메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 36, Issue 4, 2006, Pages 645-669

When fully informed states make good the threat of war: Rational escalation and the failure of bargaining

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 33747881563     PISSN: 00071234     EISSN: 14692112     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1017/S0007123406000342     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (12)

References (79)
  • 1
    • 33747884463 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • One-sided deterrence relationships have obvious empirical and theoretical import
    • Cambridge: Cambridge Studies in International Relations, Cambridge University Press
    • We therefore look at an asymmetric deterrence situation which allows us to incorporate the simplest possible escalation ladder into our model. Moreover, as Zagare and Kilgour point out, such 'one-sided deterrence relationships have obvious empirical and theoretical import': Frank Zagare and Marc Kilgour, Perfect Deterrence (Cambridge: Cambridge Studies in International Relations, Cambridge University Press, 2000), p. 135.
    • (2000) Perfect Deterrence , pp. 135
    • Zagare, F.1    Kilgour, M.2
  • 2
    • 84972159336 scopus 로고
    • Rationalist explanations for war
    • James D. Fearon, 'Rationalist Explanations for War,' International Organization, 49 (1995), 379-414;
    • (1995) International Organization , vol.49 , pp. 379-414
    • Fearon, J.D.1
  • 3
    • 0003656791 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York:Cambridge University Press
    • Robert Powell, Nuclear Deterrence Theory: The Search for Credibility (New York:Cambridge University Press, 1990). As we discuss below, these authors do explain costly conflict in equilibrium despite full information if the payers are engaged in a stochastic game. The inefficient outcome is then attributed to commitment problems.
    • (1990) Nuclear Deterrence Theory: The Search for Credibility
    • Powell, R.1
  • 4
    • 3042722111 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The inefficient use of power: Costly conflict with complete information
    • See, for example, Robert Powell, 'The Inefficient Use of Power: Costly Conflict with Complete Information', American Political Science Review, 98 (2004), 231-41;
    • (2004) American Political Science Review , vol.98 , pp. 231-241
    • Powell, R.1
  • 5
    • 1642616259 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Why do some civil wars last so long?
    • James D. Fearon, 'Why Do Some Civil Wars Last So Long?' Journal of Peace Research, 41 (2004), 275-302.
    • (2004) Journal of Peace Research , vol.41 , pp. 275-302
    • Fearon, J.D.1
  • 6
    • 3242667229 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press
    • Robert Powell, In the Shadow of Power (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1999).
    • (1999) Shadow of Power
    • Powell, R.1
  • 10
    • 84916228748 scopus 로고
    • A positive theory of fiscal deficits and government debt
    • Related work examines the incentive to run up inefficient levels of public debt (Alberto Alesina and Guido Tabellini, 'A Positive Theory of Fiscal Deficits and Government Debt', Review of Economic Studies, 57 (1990), 403-14;
    • (1990) Review of Economic Studies , vol.57 , pp. 403-414
    • Alesina, A.1    Tabellini, G.2
  • 11
    • 84959824318 scopus 로고
    • Why stubborn conservatives would run a deficit: policy with time-inconsistent preferences
    • Thorsten Persson and Lars Svensson, 'Why Stubborn Conservatives Would Run a Deficit: Policy with Time-Inconsistent Preferences', Quarterly Journal of Economics, 104 (1989), 325-45) or to create inefficient administrative procedures
    • (1989) Quarterly Journal of Economics , vol.104 , pp. 325-345
    • Persson, T.1    Svensson, L.2
  • 12
    • 0036592701 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Electoral competition, political uncertainty, and policy insulation
    • (Rui de Figueiredo, 'Electoral Competition, Political Uncertainty, and Policy Insulation', American Political Science Review, 96 (2002), 321-35).
    • (2002) American Political Science Review , vol.96 , pp. 321-335
    • De Figueiredo, R.1
  • 13
    • 33747892590 scopus 로고
    • edited and translated by Michael Howard and Peter Paret (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press)
    • Carl von Clausewitz, On War, edited and translated by Michael Howard and Peter Paret (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1984), p. 605.
    • (1984) On War , pp. 605
    • Von Clausewitz, C.1
  • 18
    • 0036790493 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A bargaining model of war and peace: Anticipating the onset, duration and outcome of war
    • Darren Filson and Suzanne Werner, 'A Bargaining Model of War and Peace: Anticipating the Onset, Duration and Outcome of War', American Journal of Political Science, 46 (2002), 819-38, p. 819.
