메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 21, Issue 2, 2000, Pages 249-307

Ancients, moderns and Americans: The republicanism-liberalism debate revisited

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0347603128     PISSN: 0143781X     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: None     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (32)

References (262)
  • 1
    • 84963041652 scopus 로고
    • Republicanism: The Career of a Concept
    • Antipathy for the republicanism-liberalism debate has grown throughout the 1990s. Daniel Rodgers' important article 'Republicanism: The Career of a Concept', The Journal of American History, 79 (1992), pp. 11-38, reads like an obituary for the concept of republicanism and the republicanism-liberalism debate. See also the comments by Drew McCoy in 'Introduction', The Republican Synthesis Revisited: Essays in Honor of George Athan Bilias, ed. Milton M. Klein, Richard D. Brown and John B. Hench (Worcester, MA, 1992), p. 12; and Rogen Kersh, 'The Founding: Liberalism Redux Review of The Foundations of American Citizenship: Liberalism, the Constitution, and Civic Virtue by Richard Sinopoli', The Review of Politics, 55 (1993), p. 729.
    • (1992) The Journal of American History , vol.79 , pp. 11-38
  • 2
    • 84963041652 scopus 로고
    • Introduction
    • ed. Milton M. Klein, Richard D. Brown and John B. Hench Worcester, MA
    • Antipathy for the republicanism-liberalism debate has grown throughout the 1990s. Daniel Rodgers' important article 'Republicanism: The Career of a Concept', The Journal of American History, 79 (1992), pp. 11-38, reads like an obituary for the concept of republicanism and the republicanism-liberalism debate. See also the comments by Drew McCoy in 'Introduction', The Republican Synthesis Revisited: Essays in Honor of George Athan Bilias, ed. Milton M. Klein, Richard D. Brown and John B. Hench (Worcester, MA, 1992), p. 12; and Rogen Kersh, 'The Founding: Liberalism Redux Review of The Foundations of American Citizenship: Liberalism, the Constitution, and Civic Virtue by Richard Sinopoli', The Review of Politics, 55 (1993), p. 729.
    • (1992) The Republican Synthesis Revisited: Essays in Honor of George Athan Bilias , pp. 12
    • McCoy, D.1
  • 3
    • 84963041652 scopus 로고
    • The Founding: Liberalism Redux Review of the Foundations of American Citizenship: Liberalism, the Constitution, and Civic Virtue by Richard Sinopoli
    • Antipathy for the republicanism-liberalism debate has grown throughout the 1990s. Daniel Rodgers' important article 'Republicanism: The Career of a Concept', The Journal of American History, 79 (1992), pp. 11-38, reads like an obituary for the concept of republicanism and the republicanism-liberalism debate. See also the comments by Drew McCoy in 'Introduction', The Republican Synthesis Revisited: Essays in Honor of George Athan Bilias, ed. Milton M. Klein, Richard D. Brown and John B. Hench (Worcester, MA, 1992), p. 12; and Rogen Kersh, 'The Founding: Liberalism Redux Review of The Foundations of American Citizenship: Liberalism, the Constitution, and Civic Virtue by Richard Sinopoli', The Review of Politics, 55 (1993), p. 729.
    • (1993) The Review of Politics , vol.55 , pp. 729
    • Kersh, R.1
  • 5
    • 0347515446 scopus 로고
    • Liberal Republicans or Republican Liberals?: The Political Thought of the Founders Reconsidered
    • th Century England and America (Ithaca, NY, 1990); I. Kramnick, 'Communications', The William and Mary Quarterly, 45 (1988), p. 818; Forrest McDonald, Novus Ordo Seclorum: The Intellectual Origins of the Constitution (Lawrence, KS, 1985); F. McDonald, 'The Intellectual World of the Founding Fathers', in Requiem: Variations on Eighteenth-Century Themes, ed. Forrest McDonald and Ellen Shapiro McDonald (Lawrence, KS, 1988), p. 9; John Murrin, 'Fundamental Values, the Founding Fathers, and the Constitution', in To Form a More Perfect Union: The Critical Ideas of the Constitution, ed. Herman Belz, Ronald Hoffman and Peter J. Albert (Charlottesville, VA, 1992), pp. 11-25; J.G.A. Pocock, 'Communications', The William and Mary Quarterly, 45 (1988), p. 817; Cass Sunstein, 'Beyond the Republican Revival', The Yale Law Journal, 97 (1988), pp. 1539-90; Mark Tushnet, Red, White, and Blue: A Critical Analysis of Constitutional Law (Cambridge, 1988), pp. 4-5; Gordon S. Wood, 'Afterword', in The Republican Synthesis Revisited, ed. Klein et al., pp. 143-51. For discussions of the movement within scholarship on the Founding to paradigmatic pluralism see Peter S. Onuf, 'Reflections on the Founding: Constitutional Historiography in Bicentennial Perspective', The William and Mary Quarterly, 46 (1989), pp. 341-75; Rodgers, 'Republicanism: The Career of a Concept', pp. 35-7.
    • (1993) Reviews in American History , vol.21 , pp. 29-30
    • Cornell, S.1
  • 6
    • 0003418397 scopus 로고
    • Durham, NC
    • th Century England and America (Ithaca, NY, 1990); I. Kramnick, 'Communications', The William and Mary Quarterly, 45 (1988), p. 818; Forrest McDonald, Novus Ordo Seclorum: The Intellectual Origins of the Constitution (Lawrence, KS, 1985); F. McDonald, 'The Intellectual World of the Founding Fathers', in Requiem: Variations on Eighteenth-Century Themes, ed. Forrest McDonald and Ellen Shapiro McDonald (Lawrence, KS, 1988), p. 9; John Murrin, 'Fundamental Values, the Founding Fathers, and the Constitution', in To Form a More Perfect Union: The Critical Ideas of the Constitution, ed. Herman Belz, Ronald Hoffman and Peter J. Albert (Charlottesville, VA, 1992), pp. 11-25; J.G.A. Pocock, 'Communications', The William and Mary Quarterly, 45 (1988), p. 817; Cass Sunstein, 'Beyond the Republican Revival', The Yale Law Journal, 97 (1988), pp. 1539-90; Mark Tushnet, Red, White, and Blue: A Critical Analysis of Constitutional Law (Cambridge, 1988), pp. 4-5; Gordon S. Wood, 'Afterword', in The Republican Synthesis Revisited, ed. Klein et al., pp. 143-51. For discussions of the movement within scholarship on the Founding to paradigmatic pluralism see Peter S. Onuf, 'Reflections on the Founding: Constitutional Historiography in Bicentennial Perspective', The William and Mary Quarterly, 46 (1989), pp. 341-75; Rodgers, 'Republicanism: The Career of a Concept', pp. 35-7.
    • (1990) The Unvarnished Doctrine: Locke, Liberalism, and the American Revolution , pp. 37-38
    • Dworetz, S.1
  • 7
    • 0039926632 scopus 로고
    • Republicanism and Liberalism in American Constitutional Thought
    • th Century England and America (Ithaca, NY, 1990); I. Kramnick, 'Communications', The William and Mary Quarterly, 45 (1988), p. 818; Forrest McDonald, Novus Ordo Seclorum: The Intellectual Origins of the Constitution (Lawrence, KS, 1985); F. McDonald, 'The Intellectual World of the Founding Fathers', in Requiem: Variations on Eighteenth-Century Themes, ed. Forrest McDonald and Ellen Shapiro McDonald (Lawrence, KS, 1988), p. 9; John Murrin, 'Fundamental Values, the Founding Fathers, and the Constitution', in To Form a More Perfect Union: The Critical Ideas of the Constitution, ed. Herman Belz, Ronald Hoffman and Peter J. Albert (Charlottesville, VA, 1992), pp. 11-25; J.G.A. Pocock, 'Communications', The William and Mary Quarterly, 45 (1988), p. 817; Cass Sunstein, 'Beyond the Republican Revival', The Yale Law Journal, 97 (1988), pp. 1539-90; Mark Tushnet, Red, White, and Blue: A Critical Analysis of Constitutional Law (Cambridge, 1988), pp. 4-5; Gordon S. Wood, 'Afterword', in The Republican Synthesis Revisited, ed. Klein et al., pp. 143-51. For discussions of the movement within scholarship on the Founding to paradigmatic pluralism see Peter S. Onuf, 'Reflections on the Founding: Constitutional Historiography in Bicentennial Perspective', The William and Mary Quarterly, 46 (1989), pp. 341-75; Rodgers, 'Republicanism: The Career of a Concept', pp. 35-7.
    • (1987) William and Mary Law Review , vol.29 , pp. 57-74
    • Horwitz, M.1
  • 8
    • 0040136971 scopus 로고
    • The "Great National Discussion": The Discourse of Politics in 1787
    • th Century England and America (Ithaca, NY, 1990); I. Kramnick, 'Communications', The William and Mary Quarterly, 45 (1988), p. 818; Forrest McDonald, Novus Ordo Seclorum: The Intellectual Origins of the Constitution (Lawrence, KS, 1985); F. McDonald, 'The Intellectual World of the Founding Fathers', in Requiem: Variations on Eighteenth-Century Themes, ed. Forrest McDonald and Ellen Shapiro McDonald (Lawrence, KS, 1988), p. 9; John Murrin, 'Fundamental Values, the Founding Fathers, and the Constitution', in To Form a More Perfect Union: The Critical Ideas of the Constitution, ed. Herman Belz, Ronald Hoffman and Peter J. Albert (Charlottesville, VA, 1992), pp. 11-25; J.G.A. Pocock, 'Communications', The William and Mary Quarterly, 45 (1988), p. 817; Cass Sunstein, 'Beyond the Republican Revival', The Yale Law Journal, 97 (1988), pp. 1539-90; Mark Tushnet, Red, White, and Blue: A Critical Analysis of Constitutional Law (Cambridge, 1988), pp. 4-5; Gordon S. Wood, 'Afterword', in The Republican Synthesis Revisited, ed. Klein et al., pp. 143-51. For discussions of the movement within scholarship on the Founding to paradigmatic pluralism see Peter S. Onuf, 'Reflections on the Founding: Constitutional Historiography in Bicentennial Perspective', The William and Mary Quarterly, 46 (1989), pp. 341-75; Rodgers, 'Republicanism: The Career of a Concept', pp. 35-7.
    • (1988) The William and Mary Quarterly , vol.45 , pp. 3-32
    • Kramnick, I.1
  • 9
    • 0011421750 scopus 로고
    • Ithaca, NY
    • th Century England and America (Ithaca, NY, 1990); I. Kramnick, 'Communications', The William and Mary Quarterly, 45 (1988), p. 818; Forrest McDonald, Novus Ordo Seclorum: The Intellectual Origins of the Constitution (Lawrence, KS, 1985); F. McDonald, 'The Intellectual World of the Founding Fathers', in Requiem: Variations on Eighteenth-Century Themes, ed. Forrest McDonald and Ellen Shapiro McDonald (Lawrence, KS, 1988), p. 9; John Murrin, 'Fundamental Values, the Founding Fathers, and the Constitution', in To Form a More Perfect Union: The Critical Ideas of the Constitution, ed. Herman Belz, Ronald Hoffman and Peter J. Albert (Charlottesville, VA, 1992), pp. 11-25; J.G.A. Pocock, 'Communications', The William and Mary Quarterly, 45 (1988), p. 817; Cass Sunstein, 'Beyond the Republican Revival', The Yale Law Journal, 97 (1988), pp. 1539-90; Mark Tushnet, Red, White, and Blue: A Critical Analysis of Constitutional Law (Cambridge, 1988), pp. 4-5; Gordon S. Wood, 'Afterword', in The Republican Synthesis Revisited, ed. Klein et al., pp. 143-51. For discussions of the movement within scholarship on the Founding to paradigmatic pluralism see Peter S. Onuf, 'Reflections on the Founding: Constitutional Historiography in Bicentennial Perspective', The William and Mary Quarterly, 46 (1989), pp. 341-75; Rodgers, 'Republicanism: The Career of a Concept', pp. 35-7.
    • (1990) th Century England and America
    • Kramnick, I.1
  • 10
    • 0348145337 scopus 로고
    • Communications
    • th Century England and America (Ithaca, NY, 1990); I. Kramnick, 'Communications', The William and Mary Quarterly, 45 (1988), p. 818; Forrest McDonald, Novus Ordo Seclorum: The Intellectual Origins of the Constitution (Lawrence, KS, 1985); F. McDonald, 'The Intellectual World of the Founding Fathers', in Requiem: Variations on Eighteenth-Century Themes, ed. Forrest McDonald and Ellen Shapiro McDonald (Lawrence, KS, 1988), p. 9; John Murrin, 'Fundamental Values, the Founding Fathers, and the Constitution', in To Form a More Perfect Union: The Critical Ideas of the Constitution, ed. Herman Belz, Ronald Hoffman and Peter J. Albert (Charlottesville, VA, 1992), pp. 11-25; J.G.A. Pocock, 'Communications', The William and Mary Quarterly, 45 (1988), p. 817; Cass Sunstein, 'Beyond the Republican Revival', The Yale Law Journal, 97 (1988), pp. 1539-90; Mark Tushnet, Red, White, and Blue: A Critical Analysis of Constitutional Law (Cambridge, 1988), pp. 4-5; Gordon S. Wood, 'Afterword', in The Republican Synthesis Revisited, ed. Klein et al., pp. 143-51. For discussions of the movement within scholarship on the Founding to paradigmatic pluralism see Peter S. Onuf, 'Reflections on the Founding: Constitutional Historiography in Bicentennial Perspective', The William and Mary Quarterly, 46 (1989), pp. 341-75; Rodgers, 'Republicanism: The Career of a Concept', pp. 35-7.
    • (1988) The William and Mary Quarterly , vol.45 , pp. 818
    • Kramnick, I.1
  • 11
    • 0004152551 scopus 로고
    • Lawrence, KS
    • th Century England and America (Ithaca, NY, 1990); I. Kramnick, 'Communications', The William and Mary Quarterly, 45 (1988), p. 818; Forrest McDonald, Novus Ordo Seclorum: The Intellectual Origins of the Constitution (Lawrence, KS, 1985); F. McDonald, 'The Intellectual World of the Founding Fathers', in Requiem: Variations on Eighteenth-Century Themes, ed. Forrest McDonald and Ellen Shapiro McDonald (Lawrence, KS, 1988), p. 9; John Murrin, 'Fundamental Values, the Founding Fathers, and the Constitution', in To Form a More Perfect Union: The Critical Ideas of the Constitution, ed. Herman Belz, Ronald Hoffman and Peter J. Albert (Charlottesville, VA, 1992), pp. 11-25; J.G.A. Pocock, 'Communications', The William and Mary Quarterly, 45 (1988), p. 817; Cass Sunstein, 'Beyond the Republican Revival', The Yale Law Journal, 97 (1988), pp. 1539-90; Mark Tushnet, Red, White, and Blue: A Critical Analysis of Constitutional Law (Cambridge, 1988), pp. 4-5; Gordon S. Wood, 'Afterword', in The Republican Synthesis Revisited, ed. Klein et al., pp. 143-51. For discussions of the movement within scholarship on the Founding to paradigmatic pluralism see Peter S. Onuf, 'Reflections on the Founding: Constitutional Historiography in Bicentennial Perspective', The William and Mary Quarterly, 46 (1989), pp. 341-75; Rodgers, 'Republicanism: The Career of a Concept', pp. 35-7.
    • (1985) Novus Ordo Seclorum: The Intellectual Origins of the Constitution
    • McDonald, F.1
  • 12
    • 0347515443 scopus 로고
    • The Intellectual World of the Founding Fathers
    • ed. Forrest McDonald and Ellen Shapiro McDonald Lawrence, KS
    • th Century England and America (Ithaca, NY, 1990); I. Kramnick, 'Communications', The William and Mary Quarterly, 45 (1988), p. 818; Forrest McDonald, Novus Ordo Seclorum: The Intellectual Origins of the Constitution (Lawrence, KS, 1985); F. McDonald, 'The Intellectual World of the Founding Fathers', in Requiem: Variations on Eighteenth-Century Themes, ed. Forrest McDonald and Ellen Shapiro McDonald (Lawrence, KS, 1988), p. 9; John Murrin, 'Fundamental Values, the Founding Fathers, and the Constitution', in To Form a More Perfect Union: The Critical Ideas of the Constitution, ed. Herman Belz, Ronald Hoffman and Peter J. Albert (Charlottesville, VA, 1992), pp. 11-25; J.G.A. Pocock, 'Communications', The William and Mary Quarterly, 45 (1988), p. 817; Cass Sunstein, 'Beyond the Republican Revival', The Yale Law Journal, 97 (1988), pp. 1539-90; Mark Tushnet, Red, White, and Blue: A Critical Analysis of Constitutional Law (Cambridge, 1988), pp. 4-5; Gordon S. Wood, 'Afterword', in The Republican Synthesis Revisited, ed. Klein et al., pp. 143-51. For discussions of the movement within scholarship on the Founding to paradigmatic pluralism see Peter S. Onuf, 'Reflections on the Founding: Constitutional Historiography in Bicentennial Perspective', The William and Mary Quarterly, 46 (1989), pp. 341-75; Rodgers, 'Republicanism: The Career of a Concept', pp. 35-7.
    • (1988) Requiem: Variations on Eighteenth-Century Themes , pp. 9
    • McDonald, F.1
  • 13
    • 0347515401 scopus 로고
    • Fundamental Values, the Founding Fathers, and the Constitution
    • ed. Herman Belz, Ronald Hoffman and Peter J. Albert Charlottesville, VA
    • th Century England and America (Ithaca, NY, 1990); I. Kramnick, 'Communications', The William and Mary Quarterly, 45 (1988), p. 818; Forrest McDonald, Novus Ordo Seclorum: The Intellectual Origins of the Constitution (Lawrence, KS, 1985); F. McDonald, 'The Intellectual World of the Founding Fathers', in Requiem: Variations on Eighteenth-Century Themes, ed. Forrest McDonald and Ellen Shapiro McDonald (Lawrence, KS, 1988), p. 9; John Murrin, 'Fundamental Values, the Founding Fathers, and the Constitution', in To Form a More Perfect Union: The Critical Ideas of the Constitution, ed. Herman Belz, Ronald Hoffman and Peter J. Albert (Charlottesville, VA, 1992), pp. 11-25; J.G.A. Pocock, 'Communications', The William and Mary Quarterly, 45 (1988), p. 817; Cass Sunstein, 'Beyond the Republican Revival', The Yale Law Journal, 97 (1988), pp. 1539-90; Mark Tushnet, Red, White, and Blue: A Critical Analysis of Constitutional Law (Cambridge, 1988), pp. 4-5; Gordon S. Wood, 'Afterword', in The Republican Synthesis Revisited, ed. Klein et al., pp. 143-51. For discussions of the movement within scholarship on the Founding to paradigmatic pluralism see Peter S. Onuf, 'Reflections on the Founding: Constitutional Historiography in Bicentennial Perspective', The William and Mary Quarterly, 46 (1989), pp. 341-75; Rodgers, 'Republicanism: The Career of a Concept', pp. 35-7.
    • (1992) To Form a More Perfect Union: The Critical Ideas of the Constitution , pp. 11-25
    • Murrin, J.1
  • 14
    • 0348145333 scopus 로고
    • Communications
    • th Century England and America (Ithaca, NY, 1990); I. Kramnick, 'Communications', The William and Mary Quarterly, 45 (1988), p. 818; Forrest McDonald, Novus Ordo Seclorum: The Intellectual Origins of the Constitution (Lawrence, KS, 1985); F. McDonald, 'The Intellectual World of the Founding Fathers', in Requiem: Variations on Eighteenth-Century Themes, ed. Forrest McDonald and Ellen Shapiro McDonald (Lawrence, KS, 1988), p. 9; John Murrin, 'Fundamental Values, the Founding Fathers, and the Constitution', in To Form a More Perfect Union: The Critical Ideas of the Constitution, ed. Herman Belz, Ronald Hoffman and Peter J. Albert (Charlottesville, VA, 1992), pp. 11-25; J.G.A. Pocock, 'Communications', The William and Mary Quarterly, 45 (1988), p. 817; Cass Sunstein, 'Beyond the Republican Revival', The Yale Law Journal, 97 (1988), pp. 1539-90; Mark Tushnet, Red, White, and Blue: A Critical Analysis of Constitutional Law (Cambridge, 1988), pp. 4-5; Gordon S. Wood, 'Afterword', in The Republican Synthesis Revisited, ed. Klein et al., pp. 143-51. For discussions of the movement within scholarship on the Founding to paradigmatic pluralism see Peter S. Onuf, 'Reflections on the Founding: Constitutional Historiography in Bicentennial Perspective', The William and Mary Quarterly, 46 (1989), pp. 341-75; Rodgers, 'Republicanism: The Career of a Concept', pp. 35-7.
    • (1988) The William and Mary Quarterly , vol.45 , pp. 817
    • Pocock, J.G.A.1
  • 15
    • 80855159534 scopus 로고
    • Beyond the Republican Revival
    • th Century England and America (Ithaca, NY, 1990); I. Kramnick, 'Communications', The William and Mary Quarterly, 45 (1988), p. 818; Forrest McDonald, Novus Ordo Seclorum: The Intellectual Origins of the Constitution (Lawrence, KS, 1985); F. McDonald, 'The Intellectual World of the Founding Fathers', in Requiem: Variations on Eighteenth-Century Themes, ed. Forrest McDonald and Ellen Shapiro McDonald (Lawrence, KS, 1988), p. 9; John Murrin, 'Fundamental Values, the Founding Fathers, and the Constitution', in To Form a More Perfect Union: The Critical Ideas of the Constitution, ed. Herman Belz, Ronald Hoffman and Peter J. Albert (Charlottesville, VA, 1992), pp. 11-25; J.G.A. Pocock, 'Communications', The William and Mary Quarterly, 45 (1988), p. 817; Cass Sunstein, 'Beyond the Republican Revival', The Yale Law Journal, 97 (1988), pp. 1539-90; Mark Tushnet, Red, White, and Blue: A Critical Analysis of Constitutional Law (Cambridge, 1988), pp. 4-5; Gordon S. Wood, 'Afterword', in The Republican Synthesis Revisited, ed. Klein et al., pp. 143-51. For discussions of the movement within scholarship on the Founding to paradigmatic pluralism see Peter S. Onuf, 'Reflections on the Founding: Constitutional Historiography in Bicentennial Perspective', The William and Mary Quarterly, 46 (1989), pp. 341-75; Rodgers, 'Republicanism: The Career of a Concept', pp. 35-7.
    • (1988) The Yale Law Journal , vol.97 , pp. 1539-1590
    • Sunstein, C.1
  • 16
    • 0004070011 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge
    • th Century England and America (Ithaca, NY, 1990); I. Kramnick, 'Communications', The William and Mary Quarterly, 45 (1988), p. 818; Forrest McDonald, Novus Ordo Seclorum: The Intellectual Origins of the Constitution (Lawrence, KS, 1985); F. McDonald, 'The Intellectual World of the Founding Fathers', in Requiem: Variations on Eighteenth-Century Themes, ed. Forrest McDonald and Ellen Shapiro McDonald (Lawrence, KS, 1988), p. 9; John Murrin, 'Fundamental Values, the Founding Fathers, and the Constitution', in To Form a More Perfect Union: The Critical Ideas of the Constitution, ed. Herman Belz, Ronald Hoffman and Peter J. Albert (Charlottesville, VA, 1992), pp. 11-25; J.G.A. Pocock, 'Communications', The William and Mary Quarterly, 45 (1988), p. 817; Cass Sunstein, 'Beyond the Republican Revival', The Yale Law Journal, 97 (1988), pp. 1539-90; Mark Tushnet, Red, White, and Blue: A Critical Analysis of Constitutional Law (Cambridge, 1988), pp. 4-5; Gordon S. Wood, 'Afterword', in The Republican Synthesis Revisited, ed. Klein et al., pp. 143-51. For discussions of the movement within scholarship on the Founding to paradigmatic pluralism see Peter S. Onuf, 'Reflections on the Founding: Constitutional Historiography in Bicentennial Perspective', The William and Mary Quarterly, 46 (1989), pp. 341-75; Rodgers, 'Republicanism: The Career of a Concept', pp. 35-7.
    • (1988) Red, White, and Blue: A Critical Analysis of Constitutional Law , pp. 4-5
    • Tushnet, M.1
  • 17
    • 0348145332 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Afterword
    • ed. Klein et al.
    • th Century England and America (Ithaca, NY, 1990); I. Kramnick, 'Communications', The William and Mary Quarterly, 45 (1988), p. 818; Forrest McDonald, Novus Ordo Seclorum: The Intellectual Origins of the Constitution (Lawrence, KS, 1985); F. McDonald, 'The Intellectual World of the Founding Fathers', in Requiem: Variations on Eighteenth-Century Themes, ed. Forrest McDonald and Ellen Shapiro McDonald (Lawrence, KS, 1988), p. 9; John Murrin, 'Fundamental Values, the Founding Fathers, and the Constitution', in To Form a More Perfect Union: The Critical Ideas of the Constitution, ed. Herman Belz, Ronald Hoffman and Peter J. Albert (Charlottesville, VA, 1992), pp. 11-25; J.G.A. Pocock, 'Communications', The William and Mary Quarterly, 45 (1988), p. 817; Cass Sunstein, 'Beyond the Republican Revival', The Yale Law Journal, 97 (1988), pp. 1539-90; Mark Tushnet, Red, White, and Blue: A Critical Analysis of Constitutional Law (Cambridge, 1988), pp. 4-5; Gordon S. Wood, 'Afterword', in The Republican Synthesis Revisited, ed. Klein et al., pp. 143-51. For discussions of the movement within scholarship on the Founding to paradigmatic pluralism see Peter S. Onuf, 'Reflections on the Founding: Constitutional Historiography in Bicentennial Perspective', The William and Mary Quarterly, 46 (1989), pp. 341-75; Rodgers, 'Republicanism: The Career of a Concept', pp. 35-7.
    • The Republican Synthesis Revisited , pp. 143-151
    • Wood, G.S.1
  • 18
    • 0346884771 scopus 로고
    • Reflections on the Founding: Constitutional Historiography in Bicentennial Perspective
    • th Century England and America (Ithaca, NY, 1990); I. Kramnick, 'Communications', The William and Mary Quarterly, 45 (1988), p. 818; Forrest McDonald, Novus Ordo Seclorum: The Intellectual Origins of the Constitution (Lawrence, KS, 1985); F. McDonald, 'The Intellectual World of the Founding Fathers', in Requiem: Variations on Eighteenth-Century Themes, ed. Forrest McDonald and Ellen Shapiro McDonald (Lawrence, KS, 1988), p. 9; John Murrin, 'Fundamental Values, the Founding Fathers, and the Constitution', in To Form a More Perfect Union: The Critical Ideas of the Constitution, ed. Herman Belz, Ronald Hoffman and Peter J. Albert (Charlottesville, VA, 1992), pp. 11-25; J.G.A. Pocock, 'Communications', The William and Mary Quarterly, 45 (1988), p. 817; Cass Sunstein, 'Beyond the Republican Revival', The Yale Law Journal, 97 (1988), pp. 1539-90; Mark Tushnet, Red, White, and Blue: A Critical Analysis of Constitutional Law (Cambridge, 1988), pp. 4-5; Gordon S. Wood, 'Afterword', in The Republican Synthesis Revisited, ed. Klein et al., pp. 143-51. For discussions of the movement within scholarship on the Founding to paradigmatic pluralism see Peter S. Onuf, 'Reflections on the Founding: Constitutional Historiography in Bicentennial Perspective', The William and Mary Quarterly, 46 (1989), pp. 341-75; Rodgers, 'Republicanism: The Career of a Concept', pp. 35-7.
    • (1989) The William and Mary Quarterly , vol.46 , pp. 341-375
    • Onuf, P.S.1
  • 19
    • 0346254492 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • th Century England and America (Ithaca, NY, 1990); I. Kramnick, 'Communications', The William and Mary Quarterly, 45 (1988), p. 818; Forrest McDonald, Novus Ordo Seclorum: The Intellectual Origins of the Constitution (Lawrence, KS, 1985); F. McDonald, 'The Intellectual World of the Founding Fathers', in Requiem: Variations on Eighteenth-Century Themes, ed. Forrest McDonald and Ellen Shapiro McDonald (Lawrence, KS, 1988), p. 9; John Murrin, 'Fundamental Values, the Founding Fathers, and the Constitution', in To Form a More Perfect Union: The Critical Ideas of the Constitution, ed. Herman Belz, Ronald Hoffman and Peter J. Albert (Charlottesville, VA, 1992), pp. 11-25; J.G.A. Pocock, 'Communications', The William and Mary Quarterly, 45 (1988), p. 817; Cass Sunstein, 'Beyond the Republican Revival', The Yale Law Journal, 97 (1988), pp. 1539-90; Mark Tushnet, Red, White, and Blue: A Critical Analysis of Constitutional Law (Cambridge, 1988), pp. 4-5; Gordon S. Wood, 'Afterword', in The Republican Synthesis Revisited, ed. Klein et al., pp. 143-51. For discussions of the movement within scholarship on the Founding to paradigmatic pluralism see Peter S. Onuf, 'Reflections on the Founding: Constitutional Historiography in Bicentennial Perspective', The William and Mary Quarterly, 46 (1989), pp. 341-75; Rodgers, 'Republicanism: The Career of a Concept', pp. 35-7.
    • Republicanism: The Career of a Concept , pp. 35-37
    • Rodgers1
  • 20
    • 0005435460 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Notre Dame, IN
    • Michael Zuckert, The Natural Rights Republic: Studies in the Foundation of the American Political Tradition (Notre Dame, IN, 1996), p. 209. Banning's 1986 article 'Jeffersonian Ideology Revisited' was central in catapulting the debate over the intellectual origins of the American republic out of the 'either republicanism or liberalism' phase and into its current configuration in which scholars are trying to determine the way in which liberalism, republicanism, and perhaps other intellectual traditions were related to each other. Lance Banning, 'Jeffersonian Ideology Revisited: Liberal and Classical Ideas in the New American Republic', The William and Mary Quarterly, 42 (1987), pp. 11-19. See also L. Banning, 'Quid Transit? Paradigms and Process in the Transformation of Republican Ideas', Reviews in American History, 17 (1989), pp. 199-204; and L. Banning, 'Retrospect and Prospect', in The Republican Synthesis Revisited, ed. Klein et al., pp. 91-117.
    • (1996) The Natural Rights Republic: Studies in the Foundation of the American Political Tradition , pp. 209
    • Zuckert, M.1
  • 21
    • 0011672216 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Jeffersonian Ideology Revisited: Liberal and Classical Ideas in the New American Republic
    • Michael Zuckert, The Natural Rights Republic: Studies in the Foundation of the American Political Tradition (Notre Dame, IN, 1996), p. 209. Banning's 1986 article 'Jeffersonian Ideology Revisited' was central in catapulting the debate over the intellectual origins of the American republic out of the 'either republicanism or liberalism' phase and into its current configuration in which scholars are trying to determine the way in which liberalism, republicanism, and perhaps other intellectual traditions were related to each other. Lance Banning, 'Jeffersonian Ideology Revisited: Liberal and Classical Ideas in the New American Republic', The William and Mary Quarterly, 42 (1987), pp. 11-19. See also L. Banning, 'Quid Transit? Paradigms and Process in the Transformation of Republican Ideas', Reviews in American History, 17 (1989), pp. 199-204; and L. Banning, 'Retrospect and Prospect', in The Republican Synthesis Revisited, ed. Klein et al., pp. 91-117.
    • (1987) The William and Mary Quarterly , vol.42 , pp. 11-19
    • Banning, L.1
  • 22
    • 0346884767 scopus 로고
    • Quid Transit? Paradigms and Process in the Transformation of Republican Ideas
    • Michael Zuckert, The Natural Rights Republic: Studies in the Foundation of the American Political Tradition (Notre Dame, IN, 1996), p. 209. Banning's 1986 article 'Jeffersonian Ideology Revisited' was central in catapulting the debate over the intellectual origins of the American republic out of the 'either republicanism or liberalism' phase and into its current configuration in which scholars are trying to determine the way in which liberalism, republicanism, and perhaps other intellectual traditions were related to each other. Lance Banning, 'Jeffersonian Ideology Revisited: Liberal and Classical Ideas in the New American Republic', The William and Mary Quarterly, 42 (1987), pp. 11-19. See also L. Banning, 'Quid Transit? Paradigms and Process in the Transformation of Republican Ideas', Reviews in American History, 17 (1989), pp. 199-204; and L. Banning, 'Retrospect and Prospect', in The Republican Synthesis Revisited, ed. Klein et al., pp. 91-117.
    • (1989) Reviews in American History , vol.17 , pp. 199-204
    • Banning, L.1
  • 23
    • 0348145296 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Retrospect and Prospect
    • ed. Klein et al.
    • Michael Zuckert, The Natural Rights Republic: Studies in the Foundation of the American Political Tradition (Notre Dame, IN, 1996), p. 209. Banning's 1986 article 'Jeffersonian Ideology Revisited' was central in catapulting the debate over the intellectual origins of the American republic out of the 'either republicanism or liberalism' phase and into its current configuration in which scholars are trying to determine the way in which liberalism, republicanism, and perhaps other intellectual traditions were related to each other. Lance Banning, 'Jeffersonian Ideology Revisited: Liberal and Classical Ideas in the New American Republic', The William and Mary Quarterly, 42 (1987), pp. 11-19. See also L. Banning, 'Quid Transit? Paradigms and Process in the Transformation of Republican Ideas', Reviews in American History, 17 (1989), pp. 199-204; and L. Banning, 'Retrospect and Prospect', in The Republican Synthesis Revisited, ed. Klein et al., pp. 91-117.
