메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 31, Issue 2, 2017, Pages 77-86

In defense of a social value requirement for clinical research

Author keywords

Clinical research; Exploitation; Moral integrity of researchers; Research ethics; Research policy; Social value

Indexed keywords

CLINICAL RESEARCH; CLINICAL TRIAL; HUMAN; MORALITY; PRACTICE GUIDELINE; RESEARCH ETHICS; SCIENTIST; CLINICAL PROTOCOL; CLINICAL TRIAL (TOPIC); ETHICS; MEDICAL ETHICS; MEDICAL RESEARCH; SOCIAL PSYCHOLOGY;

EID: 85009103713     PISSN: 02699702     EISSN: 14678519     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1111/bioe.12325     Document Type: Note
Times cited : (49)

References (48)
  • 1
    • 85009066853 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • WorldMedical Association. 2013. Declaration of Helsinki: Ethical Principles for Medical Research Involving Human Subjects. Available at, [Accessed 2 October 2016]. Council for International Organizations of Medical Sciences (CIOMS). International Ethical Guidelines for Biomedical Research Involving Human Subjects. Available at: http://www.cioms.ch/publications/guidelines/ guidelines_nov_2002_blurb.htm [Accessed 2 October 2016]
    • WorldMedical Association. 2013. Declaration of Helsinki: Ethical Principles for Medical Research Involving Human Subjects. Available at: http://www.wma.net/en/30publications/10policies/b3/ [Accessed 2 October 2016]. Council for International Organizations of Medical Sciences (CIOMS). International Ethical Guidelines for Biomedical Research Involving Human Subjects. Available at: http://www.cioms.ch/publications/guidelines/ guidelines_nov_2002_blurb.htm [Accessed 2 October 2016].
  • 2
    • 84890591215 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Nuremberg Code, Washington, DC: US Government Printing Office, 1949.Available at, [Accessed 2 October 2016]
    • The Nuremberg Code. In: Trials of War Criminals before the Nuremberg Military Tribunals under Control Council Law No. 10, vol. 2, pp. 181–182.Washington, DC: US Government Printing Office, 1949.Available at: https://history.nih.gov/research/downloads/nuremberg.pdf [Accessed 2 October 2016].
    • Trials of War Criminals before the Nuremberg Military Tribunals under Control Council Law No. 10 , vol.2 , pp. 181-182
  • 3
    • 85009102752 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • National Council for Science and Technology. 2004. Guidelines for Ethical Conduct of Biomedical Research Involving Human Subjects in Kenya. Nairobi, NCST NO. 45. Available at, [Accessed 4 October 2016]
    • National Council for Science and Technology. 2004. Guidelines for Ethical Conduct of Biomedical Research Involving Human Subjects in Kenya. Nairobi, NCST NO. 45. Available at: https://www.healthresearchweb.org/files/Kenya_Guidelines_Ethical_conduct_of_research_ involving__human_subjects.pdf [Accessed 4 October 2016].
  • 4
    • 0023452835 scopus 로고
    • Scientific Value and Validity as Ethical Requirements for Research: A Proposed Explication
    • B. Freedman. Scientific Value and Validity as Ethical Requirements for Research: A Proposed Explication. IRB 1987; 9: 7–10
    • (1987) IRB , vol.9 , pp. 7-10
    • Freedman, B.1
  • 5
    • 0033289960 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Clinical Value: The Neglected Axis in the System of Research Ethics
    • J.H. Karlawish. Clinical Value: The Neglected Axis in the System of Research Ethics. Account Res 1999; 7: 255–264
    • (1999) Account Res , vol.7 , pp. 255-264
    • Karlawish, J.H.1
  • 6
    • 0037974518 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Thinking Further about Value: Commentary on a ‘Taxonomy of Value in Clinical Research’
    • C. Grady. Thinking Further about Value: Commentary on a ‘Taxonomy of Value in Clinical Research’. IRB 2001; 24: 7–8;
    • (2001) IRB , vol.24 , pp. 7-8
    • Grady, C.1
  • 7
    • 84875236944 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Social Benefits of Human Subjects Research
    • D. Resnik. Social Benefits of Human Subjects Research. J Clin Res Best Pract 2008; 4: 1–7;
    • (2008) J Clin Res Best Pract , vol.4 , pp. 1-7
    • Resnik, D.1
  • 8
    • 84878386142 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Relevance of Relevance in Research
    • D. Shaw & B.S. Elger. The Relevance of Relevance in Research. Swiss Med Wkly 2013; 143: w13792;
    • (2013) Swiss Med Wkly , vol.143
    • Shaw, D.1    Elger, B.S.2
  • 10
    • 84929502419 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Social Value Requirement Reconsidered
    • A. Wertheimer. The Social Value Requirement Reconsidered. Bioethics 2015; 29: 301–8.
    • (2015) Bioethics , vol.29 , pp. 301-308
    • Wertheimer, A.1
  • 11
    • 84976870029 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Examining the Social Benefits Principle in Research with Human Participants
