메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 11, Issue 1, 2005, Pages 1-26

Do precedents create rules?

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 84925602717     PISSN: 13523252     EISSN: 14698048     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1017/S1352325205050019     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (101)

References (37)
  • 1
    • 0039848663 scopus 로고
    • Precedent and the Common Law,7OXFORD J. LEGAL STUD.
    • S. Perry, Judicial Obligation, Precedent and the Common Law,7OXFORD J. LEGAL STUD. 215-257 (1987).
    • (1987) Judicial Obligation , pp. 215-257
    • Perry, S.1
  • 2
    • 84864500370 scopus 로고
    • (rev. ed., 1978); M. Moore, Precedent, Induction, and Ethical Generalization, in PRECEDENT IN LAW (L. Goldstein, ed., ).
    • R.M. DWORKIN, TAKING RIGHTS SERIOUSLY 110-118 (rev. ed., 1978); M. Moore, Precedent, Induction, and Ethical Generalization, in PRECEDENT IN LAW (L. Goldstein, ed., 1987).
    • (1987) TAKING RIGHTS SERIOUSLY 110-118
    • DWORKIN, R.M.1
  • 3
    • 85022449711 scopus 로고
    • (1979); M. EISENBERG, THE NATURE OF THE COMMON LAW
    • J. RAZ, THE AUTHORITY OF LAW 185 (1979); M. EISENBERG, THE NATURE OF THE COMMON LAW 61-62 (1988).
    • (1988) THE AUTHORITY OF LAW 185 , pp. 61-62
    • RAZ, J.1
  • 5
    • 0010224322 scopus 로고
    • (1991); D.N. MacCormick, Why Cases Have Rationes and What These Are, in PRECEDENT IN LAW 170 (L. Goldstein, ed., 1987); J. Bell, Sources of Law, in ENGLISH PRIVATE LAW §§1.63-1.79 (P. Birks, ed., 2000); RAZ, Those familiar with Raz's account of rules as “protected reasons” may be particularly drawn to this conclusion. note 3, at 183-189; Larry Alexander, Constrained by Precedent, 63 S. CAL. L. REV. 1-64 (1989); FRED SCHAUER, PLAYING BY THE RULES: A PHILOSOPHICAL EXAMINATION OF RULE-BASED DECISION-MAKING IN LAW AND IN LIFE
    • See, e.g., R. CROSS & J.W. HARRIS, PRECEDENT IN ENGLISH LAW 72 (1991); D.N. MacCormick, Why Cases Have Rationes and What These Are, in PRECEDENT IN LAW 170 (L. Goldstein, ed., 1987); J. Bell, Sources of Law, in ENGLISH PRIVATE LAW §§1.63-1.79 (P. Birks, ed., 2000); RAZ, Those familiar with Raz's account of rules as “protected reasons” may be particularly drawn to this conclusion. note 3, at 183-189; Larry Alexander, Constrained by Precedent, 63 S. CAL. L. REV. 1-64 (1989); FRED SCHAUER, PLAYING BY THE RULES: A PHILOSOPHICAL EXAMINATION OF RULE-BASED DECISION-MAKING IN LAW AND IN LIFE 181-187 (1991).
    • (1991) PRECEDENT IN ENGLISH LAW 72 , pp. 181-187
    • CROSS, R.1    HARRIS, J.W.2
  • 6
    • 85022418271 scopus 로고
    • at 195; Alexander, PRECEDENT IN ENGLISH LAW 72 note 5, at 23; D.N.MACCORMICK, LEGAL REASONING AND LEGAL THEORY
    • See, e.g., RAZ, PRECEDENT IN ENGLISH LAW 72 note 3, at 195; Alexander, PRECEDENT IN ENGLISH LAW 72 note 5, at 23; D.N.MACCORMICK, LEGAL REASONING AND LEGAL THEORY 213-228 (1994).
    • (1994) PRECEDENT IN ENGLISH LAW 72 note 3 , pp. 213-228
    • RAZ1
  • 7
    • 85022383073 scopus 로고
    • at 19; MACCORMICK, PRECEDENT IN ENGLISH LAW 72 note 3 note 6, at 45; J. RAZ, PRACTICAL REASON AND NORMS 50 SCHAUER, PRECEDENT IN ENGLISH LAW 72 note 3 note 5, at
    • See Alexander, PRECEDENT IN ENGLISH LAW 72 note 3 note 5, at 19; MACCORMICK, PRECEDENT IN ENGLISH LAW 72 note 3 note 6, at 45; J. RAZ, PRACTICAL REASON AND NORMS 50 (1990); SCHAUER, PRECEDENT IN ENGLISH LAW 72 note 3 note 5, at 23-24.
    • (1990) PRECEDENT IN ENGLISH LAW 72 note 3 note 5 , pp. 23-24
    • Alexander1
  • 8
    • 85022392325 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • There are other ways of setting up a decision-making process, but for the purposes of this discussion, these alternatives can be put to one side. note 3, at
    • The term is borrowed from EISENBERG, There are other ways of setting up a decision-making process, but for the purposes of this discussion, these alternatives can be put to one side. note 3, at 10-12.
