-
1
-
-
0000832192
-
The negative constitution: A critique
-
1 For a comprehensive survey of negative constitutionalism see Susan Bander, 'The negative constitution: a critique', Michigan Law Review 88 (1989), 2271-347; also Cass Sunstein, 'Democracy and Shifting Preferences', and John Ferejohn, 'Must Preferences be Respected in a Democracy?' in David Copp, Jean Hampton, John E. Roemer (eds), The Idea of Democracy, (New York, Cambridge University Press, 1993) pp. 196-241.
-
(1989)
Michigan Law Review
, vol.88
, pp. 2271-2347
-
-
Bander, S.1
-
2
-
-
0345279823
-
Must preferences be respected in a democracy?'
-
David Copp, Jean Hampton, John E. Roemer (eds), New York, Cambridge University Press
-
1 For a comprehensive survey of negative constitutionalism see Susan Bander, 'The negative constitution: a critique', Michigan Law Review 88 (1989), 2271-347; also Cass Sunstein, 'Democracy and Shifting Preferences', and John Ferejohn, 'Must Preferences be Respected in a Democracy?' in David Copp, Jean Hampton, John E. Roemer (eds), The Idea of Democracy, (New York, Cambridge University Press, 1993) pp. 196-241.
-
(1993)
The Idea of Democracy
, pp. 196-241
-
-
Sunstein, C.1
Ferejohn, J.2
-
3
-
-
84971922771
-
Some rules of constitutional design
-
2 P. C. Ordershook, 'Some rules of constitutional design', Social Philisophy and Policy, 10 (1993) p. 202.
-
(1993)
Social Philisophy and Policy
, vol.10
, pp. 202
-
-
Ordershook, P.C.1
-
4
-
-
0002626231
-
Why a constitution?
-
Bernard Grofman and Donald Whittman (eds), New York, Agathon
-
3 R. Hardin, 'Why a constitution?', in Bernard Grofman and Donald Whittman (eds), The Federalist Papers and the New Institutionalism (New York, Agathon, 1989); Ordershook, 'Some Rules of Constitutional Design', pp. 199-202.
-
(1989)
The Federalist Papers and the New Institutionalism
-
-
Hardin, R.1
-
5
-
-
0347567400
-
-
3 R. Hardin, 'Why a constitution?', in Bernard Grofman and Donald Whittman (eds), The Federalist Papers and the New Institutionalism (New York, Agathon, 1989); Ordershook, 'Some Rules of Constitutional Design', pp. 199-202.
-
Some Rules of Constitutional Design
, pp. 199-202
-
-
Ordershook1
-
7
-
-
0040898820
-
The political form of the constitution: The separation of powers, rights, and representative democracy
-
5 R. Bellamy, 'The political form of the constitution: the separation of powers, rights, and representative democracy', Political Studies 44 (1996) 436-56.
-
(1996)
Political Studies
, vol.44
, pp. 436-456
-
-
Bellamy, R.1
-
10
-
-
0003402019
-
-
Chicago, University of Chicago Press
-
8 For a general discussion see S. Holmes, Passions and Constraints: On the Theory of Liberal Democracy (Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 1995); Duncan Ivison, The Self at Liberty: Political Argument and the Arts of Government (Ithaca, Cornell University Press, 1997).
-
(1995)
Passions and Constraints: On the Theory of Liberal Democracy
-
-
Holmes, S.1
-
11
-
-
0003777393
-
-
Ithaca, Cornell University Press
-
8 For a general discussion see S. Holmes, Passions and Constraints: On the Theory of Liberal Democracy (Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 1995); Duncan Ivison, The Self at Liberty: Political Argument and the Arts of Government (Ithaca, Cornell University Press, 1997).
