메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 61, Issue 2, 1999, Pages 219-250

Multicultural Liberals and the Rushdie Affair: A Critique of Kymlicka, Taylor, and Walzer

(1)  O'Neill, Daniel I a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 85009850647     PISSN: 00346705     EISSN: 17486858     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1017/S0034670500051986     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (20)

References (117)
  • 1
    • 25844464774 scopus 로고
    • For chronological overviews, see Syracuse: Syracuse University Press
    • For chronological overviews, see Lisa Appignanesi and Sara Maitland, eds., The Rushdie File (Syracuse: Syracuse University Press, 1990);
    • (1990) The Rushdie File
    • Appignanesi, L.1    Maitland, S.2
  • 2
    • 61949411080 scopus 로고
    • and International Centre Against Censorship
    • and Carmel Bedford, Fiction, Fact and the Fatwa (International Centre Against Censorship, 1994).
    • (1994) Fiction, Fact and the Fatwa
    • Bedford, C.1
  • 5
    • 85022524570 scopus 로고
    • For an overview of the Rushdie Affair in Britain that illustrates the fundamental importance of the book banning issue, see reports from three conferences sponsored by the Commission for Racial Equality: Law, Blasphemy and the Multi-Faith Society London: CRE, Elliot House
    • For an overview of the Rushdie Affair in Britain that illustrates the fundamental importance of the book banning issue, see reports from three conferences sponsored by the Commission for Racial Equality: Law, Blasphemy and the Multi-Faith Society; Free Speech; and Britain: A Plural Society (London: CRE, Elliot House, 1990).
    • (1990) Free Speech; and Britain: A Plural Society
  • 6
    • 84981601846 scopus 로고
    • The Rushdie Affair: Research Agenda for Political Philosophy
    • For academic discussions of the controversy that stress its importance, see
    • For academic discussions of the controversy that stress its importance, see Bhikhu Parekh, “The Rushdie Affair: Research Agenda for Political Philosophy,” Political Studies 38, no. 4 (1990): 695-709;
    • (1990) Political Studies , vol.38 , Issue.4 , pp. 695-709
    • Parekh, B.1
  • 7
    • 84971922152 scopus 로고
    • Respecting Beliefs and Rebuking Rushdie
    • Peter Jones, “Respecting Beliefs and Rebuking Rushdie,” British Journal of Political Science 20 (1990): 415-437
    • (1990) British Journal of Political Science , vol.20 , pp. 415-437
    • Jones, P.1
  • 8
    • 84981573677 scopus 로고
    • Rushdie, Race, and Religion
    • “Rushdie, Race, and Religion,” Political Studies 38, no. 4 (1990): 687-694;
    • (1990) Political Studies , vol.38 , Issue.4 , pp. 687-694
  • 9
    • 34248560097 scopus 로고
    • and the essays responding to the controversy in New York: St. Martin's Press
    • and the essays responding to the controversy in Liberalism, Multiculturalism and Toleration, ed. John Horton (New York: St. Martin's Press, 1993).
    • (1993) Liberalism, Multiculturalism and Toleration
    • Horton, J.1
  • 18
    • 0001778197 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Politics of Recognition
    • ed. Amy Gutmann (Princeton: Princeton University Press
    • Charles Taylor, “The Politics of Recognition,” in Multiculturalism: Examining the Politics of Recognition, ed. Amy Gutmann (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1994), pp. 25–73.
    • (1994) Multiculturalism: Examining the Politics of Recognition , pp. 25-73
    • Taylor, C.1
  • 21
    • 85022455168 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See chap. 5, “Taylor's Social Thesis” pp. 74–99, and chap. 11, “Walzer and Minority Rights,” pp. 220–36
    • Kymlicka, Liberalism, Community, and Culture, p. 90. See chap. 5, “Taylor's Social Thesis” pp. 74–99, and chap. 11, “Walzer and Minority Rights,” pp. 220–36.
    • Kymlicka, Liberalism, Community, and Culture , pp. 90
  • 25
    • 0004022577 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 10. Of course, a country can be both multinational and polyethnic
    • Kymlicka, Multicultural Citizenship, pp. 10–26, 10. Of course, a country can be both multinational and polyethnic.
