메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 17, Issue 4, 1998, Pages 377-410

The role of inductive reasoning in the evolution of conventions

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0032244195     PISSN: 01675249     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.2307/3505086     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (28)

References (46)
  • 1
    • 0004088235 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon Press, first published 1740
    • David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1978); first published 1740. The modern literature includes, e.g., David Lewis, Convention: A Philosophical Study (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1969); Edna Ullman-Margalit, The Evolution of Norms (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1977); Robert Sugden, The Economics of Rights, Cooperation and Welfare (Oxford: Blackwell, 1986); Ken Binmore, Game Theory and the Social Contract, Volume 1: Playing Fair (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1993); Peyton Young, "The Evolution of Conventions", Econometrica 61 (1993), pp. 57-84; Brian Skyrms, Evolution of the Social Contract (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996).
    • (1978) A Treatise of Human Nature
    • Hume, D.1
  • 2
    • 0041737882 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press
    • David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1978); first published 1740. The modern literature includes, e.g., David Lewis, Convention: A Philosophical Study (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1969); Edna Ullman-Margalit, The Evolution of Norms (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1977); Robert Sugden, The Economics of Rights, Cooperation and Welfare (Oxford: Blackwell, 1986); Ken Binmore, Game Theory and the Social Contract, Volume 1: Playing Fair (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1993); Peyton Young, "The Evolution of Conventions", Econometrica 61 (1993), pp. 57-84; Brian Skyrms, Evolution of the Social Contract (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996).
    • (1969) Convention: A Philosophical Study
    • Lewis, D.1
  • 3
    • 0042739343 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1978); first published 1740. The modern literature includes, e.g., David Lewis, Convention: A Philosophical Study (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1969); Edna Ullman-Margalit, The Evolution of Norms (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1977); Robert Sugden, The Economics of Rights, Cooperation and Welfare (Oxford: Blackwell, 1986); Ken Binmore, Game Theory and the Social Contract, Volume 1: Playing Fair (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1993); Peyton Young, "The Evolution of Conventions", Econometrica 61 (1993), pp. 57-84; Brian Skyrms, Evolution of the Social Contract (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996).
    • (1977) The Evolution of Norms
    • Ullman-Margalit, E.1
  • 4
    • 0004163157 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Blackwell
    • David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1978); first published 1740. The modern literature includes, e.g., David Lewis, Convention: A Philosophical Study (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1969); Edna Ullman-Margalit, The Evolution of Norms (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1977); Robert Sugden, The Economics of Rights, Cooperation and Welfare (Oxford: Blackwell, 1986); Ken Binmore, Game Theory and the Social Contract, Volume 1: Playing Fair (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1993); Peyton Young, "The Evolution of Conventions", Econometrica 61 (1993), pp. 57-84; Brian Skyrms, Evolution of the Social Contract (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996).
    • (1986) The Economics of Rights, Cooperation and Welfare
    • Sugden, R.1
  • 5
    • 0003917805 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press
    • David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1978); first published 1740. The modern literature includes, e.g., David Lewis, Convention: A Philosophical Study (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1969); Edna Ullman-Margalit, The Evolution of Norms (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1977); Robert Sugden, The Economics of Rights, Cooperation and Welfare (Oxford: Blackwell, 1986); Ken Binmore, Game Theory and the Social Contract, Volume 1: Playing Fair (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1993); Peyton Young, "The Evolution of Conventions", Econometrica 61 (1993), pp. 57-84; Brian Skyrms, Evolution of the Social Contract (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996).
    • (1993) Game Theory and the Social Contract, Volume 1: Playing Fair , vol.1
    • Binmore, K.1
  • 6
    • 0001944917 scopus 로고
    • The Evolution of Conventions
    • David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1978); first published 1740. The modern literature includes, e.g., David Lewis, Convention: A Philosophical Study (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1969); Edna Ullman-Margalit, The Evolution of Norms (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1977); Robert Sugden, The Economics of Rights, Cooperation and Welfare (Oxford: Blackwell, 1986); Ken Binmore, Game Theory and the Social Contract, Volume 1: Playing Fair (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1993); Peyton Young, "The Evolution of Conventions", Econometrica 61 (1993), pp. 57-84; Brian Skyrms, Evolution of the Social Contract (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996).