-
(1997)
The Self at Liberty: Political Argument and the Arts of Government
-
-
Ivison, D.1
-
14
-
-
85034168327
-
-
11 The argument for a presumption against intervention can be either foundational or practical, as Ferejohn argues. The former might be rooted in a conception of liberal neutrality towards individuals' preferences and conceptions of the good, whilst the latter might emphasize the risks of empowering fallible state officials and agencies to interfere in the private sphere. See 'Must Preferences be Respected in a Democracy?', p. 241.
-
Must Preferences Be Respected in A Democracy?
, pp. 241
-
-
-
16
-
-
0004341764
-
-
9
-
13 Dworkin, 'Constitutionalism and democracy', pp. 5, 9; also Law's Empire (Cambridge MA, Harvard University Press, 1986), pp. 381-9.
-
Constitutionalism and Democracy
, pp. 5
-
-
Dworkin1
-
17
-
-
0004166519
-
-
Cambridge MA, Harvard University Press
-
13 Dworkin, 'Constitutionalism and democracy', pp. 5, 9; also Law's Empire (Cambridge MA, Harvard University Press, 1986), pp. 381-9.
-
(1986)
Law's Empire
, pp. 381-389
-
-
-
19
-
-
0004213898
-
-
Cambridge MA, Harvard University Press
-
15 Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously (Cambridge MA, Harvard University Press, 1978) pp. 364-7.
-
(1978)
Taking Rights Seriously
, pp. 364-367
-
-
Dworkin1
-
21
-
-
84936068266
-
-
17 Dworkin identifies a particular 'interpretive, reflective attitude' (a 'protestant attitude') that judges, lawyers and citizens should take on in this forum, which is 'responsible for imagining what . . . society's public commitments to principle are'. See Law's Empire, p. 413
-
Law's Empire
, pp. 413
-
-
Dworkin1
-
22
-
-
0003772817
-
-
Princeton, Princeton University Press
-
18 R. Hardin, One For All: The Logic of Group Conflict (Princeton, Princeton University Press, 1995) p. 179. There is also a strong emphasis on Smithian and Humean themes as much as Hobbesian ones; cf. 'Hobbesian political order', Political Theory, 19 (1991), p. 172
-
(1995)
One For All: The Logic of Group Conflict
, pp. 179
-
-
Hardin, R.1
-
23
-
-
84972700447
-
Hobbesian political order
-
18 R. Hardin, One For All: The Logic of Group Conflict (Princeton, Princeton University Press, 1995) p. 179. There is also a strong emphasis on Smithian and Humean themes as much as Hobbesian ones; cf. 'Hobbesian political order', Political Theory, 19 (1991), p. 172
-
(1991)
Political Theory
, vol.19
, pp. 172
-
-
-
24
-
-
0001778197
-
-
Amy Gutman (ed.), Princeton, Princeton University Press
-
19 See C. Taylor, in Amy Gutman (ed.), Multiculturalism and The Politics of Recognition (Princeton, Princeton University Press, 1992) pp. 25-73; J. Tully, Strange Multiplicity: Constitutionalism in an Age of Diversity (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1995).
-
(1992)
Multiculturalism and The Politics of Recognition
, pp. 25-73
-
-
Taylor, C.1
-
25
-
-
0003605855
-
-
Cambridge, Cambridge University Press
-
19 See C. Taylor, in Amy Gutman (ed.), Multiculturalism and The Politics of Recognition (Princeton, Princeton University Press, 1992) pp. 25-73; J. Tully, Strange Multiplicity: Constitutionalism in an Age of Diversity (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1995).
-
(1995)
Strange Multiplicity: Constitutionalism in An Age of Diversity
-
-
Tully, J.1
-
26
-
-
0006146757
-
Liberalism and the politicization of ethnicity
-
20 W. Kymlicka, 'Liberalism and the politicization of ethnicity', Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence, IV (1991), p. 241; Hardin, One For All, p. 56.
-
(1991)
Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence
, vol.4
, pp. 241
-
-
Kymlicka, W.1
-
27
-
-
0004244354
-
-
20 W. Kymlicka, 'Liberalism and the politicization of ethnicity', Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence, IV (1991), p. 241; Hardin, One For All, p. 56.