    • Multicultural Citizenship , pp. 10-26
    • Kymlicka1
  • 27
    • 85022459528 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A “societal culture” is one which “provides its members with meaningful ways of life across the full range of human activities” (p. 76). Kymlicka discusses further the distinction between national minorities and immigrants, and what he sees as immigrants' desire for sociocultural integration in two lectures delivered in 1995, available as States Assen, The Netherlands: Van Gorcum
    • A “societal culture” is one which “provides its members with meaningful ways of life across the full range of human activities” (p. 76). Kymlicka discusses further the distinction between national minorities and immigrants, and what he sees as immigrants' desire for sociocultural integration in two lectures delivered in 1995, available as States, Nations and Cultures (Assen, The Netherlands: Van Gorcum, 1997).
    • (1997) Nations and Cultures
  • 30
    • 85022552906 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • pp. 31–33. “Special representation rights” are “guaranteed seats for ethnic or national groups within the central institutions of the larger state” (p. 7)
    • Nations and Cultures, p. 7, pp. 31–33. “Special representation rights” are “guaranteed seats for ethnic or national groups within the central institutions of the larger state” (p. 7).
    • Nations and Cultures , pp. 7
  • 31
    • 85022552906 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 80-82,158. On the fundamental importance of individual autonomy for Kymlicka, see also pp. 75,154-63; and his
    • Nations and Cultures, pp. 152, 80-82,158. On the fundamental importance of individual autonomy for Kymlicka, see also pp. 75,154-63; and his
    • Nations and Cultures , pp. 152
  • 32
    • 84865773769 scopus 로고
    • Two Models of Pluralism and Tolerance
    • where he specifically contrasts “liberal tolerance” with the Ottoman Muslim group-based form of tolerance known as the “millet system,” and criticizes Rawls's more recent work for retreating from a “comprehensive” liberal doctrine based on the value of individual autonomy
    • “Two Models of Pluralism and Tolerance,” Analyse and Kritik 13 (1992): 33-56, where he specifically contrasts “liberal tolerance” with the Ottoman Muslim group-based form of tolerance known as the “millet system,” and criticizes Rawls's more recent work for retreating from a “comprehensive” liberal doctrine based on the value of individual autonomy.
    • (1992) Analyse and Kritik , vol.13 , pp. 33-56
  • 34
  • 38
    • 85055405779 scopus 로고
    • Kymlicka on British Muslims
    • Tariq Modood, “Kymlicka on British Muslims,” Analyse and Kritik 15 (1993): 87-91;
    • (1993) Analyse and Kritik , vol.15 , pp. 87-91
    • Modood, T.1
  • 48
    • 0347729611 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Leicester, United Kingdom: The Islamic Foundation, revised and enlarged edition The terms most frequently used to describe The Satanic Verses in these pages are blasphemous, sacrilegious, offensive, insulting, abusive, hurtful, obscene, libelous, vilificatory,foul, and filthy
    • M. M. Ahsan and A. R. Kidwai, eds., Sacrilege versus Civility: Muslim Perspectives on the Satanic Verses Affair (Leicester, United Kingdom: The Islamic Foundation, revised and enlarged edition, 1993). The terms most frequently used to describe The Satanic Verses in these pages are blasphemous, sacrilegious, offensive, insulting, abusive, hurtful, obscene, libelous, vilificatory,foul, and filthy.
    • (1993) Sacrilege versus Civility: Muslim Perspectives on the Satanic Verses Affair
    • Ahsan, M.M.1    Kidwai, A.R.2
  • 49
    • 10644225767 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For these arguments, see 38-40, 53-58,147,165-71,176-78, 181,186-88,192,194-98,204-205,207,209,210-28,234-35,238-2, 245,261, 26768, 274-76, 323, 327-33 (esp.), 335, 337, 348-49, 353-54, 360-61, 372, 382, 384, 386-87, 394-02
    • For these arguments, see Sacrilege versus Civility: Muslim Perspectives on the Satanic Verses Affair, pp. 36, 38-40, 53-58,147,165-71,176-78, 181,186-88,192,194-98,204-205,207,209,210-28,234-35,238-2, 245,261, 26768, 274-76, 323, 327-33 (esp.), 335, 337, 348-49, 353-54, 360-61, 372, 382, 384, 386-87, 394-02.
