메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 101, Issue 5, 2004, Pages 221-241

Likelihood, model selection, and the Duhem-Quine problem

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 20744432982     PISSN: 0022362X     EISSN: 19398549     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.5840/jphil2004101515     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (18)

References (45)
  • 2
    • 0002820563 scopus 로고
    • Two Dogmas of Empiricism
    • Cambridge: Harvard
    • "Two Dogmas of Empiricism," in From a Logical Point of View (Cambridge: Harvard, 1953), pp. 20-46
    • (1953) From A Logical Point of View , pp. 20-46
  • 3
    • 0004242804 scopus 로고
    • Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall
    • and Philosophy of Logic (Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1970).
    • (1970) Philosophy of Logic
  • 4
    • 60949145264 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Quine's Two Dogmas
    • Distributive holists may assert that the effects on H and A are qualitatively the same (that is, that both are confirmed or both are disconfirmed) or, more ambitiously, that the effects are quantitatively the same (that is, that the degree of confirmation of H is identical with the degree of confirmation of A). For more on this taxonomy of holisms, see my "Quine's Two Dogmas," Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, LXXIV (2000): 237-80.
    • (2000) Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society , vol.74 , pp. 237-280
  • 5
    • 0003633976 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: MIT
    • I do not concede that simplicity is always an extra-evidential consideration; the point here is that this is what holists happen to believe. For discussion, see my Reconstructing the Past: Parsimony, Evolution, and Inference (Cambridge: MIT, 1988)
    • (1988) Reconstructing the Past: Parsimony, Evolution, and Inference
  • 6
    • 0011212315 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Instrumentalism, Parsimony, and the Akaike Framework
    • and my "Instrumentalism, Parsimony, and the Akaike Framework," Philosophy of Science, LXIX (2002): S112-S123.
    • (2002) Philosophy of Sciences , vol.69
  • 7
    • 0011404081 scopus 로고
    • Bayesian Personalism, the Methodology of Scientific Research Programs, and Duhem's Problem
    • See, for example, J. Dorling, "Bayesian Personalism, the Methodology of Scientific Research Programs, and Duhem's Problem," Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science, X (1979): 177-87
    • (1979) Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science , vol.10 , pp. 177-187
    • Dorling, J.1
  • 11
    • 0003393452 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Chicago: University Press, which analyzes the Duhem-Quine problem within the context of frequentist statistics
    • For a nonBayesian treatment, see Deborah Mayo's Error and the Growth of Experimental Knowledge (Chicago: University Press, 1996), which analyzes the Duhem-Quine problem within the context of frequentist statistics.
    • (1996) Error and the Growth of Experimental Knowledge
    • Mayo, D.1
  • 12
    • 24944551442 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Plurality of Bayesian Measures of Confirmation and the Problem of Measure Sensitivity
    • As a simple example of a Bayesian analysis, let us define the degree of confirmation that X receives from Y, c[X,Y], as the ratio Pr(X|Y)/Pr(X). So defined, c[X,Y] > 1 when Y positively confirms X and c[X,Y] < 1 when Y disconfirms X By Bayes's theorem, this ratio equals Pr(Y|X)/Pr(Y); thus, c[H, notO] > c[A, notO] if and only if Pr(notO|H) > Pr(notO|A), which expands to Pr(notO|H & A)Pr(A |H) + Pr(notO| H & notA)Pr(notA |H) > Pr(notO |H & A)Pr(H |A) + Pr(notO| notH & A)Pr(notH |A). Note the occurrence of Pr(A|H) and of Pr(H|A) in this expression. If we assume that H and A are probabilistically independent, the inequality reduces to Pr(notO |H & A)Pr(A) + Pr(notO| H & notA)Pr(notA) > Pr(notO |H & A)Pr(H) + Pr(notO| notH & A)Pr(notH). Notice the prior probabilities of A and of H. I do not mean to beg questions here about the proper definition of degree of confirmation, on which see Branden Fitelson, "The Plurality of Bayesian Measures of Confirmation and the Problem of Measure Sensitivity," Philosophy of Science, LXVI (1999): S362-S378. The point is just to identify the kinds of quantities that a Bayesian analysis must evaluate. Another Bayesian approach would be to compare, not the change in probability that O induces in H with the change it induces in A, but the absolute values of Pr(H|O) and Pr(A|O). Bayes's Theorem entails that Pr(H|O) > Pr(A|O) if and only if Pr(O|H)Pr(H) > Pr(O|A)Pr(A). Prior probabilities occur in this expression, and Pr(H|A) and Pr(A|H) are involved as well, since Pr(O|H) = Pr(O| H & A)Pr(A|H) + Pr(O | H & notA)Pr(notA | H) and Pr(O|A) = Pr(O | H & A)Pr(H|A) + Pr(O | notH & A)Pr(notH|A).