-
One For All
, pp. 56
-
-
Hardin1
-
29
-
-
0009445190
-
The morality of law and economics
-
22 R. Hardin 'The morality of law and economics', Law and Philosophy, 11 (1992), 331-84; J. Coleman, Markets, Morals and the Law (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1988), pp. 67-94, 133-50; G. Brennan and A. Hamlin, 'Economical constitutions', Political Studies, XLIV (1996), 605-19.
-
(1992)
Law and Philosophy
, vol.11
, pp. 331-384
-
-
Hardin, R.1
-
30
-
-
0009445190
-
-
Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 133-50
-
22 R. Hardin 'The morality of law and economics', Law and Philosophy, 11 (1992), 331-84; J. Coleman, Markets, Morals and the Law (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1988), pp. 67-94, 133-50; G. Brennan and A. Hamlin, 'Economical constitutions', Political Studies, XLIV (1996), 605-19.
-
(1988)
Markets, Morals and the Law
, pp. 67-94
-
-
Coleman, J.1
-
31
-
-
0041113813
-
Economical constitutions
-
22 R. Hardin 'The morality of law and economics', Law and Philosophy, 11 (1992), 331-84; J. Coleman, Markets, Morals and the Law (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1988), pp. 67-94, 133-50; G. Brennan and A. Hamlin, 'Economical constitutions', Political Studies, XLIV (1996), 605-19.
-
(1996)
Political Studies
, vol.44
, pp. 605-619
-
-
Brennan, G.1
Hamlin, A.2
-
34
-
-
0004244354
-
-
216, 223; also 49-56; 74-82. People identify with groups not out of some primordial urge but because it is 'rational to do what produces a particular identification and, once one has that identification, it is commonly rational to further the interests determined by that identification', (p. 60; see the examples discussed at pp. 53-6) We gain knowledge and experience of the world in particular settings, and the benefits of familiarity and easy communication are substantial
-
25 Hardin, One for All, pp. 180, 216, 223; also 49-56; 74-82. People identify with groups not out of some primordial urge but because it is 'rational to do what produces a particular identification and, once one has that identification, it is commonly rational to further the interests determined by that identification', (p. 60; see the examples discussed at pp. 53-6) We gain knowledge and experience of the world in particular settings, and the benefits of familiarity and easy communication are substantial.
-
One for All
, pp. 180
-
-
Hardin1
-
35
-
-
0004244354
-
-
and especially pp. 77, 89-91 on the 'epistemological comforts of home'
-
26 Hardin, One for All, p. 141; and especially pp. 77, 89-91 on the 'epistemological comforts of home'.
-
One for All
, pp. 141
-
-
Hardin1
-
36
-
-
0003244209
-
The rule of law
-
New York, Barnes and Noble
-
27 M. Oakeshott, 'The Rule of Law', in On History and Other Essays (New York, Barnes and Noble, 1983), pp. 157-64; J. Gray, 'Hobbes and the Modern State' and 'The Politics of Cultural Diversity', in Post-liberalism: Studies in Political Thought (New York, Routledge, 1993).
-
(1983)
On History and Other Essays
, pp. 157-164
-
-
Oakeshott, M.1
-
37
-
-
85038464626
-
'Hobbes and the modern state' and 'The politics of cultural diversity'
-
New York, Routledge
-
27 M. Oakeshott, 'The Rule of Law', in On History and Other Essays (New York, Barnes and Noble, 1983), pp. 157-64; J. Gray, 'Hobbes and the Modern State' and 'The Politics of Cultural Diversity', in Post-liberalism: Studies in Political Thought (New York, Routledge, 1993).
-
(1993)
Post-liberalism: Studies in Political Thought
-
-
Gray, J.1
-
42
-
-
85034199139
-
-
32 Gray, 'The Politics of Cultural Diversity', p. 265, Cf. F. A. Hayek, The Political Order of a Free People (London, Routledge, 1979) p. 135.