    • Sacrilege versus Civility: Muslim Perspectives on the Satanic Verses Affair , pp. 36
  • 59
    • 0347729611 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Muslim commentators consistently rejected “equality before the law” if it meant abolishing the blasphemy law entirely. The UK Action Committee on Islamic Affairs referred to this option as “equality in indignity” and dismissed it outright, while Akhtar called it “cold comfort,” leaving Muslims as unprotected as before. See 256
    • Muslim commentators consistently rejected “equality before the law” if it meant abolishing the blasphemy law entirely. The UK Action Committee on Islamic Affairs referred to this option as “equality in indignity” and dismissed it outright, while Akhtar called it “cold comfort,” leaving Muslims as unprotected as before. See Ahsan and Kidwai, Sacrilege versus Civility, pp. 349, 256.
    • Sacrilege versus Civility , pp. 349
    • Ahsan1    Kidwai2
  • 60
    • 24944588198 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • How Much Cultural and Religious Pluralism can Liberalism Tolerate
    • I draw on the following
    • I draw on the following: Jonathan Chaplin, “How Much Cultural and Religious Pluralism can Liberalism Tolerate” in Horton, Liberalism, Multiculturalism and Toleration, pp. 32-A9;
    • Horton, Liberalism, Multiculturalism and Toleration , pp. 32-A9
    • Chaplin, J.1
  • 61
    • 0009335977 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Autonomy, Toleration, and Group Rights: A Response to Will Kymlicka
    • ed. David Heyd (Princeton: Princeton University Press
    • Moshe Halbertal, “Autonomy, Toleration, and Group Rights: A Response to Will Kymlicka,” in Toleration, ed. David Heyd (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1996), pp. 106–113;
    • (1996) Toleration , pp. 106-113
    • Halbertal, M.1
  • 62
    • 84970706826 scopus 로고
    • Are There Any Cultural Rights
    • Chandran Kukathas, “Are There Any Cultural Rights” Political Theory 20, no. 1 (1992): 105-139
    • (1992) Political Theory , vol.20 , Issue.1 , pp. 105-139
    • Kukathas, C.1
  • 63
    • 84970675589 scopus 로고
    • Cultural Rights Again: Rejoinder to Kymlicka
    • “Cultural Rights Again: Rejoinder to Kymlicka,” Political Theory 20, no. 4 (1992): 674-680
    • (1992) Political Theory , vol.20 , Issue.4 , pp. 674-680
  • 64
    • 0009331980 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cultural Toleration
    • New York: New York University Press
    • “Cultural Toleration,” in Ethnicity and Group Rights, ed. Ian Shapiro and Will Kymlicka (New York: New York University Press, 1997), pp. 69–104
    • (1997) Ethnicity and Group Rights , pp. 69-104
    • Shapiro, I.1    Kymlicka, W.2
  • 65
    • 0042046194 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Multiculturalism as Fairness: Will Kymlicka's Multicultural Citizenship
    • “Multiculturalism as Fairness: Will Kymlicka's Multicultural Citizenship,” The Journal of Political Philosophy 5, no. 4 (1997): 406-427;
    • (1997) The Journal of Political Philosophy , vol.5 , Issue.4 , pp. 406-427
  • 66
    • 0010014621 scopus 로고
    • Liberalism and the Problem of Cultural Membership: A Critical Study of Kymlicka
    • and in the same number, Michael McDonald, “Should Communities Have Rights Reflections on Liberal Individualism,” pp. 217–37
    • Don Lenihan, “Liberalism and the Problem of Cultural Membership: A Critical Study of Kymlicka,” Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence 4, no. 2 (1991): 401-419, and in the same number, Michael McDonald, “Should Communities Have Rights Reflections on Liberal Individualism,” pp. 217–37;
    • (1991) Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence , vol.4 , Issue.2 , pp. 401-419
    • Lenihan, D.1
  • 67
    • 84992845486 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Equality, Autonomy, and Cultural Rights
    • Geoffrey Brahm Levey, “Equality, Autonomy, and Cultural Rights,” Political Theory 25, no. 2 (1997): 215-218;
    • (1997) Political Theory , vol.25 , Issue.2 , pp. 215-218
    • Levey, G.B.1
  • 68
    • 79952378956 scopus 로고
    • Liberalism and the Right to Culture
    • Avishai Margalit and Moshe Halbertal, “Liberalism and the Right to Culture,” Social Research 61, no. 3 (1994): 491-510;
    • (1994) Social Research , vol.61 , Issue.3 , pp. 491-510
    • Margalit, A.1    Halbertal, M.2
  • 69
    • 84937316154 scopus 로고
    • Can Liberalism Be Communitarian
    • Charles Taylor, “Can Liberalism Be Communitarian” Critical Review 8, no. 2 (1994): 257-262;