    • (1993) Econometrica , vol.61 , pp. 57-84
    • Young, P.1
  • 7
    • 84953296993 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1978); first published 1740. The modern literature includes, e.g., David Lewis, Convention: A Philosophical Study (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1969); Edna Ullman-Margalit, The Evolution of Norms (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1977); Robert Sugden, The Economics of Rights, Cooperation and Welfare (Oxford: Blackwell, 1986); Ken Binmore, Game Theory and the Social Contract, Volume 1: Playing Fair (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1993); Peyton Young, "The Evolution of Conventions", Econometrica 61 (1993), pp. 57-84; Brian Skyrms, Evolution of the Social Contract (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996).
    • (1996) Evolution of the Social Contract
    • Skyrms, B.1
  • 8
    • 0030372667 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Can We Rationally Learn to Coordinate
    • Goyal and Janssen argue, I think correctly, that the standard assumptions of rationality and common knowledge cannot explain how individuals learn to coordinate their behavior in repeated games. They show that some well-known theoretical results which appear to explain rational coordination in fact depend on hidden assumptions about the prior existence of coordinated expectations. The present paper is complementary with Goyal and Janssen's. They show how little can be derived from standard rationality assumptions; I look for an alternative model of human reasoning which can explain coordination
    • One of the few papers in the game-theoretic literature which recognizes this problem is Sanjeev Goyal and Maarten Janssen, "Can We Rationally Learn to Coordinate", Theory and Decision 40 (1996), pp. 29-49. Goyal and Janssen argue, I think correctly, that the standard assumptions of rationality and common knowledge cannot explain how individuals learn to coordinate their behavior in repeated games. They show that some well-known theoretical results which appear to explain rational coordination in fact depend on hidden assumptions about the prior existence of coordinated expectations. The present paper is complementary with Goyal and Janssen's. They show how little can be derived from standard rationality assumptions; I look for an alternative model of human reasoning which can explain coordination.
    • (1996) Theory and Decision , vol.40 , pp. 29-49
    • Goyal, S.1    Janssen, M.2
  • 9
    • 0041737877 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 1
    • Lewis, supra note 1.
    • Lewis1
  • 10
    • 0042238168 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id., at 9
    • Id., at 9.
  • 11
    • 0042238167 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id., at 8-24
    • Id., at 8-24.
  • 12
    • 0042238171 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id., at 97-100
    • Id., at 97-100.
  • 13
    • 0041737881 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Courtesy and Convention: A Theory of Normative Expectations
    • Zentrum für interdisziplinäre Forschung, Bielefeld, March
    • Robert Sugden, "Courtesy and Convention: a Theory of Normative Expectations", paper prepared for conference on Practical Rationality, Rules and Structure, Zentrum für interdisziplinäre Forschung, Bielefeld, March 1998.
    • (1998) Conference on Practical Rationality, Rules and Structure
    • Sugden, R.1
  • 15
    • 0042739344 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 1
    • This framework is now fairly standard, but it was not in 1969. Erecting this framework was one of Lewis's greatest achievements. See Lewis, supra note 1.
    • Lewis1
  • 16
    • 0004165120 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press
    • Thomas Schelling, The Strategy of Conflict (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1960).
    • (1960) The Strategy of Conflict
    • Schelling, T.1
  • 17
    • 0001613771 scopus 로고
    • The Nature of Salience: An Experimental Investigation of Pure Coordination Game
    • For our sample, the favoured meeting places in London were Piccadilly Circus and Trafalgar Square
    • With colleagues at the University of East Anglia, I have replicated Schelling's studies under more controlled experimental conditions, with large samples and substantial payoffs. Our results confirm people's ability to solve coordination problems. See Judith Mehta, Chris Starmer and Robert Sugden, "The Nature of Salience: an Experimental Investigation of Pure Coordination Game", American Economic Review 84 (1994), pp. 658-673. For our sample, the favoured meeting places in London were Piccadilly Circus and Trafalgar Square.