-
The Politics of Cultural Diversity
, pp. 265
-
-
-
44
-
-
85034199139
-
-
This antagonism to group and collective rights, and legal pluralism generally, is present in other essays as well. See n.96 below
-
33 Gray, 'The politics of cultural diversity', pp. 14, 265. This antagonism to group and collective rights, and legal pluralism generally, is present in other essays as well. See n.96 below.
-
The Politics of Cultural Diversity
, pp. 14
-
-
-
48
-
-
85034181874
-
-
Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, ch. 26, References to Leviathan henceforth shall be abbreviated to L, followed by chapter and page number.
-
37 R. Tuck (ed.), Leviathan (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1991) ch. 26, p. 183. References to Leviathan henceforth shall be abbreviated to L, followed by chapter and page number.
-
(1991)
Leviathan
, pp. 183
-
-
Tuck, R.1
-
50
-
-
85034191183
-
-
17
-
39 L 17, 226.
-
L
, pp. 226
-
-
-
51
-
-
85034175648
-
-
26
-
40 L 26, 314.
-
L
, pp. 314
-
-
-
53
-
-
85034161496
-
-
46
-
42 L 46, 700-1.
-
L
, pp. 700-701
-
-
-
54
-
-
84855571894
-
-
2.10.8, and below
-
43 Hobbes is extremely sensitive to the malleability of people's beliefs; see Elements, 2.10.8, and below.
-
Elements
-
-
Hobbes1
-
55
-
-
85034187879
-
-
26, 29, 367
-
44 See L 26, 313; 29, 367.
-
L
, pp. 313
-
-
-
56
-
-
0003803168
-
-
Cambridge, Cambridge University Press
-
45 See L 18 passim. This includes the power to make laws, vet the teaching of doctrines, appoint officers, decide and apply punishments, raise taxes, and oversee economic policy; see L 24 passim; R. Tuck Philosophy and Government: 1572-1651 (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1993), pp. 308-9.
-
(1993)
Philosophy and Government: 1572-1651
, pp. 308-309
-
-
Tuck, R.1
-
57
-
-
85034172296
-
-
But not completely so. The laws of nature apply to the sovereign as well. The crucial difference is that this is between the sovereign and God, and not his subjects
-
46 But not completely so. The laws of nature apply to the sovereign as well. The crucial difference is that this is between the sovereign and God, and not his subjects.
-
-
-
-
58
-
-
0010801255
-
-
M. M. Goldsmith, 2nd ed., London, Frank Cass
-
47 T. Hobbes, Ferdinand Toennies (ed.), M. M. Goldsmith, 2nd ed., Behemoth or the Long Parliament, (London, Frank Cass, 1969) 144.
-
(1969)