    • The Republican Synthesis Revisited , pp. 91-117
    • Banning, L.1
  • 24
    • 84959805699 scopus 로고
    • The Virtues of Liberalism: Christianity, Republicanism, and Ethics in Early American Political Discourse
    • James T. Kloppenberg, 'The Virtues of Liberalism: Christianity, Republicanism, and Ethics in Early American Political Discourse', Journal of American History, 74 (1987), p. 11. Interpretations that ignore the diversity of intellectual traditions present in the American Founding are often deterministic and question-begging and have been presented by scholars on both sides of this debate. Pocock, for example, has argued that to understand the eighteenth century fully we must trace out the persistence of civic humanism. He has then simply ignored - cast out of vision - central documents, such as the Declaration of Independence, that illustrate the importance of the social contract-natural rights tradition. Moreover, as Joyce Appleby has most persistently charged, the republican revisionists have been guilty of determinism, in particular by fastening on to a mode of interpretation that is unable to take into account the numerous changes in social practice and ideology that were taking place in the eighteenth century. In the initial stages of this debate at least, the republican revisionists were too quick to say that the Founders were locked into a conceptual world of classical republican language that precluded the development and use of other political languages. Similarly, Thomas Pangle, Paul Rahe, and before them Martin Diamond have interpreted the Founders' political thought as a species of the 'New Science of Politics' of Machiavelli, Hobbes and Locke. They have then ignored or presented perverse interpretations of important dimensions of the Founders' political thought that challenge this reading, especially Jeffersonian political economy. For the tendency of the republican revisionists to ignore the Declaration of Independence and the natural rights tradition see Scott Gerber, 'What Ever Happened to the Declaration? A Commentary on the Republican Revisionism in the Political Thought of the American Revolution', Polity, 26 (1993), pp. 207-31; and Gerber, To Secure These Rights (New York, 1995), esp. pp. 19-56. For the deterministic tendencies of the republican revisionists' methodology see Joyce Appleby, 'Republicanism in Old and New Contexts', The William and Mary Quarterly, 43 (1986), pp. 26-31. See Eugene Miller, 'What Publius Says About Interest', The Political Science Reviewer, 19 (1990), pp. 20-1, for warnings about how interpreting the political thought of the Founders through the lens of the 'New Science of Politics' can lead to interpretations that take for granted what they are designed to prove. The reductionism of Rahe, Pangle and Diamond's interpretations of Jeffersonian political economy can be grasped by comparing Diamond, 'Democracy and The Federalist: A Reconsideration of the Framers' Intent' and 'Ethics and Politics', in As Far As Republican Principles Will Admit: Essays by Martin Diamond, ed. William A. Schambra (Washington, 1992), esp. pp. 31-5, 337-68; Diamond, The Founding of the Democratic Republic (Itasca, IL, 1981), pp. 71-8; Thomas Pangle, The Spirit of Modern Republicanism: The Moral Vision of the American Founders and the Philosophy of Locke (Chicago, 1988), pp. 98-104; and Paul Rahe, Republics: Ancient and Modern: Classical Republicanism and the American Revolution (Chapel Hill, NC, & London, 1992), pp. 726-47, with McCoy, The Elusive Republic: Political Economy in Jeffersonian America (Chapel Hill, NC, 1980), pp. 120-35. See also Alan Gibson, 'The Commercial Republic and the Pluralist Critique of Marxism: An Analysis of Martin Diamond's Interpretation of Federalist 10', Polity, 25 (1993), pp. 521-8. For the way in which paradigms of interpretation change because scholars have identified a new set of problems as central, not necessarily because new paradigms envelop old ones and provide a more comprehensive interpretation of the facts, see Rodgers, 'Republicanism: The Career of a Concept', pp. 11-12.
    • (1987) Journal of American History , vol.74 , pp. 11
    • Kloppenberg, J.T.1
  • 25
    • 85050841584 scopus 로고
    • What Ever Happened to the Declaration? A Commentary on the Republican Revisionism in the Political Thought of the American Revolution
    • James T. Kloppenberg, 'The Virtues of Liberalism: Christianity, Republicanism, and Ethics in Early American Political Discourse', Journal of American History, 74 (1987), p. 11. Interpretations that ignore the diversity of intellectual traditions present in the American Founding are often deterministic and question-begging and have been presented by scholars on both sides of this debate. Pocock, for example, has argued that to understand the eighteenth century fully we must trace out the persistence of civic humanism. He has then simply ignored - cast out of vision - central documents, such as the Declaration of Independence, that illustrate the importance of the social contract-natural rights tradition. Moreover, as Joyce Appleby has most persistently charged, the republican revisionists have been guilty of determinism, in particular by fastening on to a mode of interpretation that is unable to take into account the numerous changes in social practice and ideology that were taking place in the eighteenth century. In the initial stages of this debate at least, the republican revisionists were too quick to say that the Founders were locked into a conceptual world of classical republican language that precluded the development and use of other political languages. Similarly, Thomas Pangle, Paul Rahe, and before them Martin Diamond have interpreted the Founders' political thought as a species of the 'New Science of Politics' of Machiavelli, Hobbes and Locke. They have then ignored or presented perverse interpretations of important dimensions of the Founders' political thought that challenge this reading, especially Jeffersonian political economy. For the tendency of the republican revisionists to ignore the Declaration of Independence and the natural rights tradition see Scott Gerber, 'What Ever Happened to the Declaration? A Commentary on the Republican Revisionism in the Political Thought of the American Revolution', Polity, 26 (1993), pp. 207-31; and Gerber, To Secure These Rights (New York, 1995), esp. pp. 19-56. For the deterministic tendencies of the republican revisionists' methodology see Joyce Appleby, 'Republicanism in Old and New Contexts', The William and Mary Quarterly, 43 (1986), pp. 26-31. See Eugene Miller, 'What Publius Says About Interest', The Political Science Reviewer, 19 (1990), pp. 20-1, for warnings about how interpreting the political thought of the Founders through the lens of the 'New Science of Politics' can lead to interpretations that take for granted what they are designed to prove. The reductionism of Rahe, Pangle and Diamond's interpretations of Jeffersonian political economy can be grasped by comparing Diamond, 'Democracy and The Federalist: A Reconsideration of the Framers' Intent' and 'Ethics and Politics', in As Far As Republican Principles Will Admit: Essays by Martin Diamond, ed. William A. Schambra (Washington, 1992), esp. pp. 31-5, 337-68; Diamond, The Founding of the Democratic Republic (Itasca, IL, 1981), pp. 71-8; Thomas Pangle, The Spirit of Modern Republicanism: The Moral Vision of the American Founders and the Philosophy of Locke (Chicago, 1988), pp. 98-104; and Paul Rahe, Republics: Ancient and Modern: Classical Republicanism and the American Revolution (Chapel Hill, NC, & London, 1992), pp. 726-47, with McCoy, The Elusive Republic: Political Economy in Jeffersonian America (Chapel Hill, NC, 1980), pp. 120-35. See also Alan Gibson, 'The Commercial Republic and the Pluralist Critique of Marxism: An Analysis of Martin Diamond's Interpretation of Federalist 10', Polity, 25 (1993), pp. 521-8. For the way in which paradigms of interpretation change because scholars have identified a new set of problems as central, not necessarily because new paradigms envelop old ones and provide a more comprehensive interpretation of the facts, see Rodgers, 'Republicanism: The Career of a Concept', pp. 11-12.
    • (1993) Polity , vol.26 , pp. 207-231
    • Gerber, S.1
  • 26
    • 0004134805 scopus 로고
    • New York
    • James T. Kloppenberg, 'The Virtues of Liberalism: Christianity, Republicanism, and Ethics in Early American Political Discourse', Journal of American History, 74 (1987), p. 11. Interpretations that ignore the diversity of intellectual traditions present in the American Founding are often deterministic and question-begging and have been presented by scholars on both sides of this debate. Pocock, for example, has argued that to understand the eighteenth century fully we must trace out the persistence of civic humanism. He has then simply ignored - cast out of vision - central documents, such as the Declaration of Independence, that illustrate the importance of the social contract-natural rights tradition. Moreover, as Joyce Appleby has most persistently charged, the republican revisionists have been guilty of determinism, in particular by fastening on to a mode of interpretation that is unable to take into account the numerous changes in social practice and ideology that were taking place in the eighteenth century. In the initial stages of this debate at least, the republican revisionists were too quick to say that the Founders were locked into a conceptual world of classical republican language that precluded the development and use of other political languages. Similarly, Thomas Pangle, Paul Rahe, and before them Martin Diamond have interpreted the Founders' political thought as a species of the 'New Science of Politics' of Machiavelli, Hobbes and Locke. They have then ignored or presented perverse interpretations of important dimensions of the Founders' political thought that challenge this reading, especially Jeffersonian political economy. For the tendency of the republican revisionists to ignore the Declaration of Independence and the natural rights tradition see Scott Gerber, 'What Ever Happened to the Declaration? A Commentary on the Republican Revisionism in the Political Thought of the American Revolution', Polity, 26 (1993), pp. 207-31; and Gerber, To Secure These Rights (New York, 1995), esp. pp. 19-56. For the deterministic tendencies of the republican revisionists' methodology see Joyce Appleby, 'Republicanism in Old and New Contexts', The William and Mary Quarterly, 43 (1986), pp. 26-31. See Eugene Miller, 'What Publius Says About Interest', The Political Science Reviewer, 19 (1990), pp. 20-1, for warnings about how interpreting the political thought of the Founders through the lens of the 'New Science of Politics' can lead to interpretations that take for granted what they are designed to prove. The reductionism of Rahe, Pangle and Diamond's interpretations of Jeffersonian political economy can be grasped by comparing Diamond, 'Democracy and The Federalist: A Reconsideration of the Framers' Intent' and 'Ethics and Politics', in As Far As Republican Principles Will Admit: Essays by Martin Diamond, ed. William A. Schambra (Washington, 1992), esp. pp. 31-5, 337-68; Diamond, The Founding of the Democratic Republic (Itasca, IL, 1981), pp. 71-8; Thomas Pangle, The Spirit of Modern Republicanism: The Moral Vision of the American Founders and the Philosophy of Locke (Chicago, 1988), pp. 98-104; and Paul Rahe, Republics: Ancient and Modern: Classical Republicanism and the American Revolution (Chapel Hill, NC, & London, 1992), pp. 726-47, with McCoy, The Elusive Republic: Political Economy in Jeffersonian America (Chapel Hill, NC, 1980), pp. 120-35. See also Alan Gibson, 'The Commercial Republic and the Pluralist Critique of Marxism: An Analysis of Martin Diamond's Interpretation of Federalist 10', Polity, 25 (1993), pp. 521-8. For the way in which paradigms of interpretation change because scholars have identified a new set of problems as central, not necessarily because new paradigms envelop old ones and provide a more comprehensive interpretation of the facts, see Rodgers, 'Republicanism: The Career of a Concept', pp. 11-12.
    • (1995) To Secure These Rights , pp. 19-56
    • Gerber1
  • 27
    • 0003073386 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Republicanism in Old and New Contexts
    • James T. Kloppenberg, 'The Virtues of Liberalism: Christianity, Republicanism, and Ethics in Early American Political Discourse', Journal of American History, 74 (1987), p. 11. Interpretations that ignore the diversity of intellectual traditions present in the American Founding are often deterministic and question-begging and have been presented by scholars on both sides of this debate. Pocock, for example, has argued that to understand the eighteenth century fully we must trace out the persistence of civic humanism. He has then simply ignored - cast out of vision - central documents, such as the Declaration of Independence, that illustrate the importance of the social contract-natural rights tradition. Moreover, as Joyce Appleby has most persistently charged, the republican revisionists have been guilty of determinism, in particular by fastening on to a mode of interpretation that is unable to take into account the numerous changes in social practice and ideology that were taking place in the eighteenth century. In the initial stages of this debate at least, the republican revisionists were too quick to say that the Founders were locked into a conceptual world of classical republican language that precluded the development and use of other political languages. Similarly, Thomas Pangle, Paul Rahe, and before them Martin Diamond have interpreted the Founders' political thought as a species of the 'New Science of Politics' of Machiavelli, Hobbes and Locke. They have then ignored or presented perverse interpretations of important dimensions of the Founders' political thought that challenge this reading, especially Jeffersonian political economy. For the tendency of the republican revisionists to ignore the Declaration of Independence and the natural rights tradition see Scott Gerber, 'What Ever Happened to the Declaration? A Commentary on the Republican Revisionism in the Political Thought of the American Revolution', Polity, 26 (1993), pp. 207-31; and Gerber, To Secure These Rights (New York, 1995), esp. pp. 19-56. For the deterministic tendencies of the republican revisionists' methodology see Joyce Appleby, 'Republicanism in Old and New Contexts', The William and Mary Quarterly, 43 (1986), pp. 26-31. See Eugene Miller, 'What Publius Says About Interest', The Political Science Reviewer, 19 (1990), pp. 20-1, for warnings about how interpreting the political thought of the Founders through the lens of the 'New Science of Politics' can lead to interpretations that take for granted what they are designed to prove. The reductionism of Rahe, Pangle and Diamond's interpretations of Jeffersonian political economy can be grasped by comparing Diamond, 'Democracy and The Federalist: A Reconsideration of the Framers' Intent' and 'Ethics and Politics', in As Far As Republican Principles Will Admit: Essays by Martin Diamond, ed. William A. Schambra (Washington, 1992), esp. pp. 31-5, 337-68; Diamond, The Founding of the Democratic Republic (Itasca, IL, 1981), pp. 71-8; Thomas Pangle, The Spirit of Modern Republicanism: The Moral Vision of the American Founders and the Philosophy of Locke (Chicago, 1988), pp. 98-104; and Paul Rahe, Republics: Ancient and Modern: Classical Republicanism and the American Revolution (Chapel Hill, NC, & London, 1992), pp. 726-47, with McCoy, The Elusive Republic: Political Economy in Jeffersonian America (Chapel Hill, NC, 1980), pp. 120-35. See also Alan Gibson, 'The Commercial Republic and the Pluralist Critique of Marxism: An Analysis of Martin Diamond's Interpretation of Federalist 10', Polity, 25 (1993), pp. 521-8. For the way in which paradigms of interpretation change because scholars have identified a new set of problems as central, not necessarily because new paradigms envelop old ones and provide a more comprehensive interpretation of the facts, see Rodgers, 'Republicanism: The Career of a Concept', pp. 11-12.
    • (1986) The William and Mary Quarterly , vol.43 , pp. 26-31
    • Appleby, J.1
  • 28
    • 84970202563 scopus 로고
    • What Publius Says about Interest
    • James T. Kloppenberg, 'The Virtues of Liberalism: Christianity, Republicanism, and Ethics in Early American Political Discourse', Journal of American History, 74 (1987), p. 11. Interpretations that ignore the diversity of intellectual traditions present in the American Founding are often deterministic and question-begging and have been presented by scholars on both sides of this debate. Pocock, for example, has argued that to understand the eighteenth century fully we must trace out the persistence of civic humanism. He has then simply ignored - cast out of vision - central documents, such as the Declaration of Independence, that illustrate the importance of the social contract-natural rights tradition. Moreover, as Joyce Appleby has most persistently charged, the republican revisionists have been guilty of determinism, in particular by fastening on to a mode of interpretation that is unable to take into account the numerous changes in social practice and ideology that were taking place in the eighteenth century. In the initial stages of this debate at least, the republican revisionists were too quick to say that the Founders were locked into a conceptual world of classical republican language that precluded the development and use of other political languages. Similarly, Thomas Pangle, Paul Rahe, and before them Martin Diamond have interpreted the Founders' political thought as a species of the 'New Science of Politics' of Machiavelli, Hobbes and Locke. They have then ignored or presented perverse interpretations of important dimensions of the Founders' political thought that challenge this reading, especially Jeffersonian political economy. For the tendency of the republican revisionists to ignore the Declaration of Independence and the natural rights tradition see Scott Gerber, 'What Ever Happened to the Declaration? A Commentary on the Republican Revisionism in the Political Thought of the American Revolution', Polity, 26 (1993), pp. 207-31; and Gerber, To Secure These Rights (New York, 1995), esp. pp. 19-56. For the deterministic tendencies of the republican revisionists' methodology see Joyce Appleby, 'Republicanism in Old and New Contexts', The William and Mary Quarterly, 43 (1986), pp. 26-31. See Eugene Miller, 'What Publius Says About Interest', The Political Science Reviewer, 19 (1990), pp. 20-1, for warnings about how interpreting the political thought of the Founders through the lens of the 'New Science of Politics' can lead to interpretations that take for granted what they are designed to prove. The reductionism of Rahe, Pangle and Diamond's interpretations of Jeffersonian political economy can be grasped by comparing Diamond, 'Democracy and The Federalist: A Reconsideration of the Framers' Intent' and 'Ethics and Politics', in As Far As Republican Principles Will Admit: Essays by Martin Diamond, ed. William A. Schambra (Washington, 1992), esp. pp. 31-5, 337-68; Diamond, The Founding of the Democratic Republic (Itasca, IL, 1981), pp. 71-8; Thomas Pangle, The Spirit of Modern Republicanism: The Moral Vision of the American Founders and the Philosophy of Locke (Chicago, 1988), pp. 98-104; and Paul Rahe, Republics: Ancient and Modern: Classical Republicanism and the American Revolution (Chapel Hill, NC, & London, 1992), pp. 726-47, with McCoy, The Elusive Republic: Political Economy in Jeffersonian America (Chapel Hill, NC, 1980), pp. 120-35. See also Alan Gibson, 'The Commercial Republic and the Pluralist Critique of Marxism: An Analysis of Martin Diamond's Interpretation of Federalist 10', Polity, 25 (1993), pp. 521-8. For the way in which paradigms of interpretation change because scholars have identified a new set of problems as central, not necessarily because new paradigms envelop old ones and provide a more comprehensive interpretation of the facts, see Rodgers, 'Republicanism: The Career of a Concept', pp. 11-12.
    • (1990) The Political Science Reviewer , vol.19 , pp. 20-21
    • Miller, E.1
  • 29
    • 84959805699 scopus 로고
    • Democracy and the Federalist: A Reconsideration of the Framers' Intent' and 'Ethics and Politics
    • ed. William A. Schambra Washington
    • James T. Kloppenberg, 'The Virtues of Liberalism: Christianity, Republicanism, and Ethics in Early American Political Discourse', Journal of American History, 74 (1987), p. 11. Interpretations that ignore the diversity of intellectual traditions present in the American Founding are often deterministic and question-begging and have been presented by scholars on both sides of this debate. Pocock, for example, has argued that to understand the eighteenth century fully we must trace out the persistence of civic humanism. He has then simply ignored - cast out of vision - central documents, such as the Declaration of Independence, that illustrate the importance of the social contract-natural rights tradition. Moreover, as Joyce Appleby has most persistently charged, the republican revisionists have been guilty of determinism, in particular by fastening on to a mode of interpretation that is unable to take into account the numerous changes in social practice and ideology that were taking place in the eighteenth century. In the initial stages of this debate at least, the republican revisionists were too quick to say that the Founders were locked into a conceptual world of classical republican language that precluded the development and use of other political languages. Similarly, Thomas Pangle, Paul Rahe, and before them Martin Diamond have interpreted the Founders' political
    • (1992) As Far as Republican Principles Will Admit: Essays by Martin Diamond , pp. 31-35
    • Diamond1
  • 30
    • 0010787120 scopus 로고
    • Itasca, IL
    • James T. Kloppenberg, 'The Virtues of Liberalism: Christianity, Republicanism, and Ethics in Early American Political Discourse', Journal of American History, 74 (1987), p. 11. Interpretations that ignore the diversity of intellectual traditions present in the American Founding are often deterministic and question-begging and have been presented by scholars on both sides of this debate. Pocock, for example, has argued that to understand the eighteenth century fully we must trace out the persistence of civic humanism. He has then simply ignored - cast out of vision - central documents, such as the Declaration of Independence, that illustrate the importance of the social contract-natural rights tradition. Moreover, as Joyce Appleby has most persistently charged, the republican revisionists have been guilty of determinism, in particular by fastening on to a mode of interpretation that is unable to take into account the numerous changes in social practice and ideology that were taking place in the eighteenth century. In the initial stages of this debate at least, the republican revisionists were too quick to say that the Founders were locked into a conceptual world of classical republican language that precluded the development and use of other political languages. Similarly, Thomas Pangle, Paul Rahe, and before them Martin Diamond have interpreted the Founders' political thought as a species of the 'New Science of Politics' of Machiavelli, Hobbes and Locke. They have then ignored or presented perverse interpretations of important dimensions of the Founders' political thought that challenge this reading, especially Jeffersonian political economy. For the tendency of the republican revisionists to ignore the Declaration of Independence and the natural rights tradition see Scott Gerber, 'What Ever Happened to the Declaration? A Commentary on the Republican Revisionism in the Political Thought of the American Revolution', Polity, 26 (1993), pp. 207-31; and Gerber, To Secure These Rights (New York, 1995), esp. pp. 19-56. For the deterministic tendencies of the republican revisionists' methodology see Joyce Appleby, 'Republicanism in Old and New Contexts', The William and Mary Quarterly, 43 (1986), pp. 26-31. See Eugene Miller, 'What Publius Says About Interest', The Political Science Reviewer, 19 (1990), pp. 20-1, for warnings about how interpreting the political thought of the Founders through the lens of the 'New Science of Politics' can lead to interpretations that take for granted what they are designed to prove. The reductionism of Rahe, Pangle and Diamond's interpretations of Jeffersonian political economy can be grasped by comparing Diamond, 'Democracy and The Federalist: A Reconsideration of the Framers' Intent' and 'Ethics and Politics', in As Far As Republican Principles Will Admit: Essays by Martin Diamond, ed. William A. Schambra (Washington, 1992), esp. pp. 31-5, 337-68; Diamond, The Founding of the Democratic Republic (Itasca, IL, 1981), pp. 71-8; Thomas Pangle, The Spirit of Modern Republicanism: The Moral Vision of the American Founders and the Philosophy of Locke (Chicago, 1988), pp. 98-104; and Paul Rahe, Republics: Ancient and Modern: Classical Republicanism and the American Revolution (Chapel Hill, NC, & London, 1992), pp. 726-47, with McCoy, The Elusive Republic: Political Economy in Jeffersonian America (Chapel Hill, NC, 1980), pp. 120-35. See also Alan Gibson, 'The Commercial Republic and the Pluralist Critique of Marxism: An Analysis of Martin Diamond's Interpretation of Federalist 10', Polity, 25 (1993), pp. 521-8. For the way in which paradigms of interpretation change because scholars have identified a new set of problems as central, not necessarily because new paradigms envelop old ones and provide a more comprehensive interpretation of the facts, see Rodgers, 'Republicanism: The Career of a Concept', pp. 11-12.
    • (1981) The Founding of the Democratic Republic , pp. 71-78
    • Diamond1
  • 31
    • 0003394981 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Chicago
    • James T. Kloppenberg, 'The Virtues of Liberalism: Christianity, Republicanism, and Ethics in Early American Political Discourse', Journal of American History, 74 (1987), p. 11. Interpretations that ignore the diversity of intellectual traditions present in the American Founding are often deterministic and question-begging and have been presented by scholars on both sides of this debate. Pocock, for example, has argued that to understand the eighteenth century fully we must trace out the persistence of civic humanism. He has then simply ignored - cast out of vision - central documents, such as the Declaration of Independence, that illustrate the importance of the social contract-natural rights tradition. Moreover, as Joyce Appleby has most persistently charged, the republican revisionists have been guilty of determinism, in particular by fastening on to a mode of interpretation that is unable to take into account the numerous changes in social practice and ideology that were taking place in the eighteenth century. In the initial stages of this debate at least, the republican revisionists were too quick to say that the Founders were locked into a conceptual world of classical republican language that precluded the development and use of other political languages. Similarly, Thomas Pangle, Paul Rahe, and before them Martin Diamond have interpreted the Founders' political thought as a species of the 'New Science of Politics' of Machiavelli, Hobbes and Locke. They have then ignored or presented perverse interpretations of important dimensions of the Founders' political thought that challenge this reading, especially Jeffersonian political economy. For the tendency of the republican revisionists to ignore the Declaration of Independence and the natural rights tradition see Scott Gerber, 'What Ever Happened to the Declaration? A Commentary on the Republican Revisionism in the Political Thought of the American Revolution', Polity, 26 (1993), pp. 207-31; and Gerber, To Secure These Rights (New York, 1995), esp. pp. 19-56. For the deterministic tendencies of the republican revisionists' methodology see Joyce Appleby, 'Republicanism in Old and New Contexts', The William and Mary Quarterly, 43 (1986), pp. 26-31. See Eugene Miller, 'What Publius Says About Interest', The Political Science Reviewer, 19 (1990), pp. 20-1, for warnings about how interpreting the political thought of the Founders through the lens of the 'New Science of Politics' can lead to interpretations that take for granted what they are designed to prove. The reductionism of Rahe, Pangle and Diamond's interpretations of Jeffersonian political economy can be grasped by comparing Diamond, 'Democracy and The Federalist: A Reconsideration of the Framers' Intent' and 'Ethics and Politics', in As Far As Republican Principles Will Admit: Essays by Martin Diamond, ed. William A. Schambra (Washington, 1992), esp. pp. 31-5, 337-68; Diamond, The Founding of the Democratic Republic (Itasca, IL, 1981), pp. 71-8; Thomas Pangle, The Spirit of Modern Republicanism: The Moral Vision of the American Founders and the Philosophy of Locke (Chicago, 1988), pp. 98-104; and Paul Rahe, Republics: Ancient and Modern: Classical Republicanism and the American Revolution (Chapel Hill, NC, & London, 1992), pp. 726-47, with McCoy, The Elusive Republic: Political Economy in Jeffersonian America (Chapel Hill, NC, 1980), pp. 120-35. See also Alan Gibson, 'The Commercial Republic and the Pluralist Critique of Marxism: An Analysis of Martin Diamond's Interpretation of Federalist 10', Polity, 25 (1993), pp. 521-8. For the way in which paradigms of interpretation change because scholars have identified a new set of problems as central, not necessarily because new paradigms envelop old ones and provide a more comprehensive interpretation of the facts, see Rodgers, 'Republicanism: The Career of a Concept', pp. 11-12.
    • (1988) The Spirit of Modern Republicanism: The Moral Vision of the American Founders and the Philosophy of Locke , pp. 98-104
    • Pangle, T.1
  • 32
    • 0004178688 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Chapel Hill, NC, & London
    • James T. Kloppenberg, 'The Virtues of Liberalism: Christianity, Republicanism, and Ethics in Early American Political Discourse', Journal of American History, 74 (1987), p. 11. Interpretations that ignore the diversity of intellectual traditions present in the American Founding are often deterministic and question-begging and have been presented by scholars on both sides of this debate. Pocock, for example, has argued that to understand the eighteenth century fully we must trace out the persistence of civic humanism. He has then simply ignored - cast out of vision - central documents, such as the Declaration of Independence, that illustrate the importance of the social contract-natural rights tradition. Moreover, as Joyce Appleby has most persistently charged, the republican revisionists have been guilty of determinism, in particular by fastening on to a mode of interpretation that is unable to take into account the numerous changes in social practice and ideology that were taking place in the eighteenth century. In the initial stages of this debate at least, the republican revisionists were too quick to say that the Founders were locked into a conceptual world of classical republican language that precluded the development and use of other political languages. Similarly, Thomas Pangle, Paul Rahe, and before them Martin Diamond have interpreted the Founders' political thought as a species of the 'New Science of Politics' of Machiavelli, Hobbes and Locke. They have then ignored or presented perverse interpretations of important dimensions of the Founders' political thought that challenge this reading, especially Jeffersonian political economy. For the tendency of the republican revisionists to ignore the Declaration of Independence and the natural rights tradition see Scott Gerber, 'What Ever Happened to the Declaration? A Commentary on the Republican Revisionism in the Political Thought of the American Revolution', Polity, 26 (1993), pp. 207-31; and Gerber, To Secure These Rights (New York, 1995), esp. pp. 19-56. For the deterministic tendencies of the republican revisionists' methodology see Joyce Appleby, 'Republicanism in Old and New Contexts', The William and Mary Quarterly, 43 (1986), pp. 26-31. See Eugene Miller, 'What Publius Says About Interest', The Political Science Reviewer, 19 (1990), pp. 20-1, for warnings about how interpreting the political thought of the Founders through the lens of the 'New Science of Politics' can lead to interpretations that take for granted what they are designed to prove. The reductionism of Rahe, Pangle and Diamond's interpretations of Jeffersonian political economy can be grasped by comparing Diamond, 'Democracy and The Federalist: A Reconsideration of the Framers' Intent' and 'Ethics and Politics', in As Far As Republican Principles Will Admit: Essays by Martin Diamond, ed. William A. Schambra (Washington, 1992), esp. pp. 31-5, 337-68; Diamond, The Founding of the Democratic Republic (Itasca, IL, 1981), pp. 71-8; Thomas Pangle, The Spirit of Modern Republicanism: The Moral Vision of the American Founders and the Philosophy of Locke (Chicago, 1988), pp. 98-104; and Paul Rahe, Republics: Ancient and Modern: Classical Republicanism and the American Revolution (Chapel Hill, NC, & London, 1992), pp. 726-47, with McCoy, The Elusive Republic: Political Economy in Jeffersonian America (Chapel Hill, NC, 1980), pp. 120-35. See also Alan Gibson, 'The Commercial Republic and the Pluralist Critique of Marxism: An Analysis of Martin Diamond's Interpretation of Federalist 10', Polity, 25 (1993), pp. 521-8. For the way in which paradigms of interpretation change because scholars have identified a new set of problems as central, not necessarily because new paradigms envelop old ones and provide a more comprehensive interpretation of the facts, see Rodgers, 'Republicanism: The Career of a Concept', pp. 11-12.
    • (1992) Republics: Ancient and Modern: Classical Republicanism and the American Revolution , pp. 726-747
    • Rahe, P.1
  • 33
    • 0004317436 scopus 로고
    • Chapel Hill, NC
    • James T. Kloppenberg, 'The Virtues of Liberalism: Christianity, Republicanism, and Ethics in Early American Political Discourse', Journal of American History, 74 (1987), p. 11. Interpretations that ignore the diversity of intellectual traditions present in the American Founding are often deterministic and question-begging and have been presented by scholars on both sides of this debate. Pocock, for example, has argued that to understand the eighteenth century fully we must trace out the persistence of civic humanism. He has then simply ignored - cast out of vision - central documents, such as the Declaration of Independence, that illustrate the importance of the social contract-natural rights tradition. Moreover, as Joyce Appleby has most persistently charged, the republican revisionists have been guilty of determinism, in particular by fastening on to a mode of interpretation that is unable to take into account the numerous changes in social practice and ideology that were taking place in the eighteenth century. In the initial stages of this debate at least, the republican revisionists were too quick to say that the Founders were locked into a conceptual world of classical republican language that precluded the development and use of other political languages. Similarly, Thomas Pangle, Paul Rahe, and before them Martin Diamond have interpreted the Founders' political thought as a species of the 'New Science of Politics' of Machiavelli, Hobbes and Locke. They have then ignored or presented perverse interpretations of important dimensions of the Founders' political thought that challenge this reading, especially Jeffersonian political economy. For the tendency of the republican revisionists to ignore the Declaration of Independence and the natural rights tradition see Scott Gerber, 'What Ever Happened to the Declaration? A Commentary on the Republican Revisionism in the Political Thought of the American Revolution', Polity, 26 (1993), pp. 207-31; and Gerber, To Secure These Rights (New York, 1995), esp. pp. 19-56. For the deterministic tendencies of the republican revisionists' methodology see Joyce Appleby, 'Republicanism in Old and New Contexts', The William and Mary Quarterly, 43 (1986), pp. 26-31. See Eugene Miller, 'What Publius Says About Interest', The Political Science Reviewer, 19 (1990), pp. 20-1, for warnings about how interpreting the political thought of the Founders through the lens of the 'New Science of Politics' can lead to interpretations that take for granted what they are designed to prove. The reductionism of Rahe, Pangle and Diamond's interpretations of Jeffersonian political economy can be grasped by comparing Diamond, 'Democracy and The Federalist: A Reconsideration of the Framers' Intent' and 'Ethics and Politics', in As Far As Republican Principles Will Admit: Essays by Martin Diamond, ed. William A. Schambra (Washington, 1992), esp. pp. 31-5, 337-68; Diamond, The Founding of the Democratic Republic (Itasca, IL, 1981), pp. 71-8; Thomas Pangle, The Spirit of Modern Republicanism: The Moral Vision of the American Founders and the Philosophy of Locke (Chicago, 1988), pp. 98-104; and Paul Rahe, Republics: Ancient and Modern: Classical Republicanism and the American Revolution (Chapel Hill, NC, & London, 1992), pp. 726-47, with McCoy, The Elusive Republic: Political Economy in Jeffersonian America (Chapel Hill, NC, 1980), pp. 120-35. See also Alan Gibson, 'The Commercial Republic and the Pluralist Critique of Marxism: An Analysis of Martin Diamond's Interpretation of Federalist 10', Polity, 25 (1993), pp. 521-8. For the way in which paradigms of interpretation change because scholars have identified a new set of problems as central, not necessarily because new paradigms envelop old ones and provide a more comprehensive interpretation of the facts, see Rodgers, 'Republicanism: The Career of a Concept', pp. 11-12.