    • UnlikeWertheimer, Resnik does not limit his analysis of what he calls a _strong social benefits principle_ to clinical research. However, this matters little for present purposes because his arguments clearly apply to clinical research
    • D. Resnik: Examining the Social Benefits Principle in Research with Human Participants. Health Care Anal 2016. DOI: 10.1007/s10728-016- 0326-2. UnlikeWertheimer, Resnik does not limit his analysis of what he calls a _strong social benefits principle_ to clinical research. However, this matters little for present purposes because his arguments clearly apply to clinical research.
    • (2016) Health Care Anal
    • Resnik, D.1
  • 12
    • 0034737962 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • What Makes Clinical Research Ethical?
    • E.J. Emanuel, D. Wendler & C. Grady. What Makes Clinical Research Ethical? JAMA 2000; 28: 2701–2711.
    • (2000) JAMA , vol.28 , pp. 2701-2711
    • Emanuel, E.J.1    Wendler, D.2    Grady, C.3
  • 13
    • 80051605726 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A Framework for Risk-Benefit Evaluations in BiomedicalResearch
    • A. Rid & D. Wendler. A Framework for Risk-Benefit Evaluations in BiomedicalResearch. Kennedy Inst Ethics J 2011; 21(2): 141–179.
    • (2011) Kennedy Inst Ethics J , vol.21 , Issue.2 , pp. 141-179
    • Rid, A.1    Wendler, D.2
  • 14
    • 85009063190 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • We also believe that there are upper limits on net risks to participants that cannot be justified even by tremendous social value; however, we cannot pursue this question here. Ibid
    • We also believe that there are upper limits on net risks to participants that cannot be justified even by tremendous social value; however, we cannot pursue this question here. Ibid.
  • 15
    • 85009149030 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Wertheimer, op. cit. note 5: 302
    • Wertheimer, op. cit. note 5: 302.
  • 16
    • 85009102768 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Resnik, op. cit. note 6: 5 (preprint)
    • Resnik, op. cit. note 6: 5 (preprint).
  • 17
    • 85009125089 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • CIOMS, op. cit. note 1
    • CIOMS, op. cit. note 1.
  • 18
    • 84873986488 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Refocusing the Responsiveness Requirement
    • S. Shah, R. Wolitz & E.J. Emanuel. Refocusing the Responsiveness Requirement. Bioethics 2013; 27: 151–159.
    • (2013) Bioethics , vol.27 , pp. 151-159
    • Shah, S.1    Wolitz, R.2    Emanuel, E.J.3
  • 19
    • 77957724089 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press
    • D. Wendler. 2010. The Ethics of Pediatric Research. Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press: 77–106.
    • (2010) The Ethics of Pediatric Research , pp. 77-106
    • Wendler, D.1
  • 20
    • 85009105103 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Many guidelines and regulations also allow waivers or modifications of the requirement to obtain the informed consent of competent adults when the research meets specified conditions, typically including being low risk and involving little, if any interaction with the participants. There has been surprisingly little discussion of what justifies research without consent under these conditions. Although we will not discuss the issue here, we suspect that any successful justification for waiving or modifying informed consent—just like any successful justification for research with participants who cannot consent—will have to cite at least in part the social value of the research
    • Many guidelines and regulations also allow waivers or modifications of the requirement to obtain the informed consent of competent adults when the research meets specified conditions, typically including being low risk and involving little, if any interaction with the participants. There has been surprisingly little discussion of what justifies research without consent under these conditions. Although we will not discuss the issue here, we suspect that any successful justification for waiving or modifying informed consent—just like any successful justification for research with participants who cannot consent—will have to cite at least in part the social value of the research.
  • 22
    • 0019021748 scopus 로고
    • Moral Duties of Parents and Nontherapeutic Clinical Research Procedures Involving Children
    • T.F. Ackerman. Moral Duties of Parents and Nontherapeutic Clinical Research Procedures Involving Children. Bioethics 1980; 2: 94–111.
    • (1980) Bioethics , vol.2 , pp. 94-111
    • Ackerman, T.F.1
  • 23
    • 0042093638 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Should We Presume Moral Turpitude in our Children? Small Children and Consent to Medical Research
    • J. Harris & S. Holm. Should We Presume Moral Turpitude in our Children? Small Children and Consent to Medical Research. Theor Med Bioethics 2003; 24: 121–129;