Behemoth or the Long Parliament
, pp. 144
-
-
Hobbes, T.1
Toennies, F.2
-
59
-
-
85034189199
-
-
21, 27, 345-6; 11, 162; 29 passim
-
48 L 21, 272; 27, 345-6; 11, 162; 29 passim.
-
L
, pp. 272
-
-
-
60
-
-
85034166615
-
-
14, 21, 268-9
-
49 L 14, 199; 21, 268-9.
-
L
, pp. 199
-
-
-
61
-
-
85034175684
-
-
14
-
50 L 14, 200; L 17, 223; L 18, 238; L 26, 315; L 26, 334; L 30, 388-9; L 42, 591.
-
L
, pp. 200
-
-
-
62
-
-
85034198753
-
-
17
-
50 L 14, 200; L 17, 223; L 18, 238; L 26, 315; L 26, 334; L 30, 388-9; L 42, 591.
-
L
, pp. 223
-
-
-
63
-
-
85034174286
-
-
18
-
50 L 14, 200; L 17, 223; L 18, 238; L 26, 315; L 26, 334; L 30, 388-9; L 42, 591.
-
L
, pp. 238
-
-
-
64
-
-
85034165128
-
-
26
-
50 L 14, 200; L 17, 223; L 18, 238; L 26, 315; L 26, 334; L 30, 388-9; L 42, 591.
-
L
, pp. 315
-
-
-
65
-
-
85034161663
-
-
26
-
50 L 14, 200; L 17, 223; L 18, 238; L 26, 315; L 26, 334; L 30, 388-9; L 42, 591.
-
L
, pp. 334
-
-
-
66
-
-
85034196473
-
-
30
-
50 L 14, 200; L 17, 223; L 18, 238; L 26, 315; L 26, 334; L 30, 388-9; L 42, 591.
-
L
, pp. 388-389
-
-
-
67
-
-
85034201757
-
-
42
-
50 L 14, 200; L 17, 223; L 18, 238; L 26, 315; L 26, 334; L 30, 388-9; L 42, 591.
-
L
, pp. 591
-
-
-
68
-
-
85034194422
-
-
17
-
51 L 17, 227.
-
L
, pp. 227
-
-
-
69
-
-
85034197311
-
-
30
-
52 L 30, 388.
-
L
, pp. 388
-
-
-
70
-
-
85034184064
-
-
30
-
53 L 30, 389.
-
L
, pp. 389
-
-
-
71
-
-
85034174745
-
-
30
-
54 L 30, 390-1.
-
L
, pp. 390-391
-
-
-
72
-
-
85034169756
-
-
30
-
55 L 30, 388.
-
L
, pp. 388
-
-
-
73
-
-
85034185827
-
-
21
-
56 L 21, 270.
-
L
, pp. 270
-
-
-
74
-
-
85034201769
-
-
46
-
57 L 46, 701.
-
L
, pp. 701
-
-
-
75
-
-
85034199980
-
-
19
-
58 L 19, 241-2. The 'temporal good' of the people is defined along reason of state lines in Elements, 2.9.3.
-
L
, pp. 241-242
-
-
-
77
-
-
84855571894
-
-
59 Elements, p. 141.
-
Elements
, pp. 141
-
-
-
78
-
-
85034178334
-
-
46
-
60 L 46, 701.
-
L
, pp. 701
-
-
-
79
-
-
85034186100
-
-
21
-
61 L 21, 264; i.e. the liberty enjoyed in the state of nature - L 13, 184-5.
-
L
, pp. 264
-
-
-
81
-
-
85034196363
-
-
21
-
62 L 21, 264.
-
L
, pp. 264
-
-
-
82
-
-
85034161805
-
-
18
-
63 L 18, 236: L 42-3 passim; 1 47, 709-10. See also Behemoth, pp. 56-9. See N. Malcolm, 'Hobbes and Spinoza', in Jimmy Burns (ed.), The Cambridge History of Political Thought 1450-1700 (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1991), pp. 543-4.
-
L
, pp. 236
-
-
-
83
-
-
85034195303
-
-
passim; 1 47, 709-10.
-
63 L 18, 236: L 42-3 passim; 1 47, 709-10. See also Behemoth, pp. 56-9. See N. Malcolm, 'Hobbes and Spinoza', in Jimmy Burns (ed.), The Cambridge History of Political Thought 1450-1700 (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1991), pp. 543-4.
-
L
, pp. 42-43
-
-
-
84
-
-
85034166627
-
-
63 L 18, 236: L 42-3 passim; 1 47, 709-10. See also Behemoth, pp. 56-9. See N. Malcolm, 'Hobbes and Spinoza', in Jimmy Burns (ed.), The Cambridge History of Political Thought 1450-1700 (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1991), pp. 543-4.
