메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 110, Issue 2, 2001, Pages 151-197

Real realism: The galilean strategy

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 1842830148     PISSN: 00318108     EISSN: 15581470     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1215/00318108-110-2-151     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (113)

References (111)
  • 1
    • 0010739315 scopus 로고
    • Realism and instrumentalism in nineteenth century atomism
    • So, for example, a realist might adopt a different attitude towards the ψ function in the Schrödinger formulation of quantum mechanics and towards the molecules discussed in molecular genetics. Both Michael Gardner's
    • So, for example, a realist might adopt a different attitude towards the ψ function in the Schrödinger formulation of quantum mechanics and towards the molecules discussed in molecular genetics. Both Michael Gardner's "Realism and Instrumentalism in Nineteenth Century Atomism," Philosophy of Science 46 (1979): 1-34
    • (1979) Philosophy of Science , vol.46 , pp. 1-34
  • 2
    • 0038443276 scopus 로고
    • (Princeton: Princeton University Press, ) are admirably clear that realists campaign for a license, but that their uses of that license are sensitive to details of the scientific situation
    • and Richard Miller's Fact and Method (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1987) are admirably clear that realists campaign for a license, but that their uses of that license are sensitive to details of the scientific situation.
    • (1987) Fact and Method
    • Miller'S, R.1
  • 3
    • 0346495143 scopus 로고
    • Realism, approximate truth, and philosophical method
    • This terminology is due to ed. C. Wade Savage (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, )
    • This terminology is due to Richard Boyd (see, for example, "Realism, Approximate Truth, and Philosophical Method," in Scientific Theories, ed. C. Wade Savage (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1990), 355-91).
    • (1990) Scientific Theories , pp. 355-391
    • Boyd, R.1
  • 4
    • 0002785002 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Science made up
    • The term is well suited to some who articulate the second antirealist theme ( but not to others (Richard Rorty, Arthur Fine) who strenuously reject what they see as a bad metaphysics of "constructivism" Fine, ed. Peter Galison and David Stump (Stanford: Stanford University Press, ), But Boyd's term does mark an important distinction, and I'll employ it in this essay, subject to the caveat just noted
    • The term is well suited to some who articulate the second antirealist theme (for example, Hilary Putnam, Nelson Goodman, Thomas Kuhn) but not to others (Richard Rorty, Arthur Fine) who strenuously reject what they see as a bad metaphysics of "constructivism" (see, for example, Fine, "Science Made Up," in The Disunity of Science, ed. Peter Galison and David Stump (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1996), 231-54). But Boyd's term does mark an important distinction, and I'll employ it in this essay, subject to the caveat just noted.
    • (1996) The Disunity of Science , pp. 231-254
    • Putnam, H.1    Goodman, N.2    Kuhn, T.3
  • 5
    • 85184723298 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I don't mean to suggest that this common family of arguments exhausts the arsenal of antirealists. As I'll concede explicitly in section 9, further challenges remain. But I hope to address some lines of attack that have been influential, and to prepare the way for taking up those further challenges.
  • 6
    • 35148892343 scopus 로고
    • The natural ontological attitude
    • In fact, as many commentators have noted, Fine's own position is not entirely clear. At times he writes as though he were contributing to the empiricist/realist debate, for example, in many of the discussions that run through the first two sections of chapter 5 of (Chicago: University of Chicago Press)
    • In fact, as many commentators have noted, Fine's own position is not entirely clear. At times he writes as though he were contributing to the empiricist/realist debate, for example, in many of the discussions that run through the first two sections of 'The Natural Ontological Attitude" (chapter 5 of The Shaky Game (Chicago: University of Chicago Press), 1986).
    • (1986) The Shaky Game
  • 7
    • 35148892343 scopus 로고
    • The natural ontological attitude
    • The dominant trend of NOA, however, seems to be a democratic one. Matters are further complicated by occasional remarks in which Fine seems to concede that he thinks of truth in the familiar sense that a statement "is true just in case the entities referred to stand in the referred to relations (ibid., )
    • The dominant trend of NOA, however, seems to be a democratic one. Matters are further complicated by occasional remarks in which Fine seems to concede that he thinks of truth in the familiar sense that a statement "is true just in case the entities referred to stand in the referred to relations" (ibid., 130).
    • (1986) The Shaky Game , pp. 130
  • 8
    • 84960592445 scopus 로고
    • NOA's ark: Fine for realism
    • These inspire interpreters to welcome Fine as a realist Despite the insights and wit of Musgrave's essay, it seems to me that Fine isn't so easily assimilated, in part because of his reluctance to embrace the characteristically realist idea of reference as a relation between language and mind-independent objects. I'll explore this issue in detail below
    • These inspire interpreters to welcome Fine as a realist (see, for example, Alan Musgrave, "NOA's Ark: Fine for Realism," Philosophical Quarterly 39 (1989): 383-98). Despite the insights and wit of Musgrave's essay, it seems to me that Fine isn't so easily assimilated, in part because of his reluctance to embrace the characteristically realist idea of reference as a relation between language and mind-independent objects. I'll explore this issue in detail below.
    • (1989) Philosophical Quarterly , vol.39 , pp. 383-398
    • Musgrave, A.1
  • 9
    • 85184739797 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I owe to the editors of the Philosophical Review the suggestion that this is unnecessarily cautious and that the NEA can be traced to the ancients. That suggestion may well be correct. My hesitation is based on the possibility that attributing to ancient or medieval thinkers a concept of action-guiding representational states may be an anachronism.
  • 10
    • 0004181014 scopus 로고
    • Following Barbara von Eckardt's ecumenical survey, I take contemporary cognitive science to suppose that people have psychological states that both express content and are governed by computational rules ( (Cambridge: MIT Press, ), especially )
    • Following Barbara von Eckardt's ecumenical survey, I take contemporary cognitive science to suppose that people have psychological states that both express content and are governed by computational rules (see her What is Cognitive Science? (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1993), especially 191).