    • (1980) The Elusive Republic: Political Economy in Jeffersonian America , pp. 120-135
    • McCoy1
  • 34
    • 85050169030 scopus 로고
    • The Commercial Republic and the Pluralist Critique of Marxism: An Analysis of Martin Diamond's Interpretation of Federalist 10
    • James T. Kloppenberg, 'The Virtues of Liberalism: Christianity, Republicanism, and Ethics in Early American Political Discourse', Journal of American History, 74 (1987), p. 11. Interpretations that ignore the diversity of intellectual traditions present in the American Founding are often deterministic and question-begging and have been presented by scholars on both sides of this debate. Pocock, for example, has argued that to understand the eighteenth century fully we must trace out the persistence of civic humanism. He has then simply ignored - cast out of vision - central documents, such as the Declaration of Independence, that illustrate the importance of the social contract-natural rights tradition. Moreover, as Joyce Appleby has most persistently charged, the republican revisionists have been guilty of determinism, in particular by fastening on to a mode of interpretation that is unable to take into account the numerous changes in social practice and ideology that were taking place in the eighteenth century. In the initial stages of this debate at least, the republican revisionists were too quick to say that the Founders were locked into a conceptual world of classical republican language that precluded the development and use of other political languages. Similarly, Thomas Pangle, Paul Rahe, and before them Martin Diamond have interpreted the Founders' political thought as a species of the 'New Science of Politics' of Machiavelli, Hobbes and Locke. They have then ignored or presented perverse interpretations of important dimensions of the Founders' political thought that challenge this reading, especially Jeffersonian political economy. For the tendency of the republican revisionists to ignore the Declaration of Independence and the natural rights tradition see Scott Gerber, 'What Ever Happened to the Declaration? A Commentary on the Republican Revisionism in the Political Thought of the American Revolution', Polity, 26 (1993), pp. 207-31; and Gerber, To Secure These Rights (New York, 1995), esp. pp. 19-56. For the deterministic tendencies of the republican revisionists' methodology see Joyce Appleby, 'Republicanism in Old and New Contexts', The William and Mary Quarterly, 43 (1986), pp. 26-31. See Eugene Miller, 'What Publius Says About Interest', The Political Science Reviewer, 19 (1990), pp. 20-1, for warnings about how interpreting the political thought of the Founders through the lens of the 'New Science of Politics' can lead to interpretations that take for granted what they are designed to prove. The reductionism of Rahe, Pangle and Diamond's interpretations of Jeffersonian political economy can be grasped by comparing Diamond, 'Democracy and The Federalist: A Reconsideration of the Framers' Intent' and 'Ethics and Politics', in As Far As Republican Principles Will Admit: Essays by Martin Diamond, ed. William A. Schambra (Washington, 1992), esp. pp. 31-5, 337-68; Diamond, The Founding of the Democratic Republic (Itasca, IL, 1981), pp. 71-8; Thomas Pangle, The Spirit of Modern Republicanism: The Moral Vision of the American Founders and the Philosophy of Locke (Chicago, 1988), pp. 98-104; and Paul Rahe, Republics: Ancient and Modern: Classical Republicanism and the American Revolution (Chapel Hill, NC, & London, 1992), pp. 726-47, with McCoy, The Elusive Republic: Political Economy in Jeffersonian America (Chapel Hill, NC, 1980), pp. 120-35. See also Alan Gibson, 'The Commercial Republic and the Pluralist Critique of Marxism: An Analysis of Martin Diamond's Interpretation of Federalist 10', Polity, 25 (1993), pp. 521-8. For the way in which paradigms of interpretation change because scholars have identified a new set of problems as central, not necessarily because new paradigms envelop old ones and provide a more comprehensive interpretation of the facts, see Rodgers, 'Republicanism: The Career of a Concept', pp. 11-12.
    • (1993) Polity , vol.25 , pp. 521-528
    • Gibson, A.1
  • 35
    • 0346254492 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • James T. Kloppenberg, 'The Virtues of Liberalism: Christianity, Republicanism, and Ethics in Early American Political Discourse', Journal of American History, 74 (1987), p. 11. Interpretations that ignore the diversity of intellectual traditions present in the American Founding are often deterministic and question-begging and have been presented by scholars on both sides of this debate. Pocock, for example, has argued that to understand the eighteenth century fully we must trace out the persistence of civic humanism. He has then simply ignored - cast out of vision - central documents, such as the Declaration of Independence, that illustrate the importance of the social contract-natural rights tradition. Moreover, as Joyce Appleby has most persistently charged, the republican revisionists have been guilty of determinism, in particular by fastening on to a mode of interpretation that is unable to take into account the numerous changes in social practice and ideology that were taking place in the eighteenth century. In the initial stages of this debate at least, the republican revisionists were too quick to say that the Founders were locked into a conceptual world of classical republican language that precluded the development and use of other political languages. Similarly, Thomas Pangle, Paul Rahe, and before them Martin Diamond have interpreted the Founders' political thought as a species of the 'New Science of Politics' of Machiavelli, Hobbes and Locke. They have then ignored or presented perverse interpretations of important dimensions of the Founders' political thought that challenge this reading, especially Jeffersonian political economy. For the tendency of the republican revisionists to ignore the Declaration of Independence and the natural rights tradition see Scott Gerber, 'What Ever Happened to the Declaration? A Commentary on the Republican Revisionism in the Political Thought of the American Revolution', Polity, 26 (1993), pp. 207-31; and Gerber, To Secure These Rights (New York, 1995), esp. pp. 19-56. For the deterministic tendencies of the republican revisionists' methodology see Joyce Appleby, 'Republicanism in Old and New Contexts', The William and Mary Quarterly, 43 (1986), pp. 26-31. See Eugene Miller, 'What Publius Says About Interest', The Political Science Reviewer, 19 (1990), pp. 20-1, for warnings about how interpreting the political thought of the Founders through the lens of the 'New Science of Politics' can lead to interpretations that take for granted what they are designed to prove. The reductionism of Rahe, Pangle and Diamond's interpretations of Jeffersonian political economy can be grasped by comparing Diamond, 'Democracy and The Federalist: A Reconsideration of the Framers' Intent' and 'Ethics and Politics', in As Far As Republican Principles Will Admit: Essays by Martin Diamond, ed. William A. Schambra (Washington, 1992), esp. pp. 31-5, 337-68; Diamond, The Founding of the Democratic Republic (Itasca, IL, 1981), pp. 71-8; Thomas Pangle, The Spirit of Modern Republicanism: The Moral Vision of the American Founders and the Philosophy of Locke (Chicago, 1988), pp. 98-104; and Paul Rahe, Republics: Ancient and Modern: Classical Republicanism and the American Revolution (Chapel Hill, NC, & London, 1992), pp. 726-47, with McCoy, The Elusive Republic: Political Economy in Jeffersonian America (Chapel Hill, NC, 1980), pp. 120-35. See also Alan Gibson, 'The Commercial Republic and the Pluralist Critique of Marxism: An Analysis of Martin Diamond's Interpretation of Federalist 10', Polity, 25 (1993), pp. 521-8. For the way in which paradigms of interpretation change because scholars have identified a new set of problems as central, not necessarily because new paradigms envelop old ones and provide a more comprehensive interpretation of the facts, see Rodgers, 'Republicanism: The Career of a Concept', pp. 11-12.
    • Republicanism: The Career of a Concept , pp. 11-12
    • Rodgers1
  • 36
    • 0011608066 scopus 로고
    • Ideology and the Origins of Liberal America
    • Gordon Wood, 'Ideology and the Origins of Liberal America', The William and Mary Quarterly, 44 (1987), p. 634.
    • (1987) The William and Mary Quarterly , vol.44 , pp. 634
    • Wood, G.1
  • 37
    • 0011672216 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Banning, 'Jeffersonian Ideology Revisited', p. 12; Banning, 'Quid Transit?', p. 201; Banning, 'Retrospect and Prospect', pp. 92-3, 111-13; Robert Shalhope, The Roots of Democracy: American Thought and Culture, 1760-1800 (Boston, 1990), p. xii; Zuckert, The Natural Rights Republic, pp. 209-10; Ralph Ketcham, 'Review of If Men Were Angels: James Madison and the Heartless Empire of Reason by Richard K. Matthews', William and Mary Quarterly, 52 (1995), pp. 697-702.
    • Jeffersonian Ideology Revisited , pp. 12
    • Banning1
  • 38
    • 0346884763 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Banning, 'Jeffersonian Ideology Revisited', p. 12; Banning, 'Quid Transit?', p. 201; Banning, 'Retrospect and Prospect', pp. 92-3, 111-13; Robert Shalhope, The Roots of Democracy: American Thought and Culture, 1760-1800 (Boston, 1990), p. xii; Zuckert, The Natural Rights Republic, pp. 209-10; Ralph Ketcham, 'Review of If Men Were Angels: James Madison and the Heartless Empire of Reason by Richard K. Matthews', William and Mary Quarterly, 52 (1995), pp. 697-702.
    • Quid Transit? , pp. 201
    • Banning1
  • 39
    • 0346884764 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Banning, 'Jeffersonian Ideology Revisited', p. 12; Banning, 'Quid Transit?', p. 201; Banning, 'Retrospect and Prospect', pp. 92-3, 111-13; Robert Shalhope, The Roots of Democracy: American Thought and Culture, 1760-1800 (Boston, 1990), p. xii; Zuckert, The Natural Rights Republic, pp. 209-10; Ralph Ketcham, 'Review of If Men Were Angels: James Madison and the Heartless Empire of Reason by Richard K. Matthews', William and Mary Quarterly, 52 (1995), pp. 697-702.
    • Retrospect and Prospect , pp. 92-93
    • Banning1
  • 40
    • 0040730869 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Boston
    • Banning, 'Jeffersonian Ideology Revisited', p. 12; Banning, 'Quid Transit?', p. 201; Banning, 'Retrospect and Prospect', pp. 92-3, 111-13; Robert Shalhope, The Roots of Democracy: American Thought and Culture, 1760-1800 (Boston, 1990), p. xii; Zuckert, The Natural Rights Republic, pp. 209-10; Ralph Ketcham, 'Review of If Men Were Angels: James Madison and the Heartless Empire of Reason by Richard K. Matthews', William and Mary Quarterly, 52 (1995), pp. 697-702.
    • (1990) The Roots of Democracy: American Thought and Culture, 1760-1800
    • Shalhope, R.1
  • 41
    • 0005435460 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Banning, 'Jeffersonian Ideology Revisited', p. 12; Banning, 'Quid Transit?', p. 201; Banning, 'Retrospect and Prospect', pp. 92-3, 111-13; Robert Shalhope, The Roots of Democracy: American Thought and Culture, 1760-1800 (Boston, 1990), p. xii; Zuckert, The Natural Rights Republic, pp. 209-10; Ralph Ketcham, 'Review of If Men Were Angels: James Madison and the Heartless Empire of Reason by Richard K. Matthews', William and Mary Quarterly, 52 (1995), pp. 697-702.
    • The Natural Rights Republic , pp. 209-210
    • Zuckert1
  • 42
    • 0348145287 scopus 로고
    • Review of if Men Were Angels: James Madison and the Heartless Empire of Reason by Richard K. Matthews
    • Banning, 'Jeffersonian Ideology Revisited', p. 12; Banning, 'Quid Transit?', p. 201; Banning, 'Retrospect and Prospect', pp. 92-3, 111-13; Robert Shalhope, The Roots of Democracy: American Thought and Culture, 1760-1800 (Boston, 1990), p. xii; Zuckert, The Natural Rights Republic, pp. 209-10; Ralph Ketcham, 'Review of If Men Were Angels: James Madison and the Heartless Empire of Reason by Richard K. Matthews', William and Mary Quarterly, 52 (1995), pp. 697-702.
    • (1995) William and Mary Quarterly , vol.52 , pp. 697-702
    • Ketcham, R.1
  • 43
    • 0005435460 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a particularly clear and forceful statement of this position see Zuckert, The Natural Rights Republic, pp. 7-8, 95-6, 209-10.
    • The Natural Rights Republic , pp. 7-8
    • Zuckert1
  • 44
    • 0003603039 scopus 로고
    • Chicago
    • Not all scholars of course have come to this conclusion. Many continue to interpret the Founders' political thought as a species of liberalism. In addition to works of Gerber and Pangle cited above see also John Patrick Diggins, The Lost Soul of American Politics: Virtue, Self-Interest, and the Foundations of Liberalism (Chicago, 1986); Jennifer Nedelsky, Private Property and the Limits of American Constitutionalism: The Madisonian Framework and Its Legacy (Chicago, 1990); Richard Matthews, If Men Were Angels: James Madison and the Heartless Empire of Reason (Lawrence, KS, 1995); Asher Horowitz and Richard K. Matthews, 'Narcissism of the Minor Differences: What is at Issue and What is at Stake in the Civic Humanism Question', Polity, 30 (1997), pp. 1-27.
    • (1986) The Lost Soul of American Politics: Virtue, Self-Interest, and the Foundations of Liberalism
    • Diggins, J.P.1
  • 45
    • 0003698256 scopus 로고
    • Chicago
    • Not all scholars of course have come to this conclusion. Many continue to interpret the Founders' political thought as a species of liberalism. In addition to works of Gerber and Pangle cited above see also John Patrick Diggins, The Lost Soul of American Politics: Virtue, Self-Interest, and the Foundations of Liberalism (Chicago, 1986); Jennifer Nedelsky, Private Property and the Limits of American Constitutionalism: The Madisonian Framework and Its Legacy (Chicago, 1990); Richard Matthews, If Men Were Angels: James Madison and the Heartless Empire of Reason (Lawrence, KS, 1995); Asher Horowitz and Richard K. Matthews, 'Narcissism of the Minor Differences: What is at Issue and What is at Stake in the Civic Humanism Question', Polity, 30 (1997), pp. 1-27.
    • (1990) Private Property and the Limits of American Constitutionalism: The Madisonian Framework and Its Legacy
    • Nedelsky, J.1
  • 46
    • 0003785870 scopus 로고
    • Lawrence, KS
    • Not all scholars of course have come to this conclusion. Many continue to interpret the Founders' political thought as a species of liberalism. In addition to works of Gerber and Pangle cited above see also John Patrick Diggins, The Lost Soul of American Politics: Virtue, Self-Interest, and the Foundations of Liberalism (Chicago, 1986); Jennifer Nedelsky, Private Property and the Limits of American Constitutionalism: The Madisonian Framework and Its Legacy (Chicago, 1990); Richard Matthews, If Men Were Angels: James Madison and the Heartless Empire of Reason (Lawrence, KS, 1995); Asher Horowitz and Richard K. Matthews, 'Narcissism of the Minor Differences: What is at Issue and What is at Stake in the Civic Humanism Question', Polity, 30 (1997), pp. 1-27.
    • (1995) If Men Were Angels: James Madison and the Heartless Empire of Reason
    • Matthews, R.1
  • 47
    • 8344231544 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Narcissism of the Minor Differences: What is at Issue and What is at Stake in the Civic Humanism Question
    • Not all scholars of course have come to this conclusion. Many continue to interpret the Founders' political thought as a species of liberalism. In addition to works of Gerber and Pangle cited above see also John Patrick Diggins, The Lost Soul of American Politics: Virtue, Self-Interest, and the Foundations of Liberalism (Chicago, 1986); Jennifer Nedelsky, Private Property and the Limits of American Constitutionalism: The Madisonian Framework and Its Legacy (Chicago, 1990); Richard Matthews, If Men Were Angels: James Madison and the Heartless Empire of Reason (Lawrence, KS, 1995); Asher Horowitz and Richard K. Matthews, 'Narcissism of the Minor Differences: What is at Issue and What is at Stake in the Civic Humanism Question', Polity, 30 (1997), pp. 1-27.
    • (1997) Polity , vol.30 , pp. 1-27
    • Horowitz, A.1    Matthews, R.K.2
  • 50
    • 0000444815 scopus 로고
    • Beyond Tocqueville, Myrdal, and Hartz: The Multiple Traditions in America
    • and citations to Smith's works below
    • I borrow the phrase 'multiple traditions approach' from Rogers Smith. See R. Smith, 'Beyond Tocqueville, Myrdal, and Hartz: The Multiple Traditions in America', American Political Science Review, 87 (1993), pp. 549-66, and citations to Smith's works below.
    • (1993) American Political Science Review , vol.87 , pp. 549-566
    • Smith, R.1
  • 51
    • 84928838891 scopus 로고
    • Republicanism vs. Liberalism?
    • In addition to the works analysed in the text, Jeffery Isaac and Alan Craig Houston have presented studies which, although they do not directly interpret the American Founding, have important implications for its study and should be read in conjunction with the works discussed above. Both Isaac and Houston argue that the political thought of the 'Commonwealthmen' or 'radical Whigs' of seventeenth- and eighteenth-century England was a synthesis composed centrally of liberalism, but also containing important strains of republicanism. They then hypothesize - although it is not their goal to prove - that this synthesis was also characteristic of the American Founders. See Jeffrey Isaac, 'Republicanism vs. Liberalism?', History of Political Thought, IX (1988), pp. 349-77; and A.C. Houston, Algernon Sidney and the Republican Heritage in England and America (Princeton, NJ, 1991). Moreover, James Kloppenberg's oft-cited essay 'The Virtues of Liberalism', his recently published book by the same name, and especially Jerome Huyler's study Locke in America and Richard Sinopoli's excellent book The Foundations of American Citizenship also present interpretations of the American Founding that suggest that the Founders incorporated diverse strains of political thought within a capacious conception of liberalism. See Kloppenberg, 'The Virtues of Liberalism', pp. 9-33; J. Kloppenberg, The Virtues of Liberalism (New York, 1998); Jerome Huyler, Locke in America: The Moral Philosophy of the Founding Era (Lawrence, KS, 1995); Richard Sinopoli, The Foundations of American Citizenship: Liberalism, the Constitution, and Civic Virtue (New York, 1992).
    • (1988) History of Political Thought , vol.9 , pp. 349-377
    • Isaac, J.1
  • 52
    • 0004008029 scopus 로고
    • Princeton, NJ
    • In addition to the works analysed in the text, Jeffery Isaac and Alan Craig Houston have presented studies which, although they do not directly interpret the American Founding, have important implications for its study and should be read in conjunction with the works discussed above. Both Isaac and Houston argue that the political thought of the 'Commonwealthmen' or 'radical Whigs' of seventeenth- and eighteenth-century England was a synthesis composed centrally of liberalism, but also containing important strains of republicanism. They then hypothesize - although it is not their goal to prove - that this synthesis was also characteristic of the American Founders. See Jeffrey Isaac, 'Republicanism vs. Liberalism?', History of Political Thought, IX (1988), pp. 349-77; and A.C. Houston, Algernon Sidney and the Republican Heritage in England and America (Princeton, NJ, 1991). Moreover, James Kloppenberg's oft-cited essay 'The Virtues of Liberalism', his recently published book by the same name, and especially Jerome Huyler's study Locke in America and Richard Sinopoli's excellent book The Foundations of American Citizenship also present interpretations of the American Founding that suggest that the Founders incorporated diverse strains of political thought within a capacious conception of liberalism. See Kloppenberg, 'The Virtues of Liberalism', pp. 9-33; J. Kloppenberg, The Virtues of Liberalism (New York, 1998); Jerome Huyler, Locke in America: The Moral Philosophy of the Founding Era (Lawrence, KS, 1995); Richard Sinopoli, The Foundations of American Citizenship: Liberalism, the Constitution, and Civic Virtue (New York, 1992).
    • (1991) Algernon Sidney and the Republican Heritage in England and America
    • Houston, A.C.1
  • 53
    • 0004292793 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In addition to the works analysed in the text, Jeffery Isaac and Alan Craig Houston have presented studies which, although they do not directly interpret the American Founding, have important implications for its study and should be read in conjunction with the works discussed above. Both Isaac and Houston argue that the political thought of the 'Commonwealthmen' or 'radical Whigs' of seventeenth- and eighteenth-century England was a synthesis composed centrally of liberalism, but also containing important strains of republicanism. They then hypothesize - although it is not their goal to prove - that this synthesis was also characteristic of the American Founders. See Jeffrey Isaac, 'Republicanism vs. Liberalism?', History of Political Thought, IX (1988), pp. 349-77; and A.C. Houston, Algernon Sidney and the Republican Heritage in England and America (Princeton, NJ, 1991). Moreover, James Kloppenberg's oft-cited essay 'The Virtues of Liberalism', his recently published book by the same name, and especially Jerome Huyler's study Locke in America and Richard Sinopoli's excellent book The Foundations of American Citizenship also present interpretations of the American Founding that suggest that the Founders incorporated diverse strains of political thought within a capacious conception of liberalism. See Kloppenberg, 'The Virtues of Liberalism', pp. 9-33; J. Kloppenberg, The Virtues of Liberalism (New York, 1998); Jerome Huyler, Locke in America: The Moral Philosophy of the Founding Era (Lawrence, KS, 1995); Richard Sinopoli, The Foundations of American Citizenship: Liberalism, the Constitution, and Civic Virtue (New York, 1992).
    • The Virtues of Liberalism
    • Kloppenberg, J.1
  • 54
    • 0346884747 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In addition to the works analysed in the text, Jeffery Isaac and Alan Craig Houston have presented studies which, although they do not directly interpret the American Founding, have important implications for its study and should be read in conjunction with the works discussed above. Both Isaac and Houston argue that the political thought of the 'Commonwealthmen' or 'radical Whigs' of seventeenth- and eighteenth-century England was a synthesis composed centrally of liberalism, but also containing important strains of republicanism. They then hypothesize - although it is not their goal to prove - that this synthesis was also characteristic of the American Founders. See Jeffrey Isaac, 'Republicanism vs. Liberalism?', History of Political Thought, IX (1988), pp. 349-77; and A.C. Houston, Algernon Sidney and the Republican Heritage in England and America (Princeton, NJ, 1991). Moreover, James Kloppenberg's oft-cited essay 'The Virtues of Liberalism', his recently published book by the same name, and especially Jerome Huyler's study Locke in America and Richard Sinopoli's excellent book The Foundations of American Citizenship also present interpretations of the American Founding that suggest that the Founders incorporated diverse strains of political thought within a capacious conception of liberalism. See Kloppenberg, 'The Virtues of Liberalism', pp. 9-33; J. Kloppenberg, The Virtues of Liberalism (New York, 1998); Jerome Huyler, Locke in America: The Moral Philosophy of the Founding Era (Lawrence, KS, 1995); Richard Sinopoli, The Foundations of American Citizenship: Liberalism, the Constitution, and Civic Virtue (New York, 1992).
    • Locke in America
    • Huyler, J.1
  • 55
    • 0004009097 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In addition to the works analysed in the text, Jeffery Isaac and Alan Craig Houston have presented studies which, although they do not directly interpret the American Founding, have important implications for its study and should be read in conjunction with the works discussed above. Both Isaac and Houston argue that the political thought of the 'Commonwealthmen' or 'radical Whigs' of seventeenth- and eighteenth-century England was a synthesis composed centrally of liberalism, but also containing important strains of republicanism. They then hypothesize - although it is not their goal to prove - that this synthesis was also characteristic of the American Founders. See Jeffrey Isaac, 'Republicanism vs. Liberalism?', History of Political Thought, IX (1988), pp. 349-77; and A.C. Houston, Algernon Sidney and the Republican Heritage in England and America (Princeton, NJ, 1991). Moreover, James Kloppenberg's oft-cited essay 'The Virtues of Liberalism', his recently published book by the same name, and especially Jerome Huyler's study Locke in America and Richard Sinopoli's excellent book The Foundations of American Citizenship also present interpretations of the American Founding that suggest that the Founders incorporated diverse strains of political thought within a capacious conception of liberalism. See Kloppenberg, 'The Virtues of Liberalism', pp. 9-33; J. Kloppenberg, The Virtues of Liberalism (New York, 1998); Jerome Huyler, Locke in America: The Moral Philosophy of the Founding Era (Lawrence, KS, 1995); Richard Sinopoli, The Foundations of American Citizenship: Liberalism, the Constitution, and Civic Virtue (New York, 1992).
    • The Foundations of American Citizenship
    • Sinopoli, R.1
  • 56
    • 0004292793 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In addition to the works analysed in the text, Jeffery Isaac and Alan Craig Houston have presented studies which, although they do not directly interpret the American Founding, have important implications for its study and should be read in conjunction with the works discussed above. Both Isaac and Houston argue that the political thought of the 'Commonwealthmen' or 'radical Whigs' of seventeenth- and eighteenth-century England was a synthesis composed centrally of liberalism, but also containing important strains of republicanism. They then hypothesize - although it is not their goal to prove - that this synthesis was also characteristic of the American Founders. See Jeffrey Isaac, 'Republicanism vs. Liberalism?', History of Political Thought, IX (1988), pp. 349-77; and A.C. Houston, Algernon Sidney and the Republican Heritage in England and America (Princeton, NJ, 1991). Moreover, James Kloppenberg's oft-cited essay 'The Virtues of Liberalism', his recently published book by the same name, and especially Jerome Huyler's study Locke in America and Richard Sinopoli's excellent book The Foundations of American Citizenship also present interpretations of the American Founding that suggest that the Founders incorporated diverse strains of political thought within a capacious conception of liberalism. See Kloppenberg, 'The Virtues of Liberalism', pp. 9-33; J. Kloppenberg, The Virtues of Liberalism (New York, 1998); Jerome Huyler, Locke in America: The Moral Philosophy of the Founding Era (Lawrence, KS, 1995); Richard Sinopoli, The Foundations of American Citizenship: Liberalism, the Constitution, and Civic Virtue (New York, 1992).
    • The Virtues of Liberalism , pp. 9-33
    • Kloppenberg1
  • 57
    • 0004292793 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York
    • In addition to the works analysed in the text, Jeffery Isaac and Alan Craig Houston have presented studies which, although they do not directly interpret the American Founding, have important implications for its study and should be read in conjunction with the works discussed above. Both Isaac and Houston argue that the political thought of the 'Commonwealthmen' or 'radical Whigs' of seventeenth- and eighteenth-century England was a synthesis composed centrally of liberalism, but also containing important strains of republicanism. They then hypothesize - although it is not their goal to prove - that this synthesis was also characteristic of the American Founders. See Jeffrey Isaac, 'Republicanism vs. Liberalism?', History of Political Thought, IX (1988), pp. 349-77; and A.C. Houston, Algernon Sidney and the Republican Heritage in England and America (Princeton, NJ, 1991). Moreover, James Kloppenberg's oft-cited essay 'The Virtues of Liberalism', his recently published book by the same name, and especially Jerome Huyler's study Locke in America and Richard Sinopoli's excellent book The Foundations of American Citizenship also present interpretations of the American Founding that suggest that the Founders incorporated diverse strains of political thought within a capacious conception of liberalism. See Kloppenberg, 'The Virtues of Liberalism', pp. 9-33; J. Kloppenberg, The Virtues of Liberalism (New York, 1998); Jerome Huyler, Locke in America: The Moral Philosophy of the Founding Era (Lawrence, KS, 1995); Richard Sinopoli, The Foundations of American Citizenship: Liberalism, the Constitution, and Civic Virtue (New York, 1992).
    • (1998) The Virtues of Liberalism
    • Kloppenberg, J.1
  • 58
    • 0003394238 scopus 로고
    • Lawrence, KS
    • In addition to the works analysed in the text, Jeffery Isaac and Alan Craig Houston have presented studies which, although they do not directly interpret the American Founding, have important implications for its study and should be read in conjunction with the works discussed above. Both Isaac and Houston argue that the political thought of the 'Commonwealthmen' or 'radical Whigs' of seventeenth- and eighteenth-century England was a synthesis composed centrally of liberalism, but also containing important strains of republicanism. They then hypothesize - although it is not their goal to prove - that this synthesis was also characteristic of the American Founders. See Jeffrey Isaac, 'Republicanism vs. Liberalism?', History of Political Thought, IX (1988), pp. 349-77; and A.C. Houston, Algernon Sidney and the Republican Heritage in England and America (Princeton, NJ, 1991). Moreover, James Kloppenberg's oft-cited essay 'The Virtues of Liberalism', his recently published book by the same name, and especially Jerome Huyler's study Locke in America and Richard Sinopoli's excellent book The Foundations of American Citizenship also present interpretations of the American Founding that suggest that the Founders incorporated diverse strains of political thought within a capacious conception of liberalism. See Kloppenberg, 'The Virtues of Liberalism', pp. 9-33; J. Kloppenberg, The Virtues of Liberalism (New York, 1998); Jerome Huyler, Locke in America: The Moral Philosophy of the Founding Era (Lawrence, KS, 1995); Richard Sinopoli, The Foundations of American Citizenship: Liberalism, the Constitution, and Civic Virtue (New York, 1992).
    • (1995) Locke in America: The Moral Philosophy of the Founding Era
    • Huyler, J.1
  • 59
    • 0004009097 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York
    • In addition to the works analysed in the text, Jeffery Isaac and Alan Craig Houston have presented studies which, although they do not directly interpret the American Founding, have important implications for its study and should be read in conjunction with the works discussed above. Both Isaac and Houston argue that the political thought of the 'Commonwealthmen' or 'radical Whigs' of seventeenth- and eighteenth-century England was a synthesis composed centrally of liberalism, but also containing important strains of republicanism. They then hypothesize - although it is not their goal to prove - that this synthesis was also characteristic of the American Founders. See Jeffrey Isaac, 'Republicanism vs. Liberalism?', History of Political Thought, IX (1988), pp. 349-77; and A.C. Houston, Algernon Sidney and the Republican Heritage in England and America (Princeton, NJ, 1991). Moreover, James Kloppenberg's oft-cited essay 'The Virtues of Liberalism', his recently published book by the same name, and especially Jerome Huyler's study Locke in America and Richard Sinopoli's excellent book The Foundations of American Citizenship also present interpretations of the American Founding that suggest that the Founders incorporated diverse strains of political thought within a capacious conception of liberalism. See Kloppenberg, 'The Virtues of Liberalism', pp. 9-33; J. Kloppenberg, The Virtues of Liberalism (New York, 1998); Jerome Huyler, Locke in America: The Moral Philosophy of the Founding Era (Lawrence, KS, 1995); Richard Sinopoli, The Foundations of American Citizenship: Liberalism, the Constitution, and Civic Virtue (New York, 1992).
    • (1992) The Foundations of American Citizenship: Liberalism, the Constitution, and Civic Virtue
    • Sinopoli, R.1
  • 61
    • 0347515392 scopus 로고
    • Against Simplicity: The Cultural Dimensions of the Constitution
    • J.D. Greenstone, 'Against Simplicity: The Cultural Dimensions of the Constitution', The University of Chicago Law Review, 40 (1988), pp. 438-42 (quote is on p. 439); J.D. Greenstone, 'Political Culture and American Political Development: Liberty, Union, and the Liberal Bipolarity', Studies in American Political Development: An Annual (New Haven, CT, 1986), 1, pp. 5-6; Greenstone, The Lincoln Persuasion, pp. 51-3. This interpretation is also explored in the work of one of Greenstone's students, David F. Ericson. See D.F. Ericson, The Shaping of American Liberalism: the Debates Over Ratification, Nullification, and Slavery (Chicago, 1993).
    • (1988) The University of Chicago Law Review , vol.40 , pp. 438-442
    • Greenstone, J.D.1
  • 62
    • 84971961775 scopus 로고
    • Political Culture and American Political Development: Liberty, Union, and the Liberal Bipolarity
    • New Haven, CT
    • J.D. Greenstone, 'Against Simplicity: The Cultural Dimensions of the Constitution', The University of Chicago Law Review, 40 (1988), pp. 438-42 (quote is on p. 439); J.D. Greenstone, 'Political Culture and American Political Development: Liberty, Union, and the Liberal Bipolarity', Studies in American Political Development: An Annual (New Haven, CT, 1986), 1, pp. 5-6; Greenstone, The Lincoln Persuasion, pp. 51-3. This interpretation is also explored in the work of one of Greenstone's students, David F. Ericson. See D.F. Ericson, The Shaping of American Liberalism: the Debates Over Ratification, Nullification, and Slavery (Chicago, 1993).
    • (1986) Studies in American Political Development: An Annual , vol.1 , pp. 5-6
    • Greenstone, J.D.1
  • 63
    • 0038971651 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • J.D. Greenstone, 'Against Simplicity: The Cultural Dimensions of the Constitution', The University of Chicago Law Review, 40 (1988), pp. 438-42 (quote is on p. 439); J.D. Greenstone, 'Political Culture and American Political Development: Liberty, Union, and the Liberal Bipolarity', Studies in American Political Development: An Annual (New Haven, CT, 1986), 1, pp. 5-6; Greenstone, The Lincoln Persuasion, pp. 51-3. This interpretation is also explored in the work of one of Greenstone's students, David F. Ericson. See D.F. Ericson, The Shaping of American Liberalism: the Debates Over Ratification, Nullification, and Slavery (Chicago, 1993).
    • The Lincoln Persuasion , pp. 51-53
    • Greenstone1
  • 64
    • 0003861052 scopus 로고
    • Chicago
    • J.D. Greenstone, 'Against Simplicity: The Cultural Dimensions of the Constitution', The University of Chicago Law Review, 40 (1988), pp. 438-42 (quote is on p. 439); J.D. Greenstone, 'Political Culture and American Political Development: Liberty, Union, and the Liberal Bipolarity', Studies in American Political Development: An Annual (New Haven, CT, 1986), 1, pp. 5-6; Greenstone, The Lincoln Persuasion, pp. 51-3. This interpretation is also explored in the work of one of Greenstone's students, David F. Ericson. See D.F. Ericson, The Shaping of American Liberalism: the Debates Over Ratification, Nullification, and Slavery (Chicago, 1993).
    • (1993) The Shaping of American Liberalism: The Debates over Ratification, Nullification, and Slavery
    • Ericson, D.F.1
  • 75
    • 0346884747 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I also interpret this as one of the central purposes of Huyler's excellent work, Locke in America.