-
Behemoth
, pp. 56-59
-
-
-
85
-
-
0010913433
-
Hobbes and Spinoza
-
Jimmy Burns (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1991)
-
63 L 18, 236: L 42-3 passim; 1 47, 709-10. See also Behemoth, pp. 56-9. See N. Malcolm, 'Hobbes and Spinoza', in Jimmy Burns (ed.), The Cambridge History of Political Thought 1450-1700 (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1991), pp. 543-4.
-
The Cambridge History of Political Thought 1450-1700
, pp. 543-544
-
-
Malcolm, N.1
-
86
-
-
84972344108
-
Thomas Hobbes and the proper signification of liberty
-
64 See Q. Skinner, 'Thomas Hobbes and the proper signification of liberty', Transactions of the Royal Historical Society, 40 (1990) 135; J. Tully, A Discourse on Property: John Locke and his Adversaries (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press 1980) pp. 44-8.
-
(1990)
Transactions of the Royal Historical Society
, vol.40
, pp. 135
-
-
Skinner, Q.1
-
87
-
-
84972344108
-
-
Cambridge, Cambridge University Press
-
64 See Q. Skinner, 'Thomas Hobbes and the proper signification of liberty', Transactions of the Royal Historical Society, 40 (1990) 135; J. Tully, A Discourse on Property: John Locke and his Adversaries (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press 1980) pp. 44-8.
-
(1980)
A Discourse on Property: John Locke and His Adversaries
, pp. 44-48
-
-
Tully, J.1
-
89
-
-
85034163351
-
-
19
-
66 L 19, 131; also L, 29, 221-2.
-
L
, pp. 131
-
-
-
90
-
-
85034193659
-
-
29
-
66 L 19, 131; also L, 29, 221-2.
-
L
, pp. 221-222
-
-
-
91
-
-
85034170888
-
-
14
-
67 L 14, 99; L 17, 120-1; L 21, 147-8; L 27, 206-7; L 28, 215-16.
-
L
, pp. 99
-
-
-
92
-
-
85034159406
-
-
17
-
67 L 14, 99; L 17, 120-1; L 21, 147-8; L 27, 206-7; L 28, 215-16.
-
L
, pp. 120-121
-
-
-
93
-
-
85034170137
-
-
21
-
67 L 14, 99; L 17, 120-1; L 21, 147-8; L 27, 206-7; L 28, 215-16.
-
L
, pp. 147-148
-
-
-
94
-
-
85034175767
-
-
27
-
67 L 14, 99; L 17, 120-1; L 21, 147-8; L 27, 206-7; L 28, 215-16.
-
L
, pp. 206-207
-
-
-
95
-
-
85034194907
-
-
28
-
67 L 14, 99; L 17, 120-1; L 21, 147-8; L 27, 206-7; L 28, 215-16.
-
L
, pp. 215-216
-
-
-
96
-
-
85034195676
-
-
47
-
68 L 47, 478.
-
L
, pp. 478
-
-
-
97
-
-
85034188132
-
-
18
-
69 L 18, 125. Also, Behemoth p. 144.
-
L
, pp. 125
-
-
-
98
-
-
85034171508
-
-
69 L 18, 125. Also, Behemoth p. 144.
-
Behemoth
, pp. 144
-
-
-
99
-
-
85034167522
-
-
18
-
70 L 18, 125.
-
L
, pp. 125
-
-
-
100
-
-
85034190181
-
-
16
-
71 L 16, 111.
-
L
, pp. 111
-
-
-
103
-
-
85034184009
-
-
17
-
74 L 17, 120.
-
L
, pp. 120
-
-
-
104
-
-
85034172715
-
-
19, the 'understanding is by the flame of Passions, never enlightened but dazzled'