    • (1993) What Is Cognitive Science? , pp. 191
  • 11
    • 0004203638 scopus 로고
    • In some studies, notably those of Susan Carey ((Cambridge: MIT Press, ))
    • In some studies, notably those of Susan Carey (Conceptual Change in Childhood (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1985))
    • (1985) Conceptual Change in Childhood
  • 12
    • 84936526831 scopus 로고
    • ((Cambridge: MIT Press, )), the scientific discussion seems continuous with our everyday attributions of states and contents and our everyday understandings of semantic relations
    • and Frank Keil (Concepts, Kinds, and Conceptual Development (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1989)), the scientific discussion seems continuous with our everyday attributions of states and contents and our everyday understandings of semantic relations.
    • (1989) Concepts, Kinds, and Conceptual Development
    • Keil, F.1
  • 13
    • 0004208648 scopus 로고
    • Broader ventures in cognitive science-for example, those of ((Cambridge: Harvard University Press, ))-sometimes posit a wider variety of states, but retain connections between some of these states and the notions of folk psychology
    • Broader ventures in cognitive science-for example, those of John Anderson (The Architecture of Cognition (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1983))-sometimes posit a wider variety of states, but retain connections between some of these states and the notions of folk psychology.
    • (1983) The Architecture of Cognition
    • Anderson, J.1
  • 14
    • 0004286918 scopus 로고
    • There are, perhaps, some programs in cognitive science that appear at odds with folk concepts: see, for example, (Cambridge: MIT Press, )
    • There are, perhaps, some programs in cognitive science that appear at odds with folk concepts: see, for example, Ray Jackendoff's Languages of the Mind (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1992)
    • (1992) Languages of the Mind
    • Jackendoffs, R.1
  • 15
    • 0003578232 scopus 로고
    • (Stanford: Stanford University Press, ), but even in these instances, it seems to me that we can discern the kinds of states and semantic relations that my discussions presuppose. Nonetheless, it should be conceded that the degree to which cognitive science will preserve everyday idioms is currently controversial, and there are possible developments of the subject that could undermine both the claim of this sentence and the broader strategy of the essay
    • or Ronald Langacker's Foundations of Cognitive Grammar (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1987), but even in these instances, it seems to me that we can discern the kinds of states and semantic relations that my discussions presuppose. Nonetheless, it should be conceded that the degree to which cognitive science will preserve everyday idioms is currently controversial, and there are possible developments of the subject that could undermine both the claim of this sentence and the broader strategy of the essay.
    • (1987) Foundations of Cognitive Grammar
    • Langacker'S, R.1
  • 16
    • 85184720895 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • It's worth being explicit about the relation between real realism and NOA. As pointed out in note 4, one difference is that the realist thinks we can make sense of a notion of mind-independence and use it to develop a more substantive notion of truth than Fine would allow. Real realists also believe that Fine's "homely" argument for acquiescing in science is weak (on an uncharitable reading, the NOAer appears at least uncritical if not credulous) and that, in consequence, the brief for democracy fails. As we'll see, real realists agree that their views should be supported by "homely" considerations ('The Natural Ontological Attitude," 126) but believe that Fine has mislocated them.
  • 17
  • 18
    • 85011771170 scopus 로고
    • (Princeton: Princeton University Press, )
    • George Pitcher, A Theory of Perception (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1971)
    • (1971) A Theory of Perception
    • Pitcher, G.1
  • 20
    • 0003939914 scopus 로고
    • Tor the latter case, see (Indianopolis: Hackett, ), where the experiments of Paul Kolers are used in defense of constructivism
    • Tor the latter case, see Nelson Goodman, Ways of Worldmaking (Indianopolis: Hackett, 1978), where the experiments of Paul Kolers are used in defense of constructivism.
    • (1978) Ways of Worldmaking
    • Goodman, N.1
  • 21
    • 0003945869 scopus 로고
    • (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, )
    • See, for example, Thomas Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1962/1970), 206;
    • (1962) The Structure of Scientific Revolutions , pp. 206
    • Kuhn, T.1
  • 22
    • 0004235120 scopus 로고
    • (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, ), chaps. 1-3, esp
    • Hilary Putnam, Reason, Truth and History (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981), chaps. 1-3, esp. 49;
    • (1981) Reason, Truth and History , pp. 49
    • Putnam, H.1
  • 23
    • 0003919553 scopus 로고
    • (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, ), esp
    • Richard Rorty, Objectivity, Relativism, and Truth (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), esp. 6-7;
    • (1991) Objectivity, Relativism, and Truth , pp. 6-7
    • Rorty, R.1
  • 25
    • 85184674045 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Here I am again indebted to the editors
    • Here I am again indebted to the editors.
  • 26
    • 0041831785 scopus 로고
    • The assayer
    • See Stillman Drake, ed., (New York: Doubleday, )
    • Galileo Galilei, The Assayer. See Stillman Drake, ed., Discoveries and Opinions of Galileo (New York: Doubleday, 1957), 274.
    • (1957) Discoveries and Opinions of Galileo , pp. 274
  • 27
    • 85184676259 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • It's possible to argue that contemporary understanding of the neurophysiology of color perception reinforces the antirealist cause by undermining the reductivist project. But, as Peter Bradley and Michael Tye have shown, in currently unpublished work, the details of the neuroscience can be exploited to identify more subtie reflectance properties of surfaces, and thus to generate a more sophisticated reduction.