    • (1994) American Economic Review , vol.84 , pp. 658-673
    • Mehta, J.1    Starmer, C.2    Sugden, R.3
  • 18
    • 0003256477 scopus 로고
    • Variable Universe Games
    • Ken Binmore, Alan Kirman and Piero Tani (eds.), Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press
    • For recent attempts to solve this problem, see, e.g., Michael Bacharach, "Variable Universe Games", in Ken Binmore, Alan Kirman and Piero Tani (eds.), Frontiers of Game Theory (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1993); Robert Sugden, "A Theory of Focal Points", Economic Journal 105 (1995), pp. 533-550. Michael Bacharach's theory and mine both have the feature that games are represented in terms of the descriptions that the players themselves use; there is no presumption that those players are playing the game under a common description. These theories differ from Lewis's in not treating salience as a primitive concept, but rather trying to explain it as a result of players' making use of their knowledge about descriptions.
    • (1993) Frontiers of Game Theory
    • Bacharach, M.1
  • 19
    • 0000900137 scopus 로고
    • A Theory of Focal Points
    • Michael Bacharach's theory and mine both have the feature that games are represented in terms of the descriptions that the players themselves use; there is no presumption that those players are playing the game under a common description. These theories differ from Lewis's in not treating salience as a primitive concept, but rather trying to explain it as a result of players' making use of their knowledge about descriptions
    • For recent attempts to solve this problem, see, e.g., Michael Bacharach, "Variable Universe Games", in Ken Binmore, Alan Kirman and Piero Tani (eds.), Frontiers of Game Theory (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1993); Robert Sugden, "A Theory of Focal Points", Economic Journal 105 (1995), pp. 533-550. Michael Bacharach's theory and mine both have the feature that games are represented in terms of the descriptions that the players themselves use; there is no presumption that those players are playing the game under a common description. These theories differ from Lewis's in not treating salience as a primitive concept, but rather trying to explain it as a result of players' making use of their knowledge about descriptions.
    • (1995) Economic Journal , vol.105 , pp. 533-550
    • Sugden, R.1
  • 20
    • 0041737878 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It is a fascinating puzzle to ask whether these different possibilities really are mutually supporting, or whether they are mutually destructive (as in a proof by contradiction). On the latter view, the logically correct but paradoxical implication is that we have proved by contradiction that reason does not give out (since if it did give out, reason would tell us what to do); so we know that reason tells us what to do, but we don't know what it tells us to do
    • It is a fascinating puzzle to ask whether these different possibilities really are mutually supporting, or whether they are mutually destructive (as in a proof by contradiction). On the latter view, the logically correct but paradoxical implication is that we have proved by contradiction that reason does not give out (since if it did give out, reason would tell us what to do); so we know that reason tells us what to do, but we don't know what it tells us to do.
  • 21
  • 22
    • 0003709994 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press Interestingly, however, Selten does not believe that the analysis of perfectly rational play can tell us much about actual human interaction. He is strongly committed to empirical research into human decision-making, and in this context, is deeply sceptical of rationality assumptions. I suspect that Harsanyi has more faith in the power of human rationality
    • The bravest attempt to solve the problem is probably John C. Harsanyi and Reinhard Selten, A General Theory of Equilibrium Selection in Games (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1988). Interestingly, however, Selten does not believe that the analysis of perfectly rational play can tell us much about actual human interaction. He is strongly committed to empirical research into human decision-making, and in this context, is deeply sceptical of rationality assumptions. I suspect that Harsanyi has more faith in the power of human rationality.
    • (1988) A General Theory of Equilibrium Selection in Games
    • Harsanyi, J.C.1    Selten, R.2
  • 23
    • 0041737873 scopus 로고
    • supra note 1. But I plead not guilty to most of the charges that I now make against the current form of this literature
    • I was among the pioneers of this approach. See Sugden (1986), supra note 1. But I plead not guilty to most of the charges that I now make against the current form of this literature.
    • (1986)
    • Sugden1
  • 24
    • 0040409227 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the Relevance of Learning and Evolution to Economic Theory
    • See, e.g., Tilman Börgers, "On the Relevance of Learning and Evolution to Economic Theory", Economic Journal 106 (1996), pp. 1374-1385; Tilman Börgers and Rajiv Sarin, "Learning through Reinforcement and Replicator Dynamics", draft manuscript, University College London, 1995 (forthcoming in Journal of Economic Theory).