    • (2002) American Journal of Political Science , vol.46 , pp. 819-838
    • Filson, D.1    Werner, S.2
  • 19
    • 0030210811 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bargaining in the shadow of power
    • There is avast literature on war and bargaining that appeals to uncertainty and we do not review it here. For example, Powell models rivals that have asymmetric information on each other's preferences (Robert Powell, 'Bargaining in the Shadow of Power', Games and Economic Behavior, 15(1996), 255-89;
    • (1996) Games and Economic Behavior , vol.15 , pp. 255-289
    • Powell, R.1
  • 20
    • 3242667229 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and Powell, In the Shadow of Power). The more recent literature examines the learning that occurs as a result of fighting and bargaining. In Filson and Werner one of the rivals is uncertain about the other's type and bargains accordingly.
    • Shadow of Power
    • Powell1
  • 21
    • 33747875623 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The response to negotiations as well as the outcome of battle informs about the likelihood that the rival is strong or weak (see Filson and Werner, 'A Bargaining Model of War and Peace'.
    • A Bargaining Model of War and Peace
    • Filson1    Werner2
  • 22
    • 1942505978 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bargaining and fighting: The impact of regime type on war onset, duration and outcome
    • and Darren Filson and Suzanne Werner, 'Bargaining and Fighting: The Impact of Regime Type on War Onset, Duration and Outcome', American Journal of Political Science, 48 (2004), 296-313).
    • (2004) American Journal of Political Science , vol.48 , pp. 296-313
    • Filson, D.1    Werner, S.2
  • 23
    • 9944238709 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bargaining and the nature of war
    • In a related vein, Smith and Stam model states that have inconsistent beliefs about the likelihood of winning the next battle (or fort) and these beliefs converge as the rivals fight battle after battle (Alastair Smith and Allan Stam, 'Bargaining and the Nature of War', Journal of Conflict Resolution, 48 (2004), 783-813).
    • (2004) Journal of Conflict Resolution , vol.48 , pp. 783-813
    • Smith, A.1    Stam, A.2
  • 24
    • 0032188041 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Integrating and testing models of rivalry duration
    • Scott D. Bennett, 'Integrating and Testing Models of Rivalry Duration', American Journal of Political Science, 42 (1998), 1200-32
    • (1998) American Journal of Political Science , vol.42 , pp. 1200-1232
    • Bennett, S.D.1
  • 28
    • 0032355311 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bargaining, enforcement and international cooperation
    • James D. Fearon, 'Bargaining, Enforcement and International Cooperation', International Organization, 52 (1998), 269-305.
    • (1998) International Organization , vol.52 , pp. 269-305
    • Fearon, J.D.1
  • 30
    • 0037309160 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The power to hurt: Costly conflict with completely informed states
    • Branislav L. Slantchev, 'The Power to Hurt: Costly Conflict with Completely Informed States', American Political Science Review, 97 (2003), 123-35.
    • (2003) American Political Science Review , vol.97 , pp. 123-135
    • Slantchev, B.L.1
  • 31
    • 0003019549 scopus 로고
    • Perfect equilibrium in a bargaining game
    • Ariel Rubinstein, 'Perfect Equilibrium in a Bargaining Game', Econometrica, 50 (1982), 97-110;
    • (1982) Econometrica , vol.50 , pp. 97-110
    • Rubinstein, A.1
  • 32
    • 0001104018 scopus 로고
    • Perfect equilibria in a negotiation model
    • Lutz-Alexander Busch and Quan Wen, 'Perfect Equilibria in a Negotiation Model', Econometrica, 63 (1995), 545-65.
    • (1995) Econometrica , vol.63 , pp. 545-565
    • Busch, L.-A.1    Wen, Q.2
  • 35
    • 33747879733 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Demanding x = 0 is substantially equivalent to not challenging in the first place and indeed results in an offer y = 0 and an immediate exit by the challenger in the equilibria we obtain.
  • 36
    • 33747887163 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Backdown does not mean that the challenger drops her demand altogether. It merely means that she shies away from immediate military action while her current demand stands. Whatever y the defender may offer at the next visit to BD, the challenger can repeat or modify her demand at her next visit to BC. The model can undoubtedly be complicated to allow more options and decision turns for the two sides. Our modelling choices were driven by a need for simplicity while allowing for repeated choices in the three main phases of the game (bargaining, crisis and war). The model variations that the authors investigated did not affect the qualitative results.
  • 37
    • 33747893214 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • α where α ∈ [0,1] represents the rivals' degree of risk aversion. The lower α, the more risk averse the players. We briefly explore the impact of risk aversion on model outcomes when we develop our numerical examples (see fn. 40) and provide formulae for strategic probabilities in equilibrium in fn. 35.
  • 38
    • 33747872406 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Payoffs indicated in Figure 1 are per period payoffs. The challenger's payoff is listed first.