  • 28
    • 85184713588 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Perhaps another would be to concede the point for secondary qualities and argue that only primary qualities matter to science, a view popular with some historical figures. This reply seems to me weaker, both because it raises the possibility that analogues of the skeptical arguments might be generated against some of the primary qualities and because of the apparent role that secondary qualities play in some areas of science (for example, in evolutionary biology).
  • 29
    • 85184682230 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Of course, an immense amount of ink has been spilt on questions about the status of secondary qualities, from the early modern period to the present, and there are many versions of both strategies I mention here, as well as arguments for and against them. I believe, however, that both strategies remain promising.
  • 30
    • 0004192374 scopus 로고
    • For a similar assessment, (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, )
    • For a similar assessment, see Hilary Putnam, Renewing Philosophy (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1992), 91-97.
    • (1992) Renewing Philosophy , pp. 91-97
    • Putnam, H.1
  • 31
    • 0004482340 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Oxford: Oxford University Press, ), Barry Stroud shows with great subtlety how difficult it is to formulate and to resolve the questions in this area. I am much in sympathy with the treatment he offers, particularly with his clear dissection of the idea that early modern science "unmasked" everyday views of the reality of colors
    • In The Quest for Reality (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000), Barry Stroud shows with great subtlety how difficult it is to formulate and to resolve the questions in this area. I am much in sympathy with the treatment he offers, particularly with his clear dissection of the idea that early modern science "unmasked" everyday views of the reality of colors.
    • (2000) The Quest for Reality
  • 32
    • 0039373849 scopus 로고
    • Infinity and kant's conception of the 'possibility of experience
    • Our ability to represent continuity is notoriously tricky. Charles Parsons's classic essay
    • Our ability to represent continuity is notoriously tricky. See, for example, Charles Parsons's classic essay "Infinity and Kant's Conception of the 'Possibility of Experience'," Philosophical Review 73 (1964): 182-97.
    • (1964) Philosophical Review , vol.73 , pp. 182-197
  • 33
    • 85184739556 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • In the setting of contemporary science, quantum mechanics has been the main source of challenges to realism derived from the possibility of scientific corrections of our everyday picture of reality. Here too, I would claim, piecemeal realism need not fear the limited revision that may be required, but, in accordance with the general aims of this essay, I won't elaborate the point here.
  • 34
    • 85184692972 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As we shall see, this form of argument is very intricate. Versions of it appear in Goodman (Ways of Worldmaking) and Putnam (Reason, Truth and History)
    • As we shall see, this form of argument is very intricate. Versions of it appear in Goodman (Ways of Worldmaking) and Putnam (Reason, Truth and History).
  • 35
    • 85184670019 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Here I've given two variants on the same argument, one which has deep roots in the history of philosophy (proceeding via (4a)), and one that is more recent (proceeding via (4b)), surfacing in the writings of Kuhn and Laudan. I suspect that the argument via (4b) may articulate more fully the appeal to variation in belief that leads historians and historically-minded sociologists of science to oppose realism.
  • 36
    • 85184704316 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I cover some familiar territory here because it prepares the way for the general realist strategy that I'll advocate
    • I cover some familiar territory here because it prepares the way for the general realist strategy that I'll advocate.
  • 37
    • 0003890226 scopus 로고
    • They were particularly concerned to show that the principal theoretical developments of twentieth-century physics were intelligible (and, to a lesser extent, to defend the constructs of psychological theorizing). For a thorough charting of the history, see Frederick Suppe's introduction to (Urbana: University of Illinois Press, )
    • They were particularly concerned to show that the principal theoretical developments of twentieth-century physics were intelligible (and, to a lesser extent, to defend the constructs of psychological theorizing). For a thorough charting of the history, see Frederick Suppe's introduction to The Structure of Scientific Theories (Urbana: University of Illinois Press, 1977).
    • (1977) The Structure of Scientific Theories
  • 38
    • 85184722819 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Thus, a set E is an admissible extension for a theoretical predicate T just in case there's a model of the first-order formalization of the theory in which T occurs in which all observational terms receive their standard extensions and T is assigned E. A theoretical predicate is fully interpreted if it has a unique admissible extension, partially interpreted if it has more than one admissible extension. Two points in this formulation deserve note. First, it should be clear that this is a reconstruction of a notion of partial interpretation that evolved over two decades (from the late 1930s to the early 1960s). Second, there may be tacit acceptance of further restrictions on acceptable partial interpretations. Thus, it seems likely that the domain is restricted to mathematical entities and physical objects, and that there are conditions on the extension of theoretical predicates (for example, that an n-place predicate be assigned a set of n-tuples whose kth members are physical objects);
  • 39
    • 85184691228 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • it's already demanded explicitly, of course, that the extensions of the observational predicates be their usual ones
    • it's already demanded explicitly, of course, that the extensions of the observational predicates be their usual ones.
  • 40
    • 85184702447 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • So the normal form of a definition would specify a new predicate as equivalent to some predicate formed by conjoining and disjoining observational predicates
    • So the normal form of a definition would specify a new predicate as equivalent to some predicate formed by conjoining and disjoining observational predicates;
  • 41
    • 85184723557 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • unions and intersections of sets containing only observables will always contain only observables, so we seem to be able to support (SE3)
    • unions and intersections of sets containing only observables will always contain only observables, so we seem to be able to support (SE3);
  • 42
    • 85184730495 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • obviously, maintaining that all introduction of meaningful vocabulary must take this form is extremely restrictive
    • obviously, maintaining that all introduction of meaningful vocabulary must take this form is extremely restrictive.
  • 43
    • 0009121571 scopus 로고
    • What theories are not
    • The mistake was first pointed out by Putnam in a seminal essay, (reprinted in Putnam, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, ), )
    • The mistake was first pointed out by Putnam in a seminal essay, "What Theories Are Not" (reprinted in Putnam, Philosophical Papers, vol. 1 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1975), 215-27).