    • (1994) Critical Review , vol.8 , Issue.2 , pp. 257-262
    • Taylor, C.1
  • 70
    • 0000776768 scopus 로고
    • Kymlicka, Liberalism, and Respect for Cultural Minorities
    • John Tornasi, “Kymlicka, Liberalism, and Respect for Cultural Minorities,” Ethics 105 (1995): 580-603;
    • (1995) Ethics , vol.105 , pp. 580-603
    • Tornasi, J.1
  • 71
    • 0039165825 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Plural Cultures, Contested Territories: A Critique of Kymlicka
    • Brian Walker, “Plural Cultures, Contested Territories: A Critique of Kymlicka,” Canadian Journal of Political Science 30, no. 2 (1997): 211-234;
    • (1997) Canadian Journal of Political Science , vol.30 , Issue.2 , pp. 211-234
    • Walker, B.1
  • 72
    • 0038562752 scopus 로고
    • Group Inequality and the Public Culture of Justice
    • ed. Judith Baker (Buffalo: University of Toronto Press
    • Melissa Williams, “Group Inequality and the Public Culture of Justice,” in Group Rights, ed. Judith Baker (Buffalo: University of Toronto Press, 1994), pp. 34–65
    • (1994) Group Rights , pp. 34-65
    • Williams, M.1
  • 75
    • 0002182683 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Global Crises, the Struggle for Cultural Identity and Intellectual Porkbarrelling: Cosmopolitans versus Locals, Ethnics and Nationals in an Era of De-hegemonisation
    • This is not to say, of course, that Muslims were unanimously in favor of banning the book. A small number of intellectuals, in particular, came to Rushdie's defense. (See For Rushdie: Essays by Arab and Muslim Writers in Defense of Free Speech [New York: George Braziller, 1994]). This is not surprising, since absolute agreement on free speech criteria does not exist in any culture, whereas broad consensus clearly does. If The Satanic Verses (a book written by a Muslim immigrant) is a sign of cultural hybridity and a reminder to those who would create a monolithic version of Islam, the overwhelmingly negative reaction by Muslims to the novel is a clear indication that we should be still more wary of the current postmodern academic tendency to dismiss attempts at pointing out broad patterns of cultural belief as oppressive exercises in essentialism. On this point, see ed. Pnina Weber and Tariq Modood (London: Zed Books
    • This is not to say, of course, that Muslims were unanimously in favor of banning the book. A small number of intellectuals, in particular, came to Rushdie's defense. (See For Rushdie: Essays by Arab and Muslim Writers in Defense of Free Speech [New York: George Braziller, 1994]). This is not surprising, since absolute agreement on free speech criteria does not exist in any culture, whereas broad consensus clearly does. If The Satanic Verses (a book written by a Muslim immigrant) is a sign of cultural hybridity and a reminder to those who would create a monolithic version of Islam, the overwhelmingly negative reaction by Muslims to the novel is a clear indication that we should be still more wary of the current postmodern academic tendency to dismiss attempts at pointing out broad patterns of cultural belief as oppressive exercises in essentialism. On this point, see Jonathan Friedman, “Global Crises, the Struggle for Cultural Identity and Intellectual Porkbarrelling: Cosmopolitans versus Locals, Ethnics and Nationals in an Era of De-hegemonisation” in Debating Cultural Hybridity, ed. Pnina Weber and Tariq Modood (London: Zed Books, 1997), pp. 70–89;
    • (1997) Debating Cultural Hybridity , pp. 70-89
    • Friedman, J.1
  • 80
    • 84968891181 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Consider the following: “Cases involving newly arriving immigrant groups are very different. In these cases, it is more legitimate to compel respect for liberal principles. … I do not think it is wrong for liberal states to insist that immigration entails accepting the legitimacy of state enforcement of liberal principles, so long as immigrants know this in advance, and none the less voluntarily choose to come”
    • Consider the following: “Cases involving newly arriving immigrant groups are very different. In these cases, it is more legitimate to compel respect for liberal principles. … I do not think it is wrong for liberal states to insist that immigration entails accepting the legitimacy of state enforcement of liberal principles, so long as immigrants know this in advance, and none the less voluntarily choose to come” (Multicultural Citizenship, p. 170).