    • (2003) Theor Med Bioethics , vol.24 , pp. 121-129
    • Harris, J.1    Holm, S.2
  • 24
    • 0002869851 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ethical Issues in Exposing Children to Risks in Research. 1994
    • M.A. Grodin & L.H. Glantz, eds. Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press
    • D.W. Brock. Ethical Issues in Exposing Children to Risks in Research. 1994. In Children as Research Subjects: Science, Ethics and Law. M.A. Grodin & L.H. Glantz, eds. Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press: 81–101.
    • Children as Research Subjects: Science, Ethics and Law , pp. 81-101
    • Brock, D.W.1
  • 25
    • 85009102764 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Wendler, op. cit. note 10: 154–165
    • Wendler, op. cit. note 10: 154–165.
  • 26
    • 85009096260 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Resnik makes a similar argument, although he claims that the SVR applies only to research that poses more than minimal net risks. Resnik, op. cit. note 6. In our view, this position is not tenable because any level of net risk to participants who cannot consent, however small, requires justification
    • Resnik makes a similar argument, although he claims that the SVR applies only to research that poses more than minimal net risks. Resnik, op. cit. note 6. In our view, this position is not tenable because any level of net risk to participants who cannot consent, however small, requires justification.
  • 27
    • 85009114293 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For example, Resnik briefly considers whether risk imposition justifies an SVR and concludes that _placing restrictions on consensual risktaking in research is paternalistic_. This response seems to assume both that paternalism is always ethically inappropriate and the justification for requiring social value must trace to the (paternalistic) protection of participants. Resnik, op. cit. note 6: 7 (preprint)
    • For example, Resnik briefly considers whether risk imposition justifies an SVR and concludes that _placing restrictions on consensual risktaking in research is paternalistic_. This response seems to assume both that paternalism is always ethically inappropriate and the justification for requiring social value must trace to the (paternalistic) protection of participants. Resnik, op. cit. note 6: 7 (preprint).
  • 28
    • 85009123209 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Those offering high-risk employment still have an obligation to reduce the risks where possible, suggesting that the risks of even highly valuable research should be reduced as well. Rid &Wendler, op. cit. note 8
    • Those offering high-risk employment still have an obligation to reduce the risks where possible, suggesting that the risks of even highly valuable research should be reduced as well. Rid &Wendler, op. cit. note 8.
  • 29
    • 85009082149 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Wertheimer, op. cit. note 5
    • Wertheimer, op. cit. note 5.
  • 30
    • 84922976361 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press
    • T. Nagel. Mortal Questions. 2012. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
    • (2012) Mortal Questions
    • Nagel, T.1
  • 31
    • 85009077036 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Center for Information and Study on Clinical Research Participation. 2015. Perceptions and Insights Study: Public and Patient Perceptions of Clinical Research. Report on Public Perceptions. Available at, [Accessed 2 October 2016]
    • Center for Information and Study on Clinical Research Participation. 2015. Perceptions and Insights Study: Public and Patient Perceptions of Clinical Research. Report on Public Perceptions. Available at: https://www. ciscrp.org/download/2015-perceptions-insights-study-public-perceptions/ ?wpdmdl55740 [Accessed 2 October 2016].
  • 32
    • 79953063494 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • More than the Money: A Review of the Literature Examining Health Volunteer Motivations
    • L. Stunkel & C. Grady. More than the Money: a Review of the Literature Examining Health Volunteer Motivations. Contemp Clin Trials 2011; 32: 342–52.
    • (2011) Contemp Clin Trials , vol.32 , pp. 342-352
    • Stunkel, L.1    Grady, C.2
  • 33
    • 85009126298 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Wertheimer grants that _to the extent that prospective participants are altruistically motivated to contribute to the generation of medical knowledge, . . . social value is required to warrant their confidence._ However, he suggests – wrongly, in our view – that social value considerations are irrelevant for most participants because they are motivated by self-interest.Wertheimer, op. cit. note 5: 7