  • 39
    • 33747878434 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • IV= tω with a reinterpretation of parameter t. In the current interpretation we assume t + u + v = 1 but we can instead let t + u + v < 1 with the difference being lost in the fighting. The future would then be more discounted after any war turn. This would discount costs more after a war episode, meaning that each side's capacity to inflict war costs in the future is reduced by fighting. Such a modification would leave formulae for probabilities in 6a-e unchanged, although a lower t would affect the probability values and the necessary conditions (s and r decrease, and condition c + d > tω/(1 - ω) is less stringent).
  • 40
    • 0004260007 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press), chap. 5
    • See Drew Fudenberg and Jean Tirole, Game Theory (Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press, 1995), chap. 5.
    • (1995) Game Theory
    • Fudenberg, D.1    Tirole, J.2
  • 41
    • 33747890553 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Technically, that history must lead to a subgame that is self-contained in terms of decision and information structure. This is always the case in our game structure. Also note that the prior history need not result from equilibrium play in a SPE.
  • 43
    • 33747886514 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • n). This is because, given an agreed bargain (x, 1 - x), each rival must find it in his or her interest to follow the plan, and incur the costs associated with the war episodes, in order to get the agreed share of the prize. For the same reason, pure equilibria cannot generate outcomes in which the rivals fight wars that end up costing more than the coveted asset is worth.
  • 45
    • 0004260007 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • chap. 13, for an analysis of Markov Perfect equilibria
    • See Fudenberg and Tirole, Game Theory, chap. 13, for an analysis of Markov Perfect equilibria. Although a MPE has a simple structure it retains all properties of SPEs, in particular that no deviation of any kind can be profitable. An elementary proof of this claim for our particular game structure is available from the authors upon request.
    • Game Theory
    • Fudenberg1    Tirole2
  • 46
    • 33747874645 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Details of this generalization are available from the authors upon request.
  • 47
    • 33747856809 scopus 로고
    • Re-examination of the perfectness concept for equilibrium points in extensive games
    • Theorem 2 in the Appendix specifies out of equilibrium behaviour as required for a SPE (Reinhart Selten, 'Re-examination of the Perfectness Concept for Equilibrium Points in Extensive Games', International Journal of Game Theory, 4 (1975), 25-55).
    • (1975) International Journal of Game Theory , vol.4 , pp. 25-55
    • Selten, R.1
  • 48
    • 33747879000 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • α - Κ. Overall, when the rivals are risk averse, it takes a lower counter-offer from the defender for the challenger to accept it for certain. The risk-averse challenger tends to be more cautious and this shows up in the impact of risk aversion on model outcomes (see fn. 40).
  • 49
    • 33747888973 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Details of this generalization are available from the authors upon request.
  • 50
    • 84936028847 scopus 로고
    • Equilibrium behavior in crisis bargaining games
    • A probability of war is also frequently the equilibrium outcome of incomplete information games that describe bargaining in the shadow of conflict. For example, Banks describes an asymmetric information game for which the probability of war in equilibrium increases with the informed player's payoff from war (Jeffrey S. Banks, 'Equilibrium Behavior in Crisis Bargaining Games', American Journal of Political Science, 34 (1990), 599-614). Our mixed equilibria also predict a probability of war, but in contrast to Banks, we specify the escalation process by which war occurs and it is the escalation process itself that generates the war probability in equilibrium. Banks, instead, assumes an a priori theoretical relationship between player choices and the probability of war.
    • (1990) American Journal of Political Science , vol.34 , pp. 599-614
    • Banks, J.S.1
  • 51
    • 33747886645 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 18th printing
    • Thomas C. Schelling, The Strategy of Conflict (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1960, 18th printing 2002), p. 182.
    • (1960) The Strategy of Conflict , pp. 182
    • Schelling, T.C.1
  • 52
    • 85078868493 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • D = 3 cut across the range of battle costs that the model admits.
  • 53
    • 33747884592 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • D = 3 and ω = 0.95 as in Table 1, if the protagonists pick bargaining position x = 1, y = 0, then as α decreases to 0.8, probability s that Challenger reiterates her demand at BC drops to 73.1 per cent while she would have done so with 84.2 per cent probability had she been risk neutral. Overall, as risk aversion increases, the challenger accepts the defender's counter-offer with increasing probability, war is avoided with increasing probability, and the expected length of the crisis is reduced. A full numerical exploration of the impact of risk aversion, is available from the authors upon request.
  • 54
    • 0036404908 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bargaining theory and international conflict
    • Interestingly, allowing for decisive battle wins does not encourage fighting. Numerical simulations, available from the authors upon request, show that the impact of a decisive win in battle is limited to relatively small changes in the calibration of outcomes. Nevertheless, the fact that deterrence succeeds with higher probability when wars can be won outright is noteworthy, as it confirms our central finding: perfectly informed rivals wield deterrent threats to gain or maintain possession of the contested asset, and make good on these threats by engaging in costly warfare. The possibility of winning outright emboldens challenger and defender once war is the next possible step, and this encourages the challenger to accept the defender's counteroffer before escalation. Powell points out that a war as 'costly lottery' assumption may not be neutral (Robert Powell, 'Bargaining Theory and International Conflict', Annual Review of Political Science, 5 (2002), 1-30).