    • Multicultural Citizenship , pp. 170
  • 81
    • 84937270543 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Good, the Bad, and the Intolerable
    • This remark is repeated, almost verbatim, in Summer 29
    • This remark is repeated, almost verbatim, in Kymlicka, “The Good, the Bad, and the Intolerable,” Dissent (Summer 1996): 22-30, 29.
    • (1996) Dissent , pp. 22-30
    • Kymlicka1
  • 82
    • 84973219998 scopus 로고
    • The Hidden Politics of Cultural Identification
    • On this theme, see
    • On this theme, see Amelie Oksenberg Rorty, “The Hidden Politics of Cultural Identification,” Political Theory 22, no. 1 (1994): 152-166.
    • (1994) Political Theory , vol.22 , Issue.1 , pp. 152-166
    • Rorty, A.O.1
  • 86
    • 62749149933 scopus 로고
    • The Rushdie Controversy
    • 118
    • Charles Taylor, “The Rushdie Controversy,” Public Culture 2, no. 1 (1989): 118-122, 118.
    • (1989) Public Culture , vol.2 , Issue.1 , pp. 118-122
    • Taylor, C.1
  • 91
    • 85022459511 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See most recently Taylor's “A World Consensus on Human Rights” Dissent (Summer
    • See most recently Taylor's “A World Consensus on Human Rights” Dissent (Summer 1996): 15-21.
    • (1996) , pp. 15-21
  • 92
    • 0001267896 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Understanding and Ethnocentricity
    • See esp. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • See esp., “Understanding and Ethnocentricity,” Philosophical Papers 2: Philosophy and the Human Sciences (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985), pp. 116–134;
    • (1985) Philosophical Papers 2: Philosophy and the Human Sciences , pp. 116-134
  • 93
    • 0010083144 scopus 로고
    • Explanation and Practical Reason
    • and Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • and “Explanation and Practical Reason,” Philosophical Arguments (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1995), pp. 34–60.
    • (1995) Philosophical Arguments , pp. 34-60
  • 94
    • 84937280821 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cultural Relativism and Social Criticism from a Taylorian Perspective
    • For a discussion of Taylor's cultural relativism that stresses its possibilities as a vehicle for intercultural critique, see
    • For a discussion of Taylor's cultural relativism that stresses its possibilities as a vehicle for intercultural critique, see Hartmut Rosa, “Cultural Relativism and Social Criticism from a Taylorian Perspective,” Constellations 3, no. 1 (1996): 39-60.
    • (1996) Constellations , vol.3 , Issue.1 , pp. 39-60
    • Rosa, H.1
  • 99
    • 0010091630 scopus 로고
    • Pluralism: A Political Perspective
    • See also ed. Stephen Thernstrom (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press As Kymlicka argues, the fact that Walzer fails to clearly extend his logic to the case of Native Americans and other peoples subject to U.S. expansionism is more than a little curious. See Liberalism, Community, and Culture, n. 2, pp. 235–36
    • See also, “Pluralism: A Political Perspective,” in Harvard Encyclopedia of American Ethnic Groups, ed. Stephen Thernstrom (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1980), pp. 781–787. As Kymlicka argues, the fact that Walzer fails to clearly extend his logic to the case of Native Americans and other peoples subject to U.S. expansionism is more than a little curious. See Liberalism, Community, and Culture, n. 2, pp. 235–36;
    • (1980) Harvard Encyclopedia of American Ethnic Groups , pp. 781-787
  • 101
  • 103
    • 85022564473 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New Haven: Yale University Press Walzer seems to recognize that his earlier characterization of the intentions of immigrants was inaccurate, at least to the extent it was meant to apply to recent non-Western immigrants. In his discussion of French multicultural issues, Walzer notes of these new groups (especially Muslims): “They have cultures of their own that they want to preserve and reproduce…. They want to be recognized as a group and to be allowed to act out their group identity in public…. The new immigrants, or many of them, seek some version of multiculturalism, though they are mostly not ready for the American version” (p. 40). It seems also, in conjunction with this recognition, that Walzer, like Kymlicka, is willing to make some allowance for cultural rights for these groups, but only in quite limited cases. While head scarves for French schoolgirls are acceptable (as long as the girls are uncoerced by their parents into wearing them) clitoridectomy (or female genital mutilation) of young African girls is forbidden under all circumstances. At the same time, however, Walzer