-
75 L 19, 131; the 'understanding is by the flame of Passions, never enlightened but dazzled'.
-
L
, pp. 131
-
-
-
105
-
-
85034188114
-
-
30
-
76 L 30, 232.
-
L
, pp. 232
-
-
-
106
-
-
85034173248
-
-
77 See also Hobbes, Behemoth, p. 181.
-
Behemoth
, pp. 181
-
-
-
107
-
-
85034179486
-
-
29
-
78 L 29, 221.
-
L
, pp. 221
-
-
-
109
-
-
85034157537
-
-
26
-
80 L 26, 184-5; L 24, 172. See n. 95 below.
-
L
, pp. 184-185
-
-
-
110
-
-
85034183209
-
-
24, See n. 95 below
-
80 L 26, 184-5; L 24, 172. See n. 95 below.
-
L
, pp. 172
-
-
-
113
-
-
85034186716
-
-
30
-
83 See L 30, 239. The sovereign also had the right to collect taxes without consent; see L 30, 238-9.
-
L
, pp. 239
-
-
-
114
-
-
85034189483
-
-
30
-
83 See L 30, 239. The sovereign also had the right to collect taxes without consent; see L 30, 238-9.
-
L
, pp. 238-239
-
-
-
115
-
-
85034201184
-
-
30
-
84 See L 30, 237.
-
L
, pp. 237
-
-
-
117
-
-
85034184668
-
-
21
-
86 L 21, 152.
-
L
, pp. 152
-
-
-
118
-
-
0038759392
-
-
Cambridge, Cambridge University Press
-
87 Paradoxically, this can be understood as a defence of the freedom of conscience rather than a contradiction of it. Hobbes argues that 'There ought to be no Power over the Consciences of men, but of the World it selfe, working Faith in every one, not always according to the purpose of them that Plant and Water, but of God himself, that giveth the Increase . . . it is unreasonable in them, who teach there is such danger in every little Errour, to require of a man endued with Reason of his own, to follow the Reason of any other man, or of the most voices of many other men . . .' (L 47, p. 480). This reinforces the point made earlier about the need for Leviathan to police the teaching of doctrines. But as Brett points out, if Hobbesian subjects subject themselves to restraints on their natural liberty and act justly, then they possess virtue, and the rationale for an omniscient sovereign is gone. See Annabel Brett, Liberty, Right and Nature; Individual Rights in Later Scholastic Thought (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1997), p. 234.
-
(1997)
Liberty, Right and Nature; Individual Rights in Later Scholastic Thought
, pp. 234
-
-
Brett, A.1
-
119
-
-
85034196269
-
The Contribution of Economics
-
Robert E. Goodin and Philip Pettit (eds), (Oxford, Blackwell, 1993), especially
-
88 Public choice theorists remain, perhaps, the most sophisticated practitioners of the attempt to decouple government from the delivery of most public goods, in part to 'depoliticize' the process by substituting the distributive power of politicians with that of the market. See Geoffrey Brennan, 'The Contribution of Economics', in Robert E. Goodin and Philip Pettit (eds), The Blackwell Companion to Political Philosophy (Oxford, Blackwell, 1993), especially at pp. 147-54.
-
The Blackwell Companion to Political Philosophy
, pp. 147-154
-
-
Brennan, G.1
-
120
-
-
0009380857
-
-
London, Routledge
-
89 Again, in his most recent writings, he has changed tack. Gray now castigates contemporary liberalism for 'hollowing out' the political realm, and supplanting politics with 'liberal legalism' (see Gray, Enlightenment's Wake; Politics and Culture at the Close of the Modern Age (London, Routledge, 1995) pp. 6, 76-8).
-
(1995)
Enlightenment's Wake; Politics and Culture at the Close of the Modern Age
, vol.6
, pp. 76-78
-
-
Gray1
-
122
-
-
0009418855
-
-
Oxford, Clarendon
-
91 T. Hobbes, H. Warrender (ed.), De Cive, (Oxford, Clarendon, 1983), 136; L 25, 181-2. The anti-humanist context of this passage is crucial for understanding what Hobbes is doing here (and elsewhere). See Quentin Skinner, Reason and Rhetoric in the Philosophy of Hobbes (Cambridge, Cambridee University Press, 1996), pp. 285-93.