    • (1999) Philosophy of Science , vol.66
    • Fitelson, B.1
  • 13
    • 0000501656 scopus 로고
    • Information Theory as an Extension of the Maximum Likelihood Principle
    • Budapest: Akademiai Kiado
    • "Information Theory as an Extension of the Maximum Likelihood Principle," in B. Petrov and F. Csaki, eds., Second International Symposium on Information Theory (Budapest: Akademiai Kiado, 1973), pp. 267-81.
    • (1973) Second International Symposium on Information Theory , pp. 267-281
    • Petrov, B.1    Csaki, F.2
  • 14
    • 0009094124 scopus 로고
    • 'Narrow' Aspects of Intentionality and the Information-theoretic Approach to Content
    • New York: Blackwell
    • Here I adopt terminology from Hartry Field, who talks about world-to-head and head-to-world reliability. See his "'Narrow' Aspects of Intentionality and the Information-theoretic Approach to Content," in Enrique Villanueva, ed., Information, Semantics, and Epistemology (New York: Blackwell, 1990), pp. 102-16.
    • (1990) Information, Semantics, and Epistemology , pp. 102-116
    • Villanueva, E.1
  • 15
    • 0039813178 scopus 로고
    • Temporally Oriented Laws
    • If our interest in using tuberculosis tests is to find out whether someone probably has tuberculosis, why are error characteristics defined in tenus of probabilities of the form Pr(± test outcome | ± tuberculosis), rather than in terms of probabilities of the form Pr(± tuberculosis | ± test outcome)? The reason is that the latter quantities depend on how rare or common tuberculosis is, but the former do not. It is a curious fact about our universe that probabilities of the form Pr(effect|cause) are often time-translationally invariant, whereas probabilities of the form Pr(cause| effect) rarely are. For discussion, see my "Temporally Oriented Laws," Synthese, XCIV (1993): 171-89.
    • (1993) Synthese , vol.94 , pp. 171-189
  • 17
    • 0004128472 scopus 로고
    • New York: Cambridge
    • Anthony Edwards, Likelihood (New York: Cambridge, 1972);
    • (1972) Likelihood
    • Edwards, A.1
  • 20
    • 1842830148 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Real Realism: The Galilean Strategy
    • and his "Real Realism: The Galilean Strategy," Philosophical Review, CX (2001): 151-98.
    • (2001) Philosophical Review , vol.110 , pp. 151-198
  • 21
    • 0038443276 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Princeton: University Press
    • See Richard W. Miller, Fact and Method (Princeton: University Press, 1999)
    • (1999) Fact and Method
    • Miller, R.W.1
  • 22
    • 3843150244 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bayesianism: Its Scope and Limits
    • New York: Oxford
    • and my "Bayesianism: Its Scope and Limits," in Richard Swinburne, ed., Bayes's Theorem (New York: Oxford, 2002), pp. 21-38.
    • (2002) Bayes's Theorem , pp. 21-38
    • Swinburne, R.1
  • 26
    • 12244278857 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Prediction, Accommodation, and the Problem of Overfitting
    • Adams and Le Verrier were able to accommodate the observed orbit of Uranus within the Newtonian framework by postulating an eighth planet, but did Uranus's orbit confirm the hypothesis that there is an eighth planet? It is tempting to answer this question in the negative and to insist that it was only the observation of Neptune that provided evidence. The broad epistemological question at issue here is whether using an observation to construct a hypothesis means that the observation fails to provide evidence for the hypothesis. See Christopher Hitchcock and Elliott Sober, "Prediction, Accommodation, and the Problem of Overfitting," British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, LV (2004): 1-34, for discussion.
    • (2004) British Journal for the Philosophy of Sciences , vol.55 , pp. 1-34
    • Hitchcock, C.1    Sober, E.2    Wilson3
  • 27
    • 2442624482 scopus 로고
    • Indispensability and Mathematics
    • See my "Indispensability and Mathematics," Philosophical Review, CII (1993): 35-57.