    • (2002) Annual Review of Political Science , vol.5 , pp. 1-30
    • Powell, R.1
  • 55
    • 0040211372 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In fact, Wagner argues that the assumption is distorting and 'can only lead to misleading conclusions' (Wagner, 'Bargaining and War', p. 469). Our analysis suggests that the 'costly lottery' assumption reinforces incentives that are present when wars merely impose costs.
    • Bargaining and War , pp. 469
    • Wagner1
  • 56
    • 0039988250 scopus 로고
    • Vietnamese-American peace negotiations: The failed 1965 initiatives
    • Robert K. Brigham, 'Vietnamese-American Peace Negotiations: The Failed 1965 Initiatives', Journal of American-East Asian Relations, 4 (1995), 377-94.
    • (1995) Journal of American-East Asian Relations , vol.4 , pp. 377-394
    • Brigham, R.K.1
  • 59
    • 0004056138 scopus 로고
    • New York: Penguin Books
    • Stanley Karnov, Vietnam, A History (New York: Penguin Books, 1983), p. 549.
    • (1983) Vietnam, a History , pp. 549
    • Karnov, S.1
  • 60
    • 33747886009 scopus 로고
    • PewCase401, Institute for the Study of Diplomacy. School of Foreign Service, Georgetown University
    • Thomas Princen, 'Beagle Channel Negotiations' (PewCase401, Institute for the Study of Diplomacy. School of Foreign Service, Georgetown University, 1995).
    • (1995) Beagle Channel Negotiations
    • Princen, T.1
  • 66
    • 0003749916 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Thousand Oaks, Calif.: Quantitative Applications in the Social Sciences Series, Paper 116, Sage
    • Having consulted Chistopher Mooney, Monte Carlo Simulation (Thousand Oaks, Calif.: Quantitative Applications in the Social Sciences Series, Paper 116, Sage, 1997).
    • (1997) Monte Carlo Simulation
    • Mooney, C.1
  • 67
    • 0003776426 scopus 로고
    • London: CRC Press
    • 1. The remaining paths were sorted into four groups: paths for which both parties receive strictly negative payoffs; paths for which the players received positive payoffs; paths for which one or the other receives a strictly negative payoff. Frequencies for each of the five events were calculated. This process was repeated 1,000 times generating a distribution for the frequencies of each event. In all cases, with 95 per cent confidence, we were not able to reject the null hypothesis of a normal distribution (Jarque Bera statistic < 5.99). We were therefore able to construct 95 per cent confidence interval estimates of the likelihoods of each of the five events by adding and subtracting 1.96 standard deviations to each of the means.
    • (1994) A Primer for the Monte Carlo Method
    • Sobol, I.1
  • 68
    • 33747882656 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • We add the means in the < 0 column for the challenger and the < 0 row for defender.
  • 69
    • 85078869554 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • 1), which leaves her with utility 0.
  • 70
    • 33747876757 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The possibility of winning the asset in battle does not significantly reduce the downside risk for either party. Estimates of the likelihood of various payoff events when battles can be won decisively are available from the authors upon request.
  • 71
    • 84974063223 scopus 로고
    • Rational deterrence: Theory and practice
    • Robert Jervis, 'Rational Deterrence: Theory and Practice', World Politics, 41 (1989), 183-207, p. 184.
    • (1989) World Politics , vol.41 , pp. 183-207
    • Jervis, R.1
  • 75
    • 33747877010 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • These might be different from the initial ones. To substantiate a claim of perfect equilibrium one must allow any prior development, not just prior moves conforming to equilibrium behaviour. So, whether optimal or not, prior offers x and y may have been made.
  • 76
    • 33747880998 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • s and r are 0 when y = tx -Κ and p reduces to 1 when ψ = 0. Otherwise, all are in (0, 1).
  • 77
    • 33747878558 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The Markov chain actually includes states I' and II', and its full transition matrix should formally involve two additional rows and columns. But I' and II' are absorbing states with fixed probabilities u and v of being reached and fixed outcomes. All calculations relevant to the decisions x and y and the move probabilities can therefore be limited to this 4×4 matrix for simplicity.
  • 78
    • 84858946487 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This includes the case where y>t -Κ
    • This includes the case where y>t -Κ.
  • 79
    • 0003781238 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • These arguments are standard in Markov chains and can be found in James Norris, Markov Chains (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997), p. 12).
    • (1997) Markov Chains , pp. 12


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.