    • (1975) Philosophical Papers , vol.1 , pp. 215-227
  • 44
    • 0004251932 scopus 로고
    • Of course, there is a famous Wittgensteinian puzzle about how this is done: see (Oxford: Blackwell, )
    • Of course, there is a famous Wittgensteinian puzzle about how this is done: see Philosophical Investigations (Oxford: Blackwell, 1958), §§143-42
    • (1958) Philosophical Investigations , pp. 143-144
  • 46
    • 85184735694 scopus 로고
    • Saving the noumena and Semantic analogy
    • Without attempting to say how we do it, I shall assume that we are able to project from a Finite range of instances. Other Wittgensteinian concerns about the limits of our power to project have been raised by Sklar in (both reprinted in Sklar, (Berkeley: University of California Press, )
    • Without attempting to say how we do it, I shall assume that we are able to project from a Finite range of instances. Other Wittgensteinian concerns about the limits of our power to project have been raised by Sklar in "Saving the Noumena" and "Semantic Analogy" (both reprinted in Sklar, Philosophy and Space-Time Physics (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1985).
    • (1985) Philosophy and Space-Time Physics
  • 47
    • 85184684099 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The example is Putnam's, in
    • The example is Putnam's, in "What Theories Are Not."
    • What Theories Are Not
  • 48
    • 85184735791 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Both arguments have a long pedigree and both are prominent in contemporary discussions of realism. Version A, revived by van Fraassen, is akin to considerations that Mach urged against realist interpretations of atomic chemistry (even though, as noted, van Fraassen repudiates Mach's views about perception);
  • 49
    • 0003895988 scopus 로고
    • version B, which seems to underlie some of Laudan's writings, recapitulates themes of Poincaré. It should be noted, however, that Laudan might not view his argument as making any contribution to empiricism. He describes his position as "pragmatist" (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, ), and there are reasons to think he would question the distinction between claims about observables and claims about unobservables that empiricists deploy
    • version B, which seems to underlie some of Laudan's writings, recapitulates themes of Poincaré. It should be noted, however, that Laudan might not view his argument as making any contribution to empiricism. He describes his position as "pragmatist" see Science and Relativism (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1990), and there are reasons to think he would question the distinction between claims about observables and claims about unobservables that empiricists deploy.
    • (1990) Science and Relativism
  • 50
    • 85184713743 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This idea-the "ultimate argument" for realism-became popular in the 1970s, largely because of the formulations of J. J. C. Smart, Putnam, and Boyd. It has deep historical roots. Descartes, for example, defended parts of his physics on the grounds that his successes would be incomprehensible unless his theoretical hypotheses were right.
  • 51
    • 0002270896 scopus 로고
    • A confutation of convergent realism
    • The latter challenge is formulated by Laudan (). It seems to me that the challenge can be deepened by placing it in the context of the first question, since a liberal criterion of "success" would expand the range of relevant historical examples. The discussion that follows extends the response to Laudan begun in The Advancement of Science
    • The latter challenge is formulated by Laudan ("A Confutation of Convergent Realism," Philosophy of Science 48 (1981): 19-48). It seems to me that the challenge can be deepened by placing it in the context of the first question, since a liberal criterion of "success" would expand the range of relevant historical examples. The discussion that follows extends the response to Laudan begun in The Advancement of Science.
    • (1981) Philosophy of Science , vol.48 , pp. 19-48
  • 52
    • 85184689938 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • In both instances these formulations are not entirely precise. The first is intended to allow for "predictions about the past," for example, paleontological statements that identify the likely whereabouts of as yet undiscovered fossils. The second is vague about how complete the instructions have to be (it would be folly to insist that they specify a mechanical procedure, for example) . Attending to the niceties of precise formulations would divert us from the main points of the present discussion.
  • 53
    • 85184669827 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Laudan provides a long list in "A Confutation of Convergent Realism." His list includes such things as the humoral theory of medicine, catastrophist geology, and theories of spontaneous generation. In none of these examples does it seem right to hail the theory as successful or to judge that the proponents of the theory were justified in holding it to be successful. Other doctrines on his list are more intractable.
  • 54
    • 85184738695 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Fresnel submitted a memoir presenting his theory in a prize competition sponsored by the French Academy of Sciences. One of the jurors, Poisson, a proponent of the corpuscular theory of light, recognized that Fresnel's principles implied that there would be a bright spot at the center of the shadow of a small, rotating disk, thinking that this would provide a reductio of the theory. Another juror, Arago, performed an experiment to check, and discovered the bright spot. It is a nice irony that it is named for Poisson, who had been so confident that it did not exist.
  • 55
    • 84979422873 scopus 로고
    • Structural realism: The best of both worlds
    • This proposal is lucidly elaborated by As Worrall notes, the position develops insights of Poincaré
    • This proposal is lucidly elaborated by John Worrall ("Structural Realism: The Best of Both Worlds?" Dialectica 43 (1989): 99-124). As Worrall notes, the position develops insights of Poincaré.
    • (1989) Dialectica , vol.43 , pp. 99-124
    • Worrall, J.1
  • 56
    • 84925914694 scopus 로고
    • Theories, theorists, and theoretical change
    • This approach depends on developing ideas about reference originally formulated by For details
    • This approach depends on developing ideas about reference originally formulated by Putnam, Saul Kripke, and Keith Donnellan. For details, see my 'Theories, Theorists, and Theoretical Change," Philosophical Review 87 (1978): 519-47.
    • (1978) Philosophical Review , vol.87 , pp. 519-547
    • Putnam, S.K.1    Donnellan, K.2
  • 57
    • 85184730034 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I defend this interpretation in chapter 5 of see, in particular
    • I defend this interpretation in chapter 5 of The Advancement of Science, see, in particular, 145-48.