    • Wertheimer grants that _to the extent that prospective participants are altruistically motivated to contribute to the generation of medical knowledge, . . . social value is required to warrant their confidence._ However, he suggests – wrongly, in our view – that social value considerations are irrelevant for most participants because they are motivated by self-interest.Wertheimer, op. cit. note 5: 7.
  • 34
    • 85009098499 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Emanuel et al., op. cit. note 7
    • Emanuel et al., op. cit. note 7.
  • 35
    • 85009063183 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Wertheimer, op. cit. note 5
    • Wertheimer, op. cit. note 5.
  • 36
    • 0004118270 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press
    • A. Wertheimer. 1999. Exploitation. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
    • (1999) Exploitation
    • Wertheimer, A.1
  • 37
    • 84922713719 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rethinking the Ethics of Clinical Research: Widening the lens
    • Oxford,New York: Oxford University Press
    • A. Wertheimer. 2010. Rethinking the Ethics of Clinical Research: Widening the lens. Oxford,New York: Oxford University Press.
    • (2010)
    • Wertheimer, A.1
  • 38
    • 85009127500 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Wertheimer’s argument also depends on his account of exploitation. For present purposes, we bracket possible criticism of his view and instead focus on showing that an SVR is a compelling way of avoiding exploitation — on Wertheimer’s own account – given current research practices
    • Wertheimer’s argument also depends on his account of exploitation. For present purposes, we bracket possible criticism of his view and instead focus on showing that an SVR is a compelling way of avoiding exploitation — on Wertheimer’s own account – given current research practices.
  • 39
    • 85009139624 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Wertheimer, op. cit. note 5
    • Wertheimer, op. cit. note 5.
  • 40
    • 84942315736 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Challenging the Sanctity of Donorism: Patient Tissue Providers as Payment-Worthy Contributors
    • R. Johnson & D. Wendler. Challenging the Sanctity of Donorism: Patient Tissue Providers as Payment-Worthy Contributors. Kennedy Instit Ethics J 2015; 25: 291–333.
    • (2015) Kennedy Instit Ethics J , vol.25 , pp. 291-333
    • Johnson, R.1    Wendler, D.2
  • 42
    • 85009063177 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Wertheimer, op. cit. note 5. Resnik pursues a similar line of argument in Resnik, op. cit. note 6
    • Wertheimer, op. cit. note 5. Resnik pursues a similar line of argument in Resnik, op. cit. note 6.
  • 43
    • 85009066743 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Resnik argues along these lines when he writes that _. . . scientists and institutions have numerous options for compensating the public for its investments in the science._ However, he does not consider that private investigators and sponsors are taking advantage of public funding that specifically contributes to their enterprise, and that this can justify instituting an SVR as a matter of public policy as we argue here. Resnik, op. cit. note 6: 8 (preprint)
    • Resnik argues along these lines when he writes that _. . . scientists and institutions have numerous options for compensating the public for its investments in the science._ However, he does not consider that private investigators and sponsors are taking advantage of public funding that specifically contributes to their enterprise, and that this can justify instituting an SVR as a matter of public policy as we argue here. Resnik, op. cit. note 6: 8 (preprint).
  • 44
    • 84872129305 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A Non-Paternalistic Model of Research Ethics and Oversight: Assessing the Benefits of Prospective Review
    • A.J. London. A Non-Paternalistic Model of Research Ethics and Oversight: Assessing the Benefits of Prospective Review. J Law Med Ethics 2012; 40: 930–944.
    • (2012) J Law Med Ethics , vol.40 , pp. 930-944
    • London, A.J.1
  • 45
    • 85009127993 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Resnik, op. cit. note 6
    • Resnik, op. cit. note 6.
  • 46
    • 85009096249 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Wertheimer, op. cit. note 5
    • Wertheimer, op. cit. note 5.
  • 47
    • 85009123147 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Moreover, if successful, this approach would also address the potential for participant deception or fraud discussed above (section 3.4) without insisting on an SVR
    • Moreover, if successful, this approach would also address the potential for participant deception or fraud discussed above (section 3.4) without insisting on an SVR.
  • 48
    • 85009096250 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Emanuel et al., op. cit. note 7
    • Emanuel et al., op. cit. note 7.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.