    • Locke in America
    • Huyler1
  • 76
    • 0007225425 scopus 로고
    • A "Non-Lockean" Locke and the Character of Liberalism
    • ed. Douglas MacLean and Claudia Mills Totowa, NJ
    • Nathan Tarcov, 'A "Non-Lockean" Locke and the Character of Liberalism', in Liberalism Reconsidered, ed. Douglas MacLean and Claudia Mills (Totowa, NJ, 1983), pp. 130-40. Such reappraisals of Locke's political thought parallel the effort of a number of scholars, including William Galston, Michael Walzer, Stephen Macedo, Amy Gutman and, most recently, James Kloppenberg, to provide a more sympathetic understanding of liberalism by arguing that it is more capacious than its critics charge. See William Galston, 'Defending Liberalism', American Political Science Review, 76 (1982), pp. 621-9; W. Galston, Liberal Purposes: Goods, Virtues, and Diversity in the Liberal State (New York, 1991); Michael Walzer, Spheres of Justice: A Defense of Pluralism and Equality (New York, 1983); Stephen Macedo, Liberal Virtues: Citizenship, Virtue, and Community in Liberal Constitutionalism (New York, 1990); Amy Gutman, 'Communitarian Critics of Liberalism', Philosophy and Public Affairs, 14 (1985), pp. 308-22; Kloppenberg, The Virtues of Liberalism.
    • (1983) Liberalism Reconsidered , pp. 130-140
    • Tarcov, N.1
  • 77
    • 84974065403 scopus 로고
    • Defending Liberalism
    • Nathan Tarcov, 'A "Non-Lockean" Locke and the Character of Liberalism', in Liberalism Reconsidered, ed. Douglas MacLean and Claudia Mills (Totowa, NJ, 1983), pp. 130-40. Such reappraisals of Locke's political thought parallel the effort of a number of scholars, including William Galston, Michael Walzer, Stephen Macedo, Amy Gutman and, most recently, James Kloppenberg, to provide a more sympathetic understanding of liberalism by arguing that it is more capacious than its critics charge. See William Galston, 'Defending Liberalism', American Political Science Review, 76 (1982), pp. 621-9; W. Galston, Liberal Purposes: Goods, Virtues, and Diversity in the Liberal State (New York, 1991); Michael Walzer, Spheres of Justice: A Defense of Pluralism and Equality (New York, 1983); Stephen Macedo, Liberal Virtues: Citizenship, Virtue, and Community in Liberal Constitutionalism (New York, 1990); Amy Gutman, 'Communitarian Critics of Liberalism', Philosophy and Public Affairs, 14 (1985), pp. 308-22; Kloppenberg, The Virtues of Liberalism.
    • (1982) American Political Science Review , vol.76 , pp. 621-629
    • Galston, W.1
  • 78
    • 0003491522 scopus 로고
    • New York
    • Nathan Tarcov, 'A "Non-Lockean" Locke and the Character of Liberalism', in Liberalism Reconsidered, ed. Douglas MacLean and Claudia Mills (Totowa, NJ, 1983), pp. 130-40. Such reappraisals of Locke's political thought parallel the effort of a number of scholars, including William Galston, Michael Walzer, Stephen Macedo, Amy Gutman and, most recently, James Kloppenberg, to provide a more sympathetic understanding of liberalism by arguing that it is more capacious than its critics charge. See William Galston, 'Defending Liberalism', American Political Science Review, 76 (1982), pp. 621-9; W. Galston, Liberal Purposes: Goods, Virtues, and Diversity in the Liberal State (New York, 1991); Michael Walzer, Spheres of Justice: A Defense of Pluralism and Equality (New York, 1983); Stephen Macedo, Liberal Virtues: Citizenship, Virtue, and Community in Liberal Constitutionalism (New York, 1990); Amy Gutman, 'Communitarian Critics of Liberalism', Philosophy and Public Affairs, 14 (1985), pp. 308-22; Kloppenberg, The Virtues of Liberalism.
    • (1991) Liberal Purposes: Goods, Virtues, and Diversity in the Liberal State
    • Galston, W.1
  • 79
    • 0003924191 scopus 로고
    • New York
    • Nathan Tarcov, 'A "Non-Lockean" Locke and the Character of Liberalism', in Liberalism Reconsidered, ed. Douglas MacLean and Claudia Mills (Totowa, NJ, 1983), pp. 130-40. Such reappraisals of Locke's political thought parallel the effort of a number of scholars, including William Galston, Michael Walzer, Stephen Macedo, Amy Gutman and, most recently, James Kloppenberg, to provide a more sympathetic understanding of liberalism by arguing that it is more capacious than its critics charge. See William Galston, 'Defending Liberalism', American Political Science Review, 76 (1982), pp. 621-9; W. Galston, Liberal Purposes: Goods, Virtues, and Diversity in the Liberal State (New York, 1991); Michael Walzer, Spheres of Justice: A Defense of Pluralism and Equality (New York, 1983); Stephen Macedo, Liberal Virtues: Citizenship, Virtue, and Community in Liberal Constitutionalism (New York, 1990); Amy Gutman, 'Communitarian Critics of Liberalism', Philosophy and Public Affairs, 14 (1985), pp. 308-22; Kloppenberg, The Virtues of Liberalism.
    • (1983) Spheres of Justice: A Defense of Pluralism and Equality
    • Walzer, M.1
  • 80
    • 0003796286 scopus 로고
    • New York
    • Nathan Tarcov, 'A "Non-Lockean" Locke and the Character of Liberalism', in Liberalism Reconsidered, ed. Douglas MacLean and Claudia Mills (Totowa, NJ, 1983), pp. 130-40. Such reappraisals of Locke's political thought parallel the effort of a number of scholars, including William Galston, Michael Walzer, Stephen Macedo, Amy Gutman and, most recently, James Kloppenberg, to provide a more sympathetic understanding of liberalism by arguing that it is more capacious than its critics charge. See William Galston, 'Defending Liberalism', American Political Science Review, 76 (1982), pp. 621-9; W. Galston, Liberal Purposes: Goods, Virtues, and Diversity in the Liberal State (New York, 1991); Michael Walzer, Spheres of Justice: A Defense of Pluralism and Equality (New York, 1983); Stephen Macedo, Liberal Virtues: Citizenship, Virtue, and Community in Liberal Constitutionalism (New York, 1990); Amy Gutman, 'Communitarian Critics of Liberalism', Philosophy and Public Affairs, 14 (1985), pp. 308-22; Kloppenberg, The Virtues of Liberalism.
    • (1990) Liberal Virtues: Citizenship, Virtue, and Community in Liberal Constitutionalism
    • Macedo, S.1
  • 81
    • 84935566128 scopus 로고
    • Communitarian Critics of Liberalism
    • Nathan Tarcov, 'A "Non-Lockean" Locke and the Character of Liberalism', in Liberalism Reconsidered, ed. Douglas MacLean and Claudia Mills (Totowa, NJ, 1983), pp. 130-40. Such reappraisals of Locke's political thought parallel the effort of a number of scholars, including William Galston, Michael Walzer, Stephen Macedo, Amy Gutman and, most recently, James Kloppenberg, to provide a more sympathetic understanding of liberalism by arguing that it is more capacious than its critics charge. See William Galston, 'Defending Liberalism', American Political Science Review, 76 (1982), pp. 621-9; W. Galston, Liberal Purposes: Goods, Virtues, and Diversity in the Liberal State (New York, 1991); Michael Walzer, Spheres of Justice: A Defense of Pluralism and Equality (New York, 1983); Stephen Macedo, Liberal Virtues: Citizenship, Virtue, and Community in Liberal Constitutionalism (New York, 1990); Amy Gutman, 'Communitarian Critics of Liberalism', Philosophy and Public Affairs, 14 (1985), pp. 308-22; Kloppenberg, The Virtues of Liberalism.
    • (1985) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.14 , pp. 308-322
    • Gutman, A.1
  • 82
    • 0004292793 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nathan Tarcov, 'A "Non-Lockean" Locke and the Character of Liberalism', in Liberalism Reconsidered, ed. Douglas MacLean and Claudia Mills (Totowa, NJ, 1983), pp. 130-40. Such reappraisals of Locke's political thought parallel the effort of a number of scholars, including William Galston, Michael Walzer, Stephen Macedo, Amy Gutman and, most recently, James Kloppenberg, to provide a more sympathetic understanding of liberalism by arguing that it is more capacious than its critics charge. See William Galston, 'Defending Liberalism', American Political Science Review, 76 (1982), pp. 621-9; W. Galston, Liberal Purposes: Goods, Virtues, and Diversity in the Liberal State (New York, 1991); Michael Walzer, Spheres of Justice: A Defense of Pluralism and Equality (New York, 1983); Stephen Macedo, Liberal Virtues: Citizenship, Virtue, and Community in Liberal Constitutionalism (New York, 1990); Amy Gutman, 'Communitarian Critics of Liberalism', Philosophy and Public Affairs, 14 (1985), pp. 308-22; Kloppenberg, The Virtues of Liberalism.
    • The Virtues of Liberalism
    • Kloppenberg1
  • 89
    • 31444448543 scopus 로고
    • Between Gog and Magog: The Republican Thesis and the Ideologia Americana
    • Pocock often makes this same suggestion. Republicanism, he has further contended, was never displaced by liberalism, but rather has 'survived to furnish liberalism with one of its modes of self-criticism and self-doubt'. See J.G.A. Pocock, 'Between Gog and Magog: The Republican Thesis and the Ideologia Americana', Journal of the History of Ideas, 48 (1987), p. 341.
    • (1987) Journal of the History of Ideas , vol.48 , pp. 341
    • Pocock, J.G.A.1
  • 91
    • 0346884741 scopus 로고
    • Lawrence, KS
    • Ralph Ketcham, Framed for Posterity: The Enduring Philosophy of the Constitution (Lawrence, KS, 1993), pp. 38-45, pp. 165-72 (quotes are on pp. 169 and 166). For a similar understanding of the Framers' conception of 'liberty' see also Banning, 'Jeffersonian Ideology Revisited', pp. 17-19.
    • (1993) Framed for Posterity: The Enduring Philosophy of the Constitution , pp. 38-45
    • Ketcham, R.1
  • 92
    • 0011672216 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ralph Ketcham, Framed for Posterity: The Enduring Philosophy of the Constitution (Lawrence, KS, 1993), pp. 38-45, pp. 165-72 (quotes are on pp. 169 and 166). For a similar understanding of the Framers' conception of 'liberty'
    • Jeffersonian Ideology Revisited , pp. 17-19
    • Banning1
  • 93
    • 0040730869 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • quote is from
    • See for example the studies of Robert Shalhope. Shalhope treats republicanism in the early American Republic as a 'familiar ideology permeating all walks of life' but liberalism as more of an 'unarticulated behavioral pattern'. The rise of liberalism in his account is, in part at least, a story of how liberal practices eventually became ascendant and demanded intellectual justifications. Shalhope, The Roots of Democracy (quote is from p. 50). It is in this sense that the important works of Joyce Appleby are relevant and she can also be considered among the scholars who accept the multiple traditions approach. Although she argues for an exclusively liberal interpretation of the Jeffersonians, Appleby believes that members of the Federalist Party accepted the precepts of opposition ideology. She thus sees the eighteenth century as a period of transition in which liberalism and republicanism vied for ascendancy. Even more than Shalhope, she also contends that liberalism emerged as an intellectual justification for the liberal practices that accompanied the English financial revolution and became commonplace during the eighteenth century. See especially Appleby, 'Republicanism in Old and New Contexts', pp. 20-34; J. Appleby, Liberalism and Republicanism in the Historical Imagination (Cambridge, MA, 1992); and J. Appleby, Capitalism and the New Social Order: The Republican Vision of the 1790s (New York, 1984).
    • The Roots of Democracy , pp. 50
    • Shalhope1
  • 94
    • 0003073386 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See for example the studies of Robert Shalhope. Shalhope treats republicanism in the early American Republic as a 'familiar ideology permeating all walks of life' but liberalism as more of an 'unarticulated behavioral pattern'. The rise of liberalism in his account is, in part at least, a story of how liberal practices eventually became ascendant and demanded intellectual justifications. Shalhope, The Roots of Democracy (quote is from p. 50). It is in this sense that the important works of Joyce Appleby are relevant and she can also be considered among the scholars who accept the multiple traditions approach. Although she argues for an exclusively liberal interpretation of the Jeffersonians, Appleby believes that members of the Federalist Party accepted the precepts of opposition ideology. She thus sees the eighteenth century as a period of transition in which liberalism and republicanism vied for ascendancy. Even more than Shalhope, she also contends that liberalism emerged as an intellectual justification for the liberal practices that accompanied the English financial revolution and became commonplace during the eighteenth century. See especially Appleby, 'Republicanism in Old and New Contexts', pp. 20-34; J. Appleby, Liberalism and Republicanism in the Historical Imagination (Cambridge, MA, 1992); and J. Appleby, Capitalism and the New Social Order: The Republican Vision of the 1790s (New York, 1984).
    • Republicanism in Old and New Contexts , pp. 20-34
    • Appleby1
  • 95
    • 0003637458 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA
    • See for example the studies of Robert Shalhope. Shalhope treats republicanism in the early American Republic as a 'familiar ideology permeating all walks of life' but liberalism as more of an 'unarticulated behavioral pattern'. The rise of liberalism in his account is, in part at least, a story of how liberal practices eventually became ascendant and demanded intellectual justifications. Shalhope, The Roots of Democracy (quote is from p. 50). It is in this sense that the important works of Joyce Appleby are relevant and she can also be considered among the scholars who accept the multiple traditions approach. Although she argues for an exclusively liberal interpretation of the Jeffersonians, Appleby believes that members of the Federalist Party accepted the precepts of opposition ideology. She thus sees the eighteenth century as a period of transition in which liberalism and republicanism vied for ascendancy. Even more than Shalhope, she also contends that liberalism emerged as an intellectual justification for the liberal practices that accompanied the English financial revolution and became commonplace during the eighteenth century. See especially Appleby, 'Republicanism in Old and New Contexts', pp. 20-34; J. Appleby, Liberalism and Republicanism in the Historical Imagination (Cambridge, MA, 1992); and J. Appleby, Capitalism and the New Social Order: The Republican Vision of the 1790s (New York, 1984).
    • (1992) Liberalism and Republicanism in the Historical Imagination
    • Appleby, J.1
  • 96
    • 0003859080 scopus 로고
    • New York
    • See for example the studies of Robert Shalhope. Shalhope treats republicanism in the early American Republic as a 'familiar ideology permeating all walks of life' but liberalism as more of an 'unarticulated behavioral pattern'. The rise of liberalism in his account is, in part at least, a story of how liberal practices eventually became ascendant and demanded intellectual justifications. Shalhope, The Roots of Democracy (quote is from p. 50). It is in this sense that the important works of Joyce Appleby are relevant and she can also be considered among the scholars who accept the multiple traditions approach. Although she argues for an exclusively liberal interpretation of the Jeffersonians, Appleby believes that members of the Federalist Party accepted the precepts of opposition ideology. She thus sees the eighteenth century as a period of transition in which liberalism and republicanism vied for ascendancy. Even more than Shalhope, she also contends that liberalism emerged as an intellectual justification for the liberal practices that accompanied the English financial revolution and became commonplace during the eighteenth century. See especially Appleby, 'Republicanism in Old and New Contexts', pp. 20-34; J. Appleby, Liberalism and Republicanism in the Historical Imagination (Cambridge, MA, 1992); and J. Appleby, Capitalism and the New Social Order: The Republican Vision of the 1790s (New York, 1984).
    • (1984) Capitalism and the New Social Order: The Republican Vision of the 1790s
    • Appleby, J.1
  • 98
    • 79957520258 scopus 로고
    • Polite Foundation: Citizenship and Common Sense in James Wilson's Republican Theory
    • Chicago
    • Several additional works have traced out the synthetic quality of the political thought of individual Founders. See for example Steven Conrad, 'Polite Foundation: Citizenship and Common Sense in James Wilson's Republican Theory', 1984: Supreme Court Review (Chicago, 1985), pp. 359-88, esp. pp. 383-5; Lance Banning, The Sacred Fire of Liberty: James Madison & the Founding of the Federal Republic (Ithaca, NY, 1995). For broader studies which analyse the synthetic thought of the Founders considered collectively see Banning, 'Jeffersonian Ideology Revisited', pp. 11-19; Sunstein, 'Beyond the Republican Revival', pp. 1539-90; Jean Yarbrough, 'Republicanism Reconsidered: Some Thoughts on the Foundation and Preservation of the American Republic', The Review of Politics, 41 (1979), pp. 61-95.
    • (1985) 1984: Supreme Court Review , pp. 359-388
    • Conrad, S.1
  • 99
    • 0010964753 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ithaca, NY
    • Several additional works have traced out the synthetic quality of the political thought of individual Founders. See for example Steven Conrad, 'Polite Foundation: Citizenship and Common Sense in James Wilson's Republican Theory', 1984: Supreme Court Review (Chicago, 1985), pp. 359-88, esp. pp. 383-5; Lance Banning, The Sacred Fire of Liberty: James Madison & the Founding of the Federal Republic (Ithaca, NY, 1995). For broader studies which analyse the synthetic thought of the Founders considered collectively see Banning, 'Jeffersonian Ideology Revisited', pp. 11-19; Sunstein, 'Beyond the Republican Revival', pp. 1539-90; Jean Yarbrough, 'Republicanism Reconsidered: Some Thoughts on the Foundation and Preservation of the American Republic', The Review of Politics, 41 (1979), pp. 61-95.
    • (1995) The Sacred Fire of Liberty: James Madison & the Founding of the Federal Republic
    • Banning, L.1
  • 100
    • 0011672216 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Several additional works have traced out the synthetic quality of the political thought of individual Founders. See for example Steven Conrad, 'Polite Foundation: Citizenship and Common Sense in James Wilson's Republican Theory', 1984: Supreme Court Review (Chicago, 1985), pp. 359-88, esp. pp. 383-5; Lance Banning, The Sacred Fire of Liberty: James Madison & the Founding of the Federal Republic (Ithaca, NY, 1995). For broader studies which analyse the synthetic thought of the Founders considered collectively see Banning, 'Jeffersonian Ideology Revisited', pp. 11-19; Sunstein, 'Beyond the Republican Revival', pp. 1539-90; Jean Yarbrough, 'Republicanism Reconsidered: Some Thoughts on the Foundation and Preservation of the American Republic', The Review of Politics, 41 (1979), pp. 61-95.
    • Jeffersonian Ideology Revisited , pp. 11-19
    • Banning1
  • 101
    • 0013530546 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Several additional works have traced out the synthetic quality of the political thought of individual Founders. See for example Steven Conrad, 'Polite Foundation: Citizenship and Common Sense in James Wilson's Republican Theory', 1984: Supreme Court Review (Chicago, 1985), pp. 359-88, esp. pp. 383-5; Lance Banning, The Sacred Fire of Liberty: James Madison & the Founding of the Federal Republic (Ithaca, NY, 1995). For broader studies which analyse the synthetic thought of the Founders considered collectively see Banning, 'Jeffersonian Ideology Revisited', pp. 11-19; Sunstein, 'Beyond the Republican Revival', pp. 1539-90; Jean Yarbrough, 'Republicanism Reconsidered: Some Thoughts on the Foundation and Preservation of the American Republic', The Review of Politics, 41 (1979), pp. 61-95.
    • Beyond the Republican Revival , pp. 1539-1590
    • Sunstein1
  • 102
    • 84976156391 scopus 로고
    • Republicanism Reconsidered: Some Thoughts on the Foundation and Preservation of the American Republic
    • Several additional works have traced out the synthetic quality of the political thought of individual Founders. See for example Steven Conrad, 'Polite Foundation: Citizenship and Common Sense in James Wilson's Republican Theory', 1984: Supreme Court Review (Chicago, 1985), pp. 359-88, esp. pp. 383-5; Lance Banning, The Sacred Fire of Liberty: James Madison & the Founding of the Federal Republic (Ithaca, NY, 1995). For broader studies which analyse the synthetic thought of the Founders considered collectively see Banning, 'Jeffersonian Ideology Revisited', pp. 11-19; Sunstein, 'Beyond the Republican Revival', pp. 1539-90; Jean Yarbrough, 'Republicanism Reconsidered: Some Thoughts on the Foundation and Preservation of the American Republic', The Review of Politics, 41 (1979), pp. 61-95.
    • (1979) The Review of Politics , vol.41 , pp. 61-95
    • Yarbrough, J.1
  • 106
    • 84965800079 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New Haven
    • Rogers Smith, Civic Ideals: Conflicting Visions of Citizenship in U.S. History (New Haven, 1997). This study was preceded by a number of essays in which Smith outlined dimensions of his complex argument. See R. Smith, The "American Creed" and American Identity: The Limits of Liberal Citizenship in the United States', Western Political Quarterly, 41 (1988), pp. 225-51; R. Smith, '"One United People": Second-Class Female Citizenship and the American Quest for Community', Yale Journal of Law & Humanities, 1 (1989), pp. 229-93; Smith, 'Beyond Tocqueville', pp. 549-66; R. Smith, 'Unfinished Liberalism', Social Research, 61 (1994), pp. 631-70. See also the exchanges between Smith and his critics: Jacqueline Stevens, 'Beyond Tocqueville, Please!', and Rogers Smith, 'Response to Jacqueline Stevens', American Political Science Review, 89 (December, 1995), pp. 987-95; Karen Orren, 'Structure, Sequence, and Subordination in American Political Culture: What's Tradition Got to Do With It?', and Rogers Smith, 'Response to Karen Orren', Journal of Policy History, 8 (1996), pp. 470-90. Similar interpretations which emphasize the cultural dissension and ideological confrontation in American political thought can be found in Richard J. Ellis, American Political Cultures (New York, 1993), and James A. Morone, 'The Struggle for American Culture', PS: Political Science and Politics, 29 (1996), pp. 425-30.
    • (1997) Civic Ideals: Conflicting Visions of Citizenship in U.S. History
    • Smith, R.1
  • 107
    • 84965800079 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The "American Creed" and American Identity: The Limits of Liberal Citizenship in the United States
    • Rogers Smith, Civic Ideals: Conflicting Visions of Citizenship in U.S. History (New Haven, 1997). This study was preceded by a number of essays in which Smith outlined dimensions of his complex argument. See R. Smith, The "American Creed" and American Identity: The Limits of Liberal Citizenship in the United States', Western Political Quarterly, 41 (1988), pp. 225-51; R. Smith, '"One United People": Second-Class Female Citizenship and the American Quest for Community', Yale Journal of Law & Humanities, 1 (1989), pp. 229-93; Smith, 'Beyond Tocqueville', pp. 549-66; R. Smith, 'Unfinished Liberalism', Social Research, 61 (1994), pp. 631-70. See also the exchanges between Smith and his critics: Jacqueline Stevens, 'Beyond Tocqueville, Please!', and Rogers Smith, 'Response to Jacqueline Stevens', American Political Science Review, 89 (December, 1995), pp. 987-95; Karen Orren, 'Structure, Sequence, and Subordination in American Political Culture: What's Tradition Got to Do With It?', and Rogers Smith, 'Response to Karen Orren', Journal of Policy History, 8 (1996), pp. 470-90. Similar interpretations which emphasize the cultural dissension and ideological confrontation in American political thought can be found in Richard J. Ellis, American Political Cultures (New York, 1993), and James A. Morone, 'The Struggle for American Culture', PS: Political Science and Politics, 29 (1996), pp. 425-30.
    • (1988) Western Political Quarterly , vol.41 , pp. 225-251
    • Smith, R.1
  • 108
    • 84965800079 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "One United People": Second-Class Female Citizenship and the American Quest for Community
    • Rogers Smith, Civic Ideals: Conflicting Visions of Citizenship in U.S. History (New Haven, 1997). This study was preceded by a number of essays in which Smith outlined dimensions of his complex argument. See R. Smith, The "American Creed" and American Identity: The Limits of Liberal Citizenship in the United States', Western Political Quarterly, 41 (1988), pp. 225-51; R. Smith, '"One United People": Second-Class Female Citizenship and the American Quest for Community', Yale Journal of Law & Humanities, 1 (1989), pp. 229-93; Smith, 'Beyond Tocqueville', pp. 549-66; R. Smith, 'Unfinished Liberalism', Social Research, 61 (1994), pp. 631-70. See also the exchanges between Smith and his critics: Jacqueline Stevens, 'Beyond Tocqueville, Please!', and Rogers Smith, 'Response to Jacqueline Stevens', American Political Science Review, 89 (December, 1995), pp. 987-95; Karen Orren, 'Structure, Sequence, and Subordination in American Political Culture: What's Tradition Got to Do With It?', and Rogers Smith, 'Response to Karen Orren', Journal of Policy History, 8 (1996), pp. 470-90. Similar interpretations which emphasize the cultural dissension and ideological confrontation in American political thought can be found in Richard J. Ellis, American Political Cultures (New York, 1993), and James A. Morone, 'The Struggle for American Culture', PS: Political Science and Politics, 29 (1996), pp. 425-30.
    • (1989) Yale Journal of Law & Humanities , vol.1 , pp. 229-293
    • Smith, R.1
  • 109
    • 84965800079 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rogers Smith, Civic Ideals: Conflicting Visions of Citizenship in U.S. History (New Haven, 1997). This study was preceded by a number of essays in which Smith outlined dimensions of his complex argument. See R. Smith, The "American Creed" and American Identity: The Limits of Liberal Citizenship in the United States', Western Political Quarterly, 41 (1988), pp. 225-51; R. Smith, '"One United People": Second-Class Female Citizenship and the American Quest for Community', Yale Journal of Law & Humanities, 1 (1989), pp. 229-93; Smith, 'Beyond Tocqueville', pp. 549-66; R. Smith, 'Unfinished Liberalism', Social Research, 61 (1994), pp. 631-70. See also the exchanges between Smith and his critics: Jacqueline Stevens, 'Beyond Tocqueville, Please!', and Rogers Smith, 'Response to Jacqueline Stevens', American Political Science Review, 89 (December, 1995), pp. 987-95; Karen Orren, 'Structure, Sequence, and Subordination in American Political Culture: What's Tradition Got to Do With It?', and Rogers Smith, 'Response to Karen Orren', Journal of Policy History, 8 (1996), pp. 470-90. Similar interpretations which emphasize the cultural dissension and ideological confrontation in American political thought can be found in Richard J. Ellis, American Political Cultures (New York, 1993), and James A. Morone, 'The Struggle for American Culture', PS: Political Science and Politics, 29 (1996), pp. 425-30.
    • Beyond Tocqueville , pp. 549-566
    • Smith1
  • 110
    • 84965800079 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Unfinished Liberalism
    • Rogers Smith, Civic Ideals: Conflicting Visions of Citizenship in U.S. History (New Haven, 1997). This study was preceded by a number of essays in which Smith outlined dimensions of his complex argument. See R. Smith, The "American Creed" and American Identity: The Limits of Liberal Citizenship in the United States', Western Political Quarterly, 41 (1988), pp. 225-51; R. Smith, '"One United People": Second-Class Female Citizenship and the American Quest for Community', Yale Journal of Law & Humanities, 1 (1989), pp. 229-93; Smith, 'Beyond Tocqueville', pp. 549-66; R. Smith, 'Unfinished Liberalism', Social Research, 61 (1994), pp. 631-70. See also the exchanges between Smith and his critics: Jacqueline Stevens, 'Beyond Tocqueville, Please!', and Rogers Smith, 'Response to Jacqueline Stevens', American Political Science Review, 89 (December, 1995), pp. 987-95; Karen Orren, 'Structure, Sequence, and Subordination in American Political Culture: What's Tradition Got to Do With It?', and Rogers Smith, 'Response to Karen Orren', Journal of Policy History, 8 (1996), pp. 470-90. Similar interpretations which emphasize the cultural dissension and ideological confrontation in American political thought can be found in Richard J. Ellis, American Political Cultures (New York, 1993), and James A. Morone, 'The Struggle for American Culture', PS: Political Science and Politics, 29 (1996), pp. 425-30.
    • (1994) Social Research , vol.61 , pp. 631-670
    • Smith, R.1
  • 111
    • 84965800079 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rogers Smith, Civic Ideals: Conflicting Visions of Citizenship in U.S. History (New Haven, 1997). This study was preceded by a number of essays in which Smith outlined dimensions of his complex argument. See R. Smith, The "American Creed" and American Identity: The Limits of Liberal Citizenship in the United States', Western Political Quarterly, 41 (1988), pp. 225-51; R. Smith, '"One United People": Second-Class Female Citizenship and the American Quest for Community', Yale Journal of Law & Humanities, 1 (1989), pp. 229-93; Smith, 'Beyond Tocqueville', pp. 549-66; R. Smith, 'Unfinished Liberalism', Social Research, 61 (1994), pp. 631-70. See also the exchanges between Smith and his critics: Jacqueline Stevens, 'Beyond Tocqueville, Please!', and Rogers Smith, 'Response to Jacqueline Stevens', American Political Science Review, 89 (December, 1995), pp. 987-95; Karen Orren, 'Structure, Sequence, and Subordination in American Political Culture: What's Tradition Got to Do With It?', and Rogers Smith, 'Response to Karen Orren', Journal of Policy History, 8 (1996), pp. 470-90. Similar interpretations which emphasize the cultural dissension and ideological confrontation in American political thought can be found in Richard J. Ellis, American Political Cultures (New York, 1993), and James A. Morone, 'The Struggle for American Culture', PS: Political Science and Politics, 29 (1996), pp. 425-30.
    • Beyond Tocqueville, Please!
    • Stevens, J.1
  • 112
    • 84965800079 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Response to Jacqueline Stevens
    • December
    • Rogers Smith, Civic Ideals: Conflicting Visions of Citizenship in U.S. History (New Haven, 1997). This study was preceded by a number of essays in which Smith outlined dimensions of his complex argument. See R. Smith, The "American Creed" and American Identity: The Limits of Liberal Citizenship in the United States', Western Political Quarterly, 41 (1988), pp. 225-51; R. Smith, '"One United People": Second-Class Female Citizenship and the American Quest for Community', Yale Journal of Law & Humanities, 1 (1989), pp. 229-93; Smith, 'Beyond Tocqueville', pp. 549-66; R. Smith, 'Unfinished Liberalism', Social Research, 61 (1994), pp. 631-70. See also the exchanges between Smith and his critics: Jacqueline Stevens, 'Beyond Tocqueville, Please!', and Rogers Smith, 'Response to Jacqueline Stevens', American Political Science Review, 89 (December, 1995), pp. 987-95; Karen Orren, 'Structure, Sequence, and Subordination in American Political Culture: What's Tradition Got to Do With It?', and Rogers Smith, 'Response to Karen Orren', Journal of Policy History, 8 (1996), pp. 470-90. Similar interpretations which emphasize the cultural dissension and ideological confrontation in American political thought can be found in Richard J. Ellis, American Political Cultures (New York, 1993), and James A. Morone, 'The Struggle for American Culture', PS: Political Science and Politics, 29 (1996), pp. 425-30.
    • (1995) American Political Science Review , vol.89 , pp. 987-995
    • Smith, R.1
  • 113
    • 84965800079 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rogers Smith, Civic Ideals: Conflicting Visions of Citizenship in U.S. History (New Haven, 1997). This study was preceded by a number of essays in which Smith outlined dimensions of his complex argument. See R. Smith, The "American Creed" and American Identity: The Limits of Liberal Citizenship in the United States', Western Political Quarterly, 41 (1988), pp. 225-51; R. Smith, '"One United People": Second-Class Female Citizenship and the American Quest for Community', Yale Journal of Law & Humanities, 1 (1989), pp. 229-93; Smith, 'Beyond Tocqueville', pp. 549-66; R. Smith, 'Unfinished Liberalism', Social Research, 61 (1994), pp. 631-70. See also the exchanges between Smith and his critics: Jacqueline Stevens, 'Beyond Tocqueville, Please!', and Rogers Smith, 'Response to Jacqueline Stevens', American Political Science Review, 89 (December, 1995), pp. 987-95; Karen Orren, 'Structure, Sequence, and Subordination in American Political Culture: What's Tradition Got to Do With It?', and Rogers Smith, 'Response to Karen Orren', Journal of Policy History, 8 (1996), pp. 470-90. Similar interpretations which emphasize the cultural dissension and ideological confrontation in American political thought can be found in Richard J. Ellis, American Political Cultures (New York, 1993), and James A. Morone, 'The Struggle for American Culture', PS: Political Science and Politics, 29 (1996), pp. 425-30.
    • Structure, Sequence, and Subordination in American Political Culture: What's Tradition Got to Do with It?
    • Orren, K.1
  • 114
    • 80155167284 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Response to Karen Orren
    • Rogers Smith, Civic Ideals: Conflicting Visions of Citizenship in U.S. History (New Haven, 1997). This study was preceded by a number of essays in which Smith outlined dimensions of his complex argument. See R. Smith, The "American Creed" and American Identity: The Limits of Liberal Citizenship in the United States', Western Political Quarterly, 41 (1988), pp. 225-51; R. Smith, '"One United People": Second-Class Female Citizenship and the American Quest for Community', Yale Journal of Law & Humanities, 1 (1989), pp. 229-93; Smith, 'Beyond Tocqueville', pp. 549-66; R. Smith, 'Unfinished Liberalism', Social Research, 61 (1994), pp. 631-70. See also the exchanges between Smith and his critics: Jacqueline Stevens, 'Beyond Tocqueville, Please!', and Rogers Smith, 'Response to Jacqueline Stevens', American Political Science Review, 89 (December, 1995), pp. 987-95; Karen Orren, 'Structure, Sequence, and Subordination in American Political Culture: What's Tradition Got to Do With It?', and Rogers Smith, 'Response to Karen Orren', Journal of Policy History, 8 (1996), pp. 470-90. Similar interpretations which emphasize the cultural dissension and ideological confrontation in American political thought can be found in Richard J. Ellis, American Political Cultures (New York, 1993), and James A. Morone, 'The Struggle for American Culture', PS: Political Science and Politics, 29 (1996), pp. 425-30.