    • (1996) Economic Journal , vol.106 , pp. 1374-1385
    • Börgers, T.1
  • 25
    • 0040409227 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Learning through Reinforcement and Replicator Dynamics
    • draft manuscript, University College London forthcoming
    • See, e.g., Tilman Börgers, "On the Relevance of Learning and Evolution to Economic Theory", Economic Journal 106 (1996), pp. 1374-1385; Tilman Börgers and Rajiv Sarin, "Learning through Reinforcement and Replicator Dynamics", draft manuscript, University College London, 1995 (forthcoming in Journal of Economic Theory).
    • (1995) Journal of Economic Theory
    • Börgers, T.1    Sarin, R.2
  • 26
    • 0041520714 scopus 로고
    • Sociobiology, Culture and Economic Theory
    • They argue that because the market tends to select firms which maximize profits, there can be selection in favour of employee behavior which, although individually sub-optimal, is collectively optimal (for example, cooperative behavior in within-firm Prisoner's Dilemmas)
    • See, e.g., Robert Boyd and Peter Richerson, "Sociobiology, Culture and Economic Theory", Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization 1 (1980), pp. 97-121. They argue that because the market tends to select firms which maximize profits, there can be selection in favour of employee behavior which, although individually sub-optimal, is collectively optimal (for example, cooperative behavior in within-firm Prisoner's Dilemmas).
    • (1980) Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization , vol.1 , pp. 97-121
    • Boyd, R.1    Richerson, P.2
  • 27
    • 0017819644 scopus 로고
    • Evolutionarily Stable Strategies and Game Dynamics
    • Peter Taylor and Leo Jonker, "Evolutionarily Stable Strategies and Game Dynamics", Mathematical Biosciences 40 (1978), pp. 145-156.
    • (1978) Mathematical Biosciences , vol.40 , pp. 145-156
    • Taylor, P.1    Jonker, L.2
  • 29
    • 0001601690 scopus 로고
    • Learning, Local Interaction, and Coordination
    • See Glenn Ellison, "Learning, Local Interaction, and Coordination", Econometrica 61 (1993), pp. 1047-1071; Michihiro Kandori, George J. Mailath and Rafael Rob, "Learning, Mutation, and Long Run Equilibria in Games", Econometrica 61 (1993), pp. 29-56; and Young, supra note 1.
    • (1993) Econometrica , vol.61 , pp. 1047-1071
    • Ellison, G.1
  • 30
    • 0002730095 scopus 로고
    • Learning, Mutation, and Long Run Equilibria in Games
    • See Glenn Ellison, "Learning, Local Interaction, and Coordination", Econometrica 61 (1993), pp. 1047-1071; Michihiro Kandori, George J. Mailath and Rafael Rob, "Learning, Mutation, and Long Run Equilibria in Games", Econometrica 61 (1993), pp. 29-56; and Young, supra note 1.
    • (1993) Econometrica , vol.61 , pp. 29-56
    • Kandori, M.1    Mailath, G.J.2    Rob, R.3
  • 31
    • 0042739338 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 1
    • See Glenn Ellison, "Learning, Local Interaction, and Coordination", Econometrica 61 (1993), pp. 1047-1071; Michihiro Kandori, George J. Mailath and Rafael Rob, "Learning, Mutation, and Long Run Equilibria in Games", Econometrica 61 (1993), pp. 29-56; and Young, supra note 1.
    • Young1
  • 32
    • 0042739337 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • By using the word 'natural', I mean to exclude experiments in which games are explicitly described to participants in terms of strategies and payoffs, as in game theory itself. The argument of this paper is that game theory fails to take account of the fact that in the games of real life, each person chooses actions under his own descriptions of them, and not under those that the game theorist uses. If this is a weakness in game theory, that will not be picked up in such non-naturalistic experiments
    • By using the word 'natural', I mean to exclude experiments in which games are explicitly described to participants in terms of strategies and payoffs, as in game theory itself. The argument of this paper is that game theory fails to take account of the fact that in the games of real life, each person chooses actions under his own descriptions of them, and not under those that the game theorist uses. If this is a weakness in game theory, that will not be picked up in such non-naturalistic experiments.
  • 33
    • 0043240585 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 1, at 93 (italics in original)
    • Skyrms, supra note 1, at 93 (italics in original).