    • The Advancement of Science , pp. 145-148
  • 58
    • 85184690787 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I suspect that scientific efforts to draw the distinction are relatively rare, primarily because scientists are more interested in extending theory and devising experiments than they are concerned with its "foundations."
  • 59
    • 84965073043 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I fell into this trap in I am grateful to several reviewers (especially Jarrett Leplin, Carl Matheson, and Richard Miller) who pointed out the mistake
    • I fell into this trap in The Advancement of Science. I am grateful to several reviewers (especially Jarrett Leplin, Carl Matheson, and Richard Miller) who pointed out the mistake.
    • The Advancement of Science
  • 60
    • 0002087289 scopus 로고
    • Realism, underdetermination, and the causal theory of evidence
    • This strategy has been pursued most vigorously by in a series of articles, beginning with Boyd has seen very clearly that realists must avoid the trap of taking realism to be the default position and simply clearing away objections of the kind leveled in variation B
    • This strategy has been pursued most vigorously by Richard Boyd in a series of articles, beginning with "Realism, Underdetermination, and the Causal Theory of Evidence," Noûs 7 (1973): 1-12). Boyd has seen very clearly that realists must avoid the trap of taking realism to be the default position and simply clearing away objections of the kind leveled in variation B.
    • (1973) Noûs , vol.7 , pp. 1-12
    • Boyd, R.1
  • 61
    • 85184721846 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The most prominent example for developing the transcendental strategy starts from Goodman's new riddle of induction, claiming that justified views about what predicates (or classes) are projectible must advert to hypotheses about underlying mechanisms. So, for example, geologists might legitimately project a claim about certain minerals because they believe that the minerals in question share a common microstructure that gives rise to their observable properties. Without this background belief, they would not be warranted in taking the predicates they employ to be projectible, and thus would have no justification for the commonplace types of induction that empiricists accept. For development of points like this, see Boyd "Realism, Approximate Truth, and Philosophical Method."
  • 62
    • 85184686300 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • One obvious worry is that antirealists will be able to advance some other account of the justifiability of such things as projectibility judgments-as for example in Goodman's own suggestion that projectibility is measured by entrenchment (see the final chapter of Fact, Fiction, and Forecast).
  • 63
    • 77950039721 scopus 로고
    • Testing for convergent realism
    • Something like the Galilean strategy figures in Richard Miller's defense of realism (Fact and Method). It's also prefigured in Jerrold Aronson's arguments for realism
    • Something like the Galilean strategy figures in Richard Miller's defense of realism (Fact and Method). It's also prefigured in Jerrold Aronson's arguments for realism (see 'Testing for Convergent Realism," British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 40 (1989): 255-59
    • (1989) British Journal for the Philosophy of Science , vol.40 , pp. 255-259
  • 64
    • 0004109639 scopus 로고
    • (London: Duckworth, )
    • and Realism Rescued (London: Duckworth, 1994), 194-96.
    • (1994) Realism Rescued , pp. 194-196
  • 65
    • 0003711960 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I don't pretend that all realists are either transcendentalists or Galileans. Jarrett Leplin's recent brief for realism I don't pretend that all realists are either transcendentalists or Galileans. Jarrett Leplin's recent brief for realism ((Oxford: Oxford University Press, )) urges that a realist view of science is supported because of the ability of theories to generate novel evidence. Unfortunately, Leplin's notion of novelty appears flawed. He proposes that the novelty of evidence isn't a psychological matter, depending on what the proposer of the theory thought of in coming to believe it
    • I don't pretend that all realists are either transcendentalists or Galileans. Jarrett Leplin's recent brief for realism (A Novel Defense of Scientific Realism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998)) urges that a realist view of science is supported because of the ability of theories to generate novel evidence. Unfortunately, Leplin's notion of novelty appears flawed. He proposes that the novelty of evidence isn't a psychological matter, depending on what the proposer of the theory thought of in coming to believe it;
    • (1998) A Novel Defense of Scientific Realism
  • 66
    • 85184687562 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • rather E*is novel evidence for T only if T already had an episte mological basis E that doesn't include E*. Yet if there's an epistemological basis for the theory of any kind it appears either that realists have exactly what they want-to wit, evidence for believing that the theory is true, or that the epistemological basis only allows for acceptance of the theory as empirically adequate. If the former, then the question has been begged against the anti-realist;
  • 67
    • 85184678930 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • if the latter, then Leplin needs to explain why an extra scrap of evidence beyond that required for acceptance as empirically adequate does more than simply increase the degree of rational confidence that the theory is empirically adequate.
  • 69
    • 77950052370 scopus 로고
    • van Helden, ed., (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, ). As a number of historians have made very clear, Horky's fervent opposition to Galileo was viewed by his contemporaries as dishonest
    • and van Helden, ed., Galileo's Siderius Nuncius (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1989). As a number of historians have made very clear, Horky's fervent opposition to Galileo was viewed by his contemporaries as dishonest.
    • (1989) Galileo's Siderius Nuncius
  • 70
    • 0004104658 scopus 로고
    • One can appreciate the importance of this line of reasoning in making Galileo's case by noting that, twenty years later, in his summary of the evidence for Copernicanism, he devotes much of the third day of the (Berkeley: University of California Press, ) to showing why the novelties are genuinely "beyond the moon," in the process crafting a sophisticated incipient theory of error
    • One can appreciate the importance of this line of reasoning in making Galileo's case by noting that, twenty years later, in his summary of the evidence for Copernicanism, he devotes much of the third day of the Dialogue Concerning the Two Great World Systems (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1967) to showing why the novelties are genuinely "beyond the moon," in the process crafting a sophisticated incipient theory of error.