    • (1996) Journal of Policy History , vol.8 , pp. 470-490
    • Smith, R.1
  • 115
    • 84965800079 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York
    • Rogers Smith, Civic Ideals: Conflicting Visions of Citizenship in U.S. History (New Haven, 1997). This study was preceded by a number of essays in which Smith outlined dimensions of his complex argument. See R. Smith, The "American Creed" and American Identity: The Limits of Liberal Citizenship in the United States', Western Political Quarterly, 41 (1988), pp. 225-51; R. Smith, '"One United People": Second-Class Female Citizenship and the American Quest for Community', Yale Journal of Law & Humanities, 1 (1989), pp. 229-93; Smith, 'Beyond Tocqueville', pp. 549-66; R. Smith, 'Unfinished Liberalism', Social Research, 61 (1994), pp. 631-70. See also the exchanges between Smith and his critics: Jacqueline Stevens, 'Beyond Tocqueville, Please!', and Rogers Smith, 'Response to Jacqueline Stevens', American Political Science Review, 89 (December, 1995), pp. 987-95; Karen Orren, 'Structure, Sequence, and Subordination in American Political Culture: What's Tradition Got to Do With It?', and Rogers Smith, 'Response to Karen Orren', Journal of Policy History, 8 (1996), pp. 470-90. Similar interpretations which emphasize the cultural dissension and ideological confrontation in American political thought can be found in Richard J. Ellis, American Political Cultures (New York, 1993), and James A. Morone, 'The Struggle for American Culture', PS: Political Science and Politics, 29 (1996), pp. 425-30.
    • (1993) American Political Cultures
    • Ellis, R.J.1
  • 116
    • 0030240908 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Struggle for American Culture
    • Rogers Smith, Civic Ideals: Conflicting Visions of Citizenship in U.S. History (New Haven, 1997). This study was preceded by a number of essays in which Smith outlined dimensions of his complex argument. See R. Smith, The "American Creed" and American Identity: The Limits of Liberal Citizenship in the United States', Western Political Quarterly, 41 (1988), pp. 225-51; R. Smith, '"One United People": Second-Class Female Citizenship and the American Quest for Community', Yale Journal of Law & Humanities, 1 (1989), pp. 229-93; Smith, 'Beyond Tocqueville', pp. 549-66; R. Smith, 'Unfinished Liberalism', Social Research, 61 (1994), pp. 631-70. See also the exchanges between Smith and his critics: Jacqueline Stevens, 'Beyond Tocqueville, Please!', and Rogers Smith, 'Response to Jacqueline Stevens', American Political Science Review, 89 (December, 1995), pp. 987-95; Karen Orren, 'Structure, Sequence, and Subordination in American Political Culture: What's Tradition Got to Do With It?', and Rogers Smith, 'Response to Karen Orren', Journal of Policy History, 8 (1996), pp. 470-90. Similar interpretations which emphasize the cultural dissension and ideological confrontation in American political thought can be found in Richard J. Ellis, American Political Cultures (New York, 1993), and James A. Morone, 'The Struggle for American Culture', PS: Political Science and Politics, 29 (1996), pp. 425-30.
    • (1996) PS: Political Science and Politics , vol.29 , pp. 425-430
    • Morone, J.A.1
  • 120
    • 0001997213 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Simply put, coverture was a feudal doctrine that became embedded in common law that held that upon marriage the legal identity of a married woman (a feme covert) was 'absolutely subsumed' to that of her husband. This doctrine, according to Smith, was enforced in colonial and Revolutionary America with single women (feme soles) accorded only slightly greater legal rights. In documenting the importance of the concept of 'republican motherhood' in early America, Smith follows the scholarship of Linda Kerber. Again, simply put, 'republican motherhood' referred to the belief that women were citizens and the moral equals of men, but nevertheless that their peculiar, apolitical function was to raise children to be virtuous republican citizens. In general, Smith documents how in early America, custom, common law doctrine, Protestant ideology and republicanism all converged to support what he sometimes refers to as 'domestic sphere' ideology - the belief and practice that 'women had no proper place in the public realm and only a subordinate one in the home'. See Smith, 'One United People', pp. 241-50; Smith, Civic Ideals, pp. 67-9.
    • One United People , pp. 241-250
    • Smith1
  • 121
    • 0004248236 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Simply put, coverture was a feudal doctrine that became embedded in common law that held that upon marriage the legal identity of a married woman (a feme covert) was 'absolutely subsumed' to that of her husband. This doctrine, according to Smith, was enforced in colonial and Revolutionary America with single women (feme soles) accorded only slightly greater legal rights. In documenting the importance of the concept of 'republican motherhood' in early America, Smith follows the scholarship of Linda Kerber. Again, simply put, 'republican motherhood' referred to the belief that women were citizens and the moral equals of men, but nevertheless that their peculiar, apolitical function was to raise children to be virtuous republican citizens. In general, Smith documents how in early America, custom, common law doctrine, Protestant ideology and republicanism all converged to support what he sometimes refers to as 'domestic sphere' ideology - the belief and practice that 'women had no proper place in the public realm and only a subordinate one in the home'. See Smith, 'One United People', pp. 241-50; Smith, Civic Ideals, pp. 67-9.
    • Civic Ideals , pp. 67-69
    • Smith1
  • 123
    • 0347515266 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Smith, 'Response to Stevens', p. 991; Smith 'One United People', p. 233; Smith, 'Beyond Tocqueville', p. 554. My emphasis.
    • Response to Stevens , pp. 991
    • Smith1
  • 124
    • 0001997213 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Smith, 'Response to Stevens', p. 991; Smith 'One United People', p. 233; Smith, 'Beyond Tocqueville', p. 554. My emphasis.
    • One United People , pp. 233
    • Smith1
  • 125
    • 0348145260 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • My emphasis
    • Smith, 'Response to Stevens', p. 991; Smith 'One United People', p. 233; Smith, 'Beyond Tocqueville', p. 554. My emphasis.
    • Beyond Tocqueville , pp. 554
    • Smith1
  • 128
  • 130
    • 84970629700 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Stevens, 'Beyond Tocqueville, Please!', p. 987. Smith also discusses this criticism of his thesis in Civic Ideals, pp. 27-30. See also Uday Mehta, 'Liberal Strategies of Exclusion', Politics and Society, 18 (1990), pp. 427-54.
    • Beyond Tocqueville, Please! , pp. 987
    • Stevens1
  • 131
    • 84970629700 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Stevens, 'Beyond Tocqueville, Please!', p. 987. Smith also discusses this criticism of his thesis in Civic Ideals, pp. 27-30. See also Uday Mehta, 'Liberal Strategies of Exclusion', Politics and Society, 18 (1990), pp. 427-54.
    • Civic Ideals , pp. 27-30
    • Smith1
  • 132
    • 84970629700 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Liberal Strategies of Exclusion
    • Stevens, 'Beyond Tocqueville, Please!', p. 987. Smith also discusses this criticism of his thesis in Civic Ideals, pp. 27-30. See also Uday Mehta, 'Liberal Strategies of Exclusion', Politics and Society, 18 (1990), pp. 427-54.
    • (1990) Politics and Society , vol.18 , pp. 427-454
    • Mehta, U.1
  • 133
    • 0004248236 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Smith, Civic Ideals, p. 28; See also Smith, 'Response to Stevens', p. 991.
    • Civic Ideals , pp. 28
    • Smith1
  • 139
    • 0005435460 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The common ground that has emerged within this debate is the product of movement by scholars on both sides of the debate. Scholars have argued, learned, made concessions (often silently), and we are now closer to each other in our interpretations of the Founders than we suspect. Specifically, the 'republican revolution' in scholarship led to the identification of a constellation of concepts and a language of political thought that had either been ignored or lost by previous generations of scholars. Scholars began to trace out the importance within the Founders' political thought of concepts such as public virtue, liberty understood as freedom to participate in public affairs, and the public good understood as something more than an aggregation of the individual interests of the citizenry. But almost from the beginning the choice to call this strain of eighteenth-century English Opposition Ideology 'classical republicanism' and to interpret it as an alternative to Lockean liberalism met with strong opposition from numerous scholars. These scholars therefore conducted a counter-revolution that subjected virtually every aspect of the republican interpretation to intense scrutiny and simultaneously reemphasized the importance of liberalism in the American Founding. Neo-Lockean scholars have argued that the republican revisionists accepted a deterministic approach to the study of political thought that made it impossible for them to recognize and account for the numerous changes that were taking place during the eighteenth century. Republican revisionists have also been charged with providing inaccurate definitions of republicanism and imprecise ones that in the words of one scholar have 'been plagued by language too weak to rule out anything and, hence, to mean anything'. Scholars have also challenged the republican revisionists' interpretations of Greek and Roman republicanism, of Machiavelli, of James Harrington, of the 'Neo-Harringtonians', and of the influence of republicanism in America. On the various criticisms that have been lodged against the republican synthesis see Zuckert, The Natural Rights Republic, pp. 207-8 (quote above is from Sinopoli, The Foundations of American Citizenship, p. 10). Nevertheless, the response of many of the principal proponents of the republican interpretation to this counter-revolution was not to redouble their efforts and argue for the exclusivity of republicanism in the American Founding. Instead, many of these scholars hastily retreated from some of their strongest claims, maintained that they had also never meant to suggest that republicanism and liberalism were rival and mutually exclusive traditions of political thought, and thus made considerable room for the place of liberalism within their interpretations of the Founding.
    • The Natural Rights Republic , pp. 207-208
    • Zuckert1
  • 140
    • 0004009097 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The common ground that has emerged within this debate is the product of movement by scholars on both sides of the debate. Scholars have argued, learned, made concessions (often silently), and we are now closer to each other in our interpretations of the Founders than we suspect. Specifically, the 'republican revolution' in scholarship led to the identification of a constellation of concepts and a language of political thought that had either been ignored or lost by previous generations of scholars. Scholars began to trace out the importance within the Founders' political thought of concepts such as public virtue, liberty understood as freedom to participate in public affairs, and the public good understood as something more than an aggregation of the individual interests of the citizenry. But almost from the beginning the choice to call this strain of eighteenth-century English Opposition Ideology 'classical republicanism' and to interpret it as an alternative to Lockean liberalism met with strong opposition from numerous scholars. These scholars therefore conducted a counter-revolution that subjected virtually every aspect of the republican interpretation to intense scrutiny and simultaneously reemphasized the importance of liberalism in the American Founding. Neo-Lockean scholars have argued that the republican revisionists accepted a deterministic approach to the study of political thought that made it impossible for them to recognize and account for the numerous changes that were taking place during the eighteenth century. Republican revisionists have also been charged with providing inaccurate definitions of republicanism and imprecise ones that in the words of one scholar have 'been plagued by language too weak to rule out anything and, hence, to mean anything'. Scholars have also challenged the republican revisionists' interpretations of Greek and Roman republicanism, of Machiavelli, of James Harrington, of the 'Neo-Harringtonians', and of the influence of republicanism in America. On the various criticisms that have been lodged against the republican synthesis see Zuckert, The Natural Rights Republic, pp. 207-8 (quote above is from Sinopoli, The Foundations of American Citizenship, p. 10). Nevertheless, the response of many of the principal proponents of the republican interpretation to this counter-revolution was not to redouble their efforts and argue for the exclusivity of republicanism in the American Founding. Instead, many of these scholars hastily retreated from some of their strongest claims, maintained that they had also never meant to suggest that republicanism and liberalism were rival and mutually exclusive traditions of political thought, and thus made considerable room for the place of liberalism within their interpretations of the Founding.
    • The Foundations of American Citizenship , pp. 10
    • Sinopoli1
  • 141
    • 0346884764 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is true even for the leading proponents of the 'republican synthesis', who have recently argued that they never meant to suggest otherwise. Banning, for example, has recently stated: 'I do not now, nor did I ever, think of the republican tradition as a rival or alternative to a Lockean or liberal conception of the origins and limits of political society. Indeed, I do not think that any of the major architects of the republican interpretation ever claimed that revolutionary thinking could be fully understood without regard to Locke and other early modern theories of natural rights and social compacts'. Banning, 'Retrospect and Prospect', pp. 98-9.
    • Retrospect and Prospect , pp. 98-99
    • Banning1
  • 142
    • 0007362272 scopus 로고
    • New York
    • Two different kinds of arguments have been made by scholars to suggest that the Founders, like classical republicans, constructed a political system that would engage in the formation of opinion and the development of a common character among the citizenry. The first, I would contend, fails, while the second is yet unproven. Several 'West Coast' Straussians have pointed to the Founders' goals of refining or filtering public opinion especially through representation and have equated this with the classical republican goal of educating and moulding public opinion and thus forming a common character among the citizenry. Madison and his colleagues of course did hope to refine public opinion and believed that representatives should represent the reason not the passions, of the public. Still, the Founders' conception of 'opinion' was modern and Humean, not classical. They argued that governments 'rest on opinion' and thus sought to secure an affective bond between the citizenry and people in order to create stability. Furthermore, Madison and many of his colleagues conceived of public opinion in a remarkably modern manner as a product of the society independent of the government and believed that when public opinion had crystallized that it was sovereign. In other words, while the 'West Coast' Straussians have emphasized the degree to which the Framers hoped to influence or even consciously mould public opinion towards fundamental values, Madison and his colleagues actually saw their role and the role of government in general as the much more limited one of refining existing public opinion in areas where it was not already set. The opinion of the citizenry, most of them believed, would be formed through education and participation in voluntary organizations, not by government. In general, then, the Founders' goal of refining public opinion is far different from the classical goal of promoting homonoia (political oneness) through the use of sumptuary laws and laws that establish religious belief. Forexamples of the 'West Coast' Straussians' efforts to interpret the American regime as designed to achieve classical ends see the essays in Saving the Revolution: the Federalist Papers and the American Founding, ed. Charles Kesler (New York, 1987); C. Kesler, 'The Founders and the Classics', in The Revival of Constitutionalism, ed. James W. Muller (Lincoln, NE, 1988), pp. 57-90; Colleen Sheehan, 'Madison's Party Press Essays', Interpretation: A Journal of Political Philosophy, XVII (1990), pp. 355-77; and C. Sheehan, 'The Politics of Public Opinion: James Madison's "Notes on Government"', William and Mary Quarterly, 44(1992), pp. 609-27. For a judicious evaluation of this interpretation see Harvey Flaumenhaft, 'Review of Saving the Revolution: The Federalist Papers and the American Founding', Constitutional Commentary, V (1988), pp. 460-76. For Madison's understanding of the relationship of government to public opinion see Alexander Hamilton, James Madison and John Jay, The Federalist Papers, ed. Clinton Rossiter (New York, 1961), No. 49, pp. 314-15, and the essays 'Public Opinion' and 'Charters' in The Papers of James Madison, ed. William T. Hutchinson et al. (Vols. I-X, Chicago; Vols. XI-XVII, Charlottesville, VA, 1962-), XIV, pp. 170, 191. Hereafter this work will be cited as PJM. Another case for the thesis that the Framers did not abandon concern for the development of character can perhaps be built by emphasizing the federal nature of the Constitution. This argument suggests that, although the Constitution did not explicitly provide for the education of statesmen and citizens, public support of religion, and institutions which would foster political participation, the Framers simply assumed that these concerns would be addressed by the state governments. See Jean Yarbrough, 'The Constitution and Character: The Missing Critical Principle?', in To Form a More Perfect Union, ed. Belz et al., pp. 220-1, 237-48. This argument, however, depends upon documentation not only that the laws in the state governments at the time of the adoption of the Constitution addressed such concerns, but that the Framers knew this and consciously made the decision that the state governments were the proper arena for fostering education, religion and political participation. As far as I know, no study has yet proven this case.
    • (1987) Saving the Revolution: The Federalist Papers and the American Founding
    • Kesler, C.1
  • 143
    • 0347515260 scopus 로고
    • The Founders and the Classics
    • ed. James W. Muller Lincoln, NE
    • Two different kinds of arguments have been made by scholars to suggest that the Founders, like classical republicans, constructed a political system that would engage in the formation of opinion and the development of a common character among the citizenry. The first, I would contend, fails, while the second is yet unproven. Several 'West Coast' Straussians have pointed to the Founders' goals of refining or filtering public opinion especially through representation and have equated this with the classical republican goal of educating and moulding public opinion and thus forming a common character among the citizenry. Madison and his colleagues of course did hope to refine public opinion and believed that representatives should represent the reason not the passions, of the public. Still, the Founders' conception of 'opinion' was modern and Humean, not classical. They argued that governments 'rest on opinion' and thus sought to secure an affective bond between the citizenry and people in order to create stability. Furthermore, Madison and many of his colleagues conceived of public opinion in a remarkably modern manner as a product of the society independent of the government and believed that when public opinion had crystallized that it was sovereign. In other words, while the 'West Coast' Straussians have emphasized the degree to which the Framers hoped to influence or even consciously mould public opinion towards fundamental values, Madison and his colleagues actually saw their role and the role of government in general as the much more limited one of refining existing public opinion in areas where it was not already set. The opinion of the citizenry, most of them believed, would be formed through education and participation in voluntary organizations, not by government. In general, then, the Founders' goal of refining public opinion is far different from the classical goal of promoting homonoia (political oneness) through the use of sumptuary laws and laws that establish religious belief. Forexamples of the 'West Coast' Straussians' efforts to interpret the American regime as designed to achieve classical ends see the essays in Saving the Revolution: the Federalist Papers and the American Founding, ed. Charles Kesler (New York, 1987); C. Kesler, 'The Founders and the Classics', in The Revival of Constitutionalism, ed. James W. Muller (Lincoln, NE, 1988), pp. 57-90; Colleen Sheehan, 'Madison's Party Press Essays', Interpretation: A Journal of Political Philosophy, XVII (1990), pp. 355-77; and C. Sheehan, 'The Politics of Public Opinion: James Madison's "Notes on Government"', William and Mary Quarterly, 44(1992), pp. 609-27. For a judicious evaluation of this interpretation see Harvey Flaumenhaft, 'Review of Saving the Revolution: The Federalist Papers and the American Founding', Constitutional Commentary, V (1988), pp. 460-76. For Madison's understanding of the relationship of government to public opinion see Alexander Hamilton, James Madison and John Jay, The Federalist Papers, ed. Clinton Rossiter (New York, 1961), No. 49, pp. 314-15, and the essays 'Public Opinion' and 'Charters' in The Papers of James Madison, ed. William T. Hutchinson et al. (Vols. I-X, Chicago; Vols. XI-XVII, Charlottesville, VA, 1962-), XIV, pp. 170, 191. Hereafter this work will be cited as PJM. Another case for the thesis that the Framers did not abandon concern for the development of character can perhaps be built by emphasizing the federal nature of the Constitution. This argument suggests that, although the Constitution did not explicitly provide for the education of statesmen and citizens, public support of religion, and institutions which would foster political participation, the Framers simply assumed that these concerns would be addressed by the state governments. See Jean Yarbrough, 'The Constitution and Character: The Missing Critical Principle?', in To Form a More Perfect Union, ed. Belz et al., pp. 220-1, 237-48. This argument, however, depends upon documentation not only that the laws in the state governments at the time of the adoption of the Constitution addressed such concerns, but that the Framers knew this and consciously made the decision that the state governments were the proper arena for fostering education, religion and political participation. As far as I know, no study has yet proven this case.
    • (1988) The Revival of Constitutionalism , pp. 57-90
    • Kesler, C.1
  • 144
    • 0347514360 scopus 로고
    • Madison's Party Press Essays
    • Two different kinds of arguments have been made by scholars to suggest that the Founders, like classical republicans, constructed a political system that would engage in the formation of opinion and the development of a common character among the citizenry. The first, I would contend, fails, while the second is yet unproven. Several 'West Coast' Straussians have pointed to the Founders' goals of refining or filtering public opinion especially through representation and have equated this with the classical republican goal of educating and moulding public opinion and thus forming a common character among the citizenry. Madison and his colleagues of course did hope to refine public opinion and believed that representatives should represent the reason not the passions, of the public. Still, the Founders' conception of 'opinion' was modern and Humean, not classical. They argued that governments 'rest on opinion' and thus sought to secure an affective bond between the citizenry and people in order to create stability. Furthermore, Madison and many of his colleagues conceived of public opinion in a remarkably modern manner as a product of the society independent of the government and believed that when public opinion had crystallized that it was sovereign. In other words, while the 'West Coast' Straussians have emphasized the degree to which the Framers hoped to influence or even consciously mould public opinion towards fundamental values, Madison and his colleagues actually saw their role and the role of government in general as the much more limited one of refining existing public opinion in areas where it was not already set. The opinion of the citizenry, most of them believed, would be formed through education and participation in voluntary organizations, not by government. In general, then, the Founders' goal of refining public opinion is far different from the classical goal of promoting homonoia (political oneness) through the use of sumptuary laws and laws that establish religious belief. Forexamples of the 'West Coast' Straussians' efforts to interpret the American regime as designed to achieve classical ends see the essays in Saving the Revolution: the Federalist Papers and the American Founding, ed. Charles Kesler (New York, 1987); C. Kesler, 'The Founders and the Classics', in The Revival of Constitutionalism, ed. James W. Muller (Lincoln, NE, 1988), pp. 57-90; Colleen Sheehan, 'Madison's Party Press Essays', Interpretation: A Journal of Political Philosophy, XVII (1990), pp. 355-77; and C. Sheehan, 'The Politics of Public Opinion: James Madison's "Notes on Government"', William and Mary Quarterly, 44(1992), pp. 609-27. For a judicious evaluation of this interpretation see Harvey Flaumenhaft, 'Review of Saving the Revolution: The Federalist Papers and the American Founding', Constitutional Commentary, V (1988), pp. 460-76. For Madison's understanding of the relationship of government to public opinion see Alexander Hamilton, James Madison and John Jay, The Federalist Papers, ed. Clinton Rossiter (New York, 1961), No. 49, pp. 314-15, and the essays 'Public Opinion' and 'Charters' in The Papers of James Madison, ed. William T. Hutchinson et al. (Vols. I-X, Chicago; Vols. XI-XVII, Charlottesville, VA, 1962-), XIV, pp. 170, 191. Hereafter this work will be cited as PJM. Another case for the thesis that the Framers did not abandon concern for the development of character can perhaps be built by emphasizing the federal nature of the Constitution. This argument suggests that, although the Constitution did not explicitly provide for the education of statesmen and citizens, public support of religion, and institutions which would foster political participation, the Framers simply assumed that these concerns would be addressed by the state governments. See Jean Yarbrough, 'The Constitution and Character: The Missing Critical Principle?', in To Form a More Perfect Union, ed. Belz et al., pp. 220-1, 237-48. This argument, however, depends upon documentation not only that the laws in the state governments at the time of the adoption of the Constitution addressed such concerns, but that the Framers knew this and consciously made the decision that the state governments were the proper arena for fostering education, religion and political participation. As far as I know, no study has yet proven this case.
    • (1990) Interpretation: A Journal of Political Philosophy , vol.17 , pp. 355-377
    • Sheehan, C.1
  • 145
    • 0347515256 scopus 로고
    • The Politics of Public Opinion: James Madison's "Notes on Government"
    • Two different kinds of arguments have been made by scholars to suggest that the Founders, like classical republicans, constructed a political system that would engage in the formation of opinion and the development of a common character among the citizenry. The first, I would contend, fails, while the second is yet unproven. Several 'West Coast' Straussians have pointed to the Founders' goals of refining or filtering public opinion especially through representation and have equated this with the classical republican goal of educating and moulding public opinion and thus forming a common character among the citizenry. Madison and his colleagues of course did hope to refine public opinion and believed that representatives should represent the reason not the passions, of the public. Still, the Founders' conception of 'opinion' was modern and Humean, not classical. They argued that governments 'rest on opinion' and thus sought to secure an affective bond between the citizenry and people in order to create stability. Furthermore, Madison and many of his colleagues conceived of public opinion in a remarkably modern manner as a product of the society independent of the government and believed that when public opinion had crystallized that it was sovereign. In other words, while the 'West Coast' Straussians have emphasized the degree to which the Framers hoped to influence or even consciously mould public opinion towards fundamental values, Madison and his colleagues actually saw their role and the role of government in general as the much more limited one of refining existing public opinion in areas where it was not already set. The opinion of the citizenry, most of them believed, would be formed through education and participation in voluntary organizations, not by government. In general, then, the Founders' goal of refining public opinion is far different from the classical goal of promoting homonoia (political oneness) through the use of sumptuary laws and laws that establish religious belief. Forexamples of the 'West Coast' Straussians' efforts to interpret the American regime as designed to achieve classical ends see the essays in Saving the Revolution: the Federalist Papers and the American Founding, ed. Charles Kesler (New York, 1987); C. Kesler, 'The Founders and the Classics', in The Revival of Constitutionalism, ed. James W. Muller (Lincoln, NE, 1988), pp. 57-90; Colleen Sheehan, 'Madison's Party Press Essays', Interpretation: A Journal of Political Philosophy, XVII (1990), pp. 355-77; and C. Sheehan, 'The Politics of Public Opinion: James Madison's "Notes on Government"', William and Mary Quarterly, 44(1992), pp. 609-27. For a judicious evaluation of this interpretation see Harvey Flaumenhaft, 'Review of Saving the Revolution: The Federalist Papers and the American Founding', Constitutional Commentary, V (1988), pp. 460-76. For Madison's understanding of the relationship of government to public opinion see Alexander Hamilton, James Madison and John Jay, The Federalist Papers, ed. Clinton Rossiter (New York, 1961), No. 49, pp. 314-15, and the essays 'Public Opinion' and 'Charters' in The Papers of James Madison, ed. William T. Hutchinson et al. (Vols. I-X, Chicago; Vols. XI-XVII, Charlottesville, VA, 1962-), XIV, pp. 170, 191. Hereafter this work will be cited as PJM. Another case for the thesis that the Framers did not abandon concern for the development of character can perhaps be built by emphasizing the federal nature of the Constitution. This argument suggests that, although the Constitution did not explicitly provide for the education of statesmen and citizens, public support of religion, and institutions which would foster political participation, the Framers simply assumed that these concerns would be addressed by the state governments. See Jean Yarbrough, 'The Constitution and Character: The Missing Critical Principle?', in To Form a More Perfect Union, ed. Belz et al., pp. 220-1, 237-48. This argument, however, depends upon documentation not only that the laws in the state governments at the time of the adoption of the Constitution addressed such concerns, but that the Framers knew this and consciously made the decision that the state governments were the proper arena for fostering education, religion and political participation. As far as I know, no study has yet proven this case.
    • (1992) William and Mary Quarterly , vol.44 , pp. 609-627
    • Sheehan, C.1
  • 146
    • 0346884644 scopus 로고
    • Review of Saving the Revolution: The Federalist Papers and the American Founding
    • Two different kinds of arguments have been made by scholars to suggest that the Founders, like classical republicans, constructed a political system that would engage in the formation of opinion and the development of a common character among the citizenry. The first, I would contend, fails, while the second is yet unproven. Several 'West Coast' Straussians have pointed to the Founders' goals of refining or filtering public opinion especially through representation and have equated this with the classical republican goal of educating and moulding public opinion and thus forming a common character among the citizenry. Madison and his colleagues of course did hope to refine public opinion and believed that representatives should represent the reason not the passions, of the public. Still, the Founders' conception of 'opinion' was modern and Humean, not classical. They argued that governments 'rest on opinion' and thus sought to secure an affective bond between the citizenry and people in order to create stability. Furthermore, Madison and many of his colleagues conceived of public opinion in a remarkably modern manner as a product of the society independent of the government and believed that when public opinion had crystallized that it was sovereign. In other words, while the 'West Coast' Straussians have emphasized the degree to which the Framers hoped to influence or even consciously mould public opinion towards fundamental values, Madison and his colleagues actually saw their role and the role of government in general as the much more limited one of refining existing public opinion in areas where it was not already set. The opinion of the citizenry, most of them believed, would be formed through education and participation in voluntary organizations, not by government. In general, then, the Founders' goal of refining public opinion is far different from the classical goal of promoting homonoia (political oneness) through the use of sumptuary laws and laws that establish religious belief. Forexamples of the 'West Coast' Straussians' efforts to interpret the American regime as designed to achieve classical ends see the essays in Saving the Revolution: the Federalist Papers and the American Founding, ed. Charles Kesler (New York, 1987); C. Kesler, 'The Founders and the Classics', in The Revival of Constitutionalism, ed. James W. Muller (Lincoln, NE, 1988), pp. 57-90; Colleen Sheehan, 'Madison's Party Press Essays', Interpretation: A Journal of Political Philosophy, XVII (1990), pp. 355-77; and C. Sheehan, 'The Politics of Public Opinion: James Madison's "Notes on Government"', William and Mary Quarterly, 44(1992), pp. 609-27. For a judicious evaluation of this interpretation see Harvey Flaumenhaft, 'Review of Saving the Revolution: The Federalist Papers and the American Founding', Constitutional Commentary, V (1988), pp. 460-76. For Madison's understanding of the relationship of government to public opinion see Alexander Hamilton, James Madison and John Jay, The Federalist Papers, ed. Clinton Rossiter (New York, 1961), No. 49, pp. 314-15, and the essays 'Public Opinion' and 'Charters' in The Papers of James Madison, ed. William T. Hutchinson et al. (Vols. I-X, Chicago; Vols. XI-XVII, Charlottesville, VA, 1962-), XIV, pp. 170, 191. Hereafter this work will be cited as PJM. Another case for the thesis that the Framers did not abandon concern for the development of character can perhaps be built by emphasizing the federal nature of the Constitution. This argument suggests that, although the Constitution did not explicitly provide for the education of statesmen and citizens, public support of religion, and institutions which would foster political participation, the Framers simply assumed that these concerns would be addressed by the state governments. See Jean Yarbrough, 'The Constitution and Character: The Missing Critical Principle?', in To Form a More Perfect Union, ed. Belz et al., pp. 220-1, 237-48. This argument, however, depends upon documentation not only that the laws in the state governments at the time of the adoption of the Constitution addressed such concerns, but that the Framers knew this and consciously made the decision that the state governments were the proper arena for fostering education, religion and political participation. As far as I know, no study has yet proven this case.