    • (1993) Philosophical Review , vol.102 , pp. 35-57
  • 28
    • 0003394371 scopus 로고
    • New York: Oxford
    • Whereas the Adams/Le Verrier approach to the orbit of Uranus involved "asymmetry by default," this was not the case with respect to later discussion of the anomalous perihelion of Mercury, in that modifications of the auxiliary assumptions and of Newtonian theory were both developed. See N. Rosevcare, Mercury's Perihelion from Le Verrier to Einstein (New York: Oxford, 1982)
    • (1982) Mercury's Perihelion from le Verrier to Einstein
    • Rosevcare, N.1
  • 29
    • 0009046497 scopus 로고
    • Einstein's Explanation of the Motion of Mercury's Perihelion
    • Earman, Janssen, and John D. Norton, eds, Boston: Birkhäuser
    • and John Earman and Michel Janssen, "Einstein's Explanation of the Motion of Mercury's Perihelion," in Earman, Janssen, and John D. Norton, eds., The Attraction of Gravitation: New Studies in the History of General Relativity (Boston: Birkhäuser, 1993), pp. 129-72.
    • (1993) The Attraction of Gravitation: New Studies in the History of General Relativity , pp. 129-172
    • Earman, J.1    Janssen, M.2
  • 31
    • 0000634663 scopus 로고
    • Bayes and Bust: Simplicity as a Problem for a Probabilist's Approach to Confirmation
    • See M. Forster, "Bayes and Bust: Simplicity as a Problem for a Probabilist's Approach to Confirmation," British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, XLVI (1995): 399-429
    • (1995) British Journal for the Philosophy of Science , vol.46 , pp. 399-429
    • Forster, M.1
  • 35
    • 52949086982 scopus 로고
    • How to Tell When Simpler, More Unified, or Less Ad Hoc Theories Will Provide More Accurate Predictions
    • See Forster and Sober, "How to Tell When Simpler, More Unified, or Less Ad Hoc Theories Will Provide More Accurate Predictions," British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, XLV (1994): 1-36.
    • (1994) British Journal for the Philosophy of Science , vol.45 , pp. 1-36
    • Forster1    Sober2
  • 36
    • 0000629975 scopus 로고
    • Cross-validatory Choice and Assessment of Statistical Predictions (with Discussion)
    • Does AIC play into the hands of holism by invoking simplicity? I would say not, in that the justification for AIC depends on empirical assumptions (though ones of great generality). In addition, I will be using AIC only as an example of a model selection criterion; cross-validation is another such criterion, and it involves no appeal to simplicity. As it happens, take-one-out cross-validation is asymptotically equivalent with AIC. See M. Stone's "Cross-validatory Choice and Assessment of Statistical Predictions (with Discussion)," Journal of the Royal Statistical Society, B XXXVI (1974): 111-47
    • (1974) Journal of the Royal Statistical Society, B , vol.36 , pp. 111-147
    • Stone, M.1
  • 37
    • 0000859675 scopus 로고
    • An Asymptotic Equivalence of Choice of Model by Cross-validation and Akaike's Criterion
    • and his "An Asymptotic Equivalence of Choice of Model by Cross-validation and Akaike's Criterion," Journal of the Royal Statistical Society, B XXXIX (1977): 44-47.
    • (1977) Journal of the Royal Statistical Society, B , vol.39 , pp. 44-47
  • 38
    • 79956789927 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Contest between Likelihood and Parsimony
    • See my "The Contest between Likelihood and Parsimony," Systematic Biology (2004, forthcoming).
    • (2004) Systematic Biology
  • 39
    • 0000732090 scopus 로고
    • Evolution of Protein Molecules
    • (New York: Academic)
    • "Evolution of Protein Molecules," in H. Munro, ed., Mammalian Protein Metabolism (New York: Academic, 1969), pp. 21-132.
    • (1969) Mammalian Protein Metabolism , pp. 21-132
    • Munro, H.1
  • 40
    • 0019296687 scopus 로고
    • A Simple Method for Estimating Evolutionary Rates of Base Substitutions through Comparative Studies of Nucleotide Sequences
    • "A Simple Method for Estimating Evolutionary Rates of Base Substitutions through Comparative Studies of Nucleotide Sequences,"Journal of Molecular Evolution, XVI (1980): 111-20.
    • (1980) Journal of Molecular Evolution , vol.16 , pp. 111-120
  • 41
    • 0003677357 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Molecular Evolution: Phylogenetic Approach
    • Maiden, MA: Blackwell
    • For a survey of the different models now on offer, see Roderic Page and Edward Holmes, Molecular Evolution: Phylogenetic Approach (Maiden, MA: Blackwell, 1998), pp. 148-62.
    • (1998) , pp. 148-162
    • Page, R.1    Holmes, E.2
  • 45
    • 0040511745 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Two Dogmas of Empiricism
    • "Two Dogmas of Empiricism," p. 43.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.