    • (1967) Dialogue Concerning the Two Great World Systems
  • 71
    • 85184699131 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The telescope was accepted remarkably quickly. Virtually all scholars admitted its reliability by 1615. Some of the early opposition was based on the difficulties of using telescopes, which yielded inconsistent results that could be exploited by Horky and others. Galileo worked both to improve the instruments and to offer guidance for their use, so that, within a year of the initial development, the major inconsistencies were resolved. (For valuable studies of the telescope and its validation, see the writings of van Helden.)
  • 72
    • 84873383565 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Putnam's important insight recalls M. Jourdain: we had been talking about unobservables all along. In an important respect, the Galilean strategy is thoroughly Wittgensteinian, recommending that one should "bring words back from their metaphysical to their everyday use" ()
    • Putnam's important insight recalls M. Jourdain: we had been talking about unobservables all along. In an important respect, the Galilean strategy is thoroughly Wittgensteinian, recommending that one should "bring words back from their metaphysical to their everyday use" (Philosophical Investigations, §116).
    • Philosophical Investigations , pp. 116
  • 73
    • 85184691026 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • As we shall see, this is the basis on which to respond to the Fine-Rorty charge that realist theorizing about the sciences involves tacking on dubious metaphysical assumptions, and it is also the source of pertinent concerns about realism, to wit, that realists try to extend the everyday usage into areas in which the enabling conditions of the "everyday uses" do not apply; see section 9.
  • 74
    • 85184725110 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • It's possible that an epistemological empiricist might object that I've mis-described the situation. Galileo didn't show that conclusions about unobservables could be justified through use of telescopes. Instead he changed the boundaries of the observable. But to make this response would undermine the empiricist strategy. For the notion of the observable has now been detached from the connection with unaided observation, and must now come to something like "detectable with a reliable instrument." Realists can sympathize with that notion of observability, formulating their views as claims about the reliability of particular detection devices. If those claims are to be debated by the epistemological empiricist by anything like the line of reasoning we're considering, then the empiricist will have to rely on a more basic level of observability to serve as the ultimate standard of validation. The Galilean achievement will then be seen in terms of justifying conclusions about entities that are unobservable according to this more basic conception.
  • 75
    • 0004113842 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The latter version is suggested by discussion of related forms of inference, especially in his example of the mice in the wainscoting
    • The latter version is suggested by van Fraassen's discussion of related forms of inference, especially in his example of the mice in the wainscoting. See The Scientific Image, 19-21.
    • The Scientific Image , pp. 19-21
    • Fraassen'S, V.1
  • 76
    • 85184718523 scopus 로고
    • The scientific image
    • Epistemological modesty is eloquently defended by (chap. 2). Thomas Nagel makes a criticism similar to mine in (Oxford: Oxford University Press, )
    • Epistemological modesty is eloquently defended by van Fraassen (The Scientific Image, chap. 2). Thomas Nagel makes a criticism similar to mine in The View From Nowhere (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1986), 92.
    • (1986) The View from Nowhere , pp. 92
    • Fraassen, V.1
  • 77
    • 0039272557 scopus 로고
    • The ontological status of theoretical entities
    • The point was beautifully made by ((Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, ), )
    • The point was beautifully made by Grover Maxwell in ('The Ontological Status of Theoretical Entities," Minnesota Studies in the Phibsophy of Science, vol. 3 (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1962), 3-27).
    • (1962) Minnesota Studies in the Phibsophy of Science , vol.3 , pp. 3-27
    • Maxwell, G.1
  • 78
    • 0004113842 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • responds to one version of Maxwell's challenge ()
    • Van Fraassen responds to one version of Maxwell's challenge (The Scientific Image, 13-19);
    • The Scientific Image , pp. 13-19
    • Fraassen, V.1
  • 79
    • 85184671018 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • here I'm advocating another
    • here I'm advocating another.
  • 80
    • 0000477047 scopus 로고
    • Explanatory unification
    • My gloss on systematicity here is hardly precise. For an attempt to do somewhat better, see my
    • My gloss on systematicity here is hardly precise. For an attempt to do somewhat better, see my "Explanatory Unification," Philosophy of Science 48 (1981): 507-31.
    • (1981) Philosophy of Science , vol.48 , pp. 507-531
  • 81
    • 85184692364 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • There's irony here in that the reply to Semantic Empiricism built on insights of Putnam, who is one of the primary sources of the Semantic Constructivist argument
    • There's irony here in that the reply to Semantic Empiricism built on insights of Putnam, who is one of the primary sources of the Semantic Constructivist argument.
  • 82
    • 84880522337 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It's worth noting at this point that I am relying on a common way of replying to a notorious argument of Berkeley's to the effect that we cannot conceive of an object existing unperceived. As many commentators have pointed out, Berkeley's mistake is to suppose that when we think about something, we must include ourselves "in the picture" ( ). Similarly, I suppose that we can contemplate the possibility of physical objects existing without supposing that we have to be observers, parts of the imagined scene
    • It's worth noting at this point that I am relying on a common way of replying to a notorious argument of Berkeley's to the effect that we cannot conceive of an object existing unperceived. As many commentators have pointed out, Berkeley's mistake is to suppose that when we think about something, we must include ourselves "in the picture" (see, for example, Principles of Human Knowledge, §23). Similarly, I suppose that we can contemplate the possibility of physical objects existing without supposing that we have to be observers, parts of the imagined scene.
    • Principles of Human Knowledge , pp. 23
  • 83
    • 0004053964 scopus 로고
    • Forceful presentations of the point have been offered by Alvin Goldman ((Cambridge: Harvard University Press, ), chap. 7)
    • Forceful presentations of the point have been offered by Alvin Goldman (Epistemology and Cognition (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1986), chap. 7)
    • (1986) Epistemology and Cognition
  • 85
    • 85184736816 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see, in particular, 53-54 of Musgrave's essay
    • see, in particular, 53-54 of Musgrave's essay.