    • (1988) Constitutional Commentary , vol.5 , pp. 460-476
    • Flaumenhaft, H.1
  • 147
    • 33746079283 scopus 로고
    • ed. Clinton Rossiter New York
    • Two different kinds of arguments have been made by scholars to suggest that the Founders, like classical republicans, constructed a political system that would engage in the formation of opinion and the development of a common character among the citizenry. The first, I would contend, fails, while the second is yet unproven. Several 'West Coast' Straussians have pointed to the Founders' goals of refining or filtering public opinion especially through representation and have equated this with the classical republican goal of educating and moulding public opinion and thus forming a common character among the citizenry. Madison and his colleagues of course did hope to refine public opinion and believed that representatives should represent the reason not the passions, of the public. Still, the Founders' conception of 'opinion' was modern and Humean, not classical. They argued that governments 'rest on opinion' and thus sought to secure an affective bond between the citizenry and people in order to create stability. Furthermore, Madison and many of his colleagues conceived of public opinion in a remarkably modern manner as a product of the society independent of the government and believed that when public opinion had crystallized that it was sovereign. In other words, while the 'West Coast' Straussians have emphasized the degree to which the Framers hoped to influence or even consciously mould public opinion towards fundamental values, Madison and his colleagues actually saw their role and the role of government in general as the much more limited one of refining existing public opinion in areas where it was not already set. The opinion of the citizenry, most of them believed, would be formed through education and participation in voluntary organizations, not by government. In general, then, the Founders' goal of refining public opinion is far different from the classical goal of promoting homonoia (political oneness) through the use of sumptuary laws and laws that establish religious belief. Forexamples of the 'West Coast' Straussians' efforts to interpret the American regime as designed to achieve classical ends see the essays in Saving the Revolution: the Federalist Papers and the American Founding, ed. Charles Kesler (New York, 1987); C. Kesler, 'The Founders and the Classics', in The Revival of Constitutionalism, ed. James W. Muller (Lincoln, NE, 1988), pp. 57-90; Colleen Sheehan, 'Madison's Party Press Essays', Interpretation: A Journal of Political Philosophy, XVII (1990), pp. 355-77; and C. Sheehan, 'The Politics of Public Opinion: James Madison's "Notes on Government"', William and Mary Quarterly, 44(1992), pp. 609-27. For a judicious evaluation of this interpretation see Harvey Flaumenhaft, 'Review of Saving the Revolution: The Federalist Papers and the American Founding', Constitutional Commentary, V (1988), pp. 460-76. For Madison's understanding of the relationship of government to public opinion see Alexander Hamilton, James Madison and John Jay, The Federalist Papers, ed. Clinton Rossiter (New York, 1961), No. 49, pp. 314-15, and the essays 'Public Opinion' and 'Charters' in The Papers of James Madison, ed. William T. Hutchinson et al. (Vols. I-X, Chicago; Vols. XI-XVII, Charlottesville, VA, 1962-), XIV, pp. 170, 191. Hereafter this work will be cited as PJM. Another case for the thesis that the Framers did not abandon concern for the development of character can perhaps be built by emphasizing the federal nature of the Constitution. This argument suggests that, although the Constitution did not explicitly provide for the education of statesmen and citizens, public support of religion, and institutions which would foster political participation, the Framers simply assumed that these concerns would be addressed by the state governments. See Jean Yarbrough, 'The Constitution and
    • (1961) The Federalist Papers , vol.49 , pp. 314-315
    • Hamilton, A.1    Madison, J.2    Jay, J.3
  • 148
    • 26544477680 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Public Opinion' and 'Charters'
    • Chicago
    • Two different kinds of arguments have been made by scholars to suggest that the Founders, like classical republicans, constructed a political system that would engage in the formation of opinion and the development of a common character among the citizenry. The first, I would contend, fails, while the second is yet unproven. Several 'West Coast' Straussians have pointed to the Founders' goals of refining or filtering public opinion especially through representation and have equated this with the classical republican goal of educating and moulding public opinion and thus forming a common character among the citizenry. Madison and his colleagues of course did hope to refine public opinion and believed that representatives should represent the reason not the passions, of the public. Still, the Founders' conception of 'opinion' was modern and Humean, not classical. They argued that governments 'rest on opinion' and thus sought to secure an affective bond between the citizenry and people in order to create stability. Furthermore, Madison and many of his colleagues conceived of public opinion in a remarkably modern manner as a product of the society independent of the government and believed that when public opinion had crystallized that it was sovereign. In other words, while the 'West Coast' Straussians have emphasized the degree to which the Framers hoped to influence or even consciously mould public opinion towards fundamental values, Madison and his colleagues actually saw their role and the role of government in general as the much more limited one of refining existing public opinion in areas where it was not already set. The opinion of the citizenry, most of them believed, would be formed through education and participation in voluntary organizations, not by government. In general, then, the Founders' goal of refining public opinion is far different from the classical goal of promoting homonoia (political oneness) through the use of sumptuary laws and laws that establish religious belief. Forexamples of the 'West Coast' Straussians' efforts to interpret the American regime as designed to achieve classical ends see the essays in Saving the Revolution: the Federalist Papers and the American Founding, ed. Charles Kesler (New York, 1987); C. Kesler, 'The Founders and the Classics', in The Revival of Constitutionalism, ed. James W. Muller (Lincoln, NE, 1988), pp. 57-90; Colleen Sheehan, 'Madison's Party Press Essays', Interpretation: A Journal of Political Philosophy, XVII (1990), pp. 355-77; and C. Sheehan, 'The Politics of Public Opinion: James Madison's "Notes on Government"', William and Mary Quarterly, 44(1992), pp. 609-27. For a judicious evaluation of this interpretation see Harvey Flaumenhaft, 'Review of Saving the Revolution: The Federalist Papers and the American Founding', Constitutional Commentary, V (1988), pp. 460-76. For Madison's understanding of the relationship of government to public opinion see Alexander Hamilton, James Madison and John Jay, The Federalist Papers, ed. Clinton Rossiter (New York, 1961), No. 49, pp. 314-15, and the essays 'Public Opinion' and 'Charters' in The Papers of James Madison, ed. William T. Hutchinson et al. (Vols. I-X, Chicago; Vols. XI-XVII, Charlottesville, VA, 1962-), XIV, pp. 170, 191. Hereafter this work will be cited as PJM. Another case for the thesis that the Framers did not abandon concern for the development of character can perhaps be built by emphasizing the federal nature of the Constitution. This argument suggests that, although the Constitution did not explicitly provide for the education of statesmen and citizens, public support of religion, and institutions which would foster political participation, the Framers simply assumed that these concerns would be addressed by the state governments. See Jean Yarbrough, 'The Constitution and Character: The Missing Critical Principle?', in To Form a More Perfect Union, ed. Belz et al., pp. 220-1, 237-48. This argument, however, depends upon documentation not only that the laws in the state governments at the time of the adoption of the Constitution addressed such concerns, but that the Framers knew this and consciously made the decision that the state governments were the proper arena for fostering education, religion and political participation. As far as I know, no study has yet proven this case.
    • The Papers of James Madison , vol.1-10
    • Hutchinson, W.T.1
  • 149
    • 26544455949 scopus 로고
    • Charlottesville, VA, XIV
    • Two different kinds of arguments have been made by scholars to suggest that the Founders, like classical republicans, constructed a political system that would engage in the formation of opinion and the development of a common character among the citizenry. The first, I would contend, fails, while the second is yet unproven. Several 'West Coast' Straussians have pointed to the Founders' goals of refining or filtering public opinion especially through representation and have equated this with the classical republican goal of educating and moulding public opinion and thus forming a common character among the citizenry. Madison and his colleagues of course did hope to refine public opinion and believed that representatives should represent the reason not the passions, of the public. Still, the Founders' conception of 'opinion' was modern and Humean, not classical. They argued that governments 'rest on opinion' and thus sought to secure an affective bond between the citizenry and people in order to create stability. Furthermore, Madison and many of his colleagues conceived of public opinion in a remarkably modern manner as a product of the society independent of the government and believed that when public opinion had crystallized that it was sovereign. In other words, while the 'West Coast' Straussians have emphasized the degree to which the Framers hoped to influence or even consciously mould public opinion towards fundamental values, Madison and his colleagues actually saw their role and the role of government in general as the much more limited one of refining existing public opinion in areas where it was not already set. The opinion of the citizenry, most of them believed, would be formed through education and participation in voluntary organizations, not by government. In general, then, the Founders' goal of refining public opinion is far different from the classical goal of promoting homonoia (political oneness) through the use of sumptuary laws and laws that establish religious belief. Forexamples of the 'West Coast' Straussians' efforts to interpret the American regime as designed to achieve classical ends see the essays in Saving the Revolution: the Federalist Papers and the American Founding, ed. Charles Kesler (New York, 1987); C. Kesler, 'The Founders and the Classics', in The Revival of Constitutionalism, ed. James W. Muller (Lincoln, NE, 1988), pp. 57-90; Colleen Sheehan, 'Madison's Party Press Essays', Interpretation: A Journal of Political Philosophy, XVII (1990), pp. 355-77; and C. Sheehan, 'The Politics of Public Opinion: James Madison's "Notes on Government"', William and Mary Quarterly, 44(1992), pp. 609-27. For a judicious evaluation of this interpretation see Harvey Flaumenhaft, 'Review of Saving the Revolution: The Federalist Papers and the American Founding', Constitutional Commentary, V (1988), pp. 460-76. For Madison's understanding of the relationship of government to public opinion see Alexander Hamilton, James Madison and John Jay, The Federalist Papers, ed. Clinton Rossiter (New York, 1961), No. 49, pp. 314-15, and the essays 'Public Opinion' and 'Charters' in The Papers of James Madison, ed. William T. Hutchinson et al. (Vols. I-X, Chicago; Vols. XI-XVII, Charlottesville, VA, 1962-), XIV, pp. 170, 191. Hereafter this work will be cited as PJM. Another case for the thesis that the Framers did not abandon concern for the development of character can perhaps be built by emphasizing the federal nature of the Constitution. This argument suggests that, although the Constitution did not explicitly provide for the education of statesmen and citizens, public support of religion, and institutions which would foster political participation, the Framers simply assumed that these concerns would be addressed by the state governments. See Jean Yarbrough, 'The Constitution and Character: The Missing Critical Principle?', in To Form a More Perfect Union, ed. Belz et al., pp. 220-1, 237-48. This argument, however, depends upon documentation not only that the laws in the state governments at the time of the adoption of the Constitution addressed such concerns, but that the Framers knew this and consciously made the decision that the state governments were the proper arena for fostering education, religion and political participation. As far as I know, no study has yet proven this case.
    • (1962) The Papers of James Madison , vol.11-17 , pp. 170
  • 150
    • 0347515257 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Constitution and Character: The Missing Critical Principle?
    • ed. Belz et al.
    • Two different kinds of arguments have been made by scholars to suggest that the Founders, like classical republicans, constructed a political system that would engage in the formation of opinion and the development of a common character among the citizenry. The first, I would contend, fails, while the second is yet unproven. Several 'West Coast' Straussians have pointed to the Founders' goals of refining or filtering public opinion especially through representation and have equated this with the classical republican goal of educating and moulding public opinion and thus forming a common character among the citizenry. Madison and his colleagues of course did hope to refine public opinion and believed that representatives should represent the reason not the passions, of the public. Still, the Founders' conception of 'opinion' was modern and Humean, not classical. They argued that governments 'rest on opinion' and thus sought to secure an affective bond between the citizenry and people in order to create stability. Furthermore, Madison and many of his colleagues conceived of public opinion in a remarkably modern manner as a product of the society independent of the government and believed that when public opinion had crystallized that it was sovereign. In other words, while the 'West Coast' Straussians have emphasized the degree to which the Framers hoped to influence or even consciously mould public opinion towards fundamental values, Madison and his colleagues actually saw their role and the role of government in general as the much more limited one of refining existing public opinion in areas where it was not already set. The opinion of the citizenry, most of them believed, would be formed through education and participation in voluntary organizations, not by government. In general, then, the Founders' goal of refining public opinion is far different from the classical goal of promoting homonoia (political oneness) through the use of sumptuary laws and laws that establish religious belief. Forexamples of the 'West Coast' Straussians' efforts to interpret the American regime as designed to achieve classical ends see the essays in Saving the Revolution: the Federalist Papers and the American Founding, ed. Charles Kesler (New York, 1987); C. Kesler, 'The Founders and the Classics', in The Revival of Constitutionalism, ed. James W. Muller (Lincoln, NE, 1988), pp. 57-90; Colleen Sheehan, 'Madison's Party Press Essays', Interpretation: A Journal of Political Philosophy, XVII (1990), pp. 355-77; and C. Sheehan, 'The Politics of Public Opinion: James Madison's "Notes on Government"', William and Mary Quarterly, 44(1992), pp. 609-27. For a judicious evaluation of this interpretation see Harvey Flaumenhaft, 'Review of Saving the Revolution: The Federalist Papers and the American Founding', Constitutional Commentary, V (1988), pp. 460-76. For Madison's understanding of the relationship of government to public opinion see Alexander Hamilton, James Madison and John Jay, The Federalist Papers, ed. Clinton Rossiter (New York, 1961), No. 49, pp. 314-15, and the essays 'Public Opinion' and 'Charters' in The Papers of James Madison, ed. William T. Hutchinson et al. (Vols. I-X, Chicago; Vols. XI-XVII, Charlottesville, VA, 1962-), XIV, pp. 170, 191. Hereafter this work will be cited as PJM. Another case for the thesis that the Framers did not abandon concern for the development of character can perhaps be built by emphasizing the federal nature of the Constitution. This argument suggests that, although the Constitution did not explicitly provide for the education of statesmen and citizens, public support of religion, and institutions which would foster political participation, the Framers simply assumed that these concerns would be addressed by the state governments. See Jean Yarbrough, 'The Constitution and Character: The Missing Critical Principle?', in To Form a More Perfect Union, ed. Belz et al., pp. 220-1, 237-48. This argument, however, depends upon documentation not only that the laws in the state governments at the time of the adoption of the Constitution addressed such concerns, but that the Framers knew this and consciously made the decision that the state governments were the proper arena for fostering education, religion and political participation. As far as I know, no study has yet proven this case.
    • To Form a More Perfect Union , pp. 220-221
    • Yarbrough, J.1
  • 151
    • 0003651959 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rigorous definitions and conceptual clarity, however, are what this debate has of course lacked. As a result, much of the disagreement between scholars who espouse a republican interpretation and their Neo-Lockean opponents has really been a submerged debate over the meaning of classical republicanism itself, not simply the content of the Founders' political thought. These scholars, in other words, have often argued past each other because they have used different standards for what constitutes classical republicanism. For their part, the republican revisionists have implied or set forth a series of definitions within their works. Indeed, as Michael Zuckert has recently pointed out, a retrospective rereading of the masterworks of the republican interpretation challenges whether these scholars ever achieved a common characterization of republicanism and thus whether this interpretation merits its appellation as a synthesis. As it was initially formulated by Bernard Bailyn in The Ideological Origins of the American Revolution, English opposition ideology (he did not call it classical republicanism) was characterized as a set of concepts, anxieties, hopes, and calls for specific institutional arrangements and reforms that were pervasive in seventeenth- and eighteenth-century English radical thought and became especially important in America during the Revolution. Specifically, Bailyn argued that this ideology was grounded in then commonplace political concepts such as natural rights, the contractual basis of government and praise for England's mixed Constitution. But its peculiarity came from the emphasis with which its spokesmen stressed the fragility of republics, the encroaching nature of power and the danger to liberty of rulers wielding it, fear of ministerial corruption by placemen, the necessity of vigilance against government, concern for the moral qualities that were necessary to preserve liberty including the importance of an independent, uncorrupted, land-holding citizenry, and finally appeals for a range of institutional reforms from adult manhood suffrage to binding instructions on representatives. Bailyn then interpreted this universe of concepts and apprehensions as a form of libertarianism or a 'peculiar strain of anti-authoritarianism' rooted in 'extreme solicitude for the individual and an equal hostility to government'. This ideology, he further contended, carried into modernity 'the traditional anti-statist convictions of seventeenth-century liberalism'. Bailyn thus did not contrast Anglo-American republicanism with the social contract-natural rights tradition or charge it with many of the connotations that it would later be given. Bernard Bailyn, The Ideological Origins of the American Revolution (Cambridge, MA, 1967), pp. viii, 48; B. Bailyn, 'The Central Themes of the American Revolution: An Interpretation', in Essays on the American Revolution, ed. Stephen G. Kurtz and James H. Hutson (Chapel Hill, NC, 1973), p. 9 . In different ways, however, Gordon Wood's The Creation of the American Republic, 1776-1787 (New York, 1969) and J.G.A. Pocock's The Machiavellian Moment: Florentine Political Thought and the Atlantic Republican Tradition (Princeton, NJ, 1975) transformed this understanding of Anglo-American republicanism. Wood linked English opposition ideology to an organic conception of the public good and argued that the American Revolutionaries believed that the sole purpose of government was to promote the public good. Meanwhile, Pocock maintained that English opposition ideology was a restatement of the classical republican or, as he called it, a civic humanism conception of political liberty. For Zuckert's analysis of the different variations of republicanism present in the 'republicanism synthesis' and the evolution of this interpretation see Zuckert, Natural Rights and the New Republicanism, pp. 151-64. During the 1980s, as the interpretations of the republican synthesis became more and more influential and began to be used by a variety of scholars for contemporary political purposes, classical republicanism seemingly came to be identified with both the hopes, anxieties, concepts and institutional arrangements that Bailyn had originally identified from radical Whig ideology and the three political concepts identified in the writings of Pocock and Wood: political liberty understood as the necessity of participating in ruling and being ruled in a political community, virtue understood as requiring self-sacrifice for the public good, and the public good or common interest understood as an entity that transcended the aggregate interests of the community and was not simply a residue of self-interested competition among special-interest groups. In contrast to these understandings of classical republicanism, the Aristotelean characterization of classical republicanism that I use as a standard above is drawn from Paul Rahe's Republics: Ancient and Modern.
    • The Ideological Origins of the American Revolution
    • Bailyn, B.1
  • 152
    • 0003651959 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA
    • Rigorous definitions and conceptual clarity, however, are what this debate has of course lacked. As a result, much of the disagreement between scholars who espouse a republican interpretation and their Neo-Lockean opponents has really been a submerged debate over the meaning of classical republicanism itself, not simply the content of the Founders' political thought. These scholars, in other words, have often argued past each other because they have used different standards for what constitutes classical republicanism. For their part, the republican revisionists have implied or set forth a series of definitions within their works. Indeed, as Michael Zuckert has recently pointed out, a retrospective rereading of the masterworks of the republican interpretation challenges whether these scholars ever achieved a common characterization of republicanism and thus whether this interpretation merits its appellation as a synthesis. As it was initially formulated by Bernard Bailyn in The Ideological Origins of the American Revolution, English opposition ideology (he did not call it classical republicanism) was characterized as a set of concepts, anxieties, hopes, and calls for specific institutional arrangements and reforms that were pervasive in seventeenth- and eighteenth-century English radical thought and became especially important in America during the Revolution. Specifically, Bailyn argued that this ideology was grounded in then commonplace political concepts such as natural rights, the contractual basis of government and praise for England's mixed Constitution. But its peculiarity came from the emphasis with which its spokesmen stressed the fragility of republics, the encroaching nature of power and the danger to liberty of rulers wielding it, fear of ministerial corruption by placemen, the necessity of vigilance against government, concern for the moral qualities that were necessary to preserve liberty including the importance of an independent, uncorrupted, land-holding citizenry, and finally appeals for a range of institutional reforms from adult manhood suffrage to binding instructions on representatives. Bailyn then interpreted this universe of concepts and apprehensions as a form of libertarianism or a 'peculiar strain of anti-authoritarianism' rooted in 'extreme solicitude for the individual and an equal hostility to government'. This ideology, he further contended, carried into modernity 'the traditional anti-statist convictions of seventeenth-century liberalism'. Bailyn thus did not contrast Anglo-American republicanism with the social contract-natural rights tradition or charge it with many of the connotations that it would later be given. Bernard Bailyn, The Ideological Origins of the American Revolution (Cambridge, MA, 1967), pp. viii, 48; B. Bailyn, 'The Central Themes of the American Revolution: An Interpretation', in Essays on the American Revolution, ed. Stephen G. Kurtz and James H. Hutson (Chapel Hill, NC, 1973), p. 9 . In different ways, however, Gordon Wood's The Creation of the American Republic, 1776-1787 (New York, 1969) and J.G.A. Pocock's The Machiavellian Moment: Florentine Political Thought and the Atlantic Republican Tradition (Princeton, NJ, 1975) transformed this understanding of Anglo-American republicanism. Wood linked English opposition ideology to an organic conception of the public good and argued that the American Revolutionaries believed that the sole purpose of government was to promote the public good. Meanwhile, Pocock maintained that English opposition ideology was a restatement of the classical republican or, as he called it, a civic humanism conception of political liberty. For Zuckert's analysis of the different variations of republicanism present in the 'republicanism synthesis' and the evolution of this interpretation see Zuckert, Natural Rights and the New Republicanism, pp. 151-64. During the 1980s, as the interpretations of the republican synthesis became more and more influential and began to be used by a variety of scholars for contemporary political purposes, classical republicanism seemingly came to be identified with both the hopes, anxieties, concepts and institutional arrangements that Bailyn had originally identified from radical Whig ideology and the three political concepts identified in the writings of Pocock and Wood: political liberty understood as the necessity of participating in ruling and being ruled in a political community, virtue understood as requiring self-sacrifice for the public good, and the public good or common interest understood as an entity that transcended the aggregate interests of the community and was not simply a residue of self-interested competition among special-interest groups. In contrast to these understandings of classical republicanism, the Aristotelean characterization of classical republicanism that I use as a standard above is drawn from Paul Rahe's Republics: Ancient and Modern.
    • (1967) The Ideological Origins of the American Revolution
    • Bailyn, B.1
  • 153
    • 0348145176 scopus 로고
    • The Central Themes of the American Revolution: An Interpretation
    • ed. Stephen G. Kurtz and James H. Hutson Chapel Hill, NC
    • Rigorous definitions and conceptual clarity, however, are what this debate has of course lacked. As a result, much of the disagreement between scholars who espouse a republican interpretation and their Neo-Lockean opponents has really been a submerged debate over the meaning of classical republicanism itself, not simply the content of the Founders' political thought. These scholars, in other words, have often argued past each other because they have used different standards for what constitutes classical republicanism. For their part, the republican revisionists have implied or set forth a series of definitions within their works. Indeed, as Michael Zuckert has recently pointed out, a retrospective rereading of the masterworks of the republican interpretation challenges whether these scholars ever achieved a common characterization of republicanism and thus whether this interpretation merits its appellation as a synthesis. As it was initially formulated by Bernard Bailyn in The Ideological Origins of the American Revolution, English opposition ideology (he did not call it classical republicanism) was characterized as a set of concepts, anxieties, hopes, and calls for specific institutional arrangements and reforms that were pervasive in seventeenth- and eighteenth-century English radical thought and became especially important in America during the Revolution. Specifically, Bailyn argued that this ideology was grounded in then commonplace political concepts such as natural rights, the contractual basis of government and praise for England's mixed Constitution. But its peculiarity came from the emphasis with which its spokesmen stressed the fragility of republics, the encroaching nature of power and the danger to liberty of rulers wielding it, fear of ministerial corruption by placemen, the necessity of vigilance against government, concern for the moral qualities that were necessary to preserve liberty including the importance of an independent, uncorrupted, land-holding citizenry, and finally appeals for a range of institutional reforms from adult manhood suffrage to binding instructions on representatives. Bailyn then interpreted this universe of concepts and apprehensions as a form of libertarianism or a 'peculiar strain of anti-authoritarianism' rooted in 'extreme solicitude for the individual and an equal hostility to government'. This ideology, he further contended, carried into modernity 'the traditional anti-statist convictions of seventeenth-century liberalism'. Bailyn thus did not contrast Anglo-American republicanism with the social contract-natural rights tradition or charge it with many of the connotations that it would later be given. Bernard Bailyn, The Ideological Origins of the American Revolution (Cambridge, MA, 1967), pp. viii, 48; B. Bailyn, 'The Central Themes of the American Revolution: An Interpretation', in Essays on the American Revolution, ed. Stephen G. Kurtz and James H. Hutson (Chapel Hill, NC, 1973), p. 9 . In different ways, however, Gordon Wood's The Creation of the American Republic, 1776-1787 (New York, 1969) and J.G.A. Pocock's The Machiavellian Moment: Florentine Political Thought and the Atlantic Republican Tradition (Princeton, NJ, 1975) transformed this understanding of Anglo-American republicanism. Wood linked English opposition ideology to an organic conception of the public good and argued that the American Revolutionaries believed that the sole purpose of government was to promote the public good. Meanwhile, Pocock maintained that English opposition ideology was a restatement of the classical republican or, as he called it, a civic humanism conception of political liberty. For Zuckert's analysis of the different variations of republicanism present in the 'republicanism synthesis' and the evolution of this interpretation see Zuckert, Natural Rights and the New Republicanism, pp. 151-64. During the 1980s, as the interpretations of the republican synthesis became more and more influential and began to be used by a variety of scholars for contemporary political purposes, classical republicanism seemingly came to be identified with both the hopes, anxieties, concepts and institutional arrangements that Bailyn had originally identified from radical Whig ideology and the three political concepts identified in the writings of Pocock and Wood: political liberty understood as the necessity of participating in ruling and being ruled in a political community, virtue understood as requiring self-sacrifice for the public good, and the public good or common interest understood as an entity that transcended the aggregate interests of the community and was not simply a residue of self-interested competition among special-interest groups. In contrast to these understandings of classical republicanism, the Aristotelean characterization of classical republicanism that I use as a standard above is drawn from Paul Rahe's Republics: Ancient and Modern.
    • (1973) Essays on the American Revolution , pp. 9
    • Bailyn, B.1
  • 154
    • 0003590084 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York
    • Rigorous definitions and conceptual clarity, however, are what this debate has of course lacked. As a result, much of the disagreement between scholars who espouse a republican interpretation and their Neo-Lockean opponents has really been a submerged debate over the meaning of classical republicanism itself, not simply the content of the Founders' political thought. These scholars, in other words, have often argued past each other because they have used different standards for what constitutes classical republicanism. For their part, the republican revisionists have implied or set forth a series of definitions within their works. Indeed, as Michael Zuckert has recently pointed out, a retrospective rereading of the masterworks of the republican interpretation challenges whether these scholars ever achieved a common characterization of republicanism and thus whether this interpretation merits its appellation as a synthesis. As it was initially formulated by Bernard Bailyn in The Ideological Origins of the American Revolution, English opposition ideology (he did not call it classical republicanism) was characterized as a set of concepts, anxieties, hopes, and calls for specific institutional arrangements and reforms that were pervasive in seventeenth- and eighteenth-century English radical thought and became especially important in America during the Revolution. Specifically, Bailyn argued that this ideology was grounded in then commonplace political concepts such as natural rights, the contractual basis of government and praise for England's mixed Constitution. But its peculiarity came from the emphasis with which its spokesmen stressed the fragility of republics, the encroaching nature of power and the danger to liberty of rulers wielding it, fear of ministerial corruption by placemen, the necessity of vigilance against government, concern for the moral qualities that were necessary to preserve liberty including the importance of an independent, uncorrupted, land-holding citizenry, and finally appeals for a range of institutional reforms from adult manhood suffrage to binding instructions on representatives. Bailyn then interpreted this universe of concepts and apprehensions as a form of libertarianism or a 'peculiar strain of anti-authoritarianism' rooted in 'extreme solicitude for the individual and an equal hostility to government'. This ideology, he further contended, carried into modernity 'the traditional anti-statist convictions of seventeenth-century liberalism'. Bailyn thus did not contrast Anglo-American republicanism with the social contract-natural rights tradition or charge it with many of the connotations that it would later be given. Bernard Bailyn, The Ideological Origins of the American Revolution (Cambridge, MA, 1967), pp. viii, 48; B. Bailyn, 'The Central Themes of the American Revolution: An Interpretation', in Essays on the American Revolution, ed. Stephen G. Kurtz and James H. Hutson (Chapel Hill, NC, 1973), p. 9 . In different ways, however, Gordon Wood's The Creation of the American Republic, 1776-1787 (New York, 1969) and J.G.A. Pocock's The Machiavellian Moment: Florentine Political Thought and the Atlantic Republican Tradition (Princeton, NJ, 1975) transformed this understanding of Anglo-American republicanism. Wood linked English opposition ideology to an organic conception of the public good and argued that the American Revolutionaries believed that the sole purpose of government was to promote the public good. Meanwhile, Pocock maintained that English opposition ideology was a restatement of the classical republican or, as he called it, a civic humanism conception of political liberty. For Zuckert's analysis of the different variations of republicanism present in the 'republicanism synthesis' and the evolution of this interpretation see Zuckert, Natural Rights and the New Republicanism, pp. 151-64. During the 1980s, as the interpretations of the republican synthesis became more and more influential and began to be used by a variety of scholars for contemporary political purposes, classical republicanism seemingly came to be identified with both the hopes, anxieties, concepts and institutional arrangements that Bailyn had originally identified from radical Whig ideology and the three political concepts identified in the writings of Pocock and Wood: political liberty understood as the necessity of participating in ruling and being ruled in a political community, virtue understood as requiring self-sacrifice for the public good, and the public good or common interest understood as an entity that transcended the aggregate interests of the community and was not simply a residue of self-interested competition among special-interest groups. In contrast to these understandings of classical republicanism, the Aristotelean characterization of classical republicanism that I use as a standard above is drawn from Paul Rahe's Republics: Ancient and Modern.
    • (1969) Wood's the Creation of the American Republic, 1776-1787
    • Gordon1
  • 155
    • 84884110947 scopus 로고
    • Princeton, NJ
    • Rigorous definitions and conceptual clarity, however, are what this debate has of course lacked. As a result, much of the disagreement between scholars who espouse a republican interpretation and their Neo-Lockean opponents has really been a submerged debate over the meaning of classical republicanism itself, not simply the content of the Founders' political thought. These scholars, in other words, have often argued past each other because they have used different standards for what constitutes classical republicanism. For their part, the republican revisionists have implied or set forth a series of definitions within their works. Indeed, as Michael Zuckert has recently pointed out, a retrospective rereading of the masterworks of the republican interpretation challenges whether these scholars ever achieved a common characterization of republicanism and thus whether this interpretation merits its appellation as a synthesis. As it was initially formulated by Bernard Bailyn in The Ideological Origins of the American Revolution, English opposition ideology (he did not call it classical republicanism) was characterized as a set of concepts, anxieties, hopes, and calls for specific institutional arrangements and reforms that were pervasive in seventeenth- and eighteenth-century English radical thought and became especially important in America during the Revolution. Specifically, Bailyn argued that this ideology was grounded in then commonplace political concepts such as natural rights, the contractual basis of government and praise for England's mixed Constitution. But its peculiarity came from the emphasis with which its spokesmen stressed the fragility of republics, the encroaching nature of power and the danger to liberty of rulers wielding it, fear of ministerial corruption by placemen, the necessity of vigilance against government, concern for the moral qualities that were necessary to preserve liberty including the importance of an independent, uncorrupted, land-holding citizenry, and finally appeals for a range of institutional reforms from adult manhood suffrage to binding instructions on representatives. Bailyn then interpreted this universe of concepts and apprehensions as a form of libertarianism or a 'peculiar strain of anti-authoritarianism' rooted in 'extreme solicitude for the individual and an equal hostility to government'. This ideology, he further contended, carried into modernity 'the traditional anti-statist convictions of seventeenth-century liberalism'. Bailyn thus did not contrast Anglo-American republicanism with the social contract-natural rights tradition or charge it with many of the connotations that it would later be given. Bernard Bailyn, The Ideological Origins of the American Revolution (Cambridge, MA, 1967), pp. viii, 48; B. Bailyn, 'The Central Themes of the American Revolution: An Interpretation', in Essays on the American Revolution, ed. Stephen G. Kurtz and James H. Hutson (Chapel Hill, NC, 1973), p. 9 . In different ways, however, Gordon Wood's The Creation of the American Republic, 1776-1787 (New York, 1969) and J.G.A. Pocock's The Machiavellian Moment: Florentine Political Thought and the Atlantic Republican Tradition (Princeton, NJ, 1975) transformed this understanding of Anglo-American republicanism. Wood linked English opposition ideology to an organic conception of the public good and argued that the American Revolutionaries believed that the sole purpose of government was to promote the public good. Meanwhile, Pocock maintained that English opposition ideology was a restatement of the classical republican or, as he called it, a civic humanism conception of political liberty. For Zuckert's analysis of the different variations of republicanism present in the 'republicanism synthesis' and the evolution of this interpretation see Zuckert, Natural Rights and the New Republicanism, pp. 151-64. During the 1980s, as the interpretations of the republican synthesis became more and more influential and began to be used by a variety of scholars for contemporary political purposes, classical republicanism seemingly came to be identified with both the hopes, anxieties, concepts and institutional arrangements that Bailyn had originally identified from radical Whig ideology and the three political concepts identified in the writings of Pocock and Wood: political liberty understood as the necessity of participating in ruling and being ruled in a political community, virtue understood as requiring self-sacrifice for the public good, and the public good or common interest understood as an entity that transcended the aggregate interests of the community and was not simply a residue of self-interested competition among special-interest groups. In contrast to these understandings of classical republicanism, the Aristotelean characterization of classical republicanism that I use as a standard above is drawn from Paul Rahe's Republics: Ancient and Modern.
    • (1975) The Machiavellian Moment: Florentine Political Thought and the Atlantic Republican Tradition
    • Pocock, J.G.A.1
  • 156
    • 0004040248 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rigorous definitions and conceptual clarity, however, are what this debate has of course lacked. As a result, much of the disagreement between scholars who espouse a republican interpretation and their Neo-Lockean opponents has really been a submerged debate over the meaning of classical republicanism itself, not simply the content of the Founders' political thought. These scholars, in other words, have often argued past each other because they have used different standards for what constitutes classical republicanism. For their part, the republican revisionists have implied or set forth a series of definitions within their works. Indeed, as Michael Zuckert has recently pointed out, a retrospective rereading of the masterworks of the republican interpretation challenges whether these scholars ever achieved a common characterization of republicanism and thus whether this interpretation merits its appellation as a synthesis. As it was initially formulated by Bernard Bailyn in The Ideological Origins of the American Revolution, English opposition ideology (he did not call it classical republicanism) was characterized as a set of concepts, anxieties, hopes, and calls for specific institutional arrangements and reforms that were pervasive in seventeenth- and eighteenth-century English radical thought and became especially important in America during the Revolution. Specifically, Bailyn argued that this ideology was grounded in then commonplace political concepts such as natural rights, the contractual basis of government and praise for England's mixed Constitution. But its peculiarity came from the emphasis with which its spokesmen stressed the fragility of republics, the encroaching nature of power and the danger to liberty of rulers wielding it, fear of ministerial corruption by placemen, the necessity of vigilance against government, concern for the moral qualities that were necessary to preserve liberty including the importance of an independent, uncorrupted, land-holding citizenry, and finally appeals for a range of institutional reforms from adult manhood suffrage to binding instructions on representatives. Bailyn then interpreted this universe of concepts and apprehensions as a form of libertarianism or a 'peculiar strain of anti-authoritarianism' rooted in 'extreme solicitude for the individual and an equal hostility to government'. This ideology, he further contended, carried into modernity 'the traditional anti-statist convictions of seventeenth-century liberalism'. Bailyn thus did not contrast Anglo-American republicanism with the social contract-natural rights tradition or charge it with many of the connotations that it would later be given. Bernard Bailyn, The Ideological Origins of the American Revolution (Cambridge, MA, 1967), pp. viii, 48; B. Bailyn, 'The Central Themes of the American Revolution: An Interpretation', in Essays on the American Revolution, ed. Stephen G. Kurtz and James H. Hutson (Chapel Hill, NC, 1973), p. 9 . In different ways, however, Gordon Wood's The Creation of the American Republic, 1776-1787 (New York, 1969) and J.G.A. Pocock's The Machiavellian Moment: Florentine Political Thought and the Atlantic Republican Tradition (Princeton, NJ, 1975) transformed this understanding of Anglo-American republicanism. Wood linked English opposition ideology to an organic conception of the public good and argued that the American Revolutionaries believed that the sole purpose of government was to promote the public good. Meanwhile, Pocock maintained that English opposition ideology was a restatement of the classical republican or, as he called it, a civic humanism conception of political liberty. For Zuckert's analysis of the different variations of republicanism present in the 'republicanism synthesis' and the evolution of this interpretation see Zuckert, Natural Rights and the New Republicanism, pp. 151-64. During the 1980s, as the interpretations of the republican synthesis became more and more influential and began to be used by a variety of scholars for contemporary political purposes, classical republicanism seemingly came to be identified with both the hopes, anxieties, concepts and institutional arrangements that Bailyn had originally identified from radical Whig ideology and the three political concepts identified in the writings of Pocock and Wood: political liberty understood as the necessity of participating in ruling and being ruled in a political community, virtue understood as requiring self-sacrifice for the public good, and the public good or common interest understood as an entity that transcended the aggregate interests of the community and was not simply a residue of self-interested competition among special-interest groups. In contrast to these understandings of classical republicanism, the Aristotelean characterization of classical republicanism that I use as a standard above is drawn from Paul Rahe's Republics: Ancient and Modern.
