 Boston Law Review 541;
    • (1986) Boston Law Review , vol.66 , pp. 541
    • Allen, R.J.1
  • 136
    • 33751327450 scopus 로고
    • 'The Costs of Acceptability: Blue Buses, Agent Orange, and Aversion to Statistical Evidence'
    • Neil B. Cohen, 'The Costs of Acceptability: Blue Buses, Agent Orange, and Aversion to Statistical Evidence' (1986) 66 Boston Law Review 563
    • (1986) Boston Law Review , vol.66 , pp. 563
    • Cohen, N.B.1
  • 137
    • 3042983274 scopus 로고
    • 'The Hearsay Rule and the Stability of Verdicts: A Response to Professor Nesson'
    • and Roger C. Park, 'The Hearsay Rule and the Stability of Verdicts: A Response to Professor Nesson' (1986) 70 Minnesota Law Review 1057.
    • (1986) Minnesota Law Review , vol.70 , pp. 1057
    • Park, R.C.1
  • 138
    • 33751349895 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Daubert and the Acceptability of Legal Decisions'
    • Nesson's thesis is applied by available at
    • Nesson's thesis is applied by Carl F. Carnor, 'Daubert and the Acceptability of Legal Decisions' (2005) 5 Journal of Philosophy, Science and Law, available at www.psljournal.com/archives/all/cranor.cfm.
    • (2005) Journal of Philosophy, Science and Law , vol.5
    • Carnor, C.F.1
  • 139
    • 84934858934 scopus 로고
    • 'The Evidence or the Event? On Judicial Proof and the Acceptability of Verdicts'
    • Nesson, n 85 above, 1373.
    • (1985) Harvard Law Review , vol.98 , pp. 1373
    • Nesson, C.1
  • 140
    • 84934858934 scopus 로고
    • 'The Evidence or the Event? On Judicial Proof and the Acceptability of Verdicts'
    • ibid 1374.
    • (1985) Harvard Law Review , vol.98 , pp. 1374
    • Nesson, C.1
  • 141
    • 84934858934 scopus 로고
    • 'The Evidence or the Event? On Judicial Proof and the Acceptability of Verdicts'
    • See the contemplative remarks in his conclusion
    • See the contemplative remarks in his conclusion, ibid 1391.
    • (1985) Harvard Law Review , vol.98 , pp. 1391
    • Nesson, C.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.