  • 86
    • 85184739762 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • As we saw in section 3, realists ought to avoid the notorious "veil of perception" doctrine, according to which we perceive objects indirecly by perceiving sensa directly; the right thing to say is that we perceive the objects by being in (or "having") certain kinds of sensory states. The constructivist advocacy of (SC4) to accuse realists of engaging in metaphysics thus needs the kind of Austinian therapy I try to offer here.
  • 87
    • 85184722896 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This is how Putnam's celebrated arguments get started (see "Models and Reality," and the early chapters of Reason, Truth and History). Putnam proves a much stronger result than the standard conclusion that one can satisfy a set of sentences by permuting elements in the domain of the model; his construction reveals how the permutation can preserve the ways in which the truth values of sentences vary as the state of the world changes.
  • 88
    • 0004199040 scopus 로고
    • In responding to those, like ((Princeton: Princeton University Press, )), who would insist on causal constraints on the assignment of referents, Putnam argues that the alleged causal constraints are just more sentences to be held true and thus fall under his permutation argument (Reason, Truth and History, chap. 2)
    • In responding to those, like Michael Devitt (Realism and Truth (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1984)), who would insist on causal constraints on the assignment of referents, Putnam argues that the alleged causal constraints are just more sentences to be held true and thus fall under his permutation argument (Reason, Truth and History, chap. 2).
    • (1984) Realism and Truth
    • Devitt, M.1
  • 89
    • 85184721818 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • It should be noted that emphasizing the causal relations between the objects and the subject makes it look as though her language could be meaningful even in the absence of others, thus flouting the Private Language Argument (Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, §§258ff.). But there's no need for realists to quarrel with this argument. The causal relations that fix meaning and reference can be taken to include relations among speakers. For the realist's purposes, the important point is not whether the causal constraints are so inclusive or whether they fix the referents for a group of speakers, but rather that they hold independently of the imaginary observer.
  • 90
    • 85184718402 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This part of the argument appeals to a point about causal explanation that goes back to Collingwood, a point that Putnam revives in his discussions (). It can be presented as the thought that attributions of causation always make selections from the complete set of causal antecedents and that the selection depends on our interests
    • This part of the argument appeals to a point about causal explanation that goes back to Collingwood, a point that Putnam revives in his discussions (Reason, Truth and History, 51). It can be presented as the thought that attributions of causation always make selections from the complete set of causal antecedents and that the selection depends on our interests.
    • Reason, Truth and History , pp. 51
  • 91
    • 85184727410 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dealing completely with all five objections would require a book or a series of essays. But I shall hope to say enough to demonstrate that realists have resources for answering the criticisms
    • Dealing completely with all five objections would require a book or a series of essays. But I shall hope to say enough to demonstrate that realists have resources for answering the criticisms.
  • 92
    • 0003799915 scopus 로고
    • (Cambridge: MIT Press, ), chapter 2
    • See Word and Object (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1960), chapter 2.
    • (1960) Word and Object
  • 93
    • 85184702410 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I am grateful to an anonymous referee for raising this worry
    • I am grateful to an anonymous referee for raising this worry.
  • 94
    • 33748797359 scopus 로고
    • Sets and semantics
    • See Jonathan Lear "Sets and Semantics," Journal of Philosophy 74 (1977): 86-102;
    • (1977) Journal of Philosophy , vol.74 , pp. 86-102
    • Lear, J.1
  • 95
    • 0009129250 scopus 로고
    • Mathematical truth
    • Lear applies Paul Benacerraf s famous dilemma about mathematical truth and knowledge to the case of the reference of mathematical terms ( )
    • Lear applies Paul Benacerraf s famous dilemma about mathematical truth and knowledge to the case of the reference of mathematical terms (see Benacerraf, "Mathematical Truth, "Journal of Philosophy 70 (1973): 661-79).
    • (1973) Journal of Philosophy , vol.70 , pp. 661-679
    • Benacerraf1
  • 96
    • 0004032206 scopus 로고
    • Of course, those who hope for a fully naturalistic account of reference must either assume that mathematical terms are in principle dispensable or else come to terms with a more refined version of the semantic problem. My tentative preference would be to account for the terms of elementary arithmetic and geometry along the lines proposed in (New York: Oxford University Press, ) although I would now adopt a fictionalist (Hilbertian) strategy for the higher reaches of mathematics
    • Of course, those who hope for a fully naturalistic account of reference must either assume that mathematical terms are in principle dispensable or else come to terms with a more refined version of the semantic problem. My tentative preference would be to account for the terms of elementary arithmetic and geometry along the lines proposed in The Nature of Mathematical Knowledge (New York: Oxford University Press, 1983) although I would now adopt a fictionalist (Hilbertian) strategy for the higher reaches of mathematics.
    • (1983) The Nature of Mathematical Knowledge
  • 97
    • 85184732546 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a forceful presentation of such worries, see Sklar, "Semantic Analogy," where the point is directed at the proposals made by Putnam ("What Theories Are Not")
    • For a forceful presentation of such worries, see Sklar, "Semantic Analogy," where the point is directed at the proposals made by Putnam ("What Theories Are Not").
  • 98
    • 85184730120 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 2d ed. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, ), and chapter 3
    • See Paul Horwich, Truth, 2d ed. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999), 22-23 and chapter 3.