    • The term is borrowed from EISENBERG , pp. 10-12
  • 12
    • 85022441625 scopus 로고
    • in LEGAL THEORY AND LEGAL HISTORY: ESSAYS ON THE COMMON LAW 372 (1973); Perry, Rules may also be advantageous if the decisions made using them will (over a range of cases) accord better with the underlying balance of reasons than decisions made directly attempting to apply those reasons. note 5 note 7 note 1, at 227-229; Moore, Rules may also be advantageous if the decisions made using them will (over a range of cases) accord better with the underlying balance of reasons than decisions made directly attempting to apply those reasons. note 5 note 7 note 2, at 185; Fred Schauer, Is the Common Law Law? 77 CAL. L. REV.
    • A.W.B. Simpson, The Common Law and Legal Theory, in LEGAL THEORY AND LEGAL HISTORY: ESSAYS ON THE COMMON LAW 372 (1973); Perry, Rules may also be advantageous if the decisions made using them will (over a range of cases) accord better with the underlying balance of reasons than decisions made directly attempting to apply those reasons. note 5 note 7 note 1, at 227-229; Moore, Rules may also be advantageous if the decisions made using them will (over a range of cases) accord better with the underlying balance of reasons than decisions made directly attempting to apply those reasons. note 5 note 7 note 2, at 185; Fred Schauer, Is the Common Law Law? 77 CAL. L. REV. 455-471 (1989), at 455.
    • (1989) The Common Law and Legal Theory , pp. 455
    • Simpson, A.W.B.1
  • 13
    • 85022447826 scopus 로고
    • (1987) 1 QB 853 (Court of Appeal): the earlier decision, Graham (1982) 74 Cr App R 235 (Court of Appeal), had been endorsed by the House of Lords in Howe AC
    • Sharp (1987) 1 QB 853 (Court of Appeal): the earlier decision, Graham (1982) 74 Cr App R 235 (Court of Appeal), had been endorsed by the House of Lords in Howe (1987) AC 417.
    • (1987) Sharp , pp. 417
  • 14
    • 85022433892 scopus 로고
    • in OXFORD ESSAYS IN JURISPRUDENCE 168-169 (A.G. Guest, ed., ); MACCORMICK, Sharp note 6, at 82-83; RAZ, Sharp note 3, at 184; EISENBERG, Sharp note 3, at
    • See, e.g., A.W.B. Simpson, The RatioDecidendi of a Case and Doctrine of Precedent, in OXFORD ESSAYS IN JURISPRUDENCE 168-169 (A.G. Guest, ed., 1961); MACCORMICK, Sharp note 6, at 82-83; RAZ, Sharp note 3, at 184; EISENBERG, Sharp note 3, at 51-61.
    • (1961) The RatioDecidendi of a Case and Doctrine of Precedent , pp. 51-61
    • Simpson, A.W.B.1
  • 16
    • 85022379238 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see DWORKIN, The Meaning of a Precedent note 2, at 110-111; and Perry, The Meaning of a Precedent note 1, at
    • For two different approaches of this kind, see DWORKIN, The Meaning of a Precedent note 2, at 110-111; and Perry, The Meaning of a Precedent note 1, at 235.
    • For two different approaches of this kind , pp. 235
  • 17
    • 85022429628 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For two different approaches of this kind note 14, at 469-471, though Schauer's proposal is more closely tied to Eisenberg's account, For two different approaches of this kind note 3, of the common law.
    • This is derived from Schauer, For two different approaches of this kind note 14, at 469-471, though Schauer's proposal is more closely tied to Eisenberg's account, For two different approaches of this kind note 3, of the common law.
    • This is derived from Schauer
  • 18
    • 85022435788 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is derived from Schauer note 3, at 188, 187. Raz qualifies the later statement by saying that a modified rule “can usually be justified only be reasoning very similar to that justifying the original rule” (emphasis added), but it is unclear what situations this covers.
    • The quotes are from RAZ, This is derived from Schauer note 3, at 188, 187. Raz qualifies the later statement by saying that a modified rule “can usually be justified only be reasoning very similar to that justifying the original rule” (emphasis added), but it is unclear what situations this covers.
    • The quotes are from RAZ
  • 19
    • 0040013283 scopus 로고
    • this makes the view quite similar to the tradition which holds that distinguishing is simply a case of reinterpretation-a tradition rejected by RAZ, The quotes are from RAZ note 3, at
    • As noted by N. SIMMONDS, THE DECLINE OF JURIDICAL REASON 112-114 (1984), this makes the view quite similar to the tradition which holds that distinguishing is simply a case of reinterpretation-a tradition rejected by RAZ, The quotes are from RAZ note 3, at 183-185.
    • (1984) THE DECLINE OF JURIDICAL REASON 112-114 , pp. 183-185
    • SIMMONDS, N.1
  • 21
    • 85022424006 scopus 로고
    • (No.2) 1 WLR 783 (Queen's Bench Division). I do not mean that this is a better rationale, merely that the courts have abandoned the earlier rationale.