believes the “subordination of women–manifest in seclusion, bodily concealment, or actual mutilation–is not aimed solely at the enforcement of patriarchal property rights. It also has to do with cultural or religious reproduction” (p. 64). Therefore, “traditionalists” will argue that toleration in multicultural societies requires tolerating different communities' social practices, i.e., that toleration implies a right to communal reproduction. But, Walzer contends: “This right, if it exists, comes into conflict with the rights of individual citizens–which were once confined to men and were therefore not so dangerous, but are now extended to women. It seems inevitable that individual rights will win out in the long run. … Communal reproduction will then be less certain or, at least, it will be realized through processes that yield less uniform results. Traditionalists will have to learn a toleration of their own–for different versions of their own culture or religion” (p. 65). What Walzer fails to mention is the specific character of these new versions of old cultures–they will be liberal or, to use Kymlicka's terms, they will have become “liberalized.” This poses a serious problem for Walzer, given his understanding of justice, as I argue below. The question I am posing is not whether Walzer personally finds particular cultural practices repugnant, but the extent to which his theory of justice provides adequate grounds for criticizing them
    • In his most recent book, On Toleration (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1997), Walzer seems to recognize that his earlier characterization of the intentions of immigrants was inaccurate, at least to the extent it was meant to apply to recent non-Western immigrants. In his discussion of French multicultural issues, Walzer notes of these new groups (especially Muslims): “They have cultures of their own that they want to preserve and reproduce…. They want to be recognized as a group and to be allowed to act out their group identity in public…. The new immigrants, or many of them, seek some version of multiculturalism, though they are mostly not ready for the American version” (p. 40). It seems also, in conjunction with this recognition, that Walzer, like Kymlicka, is willing to make some allowance for cultural rights for these groups, but only in quite limited cases. While head scarves for French schoolgirls are acceptable (as long as the girls are uncoerced by their parents into wearing them) clitoridectomy (or female genital mutilation) of young African girls is forbidden under all circumstances. At the same time, however, Walzer believes the “subordination of women–manifest in seclusion, bodily concealment, or actual mutilation–is not aimed solely at the enforcement of patriarchal property rights. It also has to do with cultural or religious reproduction” (p. 64). Therefore, “traditionalists” will argue that toleration in multicultural societies requires tolerating different communities' social practices, i.e., that toleration implies a right to communal reproduction. But, Walzer contends: “This right, if it exists, comes into conflict with the rights of individual citizens–which were once confined to men and were therefore not so dangerous, but are now extended to women. It seems inevitable that individual rights will win out in the long run. … Communal reproduction will then be less certain or, at least, it will be realized through processes that yield less uniform results. Traditionalists will have to learn a toleration of their own–for different versions of their own culture or religion” (p. 65). What Walzer fails to mention is the specific character of these new versions of old cultures–they will be liberal or, to use Kymlicka's terms, they will have become “liberalized.” This poses a serious problem for Walzer, given his understanding of justice, as I argue below. The question I am posing is not whether Walzer personally finds particular cultural practices repugnant, but the extent to which his theory of justice provides adequate grounds for criticizing them.
    • (1997) In his most recent book, On Toleration
  • 104
    • 85009850664 scopus 로고
    • The Sins of Salman
    • 10 April 14
    • Michael Walzer, “The Sins of Salman,” The New Republic, 10 April 1989, pp. 13–15, 14.
    • (1989) The New Republic , pp. 13-15
    • Walzer, M.1
  • 112
    • 0006991014 scopus 로고
    • Spherical Justice and Global Injustice
    • ed. David Miller and Michael Walzer (Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • Brian Barry, “Spherical Justice and Global Injustice,” in Pluralism, Justice, and Equality, ed. David Miller and Michael Walzer (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995), pp. 67–80.