    • (1999) Truth , pp. 22-23
    • Horwich, P.1
  • 99
    • 25444486890 scopus 로고
    • Do we (Epistemologists) need a theory of truth
    • Other important articulations of the position are provided by
    • Other important articulations of the position are provided by Michael Williams, "Do We (Epistemologists) Need a Theory of Truth?" Philosophical Topics 14 (1986): 223-42
    • (1986) Philosophical Topics , vol.14 , pp. 223-242
    • Williams, M.1
  • 100
    • 85164851046 scopus 로고
    • What kind of explanation is truth
    • ed. J. Leplin (Berkeley: University of California Press, )
    • and by Michael Levin, "What Kind of Explanation is Truth?" in Scientific Realism, ed. J. Leplin (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1984), 124-39.
    • (1984) Scientific Realism , pp. 124-139
    • Levin, M.1
  • 101
    • 0011570095 scopus 로고
    • Tarski's theory of truth
    • Here I should note explicidy that the type of correspondence theory I envisage is one like that originally sketched by One important difference, however, is that I don't see a naturalistic account of reference as necessarily involving a reduction to a physicalist vocabulary. Naturalists who are antireductionists with respect to some sciences (for example, parts of biology) should allow that the basis for a reduction of the notion of reference may outstrip the resources of physics
    • Here I should note explicidy that the type of correspondence theory I envisage is one like that originally sketched by Hartry Field in "Tarski's Theory of Truth, "Journal of Philosophy 69 (1972): 347-75. One important difference, however, is that I don't see a naturalistic account of reference as necessarily involving a reduction to a physicalist vocabulary. Naturalists who are antireductionists with respect to some sciences (for example, parts of biology) should allow that the basis for a reduction of the notion of reference may outstrip the resources of physics.
    • (1972) Journal of Philosophy , vol.69 , pp. 347-375
    • Field, H.1
  • 102
    • 24944559601 scopus 로고
    • A critique of deflationism
    • The line of response I have offered is akin to that proposed by , in particular note 30. I elaborate it in greater detail in "On The Explanatory Power of Correspondence Truth," forthcoming in Philosophy and Phenomenological Research
    • The line of response I have offered is akin to that proposed by Anil Gupta, "A Critique of Deflationism," Philosophical Topics 21 (1993): 57-81, in particular note 30. I elaborate it in greater detail in "On The Explanatory Power of Correspondence Truth," forthcoming in Philosophy and Phenomenological Research.
    • (1993) Philosophical Topics , vol.21 , pp. 57-81
    • Gupta, A.1
  • 103
    • 85184689177 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This is doubly mistaken, for there is an important difference between Quinean underdetermination (roughly, cases in which rival theories are supposed to receive exactly the same support from the same body of evidence) and Kuhnian underdetermination (roughly, cases in which rival theories are successful in rather different ways). In the text, I suggest that Quinean underdetermination has varying force in different areas of science. I have tried to address issues of Kuhnian underdetermination in chapter 7 of The Advancement of Science.
  • 104
    • 85184727766 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • In part, the bogey of underdetermination may stem from the view that scientific theories are readily formalized and that the formalization will automatically lead to ways of constructing serious alternatives. My quick appeal to a central doctrine within molecular biology is intended to reduce confidence in this view. I have attempted to address issues about underdetermination more thoroughly (but probably still not thoroughly enough) in Science, Truth, and Democracy (New York: Oxford University Press, forthcoming).
  • 105
    • 85184699121 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Rorty (Consequences of Pragmatism, xxvi) suggests that realists are committed to strong theses about the objective divisions of the natural world. Both Goodman (Ways of World-making) and Putnam (Reason, Truth, and History, 49) seem to agree.
  • 106
    • 84872896578 scopus 로고
    • Truth and convention
    • So it seems to me that real realism can simply dodge Putnam's challenge to specify just how many objects there are in a particular (toy) world containing three individuals (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, )
    • So it seems to me that real realism can simply dodge Putnam's challenge to specify just how many objects there are in a particular (toy) world containing three individuals (see his "Truth and Convention," in Realism with a Human Face (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1994);
    • (1994) Realism with A Human Face
  • 107
    • 85184739608 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • the challenge turns on whether we are to count mereological sums
    • the challenge turns on whether we are to count mereological sums.
  • 108
    • 85184723022 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Here real realism diverges from stronger doctrines held by some realists (for example Richard Boyd and Michael Devitt) and from my own earlier self (as in chapter 4 of The Advancement of Science). An advantage of the Boyd- Devitt commitment to objective natural kinds may lie in facilitating the development of a detailed account of reference (see the earlier discussion in this section).
  • 109
    • 0007287157 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Refining the causal theory of reference for natural kind terms
    • For an approach that seeks a causal account without any such commitment
    • For an approach that seeks a causal account without any such commitment, see P. Kyle Stanford and Philip Kitcher, "Refining the Causal Theory of Reference for Natural Kind Terms," Philosophical Studies 97 (2000): 99-129.
    • (2000) Philosophical Studies , vol.97 , pp. 99-129
    • Kyle Stanford, P.1    Kitcher, P.2
  • 110
    • 0003524188 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Real realism is, I take it, strictly between NOA and Putnam's metaphysical realism. It is also quite distinct from Putnam's internal realism. Ernesto Garcia has, however, suggested to me that it may be consonant with views expressed in Putnam's recent work, particularly the return to Austin begun in (Columbia University Press, )
    • Real realism is, I take it, strictly between NOA and Putnam's metaphysical realism. It is also quite distinct from Putnam's internal realism. Ernesto Garcia has, however, suggested to me that it may be consonant with views expressed in Putnam's recent work, particularly the return to Austin begun in The Threefold Cord: Mind, Body, and World (Columbia University Press, 1999).
    • (1999) The Threefold Cord: Mind, Body, and World
  • 111
    • 85184721986 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • That seems to me a possibility worth exploring, but the exploration must await another occasion
    • That seems to me a possibility worth exploring, but the exploration must await another occasion.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.