    • Natural Rights and the New Republicanism , pp. 151-164
    • Zuckert1
  • 157
    • 0004178688 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rigorous definitions and conceptual clarity, however, are what this debate has of course lacked. As a result, much of the disagreement between scholars who espouse a republican interpretation and their Neo-Lockean opponents has really been a submerged debate over the meaning of classical republicanism itself, not simply the content of the Founders' political thought. These scholars, in other words, have often argued past each other because they have used different standards for what constitutes classical republicanism. For their part, the republican revisionists have implied or set forth a series of definitions within their works. Indeed, as Michael Zuckert has recently pointed out, a retrospective rereading of the masterworks of the republican interpretation challenges whether these scholars ever achieved a common characterization of republicanism and thus whether this interpretation merits its appellation as a synthesis. As it was initially formulated by Bernard Bailyn in The Ideological Origins of the American Revolution, English opposition ideology (he did not call it classical republicanism) was characterized as a set of concepts, anxieties, hopes, and calls for specific institutional arrangements and reforms that were pervasive in seventeenth- and eighteenth-century English radical thought and became especially important in America during the Revolution. Specifically, Bailyn argued that this ideology was grounded in then commonplace political concepts such as natural rights, the contractual basis of government and praise for England's mixed Constitution. But its peculiarity came from the emphasis with which its spokesmen stressed the fragility of republics, the encroaching nature of power and the danger to liberty of rulers wielding it, fear of ministerial corruption by placemen, the necessity of vigilance against government, concern for the moral qualities that were necessary to preserve liberty including the importance of an independent, uncorrupted, land-holding citizenry, and finally appeals for a range of institutional reforms from adult manhood suffrage to binding instructions on representatives. Bailyn then interpreted this universe of concepts and apprehensions as a form of libertarianism or a 'peculiar strain of anti-authoritarianism' rooted in 'extreme solicitude for the individual and an equal hostility to government'. This ideology, he further contended, carried into modernity 'the traditional anti-statist convictions of seventeenth-century liberalism'. Bailyn thus did not contrast Anglo-American republicanism with the social contract-natural rights tradition or charge it with many of the connotations that it would later be given. Bernard Bailyn, The Ideological Origins of the American Revolution (Cambridge, MA, 1967), pp. viii, 48; B. Bailyn, 'The Central Themes of the American Revolution: An Interpretation', in Essays on the American Revolution, ed. Stephen G. Kurtz and James H. Hutson (Chapel Hill, NC, 1973), p. 9 . In different ways, however, Gordon Wood's The Creation of the American Republic, 1776-1787 (New York, 1969) and J.G.A. Pocock's The Machiavellian Moment: Florentine Political Thought and the Atlantic Republican Tradition (Princeton, NJ, 1975) transformed this understanding of Anglo-American republicanism. Wood linked English opposition ideology to an organic conception of the public good and argued that the American Revolutionaries believed that the sole purpose of government was to promote the public good. Meanwhile, Pocock maintained that English opposition ideology was a restatement of the classical republican or, as he called it, a civic humanism conception of political liberty. For Zuckert's analysis of the different variations of republicanism present in the 'republicanism synthesis' and the evolution of this interpretation see Zuckert, Natural Rights and the New Republicanism, pp. 151-64. During the 1980s, as the interpretations of the republican synthesis became more and more influential and began to be used by a variety of scholars for contemporary political purposes, classical republicanism seemingly came to be identified with both the hopes, anxieties, concepts and institutional arrangements that Bailyn had originally identified from radical Whig ideology and the three political concepts identified in the writings of Pocock and Wood: political liberty understood as the necessity of participating in ruling and being ruled in a political community, virtue understood as requiring self-sacrifice for the public good, and the public good or common interest understood as an entity that transcended the aggregate interests of the community and was not simply a residue of self-interested competition among special-interest groups. In contrast to these understandings of classical republicanism, the Aristotelean characterization of classical republicanism that I use as a standard above is drawn from Paul Rahe's Republics: Ancient and Modern.
    • Republics: Ancient and Modern
    • Rahe, P.1
  • 158
    • 0004224477 scopus 로고
    • New York, Book I, especially Chs. I and II
    • The Politics of Aristotle, ed. Ernest Barker (New York, 1958), Book I, especially Chs. I and II, pp. 1-8. Quote is from p. 7. See also Rahe, Republics: Ancient and Modern, pp. 28-54.
    • (1958) The Politics of Aristotle , pp. 1-8
    • Barker, E.1
  • 159
    • 0004178688 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Politics of Aristotle, ed. Ernest Barker (New York, 1958), Book I, especially Chs. I and II, pp. 1-8. Quote is from p. 7. See also Rahe, Republics: Ancient and Modern, pp. 28-54.
    • Republics: Ancient and Modern , pp. 28-54
    • Rahe1
  • 163
    • 0004178688 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., p. 31. Jean Bethke Elshtain has also recently emphasized this difference between classical and modern republics. 'The classical view', she observes, 'is that the city-state should have complete control of human bodies for the purposes of labor, procreation, and war.' J.B. Elshtain, '"In Common Together": Unity, Diversity, and Civic Virtue', in 'The Constitution of the People' Reflections on Citizens and Civil Society, ed. Robert E. Calvert (Lawrence, KS, 1991), especially pp. 69-72 (quote is on p. 70).
    • Republics: Ancient and Modern , pp. 31
  • 164
    • 84866834158 scopus 로고
    • "In Common Together": Unity, Diversity, and Civic Virtue
    • ed. Robert E. Calvert Lawrence, KS, quote is on p. 70
    • Ibid., p. 31. Jean Bethke Elshtain has also recently emphasized this difference between classical and modern republics. 'The classical view', she observes, 'is that the city-state should have complete control of human bodies for the purposes of labor, procreation, and war.' J.B. Elshtain, '"In Common Together": Unity, Diversity, and Civic Virtue', in 'The Constitution of the People' Reflections on Citizens and Civil Society, ed. Robert E. Calvert (Lawrence, KS, 1991), especially pp. 69-72 (quote is on p. 70).
    • (1991) 'The Constitution of the People' Reflections on Citizens and Civil Society , pp. 69-72
    • Elshtain, J.B.1
  • 166
    • 0003590084 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Lance Banning acknowledges this when he writes: '"Classical Republicanism" it now appears, has proved a deeply troubling term for the collection of ideas whose influence on the Revolution scholars have been emphasizing since the publication of Wood's Creation of the American Republic. Over time, that term, which was originally employed for sensible and solid reasons, has encouraged an impression that the thinking of the early Revolution was considerably less modern than it was - less modern, at a minimum, than "modern" ordinarily implies for scholars trained in political theory.' Banning, The Sacred Fire of Liberty, p. 215.
    • Creation of the American Republic
    • Wood1
  • 167
    • 0010964753 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Lance Banning acknowledges this when he writes: '"Classical Republicanism" it now appears, has proved a deeply troubling term for the collection of ideas whose influence on the Revolution scholars have been emphasizing since the publication of Wood's Creation of the American Republic. Over time, that term, which was originally employed for sensible and solid reasons, has encouraged an impression that the thinking of the early Revolution was considerably less modern than it was - less modern, at a minimum, than "modern" ordinarily implies for scholars trained in political theory.' Banning, The Sacred Fire of Liberty, p. 215.
    • The Sacred Fire of Liberty , pp. 215
    • Banning1
  • 168
    • 0346883764 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Hamilton, The Federalist, No. 15, pp. 110-11; James Madison, 'Vices of the Political System of the United States', PJM, IX, p. 356.
    • The Federalist , vol.15 , pp. 110-111
    • Hamilton1
  • 169
    • 0346884640 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Vices of the Political System of the United States
    • See Hamilton, The Federalist, No. 15, pp. 110-11; James Madison, 'Vices of the Political System of the United States', PJM, IX, p. 356.
    • PJM , vol.9 , pp. 356
    • Madison, J.1
  • 170
    • 0010964753 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Indeed, classical democracy and the conception of political liberty that went with it were never options for the Founders in the first place. Representation was accepted within Anglo-American republicanism long before the American Founding and none of the Founders really envisioned anything but a representative republic. Furthermore, the state governments at the time of the adoption of the Constitution were of course designed on the principle of representation, not collective deliberation, and were, as Hamilton pointed out, already much larger than ancient republics. See Banning, The Sacred Fire of Liberty, pp. 216-17; Hamilton, The Federalist, No. 9, pp. 73-4.
    • The Sacred Fire of Liberty , pp. 216-217
    • Banning1
  • 171
    • 0346253426 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Indeed, classical democracy and the conception of political liberty that went with it were never options for the Founders in the first place. Representation was accepted within Anglo-American republicanism long before the American Founding and none of the Founders really envisioned anything but a representative republic. Furthermore, the state governments at the time of the adoption of the Constitution were of course designed on the principle of representation, not collective deliberation, and were, as Hamilton pointed out, already much larger than ancient republics. See Banning, The Sacred Fire of Liberty, pp. 216-17; Hamilton, The Federalist, No. 9, pp. 73-4.
    • The Federalist , vol.9 , pp. 73-74
    • Hamilton1
  • 172
    • 0347514359 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The Founders believed that promotion of the public good or common interest was still one of the primary purposes of government and thus, at least on the surface, seem to share this understanding of the function of government with classical republicanism. Nevertheless, the Founders' understanding of the common interest was profoundly different from the classical conception of a public good. In classical political thought, the 'public good' implied a full-blown defence of a specific conception of the good life. In the Founders' conception of a 'common interest', however, this concept took on a much more economic meaning - a meaning which does not involve the promotion of a single conception of the good life and thus does not challenge the characterization of their political system as a species of deontological liberalism. In other words, the Founders' conception of a common interest was compatible with individual autonomy and a high degree of scepticism about what constitutes the good life and an unwillingness to have the government foster it.
  • 174
    • 0005435460 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Zuckert makes this point with characteristic clarity: 'The distance of the republican conception from the theory of the Declaration should be apparent from even this brief sketch. According to the republican thesis, human beings are intensely political (Pocock) and/or communal (Wood); according to the Declaration, human beings are not originally or naturally political - the origin is a state of nature understood as an apolitical condition. Although polity is essential, it is not natural; it is made by human beings. Politics, according to the Declaration, is for the sake of natural rights, and natural rights are emphatically prepolitical. The Declaration nowhere intimates that in political participation lies human fulfillment; in place of human fulfillment is the right to the pursuit of happiness.' Zuckert, The Natural Rights Republic, p. 206.
    • The Natural Rights Republic , pp. 206
    • Zuckert1
  • 175
    • 0002255759 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bailyn, Ideological Origins, p. 43; Bernard Bailyn, The Origin of American Politics (New York, 1968), p. 53.
    • Ideological Origins , pp. 43
    • Bailyn1
  • 177
    • 0346884747 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The significance of Cato's Letters is for example stressed by Huyler, Zuckert and Shalhope. See Huyler, Locke in America, pp. 211-30; Zuckert, Natural Rights and the New Republicanism, pp. xix-xx, 305-19; Shalhope, The Roots of Democracy, pp. 41-2.
    • Locke in America , pp. 211-230
    • Huyler1
  • 178
    • 0004040248 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The significance of Cato's Letters is for example stressed by Huyler, Zuckert and Shalhope. See Huyler, Locke in America, pp. 211-30; Zuckert, Natural Rights and the New Republicanism, pp. xix-xx, 305-19; Shalhope, The Roots of Democracy, pp. 41-2.
    • Natural Rights and the New Republicanism
    • Zuckert1
  • 179
    • 0040730869 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The significance of Cato's Letters is for example stressed by Huyler, Zuckert and Shalhope. See Huyler, Locke in America, pp. 211-30; Zuckert, Natural Rights and the New Republicanism, pp. xix-xx, 305-19; Shalhope, The Roots of Democracy, pp. 41-2.
    • The Roots of Democracy , pp. 41-42
    • Shalhope1
  • 180
    • 0003651959 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA, Enlarged Edition
    • Bernard Bailyn, The Ideological Origins of the American Revolution (Cambridge, MA, 1992. Enlarged Edition), pp. 351-79; The Federalist, No. 24, pp. 157-62; The Federalist, No. 26, pp. 168-74.
    • (1992) The Ideological Origins of the American Revolution , pp. 351-379
    • Bailyn, B.1
  • 181
    • 0348144355 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bernard Bailyn, The Ideological Origins of the American Revolution (Cambridge, MA, 1992. Enlarged Edition), pp. 351-79; The Federalist, No. 24, pp. 157-62; The Federalist, No. 26, pp. 168-74.
    • The Federalist , vol.24 , pp. 157-162
  • 182
    • 0348144356 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bernard Bailyn, The Ideological Origins of the American Revolution (Cambridge, MA, 1992. Enlarged Edition), pp. 351-79; The Federalist, No. 24, pp. 157-62; The Federalist, No. 26, pp. 168-74.
    • The Federalist , vol.26 , pp. 168-174
  • 183
    • 0004299644 scopus 로고
    • Ithaca, NY
    • Lance Banning, The Jeffersonian Persuasion: Evolution of a Party Ideology (Ithaca, NY, 1978); L. Banning, 'Republican Ideology and the Triumph of the Constitution, 1789 to 1793', The William and Mary Quarterly, 31 (1974), pp. 178-9; John Murrin, 'The Great Inversion, or Court versus Country: A Comparison of the Revolutionary Settlements in England (1688-1721) and America (1776-1816)', in Three British Revolutions: 1641, 1688, 1776, ed. J.G.A. Pocock (Princeton, NJ, 1980), pp. 368-453; McCoy, The Elusive Republic; Stanley Elkins and Eric McKitrick, The Age of Federalism (New York, 1993).
    • (1978) The Jeffersonian Persuasion: Evolution of a Party Ideology
    • Banning, L.1
  • 184
    • 0011608617 scopus 로고
    • Republican Ideology and the Triumph of the Constitution, 1789 to 1793
    • Lance Banning, The Jeffersonian Persuasion: Evolution of a Party Ideology (Ithaca, NY, 1978); L. Banning, 'Republican Ideology and the Triumph of the Constitution, 1789 to 1793', The William and Mary Quarterly, 31 (1974), pp. 178-9; John Murrin, 'The Great Inversion, or Court versus Country: A Comparison of the Revolutionary Settlements in England (1688-1721) and America (1776-1816)', in Three British Revolutions: 1641, 1688, 1776, ed. J.G.A. Pocock (Princeton, NJ, 1980), pp. 368-453; McCoy, The Elusive Republic; Stanley Elkins and Eric McKitrick, The Age of Federalism (New York, 1993).
    • (1974) The William and Mary Quarterly , vol.31 , pp. 178-179
    • Banning, L.1
  • 185
    • 0040209375 scopus 로고
    • The Great Inversion, or Court versus Country: A Comparison of the Revolutionary Settlements in England (1688-1721) and America (1776-1816)
    • ed. J.G.A. Pocock Princeton, NJ
    • Lance Banning, The Jeffersonian Persuasion: Evolution of a Party Ideology (Ithaca, NY, 1978); L. Banning, 'Republican Ideology and the Triumph of the Constitution, 1789 to 1793', The William and Mary Quarterly, 31 (1974), pp. 178-9; John Murrin, 'The Great Inversion, or Court versus Country: A Comparison of the Revolutionary Settlements in England (1688-1721) and America (1776-1816)', in Three British Revolutions: 1641, 1688, 1776, ed. J.G.A. Pocock (Princeton, NJ, 1980), pp. 368-453; McCoy, The Elusive Republic; Stanley Elkins and Eric McKitrick, The Age of Federalism (New York, 1993).
    • (1980) Three British Revolutions: 1641, 1688, 1776 , pp. 368-453
    • Murrin, J.1
  • 186
    • 0007256833 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Lance Banning, The Jeffersonian Persuasion: Evolution of a Party Ideology (Ithaca, NY, 1978); L. Banning, 'Republican Ideology and the Triumph of the Constitution, 1789 to 1793', The William and Mary Quarterly, 31 (1974), pp. 178-9; John Murrin, 'The Great Inversion, or Court versus Country: A Comparison of the Revolutionary Settlements in England (1688-1721) and America (1776-1816)', in Three British Revolutions: 1641, 1688, 1776, ed. J.G.A. Pocock (Princeton, NJ, 1980), pp. 368-453; McCoy, The Elusive Republic; Stanley Elkins
    • The Elusive Republic
    • McCoy1
  • 187
    • 0004266845 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York
    • Lance Banning, The Jeffersonian Persuasion: Evolution of a Party Ideology (Ithaca, NY, 1978); L. Banning, 'Republican Ideology and the Triumph of the Constitution, 1789 to 1793', The William and Mary Quarterly, 31 (1974), pp. 178-9; John Murrin, 'The Great Inversion, or Court versus Country: A Comparison of the Revolutionary Settlements in England (1688-1721) and America (1776-1816)', in Three British Revolutions: 1641, 1688, 1776, ed. J.G.A. Pocock (Princeton, NJ, 1980), pp. 368-453; McCoy, The Elusive Republic; Stanley Elkins and Eric McKitrick, The Age of Federalism (New York, 1993).
    • (1993) The Age of Federalism
    • Elkins, S.1    McKitrick, E.2
  • 189
    • 0347514355 scopus 로고
    • Some Second Thoughts on Virtue and the Course of Revolutionary Thinking
    • ed. Terence Ball and J.G.A. Pocock Lawrence, KS
    • See Lance Banning, 'Some Second Thoughts on Virtue and the Course of Revolutionary Thinking', in Conceptual Change and the Constitution, ed. Terence Ball and J.G.A. Pocock (Lawrence, KS, 1988), pp. 194-212; Banning, 'Retrospect and Prospect', pp. 106-17; Lance Banning, Jefferson and Madison: Three Conversations From the Founding (Madison, WI, 1995), pp. 57-99. Bailyn, Ideological Origins, pp. 368-79; Richard Vetterli and Gary Bryner, In Search of The Republic: Public Virtue and the Roots of American Government (Totowa, NJ, 1987); John Ashworth, 'The Jeffersonians: Classical Republicans or Liberal Capitalists?', Journal of American Studies, 18 (1984), pp. 428-30; Kloppenberg, 'The Virtues of Liberalism', pp. 9-33; Sinopoli, The Foundations of American Citizenship; Richard Sinopoli, 'Liberalism, Republicanism & the Constitution', Polity, 19 (1984), pp. 331-52. Most scholars seem also to have concluded that this understanding of virtue was further modified during the late eighteenth and early nineteenth century and increasingly became equated with 'benevolence', 'bourgeois propriety' and 'feminine purity'. See Kloppenberg, 'The Virtues of Liberalism', p. 29; Gordon S. Wood, The Radicalism of the American Revolution (New York, 1992), pp. 213-25, 356-7.
    • (1988) Conceptual Change and the Constitution , pp. 194-212
    • Banning, L.1
  • 190
    • 0346884764 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Lance Banning, 'Some Second Thoughts on Virtue and the Course of Revolutionary Thinking', in Conceptual Change and the Constitution, ed. Terence Ball and J.G.A. Pocock (Lawrence, KS, 1988), pp. 194-212; Banning, 'Retrospect and Prospect', pp. 106-17; Lance Banning, Jefferson and Madison: Three Conversations From the Founding (Madison, WI, 1995), pp. 57-99. Bailyn, Ideological Origins, pp. 368-79; Richard Vetterli and Gary Bryner, In Search of The Republic: Public Virtue and the Roots of American Government (Totowa, NJ, 1987); John Ashworth, 'The Jeffersonians: Classical Republicans or Liberal Capitalists?', Journal of American Studies, 18 (1984), pp. 428-30; Kloppenberg, 'The Virtues of Liberalism', pp. 9-33; Sinopoli, The Foundations of American Citizenship; Richard Sinopoli, 'Liberalism, Republicanism & the Constitution', Polity, 19 (1984), pp. 331-52. Most scholars seem also to have concluded that this understanding of virtue was further modified during the late eighteenth and early nineteenth century and increasingly became equated with 'benevolence', 'bourgeois propriety' and 'feminine purity'. See Kloppenberg, 'The Virtues of Liberalism', p. 29; Gordon S. Wood, The Radicalism of the American Revolution (New York, 1992), pp. 213-25, 356-7.
    • Retrospect and Prospect , pp. 106-117
    • Banning1
  • 191
    • 0010714670 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Madison, WI
    • See Lance Banning, 'Some Second Thoughts on Virtue and the Course of Revolutionary Thinking', in Conceptual Change and the Constitution, ed. Terence Ball and J.G.A. Pocock (Lawrence, KS, 1988), pp. 194-212; Banning, 'Retrospect and Prospect', pp. 106-17; Lance Banning, Jefferson and Madison: Three Conversations From the Founding (Madison, WI, 1995), pp. 57-99. Bailyn, Ideological Origins, pp. 368-79; Richard Vetterli and Gary Bryner, In Search of The Republic: Public Virtue and the Roots of American Government (Totowa, NJ, 1987); John Ashworth, 'The Jeffersonians: Classical Republicans or Liberal Capitalists?', Journal of American Studies, 18 (1984), pp. 428-30; Kloppenberg, 'The Virtues of Liberalism', pp. 9-33; Sinopoli, The Foundations of American Citizenship; Richard Sinopoli, 'Liberalism, Republicanism & the Constitution', Polity, 19 (1984), pp. 331-52. Most scholars seem also to have concluded that this understanding of virtue was further modified during the late eighteenth and early nineteenth century and increasingly became equated with 'benevolence', 'bourgeois propriety' and 'feminine purity'. See Kloppenberg, 'The Virtues of Liberalism', p. 29; Gordon S. Wood, The Radicalism of the American Revolution (New York, 1992), pp. 213-25, 356-7.
    • (1995) Jefferson and Madison: Three Conversations from the Founding , pp. 57-99
    • Banning, L.1
  • 192
    • 0002255759 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Lance Banning, 'Some Second Thoughts on Virtue and the Course of Revolutionary Thinking', in Conceptual Change and the Constitution, ed. Terence Ball and J.G.A. Pocock (Lawrence, KS, 1988), pp. 194-212; Banning, 'Retrospect and Prospect', pp. 106-17; Lance Banning, Jefferson and Madison: Three Conversations From the Founding (Madison, WI, 1995), pp. 57-99. Bailyn, Ideological Origins, pp. 368-79; Richard Vetterli and Gary Bryner, In Search of The Republic: Public Virtue and the Roots of American Government (Totowa, NJ, 1987); John Ashworth, 'The Jeffersonians: Classical Republicans or Liberal Capitalists?', Journal of American Studies, 18 (1984), pp. 428-30; Kloppenberg, 'The Virtues of Liberalism', pp. 9-33; Sinopoli, The Foundations of American Citizenship; Richard Sinopoli, 'Liberalism, Republicanism & the Constitution', Polity, 19 (1984), pp. 331-52. Most scholars seem also to have concluded that this understanding of virtue was further modified during the late eighteenth and early nineteenth century and increasingly became equated with 'benevolence', 'bourgeois propriety' and 'feminine purity'. See Kloppenberg, 'The Virtues of Liberalism', p. 29; Gordon S. Wood, The Radicalism of the American Revolution (New York, 1992), pp. 213-25, 356-7.
    • Ideological Origins , pp. 368-379
    • Bailyn1
  • 193
    • 0041170103 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Totowa, NJ
    • See Lance Banning, 'Some Second Thoughts on Virtue and the Course of Revolutionary Thinking', in Conceptual Change and the Constitution, ed. Terence Ball and J.G.A. Pocock (Lawrence, KS, 1988), pp. 194-212; Banning, 'Retrospect and Prospect', pp. 106-17; Lance Banning, Jefferson and Madison: Three Conversations From the Founding (Madison, WI, 1995), pp. 57-99. Bailyn, Ideological Origins, pp. 368-79; Richard Vetterli and Gary Bryner, In Search of The Republic: Public Virtue and the Roots of American Government (Totowa, NJ, 1987); John Ashworth, 'The Jeffersonians: Classical Republicans or Liberal Capitalists?', Journal of American Studies, 18 (1984), pp. 428-30; Kloppenberg, 'The Virtues of Liberalism', pp. 9-33; Sinopoli, The Foundations of American Citizenship; Richard Sinopoli, 'Liberalism, Republicanism & the Constitution', Polity, 19 (1984), pp. 331-52. Most scholars seem also to have concluded that this understanding of virtue was further modified during the late eighteenth and early nineteenth century and increasingly became equated with 'benevolence', 'bourgeois propriety' and 'feminine purity'. See Kloppenberg, 'The Virtues of Liberalism', p. 29; Gordon S. Wood, The Radicalism of the American Revolution (New York, 1992), pp. 213-25, 356-7.
    • (1987) In Search of the Republic: Public Virtue and the Roots of American Government
    • Vetterli, R.1    Bryner, G.2
  • 194
    • 84928095031 scopus 로고
    • The Jeffersonians: Classical Republicans or Liberal Capitalists?
    • See Lance Banning, 'Some Second Thoughts on Virtue and the Course of Revolutionary Thinking', in Conceptual Change and the Constitution, ed. Terence Ball and J.G.A. Pocock (Lawrence, KS, 1988), pp. 194-212; Banning, 'Retrospect and Prospect', pp. 106-17; Lance Banning, Jefferson and Madison: Three Conversations From the Founding (Madison, WI, 1995), pp. 57-99. Bailyn, Ideological Origins, pp. 368-79; Richard Vetterli and Gary Bryner, In Search of The Republic: Public Virtue and the Roots of American Government (Totowa, NJ, 1987); John Ashworth, 'The Jeffersonians: Classical Republicans or Liberal Capitalists?', Journal of American Studies, 18 (1984), pp. 428-30; Kloppenberg, 'The Virtues of Liberalism', pp. 9-33; Sinopoli, The Foundations of American Citizenship; Richard Sinopoli, 'Liberalism, Republicanism & the Constitution', Polity, 19 (1984), pp. 331-52. Most scholars seem also to have concluded that this understanding of virtue was further modified during the late eighteenth and early nineteenth century and increasingly became equated with 'benevolence', 'bourgeois propriety' and 'feminine purity'. See Kloppenberg, 'The Virtues of Liberalism', p. 29; Gordon S. Wood, The Radicalism of the American Revolution (New York, 1992), pp. 213-25, 356-7.
    • (1984) Journal of American Studies , vol.18 , pp. 428-430
    • Ashworth, J.1
  • 195
    • 0004292793 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Lance Banning, 'Some Second Thoughts on Virtue and the Course of Revolutionary Thinking', in Conceptual Change and the Constitution, ed. Terence Ball and J.G.A. Pocock (Lawrence, KS, 1988), pp. 194-212; Banning, 'Retrospect and Prospect', pp. 106-17; Lance Banning, Jefferson and Madison: Three Conversations From the Founding (Madison, WI, 1995), pp. 57-99. Bailyn, Ideological Origins, pp. 368-79; Richard Vetterli and Gary Bryner, In Search of The Republic: Public Virtue and the Roots of American Government (Totowa, NJ, 1987); John Ashworth, 'The Jeffersonians: Classical Republicans or Liberal Capitalists?', Journal of American Studies, 18 (1984), pp. 428-30; Kloppenberg, 'The Virtues of Liberalism', pp. 9-33; Sinopoli, The Foundations of American Citizenship; Richard Sinopoli, 'Liberalism, Republicanism & the Constitution', Polity, 19 (1984), pp. 331-52. Most scholars seem also to have concluded that this understanding of virtue was further modified during the late eighteenth and early nineteenth century and increasingly became equated with 'benevolence', 'bourgeois propriety' and 'feminine purity'. See Kloppenberg, 'The Virtues of Liberalism', p. 29; Gordon S. Wood, The Radicalism of the American Revolution (New York, 1992), pp. 213-25, 356-7.
    • The Virtues of Liberalism , pp. 9-33
    • Kloppenberg1
  • 196
    • 0004009097 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Lance Banning, 'Some Second Thoughts on Virtue and the Course of Revolutionary Thinking', in Conceptual Change and the Constitution, ed. Terence Ball and J.G.A. Pocock (Lawrence, KS, 1988), pp. 194-212; Banning, 'Retrospect and Prospect', pp. 106-17; Lance Banning, Jefferson and Madison: Three Conversations From the Founding (Madison, WI, 1995), pp. 57-99. Bailyn, Ideological Origins, pp. 368-79; Richard Vetterli and Gary Bryner, In Search of The Republic: Public Virtue and the Roots of American Government (Totowa, NJ, 1987); John Ashworth, 'The Jeffersonians: Classical Republicans or Liberal Capitalists?', Journal of American Studies, 18 (1984), pp. 428-30; Kloppenberg, 'The Virtues of Liberalism', pp. 9-33; Sinopoli, The Foundations of American Citizenship; Richard Sinopoli, 'Liberalism, Republicanism & the Constitution', Polity, 19 (1984), pp. 331-52. Most scholars seem also to have concluded that this understanding of virtue was further modified during the late eighteenth and early nineteenth century and increasingly became equated with 'benevolence', 'bourgeois propriety' and 'feminine purity'. See Kloppenberg, 'The Virtues of Liberalism', p. 29; Gordon S. Wood, The Radicalism of the American Revolution (New York, 1992), pp. 213-25, 356-7.
    • The Foundations of American Citizenship
    • Sinopoli1
  • 197
    • 84928461909 scopus 로고
    • Liberalism, Republicanism & the Constitution
    • See Lance Banning, 'Some Second Thoughts on Virtue and the Course of Revolutionary Thinking', in Conceptual Change and the Constitution, ed. Terence Ball and J.G.A. Pocock (Lawrence, KS, 1988), pp. 194-212; Banning, 'Retrospect and Prospect', pp. 106-17; Lance Banning, Jefferson and Madison: Three Conversations From the Founding (Madison, WI, 1995), pp. 57-99. Bailyn, Ideological Origins, pp. 368-79; Richard Vetterli and Gary Bryner, In Search of The Republic: Public Virtue and the Roots of American Government (Totowa, NJ, 1987); John Ashworth, 'The Jeffersonians: Classical Republicans or Liberal Capitalists?', Journal of American Studies, 18 (1984), pp. 428-30; Kloppenberg, 'The Virtues of Liberalism', pp. 9-33; Sinopoli, The Foundations of American Citizenship; Richard Sinopoli, 'Liberalism, Republicanism & the Constitution', Polity, 19 (1984), pp. 331-52. Most scholars seem also to have concluded that this understanding of virtue was further modified during the late eighteenth and early nineteenth century and increasingly became equated with 'benevolence', 'bourgeois propriety' and 'feminine purity'. See Kloppenberg, 'The Virtues of Liberalism', p. 29; Gordon S. Wood, The Radicalism of the American Revolution (New York, 1992), pp. 213-25, 356-7.
    • (1984) Polity , vol.19 , pp. 331-352
    • Sinopoli, R.1
  • 198
    • 0004292793 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Lance Banning, 'Some Second Thoughts on Virtue and the Course of Revolutionary Thinking', in Conceptual Change and the Constitution, ed. Terence Ball and J.G.A. Pocock (Lawrence, KS, 1988), pp. 194-212; Banning, 'Retrospect and Prospect', pp. 106-17; Lance Banning, Jefferson and Madison: Three Conversations From the Founding (Madison, WI, 1995), pp. 57-99. Bailyn, Ideological Origins, pp. 368-79; Richard Vetterli and Gary Bryner, In Search of The Republic: Public Virtue and the Roots of American Government (Totowa, NJ, 1987); John Ashworth, 'The Jeffersonians: Classical Republicans or Liberal Capitalists?', Journal of American Studies, 18 (1984), pp. 428-30; Kloppenberg, 'The Virtues of Liberalism', pp. 9-33; Sinopoli, The Foundations of American Citizenship; Richard Sinopoli, 'Liberalism, Republicanism & the Constitution', Polity, 19 (1984), pp. 331-52. Most scholars seem also to have concluded that this understanding of virtue was further modified during the late eighteenth and early nineteenth century and increasingly became equated with 'benevolence', 'bourgeois propriety' and 'feminine purity'. See Kloppenberg, 'The Virtues of Liberalism', p. 29; Gordon S. Wood, The Radicalism of the American Revolution (New York, 1992), pp. 213-25, 356-7.
    • The Virtues of Liberalism , pp. 29
    • Kloppenberg1
  • 199
    • 0004228462 scopus 로고
    • New York
    • See Lance Banning, 'Some Second Thoughts on Virtue and the Course of Revolutionary Thinking', in Conceptual Change and the Constitution, ed. Terence Ball and J.G.A. Pocock (Lawrence, KS, 1988), pp. 194-212; Banning, 'Retrospect and Prospect', pp. 106-17; Lance Banning, Jefferson and Madison: Three Conversations From the Founding (Madison, WI, 1995), pp. 57-99. Bailyn, Ideological Origins, pp. 368-79; Richard Vetterli and Gary Bryner, In Search of The Republic: Public Virtue and the Roots of American Government (Totowa, NJ, 1987); John Ashworth, 'The Jeffersonians: Classical Republicans or Liberal Capitalists?', Journal of American Studies, 18 (1984), pp. 428-30; Kloppenberg, 'The Virtues of Liberalism', pp. 9-33; Sinopoli, The Foundations of American Citizenship; Richard Sinopoli, 'Liberalism, Republicanism & the Constitution', Polity, 19 (1984), pp. 331-52. Most scholars seem also to have concluded that this understanding of virtue was further modified during the late eighteenth and early nineteenth century and increasingly became equated with 'benevolence', 'bourgeois propriety' and 'feminine purity'. See Kloppenberg, 'The Virtues of Liberalism', p. 29; Gordon S. Wood, The Radicalism of the American Revolution (New York, 1992), pp. 213-25, 356-7.
