메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 8, Issue , 2001, Pages 127-151

Semantic and pragmatic relations and their intended eVects

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 85190655776     PISSN: 13876724     EISSN: None     Source Type: Book Series    
DOI: 10.1075/hcp.8.08kno     Document Type: Chapter
Times cited : (14)

References (24)
  • 1
    • 85190671659 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sweetser in fact adresses two early versions of the bipartite distinction formulated by Ross (1967) and Davison (1973). However, her criticisms apply to the more recent versions too
    • Sweetser in fact adresses two early versions of the bipartite distinction formulated by Ross (1967) and Davison (1973). However, her criticisms apply to the more recent versions too.
  • 2
    • 85190689612 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • fact, Sweetser (1990, 92) is unwilling to commit to the view that explicit performative should be understood as contributing to the semantics of a sentence. But the rationale for this is mainly concern for a proper demarcation the domains of 'semantics'and 'pragmatics'; the only relevant implication for our purposes is that the performative glosses are to be understood as falling in the latter domain rather than the former
    • In fact, Sweetser (1990, p. 92) is unwilling to commit to the view that explicit performative should be understood as contributing to the semantics of a sentence. But the rationale for this is mainly concern for a proper demarcation the domains of 'semantics'and 'pragmatics'; the only relevant implication for our purposes is that the performative glosses are to be understood as falling in the latter domain rather than the former.
  • 3
    • 85190712453 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Or perhaps more precisely, as stating that the proposition R(f (U1), f (U2)) is asserted by the speaker
    • Or perhaps more precisely, as stating that the proposition R(f (U1), f (U2)) is asserted by the speaker.
  • 4
    • 85190667178 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note that the account works equally well if the conditional is interpreted as a habitual: there are none of the problems associated with conditional, future or repeated speech acts that would arise if we extended the SPEECH-ACT account. Note that the protasis has to be evaluated from the perspective of the hearer in this case. This reading certainly seems possible, but it might be thought that it could also be evaluated from the speaker's perspective (i.e. the hearer comes to the speaker for a loan if the hearer believes the speaker believes he has run out of money). If this is considered a problem, it could be borne in mind that the intended eVect of an indicative utterance with content can also be taken to be that the hearer believes that the speaker believes that With this alternative interpretation, both of the required perspectives are available. 5. Spooren (1989) apparently suggests that a violated expectation does arise in a case such as (43), as the necessary additional premise (in this case, that there is food to be found) is an implicature of the utterance expressing the protagonist's goal (i.e. John was hungry). While we must certainly implicate the fact that John has a goal if this is not explicitly stated, there seems good reason to suggest that the speaker's informing the hearer about this goal should lead to an implicature that the goal is satisWable. If anything, hearers are used to hearing about situations in which a protagonist's goals are not satisWed: this is certainly the predominant case in narratives
    • Note that the account works equally well if the conditional is interpreted as a habitual: there are none of the problems associated with conditional, future or repeated speech acts that would arise if we extended the SPEECH-ACT account. Note that the protasis has to be evaluated from the perspective of the hearer in this case. This reading certainly seems possible, but it might be thought that it could also be evaluated from the speaker's perspective (i.e. the hearer comes to the speaker for a loan if the hearer believes the speaker believes he has run out of money). If this is considered a problem, it could be borne in mind that the intended eVect of an indicative utterance with content p can also be taken to be that the hearer believes that the speaker believes that p. With this alternative interpretation, both of the required perspectives are available. 5. Spooren (1989) apparently suggests that a violated expectation does arise in a case such as (43), as the necessary additional premise (in this case, that there is food to be found) is an implicature of the utterance expressing the protagonist's goal (i.e. John was hungry). While we must certainly implicate the fact that John has a goal if this is not explicitly stated, there seems no good reason to suggest that the speaker's informing the hearer about this goal should lead to an implicature that the goal is satisWable. If anything, hearers are used to hearing about situations in which a protagonist's goals are not satisWed: this is certainly the predominant case in narratives.