-
(1983)
De Cive
, pp. 136
-
-
Hobbes, T.1
Warrender, H.2
-
123
-
-
85034196243
-
-
25, The anti-humanist context of this passage is crucial for understanding what Hobbes is doing here (and elsewhere)
-
91 T. Hobbes, H. Warrender (ed.), De Cive, (Oxford, Clarendon, 1983), 136; L 25, 181-2. The anti-humanist context of this passage is crucial for understanding what Hobbes is doing here (and elsewhere). See Quentin Skinner, Reason and Rhetoric in the Philosophy of Hobbes (Cambridge, Cambridee University Press, 1996), pp. 285-93.
-
L
, pp. 181-182
-
-
-
124
-
-
0003650067
-
-
Cambridge, Cambridee University Press
-
91 T. Hobbes, H. Warrender (ed.), De Cive, (Oxford, Clarendon, 1983), 136; L 25, 181-2. The anti-humanist context of this passage is crucial for understanding what Hobbes is doing here (and elsewhere). See Quentin Skinner, Reason and Rhetoric in the Philosophy of Hobbes (Cambridge, Cambridee University Press, 1996), pp. 285-93.
-
(1996)
Reason and Rhetoric in the Philosophy of Hobbes
, pp. 285-293
-
-
Skinner, Q.1
-
125
-
-
85034160503
-
-
144
-
92 See Behemoth, pp. 155, 144.
-
Behemoth
, pp. 155
-
-
-
127
-
-
0004352115
-
-
94 Democracy, if it is justifiable, is just 'a convenient device whose usefulness turns on its contribution to peace and the renewal of valuable forms of common life' (Gray, Enlightenment's Wake, p. 140).
-
Enlightenment's Wake
, pp. 140
-
-
Gray1
-
128
-
-
0004027182
-
-
Oxford, Oxford University Press
-
95 See Hobbes's views on civil and political associations or 'Bodies Politique' (discussed in L 22): 'In Bodies Politique, the power of the Representative is alwaies Limited: And that which prescribeth the Limites thereof, is the Power Soveraign' (L 22, 155-6). It follows that Oakeshott's claim that Hobbes's Leviathan is a societas rather than a universitas, where the former is characterized (in part) by the tolerance of associations which are 'eccentric' or 'indifferent to the pursuit of the purposes of the association' and which require no authorization, is also fatally undermined. Cf. On Human Conduct (Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1975) pp. 201-5.
-
(1975)
On Human Conduct
, pp. 201-205
-
-
-
129
-
-
85034164959
-
-
But compare an earlier essay by Gray, published in the same volume, wherein he argues that a 'stable modus vivendi' (the qualifier is significant) requires a 'common stock of norms and conventions' or even a common culture or nationality (pp. 29, 24). The kind of diversity that is 'incompatible with civil society in Britain is that which rejects the constitutive practices that give it its identity . . . [such as] the rule of law. Cultural traditions that repudiate these practices cannot be objects of toleration for liberal civil society in Britain or anywhere else (p. 25, emphasis added). Any attempt 'to give legal force' to different group views or practices is 'likely further to fragment us, and to evoke intolerance among us' (p. 21)
-
96 Enligthenment's Wake, p. 140. But compare an earlier essay by Gray, published in the same volume, wherein he argues that a 'stable modus vivendi' (the qualifier is significant) requires a 'common stock of norms and conventions' or even a common culture or nationality (pp. 29, 24). The kind of diversity that is 'incompatible with civil society in Britain is that which rejects the constitutive practices that give it its identity . . . [such as] the rule of law. Cultural traditions that repudiate these practices cannot be objects of toleration for liberal civil society in Britain or anywhere else (p. 25, emphasis added). Any attempt 'to give legal force' to different group views or practices is 'likely further to fragment us, and to evoke intolerance among us' (p. 21).
-
Enligthenment's Wake
, pp. 140
-
-
|