    • Skyrms1
  • 34
    • 0043240586 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id., at 102
    • Id., at 102.
  • 35
    • 0042238166 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 2. Goyal and Janssen show that these problems are crippling for the project of creating a theory of equilibrium selection based on ideal Bayesian rationality
    • This is an example of the class of problems discussed by Goyal and Janssen, supra note 2. Goyal and Janssen show that these problems are crippling for the project of creating a theory of equilibrium selection based on ideal Bayesian rationality.
    • Goyal1    Janssen2
  • 36
    • 0043240590 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • There is also a "knife-edge" mixed-strategy equilibrium
    • There is also a "knife-edge" mixed-strategy equilibrium.
  • 37
    • 0043240587 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is not a flippant question. At least in my home town, I think I there are slightly different conventions on the roads at weekday rush hours and at weekends: rush hour drivers seem more ready to give way to vehicles entering busy roads from side streets. By the official rules, traffic on the main road always has priority, so when traffic is heavy, the side-street drivers have to depend on the courtesy of the main-road drivers
    • This is not a flippant question. At least in my home town, I think I there are slightly different conventions on the roads at weekday rush hours and at weekends: rush hour drivers seem more ready to give way to vehicles entering busy roads from side streets. By the official rules, traffic on the main road always has priority, so when traffic is heavy, the side-street drivers have to depend on the courtesy of the main-road drivers.
  • 38
    • 0041737876 scopus 로고
    • supra note 12. The idea is of a game which is described entirely in propositions of the form "There exist(s) ...", in which no labelling words are used (e.g. "There exist two players ...")
    • This concept of a "pared-down" game corresponds with the concept of an existential game, which I analyze in Sugden (1995), supra note 12. The idea is of a game which is described entirely in propositions of the form "There exist(s) ...", in which no labelling words are used (e.g. "There exist two players ...").
    • (1995)
    • Sugden1
  • 39
    • 0041737879 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 14
    • Goodman, supra note 14.
    • Goodman1
  • 40
    • 0042739340 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This temptation leads to the familiar idea that induction can be justified if we presuppose the "uniformity of nature". Even in relation to natural science, I prefer Goodman's more conventionalist approach to "projectibility". Id
    • This temptation leads to the familiar idea that induction can be justified if we presuppose the "uniformity of nature". Even in relation to natural science, I prefer Goodman's more conventionalist approach to "projectibility". Id.
  • 41
    • 0041737880 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 14
    • A Humean sceptic will immediately ask what I mean by "regularities in the world". But I am not trying to solve Hume's problem of induction. What I am looking for is a psychological theory which explains from outside how human beings make inductive inferences. That theory does not have to be grounded in induction. See Hume, supra note 14; and Goodman, supra.
    • Hume1
  • 42
    • 0042739341 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra
    • A Humean sceptic will immediately ask what I mean by "regularities in the world". But I am not trying to solve Hume's problem of induction. What I am looking for is a psychological theory which explains from outside how human beings make inductive inferences. That theory does not have to be grounded in induction. See Hume, supra note 14; and Goodman, supra.
    • Goodman1
  • 44
    • 0009096444 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Rationality of Adaptive Agents
    • Kenneth J. Arrow, Enrico Colombatto, Mark Perlman and Christian Schmidt (eds.), Basingstoke: Macmillan
    • See John H. Holland, K. J. Holyoak, R. E. Nisbett and P. R. Thagard, Induction: Processes of Inference, Learning and Discovery (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1986); John H. Holland, "The Rationality of Adaptive Agents", in Kenneth J. Arrow, Enrico Colombatto, Mark Perlman and Christian Schmidt (eds.), The Rational Foundations of Economic Behavior (Basingstoke: Macmillan, 1996).
    • (1996) The Rational Foundations of Economic Behavior
    • Holland, J.H.1
  • 45
    • 0043240591 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 8, at 174
    • This might be a way of understanding Putnam's important idea that all forms of social cooperation - even choral societies and amateur football clubs - are mutually supporting, and that networks of civic engagement provide "templates" for future collaboration. Putnam, supra note 8, at 174.
    • Putnam1
  • 46
    • 0042238169 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 10, at 97-98
    • Schelling, supra note 10, at 97-98.
    • Schelling1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.