  • 5
    • 0002525049 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Coherence relations: Towards a general speciWcation
    • Bateman, J., & Rondhuis, K. J. (1997). Coherence relations: Towards a general speciWcation. Discourse Processes, 24, 3-49.
    • (1997) Discourse Processes , vol.24 , pp. 3-49
    • Bateman, J.1    Rondhuis, K.J.2
  • 7
    • 0005882962 scopus 로고
    • Generating connectives
    • Elhadad, M., & McKeown, K. R. (1990). Generating connectives. In COLING-90, 97-101.
    • (1990) COLING-90 , pp. 97-101
    • Elhadad, M.1    McKeown, K.R.2
  • 9
    • 0003673818 scopus 로고
    • On the coherence and structure of discourse
    • Center for the Study of Language and Information, Stanford University
    • Hobbs, J. R. (1985). On the coherence and structure of discourse. Technical Report CSLI-85-37, Center for the Study of Language and Information, Stanford University.
    • (1985) Technical Report CSLI-85-37
    • Hobbs, J.R.1
  • 10
    • 0027677780 scopus 로고
    • Automated discourse generation using discourse structure relations
    • Hovy, E. (1993). Automated discourse generation using discourse structure relations. ArtiWcial Intelligence, 63, 341-385.
    • (1993) ArtiWcial Intelligence , vol.63 , pp. 341-385
    • Hovy, E.1
  • 11
    • 0000137594 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A feature-based account of the relations signalled by sentence and clause connectives
    • Knott, A., & Mellish, C. (1996). A feature-based account of the relations signalled by sentence and clause connectives. Language and Speech, 39, 143-183.
    • (1996) Language and Speech , vol.39 , pp. 143-183
    • Knott, A.1    Mellish, C.2
  • 12
    • 0013085323 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ph.D. thesis, Tilburg, The Netherlands: Katholieke Universiteit Brabant
    • Lagerwerf, L. (1998). Causal connectives have presuppositions. Ph.D. thesis, Tilburg, The Netherlands: Katholieke Universiteit Brabant.
    • (1998) Causal connectives have presuppositions
    • Lagerwerf, L.1
  • 13
    • 84961480199 scopus 로고
    • Rhetorical structure theory: A theory of text organization
    • Mann, W. C., & Thompson, S. A. (1988). Rhetorical structure theory: A theory of text organization. Text, 8, 243-281.
    • (1988) Text , vol.8 , pp. 243-281
    • Mann, W.C.1    Thompson, S.A.2
  • 15
    • 85055278530 scopus 로고
    • A problem for RST: The need for multi-level discourse analysis
    • Moore, J., & Pollack, M. (1992). A problem for RST: The need for multi-level discourse analysis. Computational Linguistics, 18, 537-544.
    • (1992) Computational Linguistics , vol.18 , pp. 537-544
    • Moore, J.1    Pollack, M.2
  • 16
    • 84937309746 scopus 로고
    • Planning text for advisory dialogues: Capturing intentional and rhetorical information
    • Moore, J. D., & Paris, C. L. (1993). Planning text for advisory dialogues: Capturing intentional and rhetorical information. Computational Linguistics, 19, 651-694.
    • (1993) Computational Linguistics , vol.19 , pp. 651-694
    • Moore, J.D.1    Paris, C.L.2
  • 17
    • 10444283080 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the pragmatic nature of causal and contrastive connectives
    • Oversteegen, L. (1997). On the pragmatic nature of causal and contrastive connectives. Discourse Processes, 24, 51-86.
    • (1997) Discourse Processes , vol.24 , pp. 51-86
    • Oversteegen, L.1
  • 18
    • 0000989129 scopus 로고
    • Ideational and pragmatic markers of discourse structure
    • Redeker, G. (1990). Ideational and pragmatic markers of discourse structure. Journal of Pragmatics, 14, 367-381.
    • (1990) Journal of Pragmatics , vol.14 , pp. 367-381
    • Redeker, G.1
  • 19
    • 0004215536 scopus 로고
    • Ph.D. thesis, MIT. Now reprinted as InWnite Syntax. Norwood, NJ: Ablex, 1986
    • Ross, J. R. (1967). Constraints on variables in syntax. Ph.D. thesis, MIT. Now reprinted as InWnite Syntax. Norwood, NJ: Ablex, 1986.
    • (1967) Constraints on variables in syntax
    • Ross, J.R.1
  • 20
    • 2942597358 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Coherence relations in context; on the categorization of positive causal relations
    • Sanders, T. (1997). Coherence relations in context; on the categorization of positive causal relations. Discourse Processes, 24, 119-147.
    • (1997) Discourse Processes , vol.24 , pp. 119-147
    • Sanders, T.1
  • 24


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.