    • (1995) Pluralism, Justice, and Equality , pp. 67-80
    • Barry, B.1
  • 113
    • 0004025594 scopus 로고
    • This conclusion is not altered by Walzer's numerous attempts to defend the viability of social criticism from within the framework set forth in Spheres of Justice (see esp. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • This conclusion is not altered by Walzer's numerous attempts to defend the viability of social criticism from within the framework set forth in Spheres of Justice (see esp., Interpretation and Social Criticism [Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1987];
    • (1987) Interpretation and Social Criticism
  • 114
    • 33845796878 scopus 로고
    • New York: Basic Books
    • The Company of Critics [New York: Basic Books, 1988];
    • (1988) The Company of Critics
  • 115
    • 0007362192 scopus 로고
    • Objectivity and Social Meaning
    • ed. Martha Nussbaum and Amartya Sen [Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • “Objectivity and Social Meaning,” in The Quality of Life, ed. Martha Nussbaum and Amartya Sen [Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1993], pp. 165–177;
    • (1993) The Quality of Life , pp. 165-177
  • 116
    • 0003466809 scopus 로고
    • Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press Responding to heavy criticism, Walzer has attempted to show how (a) social criticism is most effective when it is internal, or intra-community and (b) a “thin moral minimum,” or set of precepts actually shared across cultures, can provide a universal standard of justice. This only goes a small way toward extricating Walzer from the consequences of his conventionalism. As far as (a) is concerned, the role of the social critic for Walzer is to demonstrate how his/her society fails to live up to its “true” values. This means the “real” social consensus inevitably defines the horizon of legitimate dissent, with predictably conservative results. Moreover, the mere existence of a small number of internal social critics in an “illiberal” culture, the moral justness of which Walzer has already accepted, is of little consequence. If the relevant culture in question is not committed to the liberal version of individual autonomy, why should it listen to its internal social critics Walzer has not provided a convincing response to this question. As concerns (b), I have shown above how a reading of the Muslim literature on the Rushdie affair makes clear that the lack of a “thin” consensus was not the cause of the controversy. Muslims accepted free speech, as an abstract principle, but disagreed completely with Western liberals on its interpretation. What the Rushdie controversy makes evident is that “thin” consensus on abstract principles means little in the absence of “thick” cultural agreement about the meaning of those principles in practice. Absent this “thick” agreement, Walzer is led, ineluctably, back to his original conventionalist position. In short, in cases like the Rushdie affair where cultures actually conflict, Walzer is poorly positioned to take a critical stance on the debate, and his denial of minority cultural rights claims can only seem morally unjust on the basis of his own prior arguments
    • Thick and Thin [Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1994]). Responding to heavy criticism, Walzer has attempted to show how (a) social criticism is most effective when it is internal, or intra-community and (b) a “thin moral minimum,” or set of precepts actually shared across cultures, can provide a universal standard of justice. This only goes a small way toward extricating Walzer from the consequences of his conventionalism. As far as (a) is concerned, the role of the social critic for Walzer is to demonstrate how his/her society fails to live up to its “true” values. This means the “real” social consensus inevitably defines the horizon of legitimate dissent, with predictably conservative results. Moreover, the mere existence of a small number of internal social critics in an “illiberal” culture, the moral justness of which Walzer has already accepted, is of little consequence. If the relevant culture in question is not committed to the liberal version of individual autonomy, why should it listen to its internal social critics Walzer has not provided a convincing response to this question. As concerns (b), I have shown above how a reading of the Muslim literature on the Rushdie affair makes clear that the lack of a “thin” consensus was not the cause of the controversy. Muslims accepted free speech, as an abstract principle, but disagreed completely with Western liberals on its interpretation. What the Rushdie controversy makes evident is that “thin” consensus on abstract principles means little in the absence of “thick” cultural agreement about the meaning of those principles in practice. Absent this “thick” agreement, Walzer is led, ineluctably, back to his original conventionalist position. In short, in cases like the Rushdie affair where cultures actually conflict, Walzer is poorly positioned to take a critical stance on the debate, and his denial of minority cultural rights claims can only seem morally unjust on the basis of his own prior arguments.
    • (1994) Thick and Thin


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.