    • (1992) The Radicalism of the American Revolution , pp. 213-225
    • Wood, G.S.1
  • 202
    • 0003787331 scopus 로고
    • Chicago
    • See the classic expressions of this view in David Truman, The Governmental Process: Political Interests and Public Opinion (New York, 1951), pp. 50-1, and Arthur Bentley, The Process of Government: A Study of Social Pressures (Chicago, 1908).
    • (1908) The Process of Government: A Study of Social Pressures
    • Bentley, A.1
  • 203
    • 0347514350 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See The Federalist, No. 49, p. 317.
    • The Federalist , vol.49 , pp. 317
  • 204
    • 84903061228 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Federalist, No. 51, p. 322.
    • The Federalist , vol.51 , pp. 322
  • 207
    • 0039101716 scopus 로고
    • The Compromised Republic: Public Purposelessness in America
    • ed. Robert H. Horwitz Charlottesville, VA
    • Benjamin Barber, 'The Compromised Republic: Public Purposelessness in America', in The Moral Foundations of the American Republic, ed. Robert H. Horwitz (Charlottesville, VA, 1979), p. 19.
    • (1979) The Moral Foundations of the American Republic , pp. 19
    • Barber, B.1
  • 208
    • 0007407872 scopus 로고
    • New York
    • George Will, Statecraft as Soulcraft: What Government Does (New York, 1983), pp. 31, 38. Examples of this thesis can be found in Barber, 'The Compromised Republic', esp. pp. 20-30; Robert Dahl, A Preface to Democratic Theory (Chicago, 1956), pp. 1-33; Martin Diamond, 'Democracy and The Federalist: A Reconsideration of the Framers' Intent', 'The Federalist, 1787-1788', 'Ethics and Politics: The American Way', in As Far As Republican Principles Will Admit, pp. 17-36, 37-57, 337-68; Richard Hofstadter, The American Political Tradition, pp. 3-21; Isaac Kramnick, 'Editor's Introduction', in The Federalist Papers, ed. Isaac Kramnick (London, 1987), pp. 73-4; Arthur Lovejoy, 'The Theory of Human Nature in the American Constitution and the Method of Counterpoise', in Reflections on Human Nature (Baltimore, 1961), pp. 37-65; Sheldon Wolin, Politics and Vision: Continuity and Innovation in Western Political Thought (Boston, 1960), pp. 388-93. Even Gordon Wood's The Creation of the American Republic can be read as setting forth a pluralist interpretation. Consider Wood's analysis on pp. 605-6.
    • (1983) Statecraft as Soulcraft: What Government Does , pp. 31
    • Will, G.1
  • 209
    • 0347514343 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • George Will, Statecraft as Soulcraft: What Government Does (New York, 1983), pp. 31, 38. Examples of this thesis can be found in Barber, 'The Compromised Republic', esp. pp. 20-30; Robert Dahl, A Preface to Democratic Theory (Chicago, 1956), pp. 1-33; Martin Diamond, 'Democracy and The Federalist: A Reconsideration of the Framers' Intent', 'The Federalist, 1787-1788', 'Ethics and Politics: The American Way', in As Far As Republican Principles Will Admit, pp. 17-36, 37-57, 337-68; Richard Hofstadter, The American Political Tradition, pp. 3-21; Isaac Kramnick, 'Editor's Introduction', in The Federalist Papers, ed. Isaac Kramnick (London, 1987), pp. 73-4; Arthur Lovejoy, 'The Theory of Human Nature in the American Constitution and the Method of Counterpoise', in Reflections on Human Nature (Baltimore, 1961), pp. 37-65; Sheldon Wolin, Politics and Vision: Continuity and Innovation in Western Political Thought (Boston, 1960), pp. 388-93. Even Gordon Wood's The Creation of the American Republic can be read as setting forth a pluralist interpretation. Consider Wood's analysis on pp. 605-6.
    • The Compromised Republic , pp. 20-30
    • Barber1
  • 210
    • 0004167736 scopus 로고
    • Chicago
    • George Will, Statecraft as Soulcraft: What Government Does (New York, 1983), pp. 31, 38. Examples of this thesis can be found in Barber, 'The Compromised Republic', esp. pp. 20-30; Robert Dahl, A Preface to Democratic Theory (Chicago, 1956), pp. 1-33; Martin Diamond, 'Democracy and The Federalist: A Reconsideration of the Framers' Intent', 'The Federalist, 1787-1788', 'Ethics and Politics: The American Way', in As Far As Republican Principles Will Admit, pp. 17-36, 37-57, 337-68; Richard Hofstadter, The American Political Tradition, pp. 3-21; Isaac Kramnick, 'Editor's Introduction', in The Federalist Papers, ed. Isaac Kramnick (London, 1987), pp. 73-4; Arthur Lovejoy, 'The Theory of Human Nature in the American Constitution and the Method of Counterpoise', in Reflections on Human Nature (Baltimore, 1961), pp. 37-65; Sheldon Wolin, Politics and Vision: Continuity and Innovation in Western Political Thought (Boston, 1960), pp. 388-93. Even Gordon Wood's The Creation of the American Republic can be read as setting forth a pluralist interpretation. Consider Wood's analysis on pp. 605-6.
    • (1956) A Preface to Democratic Theory , pp. 1-33
    • Dahl, R.1
  • 211
    • 0348144336 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Democracy and the Federalist: A Reconsideration of the Framers' Intent
    • George Will, Statecraft as Soulcraft: What Government Does (New York, 1983), pp. 31, 38. Examples of this thesis can be found in Barber, 'The Compromised Republic', esp. pp. 20-30; Robert Dahl, A Preface to Democratic Theory (Chicago, 1956), pp. 1-33; Martin Diamond, 'Democracy and The Federalist: A Reconsideration of the Framers' Intent', 'The Federalist, 1787-1788', 'Ethics and Politics: The American Way', in As Far As Republican Principles Will Admit, pp. 17-36, 37-57, 337-68; Richard Hofstadter, The American Political Tradition, pp. 3-21; Isaac Kramnick, 'Editor's Introduction', in The Federalist Papers, ed. Isaac Kramnick (London, 1987), pp. 73-4; Arthur Lovejoy, 'The Theory of Human Nature in the American Constitution and the Method of Counterpoise', in Reflections on Human Nature (Baltimore, 1961), pp. 37-65; Sheldon Wolin, Politics and Vision: Continuity and Innovation in Western Political Thought (Boston, 1960), pp. 388-93. Even Gordon Wood's The Creation of the American Republic can be read as setting forth a pluralist interpretation. Consider Wood's analysis on pp. 605-6.
    • The Federalist, 1787-1788
    • Diamond, M.1
  • 212
    • 0347514344 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ethics and Politics: The American Way
    • George Will, Statecraft as Soulcraft: What Government Does (New York, 1983), pp. 31, 38. Examples of this thesis can be found in Barber, 'The Compromised Republic', esp. pp. 20-30; Robert Dahl, A Preface to Democratic Theory (Chicago, 1956), pp. 1-33; Martin Diamond, 'Democracy and The Federalist: A Reconsideration of the Framers' Intent', 'The Federalist, 1787-1788', 'Ethics and Politics: The American Way', in As Far As Republican Principles Will Admit, pp. 17-36, 37-57, 337-68; Richard Hofstadter, The American Political Tradition, pp. 3-21; Isaac Kramnick, 'Editor's Introduction', in The Federalist Papers, ed. Isaac Kramnick (London, 1987), pp. 73-4; Arthur Lovejoy, 'The Theory of Human Nature in the American Constitution and the Method of Counterpoise', in Reflections on Human Nature (Baltimore, 1961), pp. 37-65; Sheldon Wolin, Politics and Vision: Continuity and Innovation in Western Political Thought (Boston, 1960), pp. 388-93. Even Gordon Wood's The Creation of the American Republic can be read as setting forth a pluralist interpretation. Consider Wood's analysis on pp. 605-6.
    • As Far as Republican Principles Will Admit , pp. 17-36
  • 213
    • 0003790885 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • George Will, Statecraft as Soulcraft: What Government Does (New York, 1983), pp. 31, 38. Examples of this thesis can be found in Barber, 'The Compromised Republic', esp. pp. 20-30; Robert Dahl, A Preface to Democratic Theory (Chicago, 1956), pp. 1-33; Martin Diamond, 'Democracy and The Federalist: A Reconsideration of the Framers' Intent', 'The Federalist, 1787-1788', 'Ethics and Politics: The American Way', in As Far As Republican Principles Will Admit, pp. 17-36, 37-57, 337-68; Richard Hofstadter, The American Political Tradition, pp. 3-21; Isaac Kramnick, 'Editor's Introduction', in The Federalist Papers, ed. Isaac Kramnick (London, 1987), pp. 73-4; Arthur Lovejoy, 'The Theory of Human Nature in the American Constitution and the Method of Counterpoise', in Reflections on Human Nature (Baltimore, 1961), pp. 37-65; Sheldon Wolin, Politics and Vision: Continuity and Innovation in Western Political Thought (Boston, 1960), pp. 388-93. Even Gordon Wood's The Creation of the American Republic can be read as setting forth a pluralist interpretation. Consider Wood's analysis on pp. 605-6.
    • The American Political Tradition , pp. 3-21
    • Hofstadter, R.1
  • 214
    • 0348144335 scopus 로고
    • Editor's Introduction
    • ed. Isaac Kramnick London
    • George Will, Statecraft as Soulcraft: What Government Does (New York, 1983), pp. 31, 38. Examples of this thesis can be found in Barber, 'The Compromised Republic', esp. pp. 20-30; Robert Dahl, A Preface to Democratic Theory (Chicago, 1956), pp. 1-33; Martin Diamond, 'Democracy and The Federalist: A Reconsideration of the Framers' Intent', 'The Federalist, 1787-1788', 'Ethics and Politics: The American Way', in As Far As Republican Principles Will Admit, pp. 17-36, 37-57, 337-68; Richard Hofstadter, The American Political Tradition, pp. 3-21; Isaac Kramnick, 'Editor's Introduction', in The Federalist Papers, ed. Isaac Kramnick (London, 1987), pp. 73-4; Arthur Lovejoy, 'The Theory of Human Nature in the American Constitution and the Method of Counterpoise', in Reflections on Human Nature (Baltimore, 1961), pp. 37-65; Sheldon Wolin, Politics and Vision: Continuity and Innovation in Western Political Thought (Boston, 1960), pp. 388-93. Even Gordon Wood's The Creation of the American Republic can be read as setting forth a pluralist interpretation. Consider Wood's analysis on pp. 605-6.
    • (1987) The Federalist Papers , pp. 73-74
    • Kramnick, I.1
  • 215
    • 0348144332 scopus 로고
    • The Theory of Human Nature in the American Constitution and the Method of Counterpoise
    • Baltimore
    • George Will, Statecraft as Soulcraft: What Government Does (New York, 1983), pp. 31, 38. Examples of this thesis can be found in Barber, 'The Compromised Republic', esp. pp. 20-30; Robert Dahl, A Preface to Democratic Theory (Chicago, 1956), pp. 1-33; Martin Diamond, 'Democracy and The Federalist: A Reconsideration of the Framers' Intent', 'The Federalist, 1787-1788', 'Ethics and Politics: The American Way', in As Far As Republican Principles Will Admit, pp. 17-36, 37-57, 337-68; Richard Hofstadter, The American Political Tradition, pp. 3-21; Isaac Kramnick, 'Editor's Introduction', in The Federalist Papers, ed. Isaac Kramnick (London, 1987), pp. 73-4; Arthur Lovejoy, 'The Theory of Human Nature in the American Constitution and the Method of Counterpoise', in Reflections on Human Nature (Baltimore, 1961), pp. 37-65; Sheldon Wolin, Politics and Vision: Continuity and Innovation in Western Political Thought (Boston, 1960), pp. 388-93. Even Gordon Wood's The Creation of the American Republic can be read as setting forth a pluralist interpretation. Consider Wood's analysis on pp. 605-6.
    • (1961) Reflections on Human Nature , pp. 37-65
    • Lovejoy, A.1
  • 216
    • 0004207993 scopus 로고
    • Boston
    • George Will, Statecraft as Soulcraft: What Government Does (New York, 1983), pp. 31, 38. Examples of this thesis can be found in Barber, 'The Compromised Republic', esp. pp. 20-30; Robert Dahl, A Preface to Democratic Theory (Chicago, 1956), pp. 1-33; Martin Diamond, 'Democracy and The Federalist: A Reconsideration of the Framers' Intent', 'The Federalist, 1787-1788', 'Ethics and Politics: The American Way', in As Far As Republican Principles Will Admit, pp. 17-36, 37-57, 337-68; Richard Hofstadter, The American Political Tradition, pp. 3-21; Isaac Kramnick, 'Editor's Introduction', in The Federalist Papers, ed. Isaac Kramnick (London, 1987), pp. 73-4; Arthur Lovejoy, 'The Theory of Human Nature in the American Constitution and the Method of Counterpoise', in Reflections on Human Nature (Baltimore, 1961), pp. 37-65; Sheldon Wolin, Politics and Vision: Continuity and Innovation in Western Political Thought (Boston, 1960), pp. 388-93. Even Gordon Wood's The Creation of the American Republic can be read as setting forth a pluralist interpretation. Consider Wood's analysis on pp. 605-6.
    • (1960) Politics and Vision: Continuity and Innovation in Western Political Thought , pp. 388-393
    • Wolin, S.1
  • 217
    • 0003590084 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • George Will, Statecraft as Soulcraft: What Government Does (New York, 1983), pp. 31, 38. Examples of this thesis can be found in Barber, 'The Compromised Republic', esp. pp. 20-30; Robert Dahl, A Preface to Democratic Theory (Chicago, 1956), pp. 1-33; Martin Diamond, 'Democracy and The Federalist: A Reconsideration of the Framers' Intent', 'The Federalist, 1787-1788', 'Ethics and Politics: The American Way', in As Far As Republican Principles Will Admit, pp. 17-36, 37-57, 337-68; Richard Hofstadter, The American Political Tradition, pp. 3-21; Isaac Kramnick, 'Editor's Introduction', in The Federalist Papers, ed. Isaac Kramnick (London, 1987), pp. 73-4; Arthur Lovejoy, 'The Theory of Human Nature in the American Constitution and the Method of Counterpoise', in Reflections on Human Nature (Baltimore, 1961), pp. 37-65; Sheldon Wolin, Politics and Vision: Continuity and Innovation in Western Political Thought (Boston, 1960), pp. 388-93. Even Gordon Wood's The Creation of the American Republic can be read as setting forth a pluralist interpretation. Consider Wood's analysis on pp. 605-6.
    • The Creation of the American Republic , pp. 605-606
    • Wood, G.1
  • 218
    • 0346883754 scopus 로고
    • Commerce and Character
    • Ithaca, NY
    • Ralph Lerner, 'Commerce and Character', in The Thinking Revolutionary: Principle and Practice in the New Republic (Ithaca, NY, 1979), pp. 195-221; Hiram Caton, The Politics of Progress: The Origins and Development of the Commercial Republic, 1600-1835 (Gainesville, FL, 1988), pp. 459-78; Martin Diamond, 'Ethics and Politics: The American Way', in As Far As Republican Principles Will Admit, pp. 337-68; John R. Nelson, Liberty and Property: Political Economy and Policymaking in the New Nation, 1789-1812 (Baltimore, MD, 1987). See also Albert Hirshman, The Passions and the Interests: Political Arguments For Capitalism Before Its Triumph (Princeton, NJ, 1977).
    • (1979) The Thinking Revolutionary: Principle and Practice in the New Republic , pp. 195-221
    • Lerner, R.1
  • 219
    • 0004039933 scopus 로고
    • Gainesville, FL
    • Ralph Lerner, 'Commerce and Character', in The Thinking Revolutionary: Principle and Practice in the New Republic (Ithaca, NY, 1979), pp. 195-221; Hiram Caton, The Politics of Progress: The Origins and Development of the Commercial Republic, 1600-1835 (Gainesville, FL, 1988), pp. 459-78; Martin Diamond, 'Ethics and Politics: The American Way', in As Far As Republican Principles Will Admit, pp. 337-68; John R. Nelson, Liberty and Property: Political Economy and Policymaking in the New Nation, 1789-1812 (Baltimore, MD, 1987). See also Albert Hirshman, The Passions and the Interests: Political Arguments For Capitalism Before Its Triumph (Princeton, NJ, 1977).
    • (1988) The Politics of Progress: The Origins and Development of the Commercial Republic, 1600-1835 , pp. 459-478
    • Caton, H.1
  • 220
    • 84929802027 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ethics and Politics: The American Way
    • Ralph Lerner, 'Commerce and Character', in The Thinking Revolutionary: Principle and Practice in the New Republic (Ithaca, NY, 1979), pp. 195-221; Hiram Caton, The Politics of Progress: The Origins and Development of the Commercial Republic, 1600-1835 (Gainesville, FL, 1988), pp. 459-78; Martin Diamond, 'Ethics and Politics: The American Way', in As Far As Republican Principles Will Admit, pp. 337-68; John R. Nelson, Liberty and Property: Political Economy and Policymaking in the New Nation, 1789-1812 (Baltimore, MD, 1987). See also Albert Hirshman, The Passions and the Interests: Political Arguments For Capitalism Before Its Triumph (Princeton, NJ, 1977).
    • As Far As Republican Principles Will Admit , pp. 337-368
    • Diamond, M.1
  • 221
    • 0003695006 scopus 로고
    • Baltimore, MD
    • Ralph Lerner, 'Commerce and Character', in The Thinking Revolutionary: Principle and Practice in the New Republic (Ithaca, NY, 1979), pp. 195-221; Hiram Caton, The Politics of Progress: The Origins and Development of the Commercial Republic, 1600-1835 (Gainesville, FL, 1988), pp. 459-78; Martin Diamond, 'Ethics and Politics: The American Way', in As Far As Republican Principles Will Admit, pp. 337-68; John R. Nelson, Liberty and Property: Political Economy and Policymaking in the New Nation, 1789-1812 (Baltimore, MD, 1987). See also Albert Hirshman, The Passions and the Interests: Political Arguments For Capitalism Before Its Triumph (Princeton, NJ, 1977).
    • (1987) Liberty and Property: Political Economy and Policymaking in the New Nation, 1789-1812
    • Nelson, J.R.1
  • 222
    • 0004061036 scopus 로고
    • Princeton, NJ
    • Ralph Lerner, 'Commerce and Character', in The Thinking Revolutionary: Principle and Practice in the New Republic (Ithaca, NY, 1979), pp. 195-221; Hiram Caton, The Politics of Progress: The Origins and Development of the Commercial Republic, 1600-1835 (Gainesville, FL, 1988), pp. 459-78; Martin Diamond, 'Ethics and Politics: The American Way', in As Far As Republican Principles Will Admit, pp. 337-68; John R. Nelson, Liberty and Property: Political Economy and Policymaking in the New Nation, 1789-1812 (Baltimore, MD, 1987). See also Albert Hirshman, The Passions and the Interests: Political Arguments For Capitalism Before Its Triumph (Princeton, NJ, 1977).
    • (1977) The Passions and the Interests: Political Arguments for Capitalism before Its Triumph
    • Hirshman, A.1
  • 223
    • 84928440484 scopus 로고
    • Impartial Representation and the Extended Republic: Towards a Comprehensive and Balanced Interpretation of the Tenth Federalist
    • Alan Gibson, 'Impartial Representation and the Extended Republic: Towards a Comprehensive and Balanced Interpretation of the Tenth Federalist', History of Political Thought, 12 (1991), pp. 276-9.
    • (1991) History of Political Thought , vol.12 , pp. 276-279
    • Gibson, A.1
  • 225
    • 0037507734 scopus 로고
    • Deliberative Democracy: The Majority Principle in Republican Government
    • ed. Robert A. Goldwin and William A. Schambra Washington, DC
    • Joseph M. Bessette, 'Deliberative Democracy: The Majority Principle in Republican Government', How Democratic Is the Constitution?, ed. Robert A. Goldwin and William A. Schambra (Washington, DC, 1980), pp. 102-16.
    • (1980) How Democratic Is the Constitution? , pp. 102-116
    • Bessette, J.M.1
  • 226
    • 0007256833 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • McCoy, The Elusive Republic, pp. 120-35; See also Elkins and McKitrick, The Age of Federalism, pp. 79-92, 195-208; Lienesch, New Order of the Ages, pp. 83-96.
    • The Elusive Republic , pp. 120-135
    • McCoy1
  • 227
    • 0004266845 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • McCoy, The Elusive Republic, pp. 120-35; See also Elkins and McKitrick, The Age of Federalism, pp. 79-92, 195-208; Lienesch, New Order of the Ages, pp. 83-96.
    • The Age of Federalism , pp. 79-92
    • Elkins1    McKitrick2
  • 228
    • 0040019182 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • McCoy, The Elusive Republic, pp. 120-35; See also Elkins and McKitrick, The Age of Federalism, pp. 79-92, 195-208; Lienesch, New Order of the Ages, pp. 83-96.
    • New Order of the Ages , pp. 83-96
    • Lienesch1
  • 231
    • 84925975753 scopus 로고
    • Commercial Farming and the "Agrarian Myth" in the Early Republic
    • This is the essential truth in Joyce Appleby's characterization of Jeffersonian political economy. See especially Appleby, 'Commercial Farming and the "Agrarian Myth" in the Early Republic', Journal of American History, 68 (1982), pp. 833-49.
    • (1982) Journal of American History , vol.68 , pp. 833-849
    • Appleby1
  • 232
    • 77954072368 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Republican Distribution of Citizens
    • Madison, 'Republican Distribution of Citizens', PJM, XIV, p. 245.
    • PJM , vol.14 , pp. 245
    • Madison1
  • 233
    • 0007256833 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • McCoy, The Elusive Republic, pp. 120-35. See also John Ashworth, 'The Jeffersonians: Classical Republicans or Liberal Capitalists', pp. 425-35; Lienesch, New Order of the Ages, pp. 82-115.
    • The Elusive Republic , pp. 120-135
    • McCoy1
  • 235
    • 0040019182 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • McCoy, The Elusive Republic, pp. 120-35. See also John Ashworth, 'The Jeffersonians: Classical Republicans or Liberal Capitalists', pp. 425-35; Lienesch, New Order of the Ages, pp. 82-115.
    • New Order of the Ages , pp. 82-115
    • Lienesch1
  • 238
    • 0004188692 scopus 로고
    • New York
    • Jean Bethke Elshtain seemingly speaks for many scholars when she writes: 'Curiously, the framers of the American Constitution paid little explicit attention to such institutions, including the family. Perhaps they did not do so because they simply assumed that these associations of civil society were vital and would be long-lasting.' J.B. Elshtain, Democracy on Trial (New York, 1995), p. 6. So far little scholarship has been devoted to challenging this common assumption, but for one exception see the essays in 'The Constitution of the People': Reflections on Citizens and Civil Society, ed. Robert E. Calvert (Lawrence, KS, 1991).
    • (1995) Democracy on Trial , pp. 6
    • Elshtain, J.B.1
  • 239
    • 0041929362 scopus 로고
    • Lawrence, KS
    • Jean Bethke Elshtain seemingly speaks for many scholars when she writes: 'Curiously, the framers of the American Constitution paid little explicit attention to such institutions, including the family. Perhaps they did not do so because they simply assumed that these associations of civil society were vital and would be long-lasting.' J.B. Elshtain, Democracy on Trial (New York, 1995), p. 6. So far little scholarship has been devoted to challenging this common assumption, but for one exception see the essays in 'The Constitution of the People': Reflections on Citizens and Civil Society, ed. Robert E. Calvert (Lawrence, KS, 1991).
    • (1991) 'The Constitution of the People': Reflections on Citizens and Civil Society
    • Calvert, R.E.1
  • 240
    • 0003590084 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It is in this context that Gordon Wood's famous closing remarks to The Creation of the American Republic should be reconsidered thirty years after they were written. The political theory of the American Founders, Wood wrote, was 'diffusive and open ended; it was not delineated in a single book; it was peculiarly the product of a democratic society, without a precise beginning or an ending. It was not political theory in the grand manner, but it was political theory worthy of a prominent place in the history of Western thought.' Wood, The Creation of the American Republic, p. 615.
    • The Creation of the American Republic , pp. 615
    • Wood1
  • 241
    • 0346253429 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The belief that the Founders saw themselves as participants in a battle between the ancients and the moderns seems to be, in some form at least, an almost universally accepted point in this debate. As a result of the scholarship of the late Martin Diamond, many Straussians begin from this point. See As Far As Republican Principles Will Admit; Thomas Pangle's The Spirit of Modern Republicanism and The Ennobling of Democracy: The Challenge of the Postmodern Era (Baltimore, 1992), pp. 93-102; and especially Rahe, Republics: Ancient and Modern. The proponents of the republican synthesis also seem to hold this same view in a modified form. The Pocock-Banning St Louis version of the republican interpretation traces the continuity of classical republican concepts (especially positive liberty) into the American Founding and then throughout American history. In contrast, the Bailyn-Wood Harvard republican interpretation suggests that the American Founding should be viewed as resting on the pivot between the exhaustion of classical and emergence of modern political concepts. Both of these interpretations, however, suggest that the Founders held a dualistic view of the history of political thought and viewed themselves somewhere on a continuum between liberal and classical political thought. The Straussians and the scholars of the republican interpretation, however, have assumed rather than convincingly shown that this was indeed the Founders' self-understanding of the history of political thought and their place within it. Until such a case is convincingly made, such interpretations are problematic because they contradict the foundational assumption about interpretation held by both groups, namely that past political thinkers should be interpreted from a genuinely historical perspective that attempts first to understand how they understood themselves.
    • As Far as Republican Principles Will Admit
  • 242
    • 0346883737 scopus 로고
    • Baltimore
    • The belief that the Founders saw themselves as participants in a battle between the ancients and the moderns seems to be, in some form at least, an almost universally accepted point in this debate. As a result of the scholarship of the late Martin Diamond, many Straussians begin from this point. See As Far As Republican Principles Will Admit; Thomas Pangle's The Spirit of Modern Republicanism and The Ennobling of Democracy: The Challenge of the Postmodern Era (Baltimore, 1992), pp. 93-102; and especially Rahe, Republics: Ancient and Modern. The proponents of the republican synthesis also seem to hold this same view in a modified form. The Pocock-Banning St Louis version of the republican interpretation traces the continuity of classical republican concepts (especially positive liberty) into the American Founding and then throughout American history. In contrast, the Bailyn-Wood Harvard republican interpretation suggests that the American Founding should be viewed as resting on the pivot between the exhaustion of classical and emergence of modern political concepts. Both of these interpretations, however, suggest that the Founders held a dualistic view of the history of political thought and viewed themselves somewhere on a continuum between liberal and classical political thought. The Straussians and the scholars of the republican interpretation, however, have assumed rather than convincingly shown that this was indeed the Founders' self-understanding of the history of political thought and their place within it. Until such a case is convincingly made, such interpretations are problematic because they contradict the foundational assumption about interpretation held by both groups, namely that past political thinkers should be interpreted from a genuinely historical perspective that attempts first to understand how they understood themselves.
    • (1992) The Spirit of Modern Republicanism and the Ennobling of Democracy: The Challenge of the Postmodern Era , pp. 93-102
    • Pangle, T.1
  • 243
    • 0004178688 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The belief that the Founders saw themselves as participants in a battle between the ancients and the moderns seems to be, in some form at least, an almost universally accepted point in this debate. As a result of the scholarship of the late Martin Diamond, many Straussians begin from this point. See As Far As Republican Principles Will Admit; Thomas Pangle's The Spirit of Modern Republicanism and The Ennobling of Democracy: The Challenge of the Postmodern Era (Baltimore, 1992), pp. 93-102; and especially Rahe, Republics: Ancient and Modern. The proponents of the republican synthesis also seem to hold this same view in a modified form. The Pocock-Banning St Louis version of the republican interpretation traces the continuity of classical republican concepts (especially positive liberty) into the American Founding and then throughout American history. In contrast, the Bailyn-Wood Harvard republican interpretation suggests that the American Founding should be viewed as resting on the pivot between the exhaustion of classical and emergence of modern political concepts. Both of these interpretations, however, suggest that the Founders held a dualistic view of the history of political thought and viewed themselves somewhere on a continuum between liberal and classical political thought. The Straussians and the scholars of the republican interpretation, however, have assumed rather than convincingly shown that this was indeed the Founders' self-understanding of the history of political thought and their place within it. Until such a case is convincingly made, such interpretations are problematic because they contradict the foundational assumption about interpretation held by both groups, namely that past political thinkers should be interpreted from a genuinely historical perspective that attempts first to understand how they understood themselves.
    • Republics: Ancient and Modern
    • Rahe1
  • 244
    • 79957105391 scopus 로고
    • The Least Imperfect Government: On Martin Diamond's "Ethics and Politics"
    • In a short but highly provocative appreciation of the scholarship of Martin Diamond, Diamond's friend Marvin Meyers eloquently made several points that have influenced the interpretation presented below. The Founders, Meyers wrote, 'simply did not cast themselves in a universal war between the Moderns and the Ancients'. We should, he continued, 'try faithfully to look through their eyes and texts, acknowledge provisionally their chosen masters, friends, and adversaries. In short, we might do well to borrow their map to the great political and moral campaign of history before superimposing our own.' According to Meyers, such an approach will teach us that the Framers did indeed engage in a 'great campaign', but not against classical Athens or Rome. Instead, Meyers insists, 'their evil Old Regime was rather a model of Early Modern polity that blended remnants of the canon and the feudal law, loosely conceived (by John Adams, for example) as general forms of clerical and aristocratic oppression, with a new kind of enlightened despotism, concentrating and rationalizing and enlarging the power of the state through its monarchical head.' This model of the early modern polity was evident to the Founders most immediately in the corrupt British monarchy of George III but it was also evident in numerous other regimes led by ambitious princes. Finally, Meyers notes that when this view of the Founders' project is accepted, then it becomes clear that they did not view themselves as lowering the ends of politics, but rather as elevating America to the 'full dignity of human nature'. See Marvin Meyers, 'The Least Imperfect Government: On Martin Diamond's "Ethics and Politics"', Interpretation: A Journal of Political Philosophy, 8 (1980), pp. 11-13 for above quotes.
    • (1980) Interpretation: A Journal of Political Philosophy , vol.8 , pp. 11-13
    • Meyers, M.1
  • 245
    • 0346883743 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Federalist, No. 10, p. 81. See also The Federalist, No. 9, pp. 71-2; The Federalist, No. 10, p. 77.
    • The Federalist , vol.10 , pp. 81
  • 246
    • 0346883738 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Federalist, No. 10, p. 81. See also The Federalist, No. 9, pp. 71-2; The Federalist, No. 10, p. 77.
    • The Federalist , vol.9 , pp. 71-72
  • 247
    • 0348144318 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Federalist, No. 10, p. 81. See also The Federalist, No. 9, pp. 71-2; The Federalist, No. 10, p. 77.
    • The Federalist , vol.10 , pp. 77
  • 248
    • 0347514329 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Federalist, No. 18, p. 128.
    • The Federalist , vol.18 , pp. 128
  • 249
    • 0011400433 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Federalist, No. 20, p. 138.
    • The Federalist , vol.20 , pp. 138
  • 250
    • 79957041953 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Notes on Ancient and Modern Confederacies
    • Madison's 'Notes on Ancient and Modern Confederacies', PJM, IX, pp. 3-24; The Federalist, Nos. 18-20, pp. 122-38.
    • PJM , vol.9 , pp. 3-24
    • Madison1
  • 251
    • 0346253428 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Madison's 'Notes on Ancient and Modern Confederacies', PJM, IX, pp. 3-24; The Federalist, Nos. 18-20, pp. 122-38.
    • The Federalist , vol.18 , Issue.20 , pp. 122-138
  • 252
    • 0347514330 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • In contrast, the Anti-federalists and many of the Jeffersonians remained closely fastened to the synthesis of opposition ideology and natural rights philosophy that had accompanied the Revolution. In particular, their undiluted attachment to the fears and anxieties of opposition ideology led them to interpret the experiences of the 1780s profoundly differently from the Framers of the Constitution. Unlike the Framers, the Anti-federalists continued to believe that the central threat to liberty was unaccountable rulers (not majority factions). The Anti-federalists therefore could not accept the institutional innovations that the Framers offered. Direct forms of representation, a scheme of separation of powers designed to prevent independent acts of tyranny by rulers, a small republic, and a revitalized confederation in which the lion's share of power remained in the states, according to the Anti-federalists, would be necessary if liberty was to be preserved.
  • 253
    • 0007256833 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • McCoy, The Elusive Republic, pp. 19-23. See also Lienesch, New Order of the Ages, pp. 83-5.
    • The Elusive Republic , pp. 19-23
    • McCoy1
  • 255
    • 0347514331 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • When the synergism between natural rights philosophy and opposition ideology is recognized, it becomes possible to understand how many of the Founders not only could have viewed the American Revolution as a response to the loss of virtue in Britain, but also could have believed that this loss of virtue threatened the natural rights of mankind, violated the terms of the original contract, and justified rebellion.
  • 260


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.