    • See Robert Goff J's judgment in BP Exploration v. Hunt (No.2) (1979) 1 WLR 783 (Queen's Bench Division). I do not mean that this is a better rationale, merely that the courts have abandoned the earlier rationale.
    • (1979) Robert Goff J's judgment in BP Exploration v. Hunt
  • 23
    • 85022406897 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This provides a simpler explanation for the way principles are treated than Perry's argument that while courts are bound by the principles the precedent court relied upon note 3, at 187; cf. Alexander, This provides a simpler explanation for the way principles are treated than Perry's argument that while courts are bound by the principles the precedent court relied upon note 5, at 42-44. The clearest example of precedent operating on the facts reported in the case rather than the actual facts is striking out applications, where the court decides that the plaintiff's allegations, even were they to be proved, do not disclose a cause of action.
    • This explains the judicial practice noted by RAZ, This provides a simpler explanation for the way principles are treated than Perry's argument that while courts are bound by the principles the precedent court relied upon note 3, at 187; cf. Alexander, This provides a simpler explanation for the way principles are treated than Perry's argument that while courts are bound by the principles the precedent court relied upon note 5, at 42-44. The clearest example of precedent operating on the facts reported in the case rather than the actual facts is striking out applications, where the court decides that the plaintiff's allegations, even were they to be proved, do not disclose a cause of action.
    • This explains the judicial practice noted by RAZ
  • 24
    • 85022402858 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The class of cases with identical facts is an empty set in reality; and in any case it leaves the problem of explaining how all those other “rule-applying” situations manage to change the law.
    • Nor is it a response to this point to say that there could be a case with identical facts that did not have this effect. The class of cases with identical facts is an empty set in reality; and in any case it leaves the problem of explaining how all those other “rule-applying” situations manage to change the law.
    • Nor is it a response to this point to say that there could be a case with identical facts that did not have this effect
  • 25
    • 85022451142 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nor is it a response to this point to say that there could be a case with identical facts that did not have this effect. note 5, at 44-45, except that the reason-based view of precedent is not a hybrid using rules but a unified account of case-by-case decisionmaking.
    • The role of the ratio might suggest some affinity with Alexander's taxonomy of rule/result hybrid views of precedent, Nor is it a response to this point to say that there could be a case with identical facts that did not have this effect. note 5, at 44-45, except that the reason-based view of precedent is not a hybrid using rules but a unified account of case-by-case decisionmaking.
    • The role of the ratio might suggest some affinity with Alexander's taxonomy of rule/result hybrid views of precedent
  • 26
    • 85022377514 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The role of the ratio might suggest some affinity with Alexander's taxonomy of rule/result hybrid views of precedent note 14, at 372; Moore, The role of the ratio might suggest some affinity with Alexander's taxonomy of rule/result hybrid views of precedent note 2, at 185-186; Perry, The role of the ratio might suggest some affinity with Alexander's taxonomy of rule/result hybrid views of precedent note 1, at 235-237; Schauer, The role of the ratio might suggest some affinity with Alexander's taxonomy of rule/result hybrid views of precedent note 14, at
    • Contrary to a common objection; Simpson, The role of the ratio might suggest some affinity with Alexander's taxonomy of rule/result hybrid views of precedent note 14, at 372; Moore, The role of the ratio might suggest some affinity with Alexander's taxonomy of rule/result hybrid views of precedent note 2, at 185-186; Perry, The role of the ratio might suggest some affinity with Alexander's taxonomy of rule/result hybrid views of precedent note 1, at 235-237; Schauer, The role of the ratio might suggest some affinity with Alexander's taxonomy of rule/result hybrid views of precedent note 14, at 455.
    • Contrary to a common objection; Simpson , pp. 455
  • 28
    • 85022429542 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • by contrast, legislative acts such as Bills of Attainder.
    • Note, by contrast, legislative acts such as Bills of Attainder.
    • Note
  • 29
    • 85022401968 scopus 로고
    • see RAZ, Note note 3, at 16-19; J. Raz, Facing Up, 62 S. CAL. L. REV. 1153-1235, at 1160-1162. On exclusionary reasons, see RAZ, Note note 7, at 35-48, 73-84, 178-99; Raz, Facing Up, at
    • On protected reasons, see RAZ, Note note 3, at 16-19; J. Raz, Facing Up, 62 S. CAL. L. REV. 1153-1235 (1989), at 1160-1162. On exclusionary reasons, see RAZ, Note note 7, at 35-48, 73-84, 178-99; Raz, Facing Up, at 1154-79.
    • (1989) On protected reasons , pp. 1154-1179
  • 30
    • 85022436019 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • at 188-89; SCHAUER, My understanding is that Raz claims that rules are general protected reasons, not that all general protected reasons are, ipso facto, rules. note 5, at 187. The power to overrule is even more limited in operation.
    • RAZ, My understanding is that Raz claims that rules are general protected reasons, not that all general protected reasons are, ipso facto, rules. note 3, at 188-89; SCHAUER, My understanding is that Raz claims that rules are general protected reasons, not that all general protected reasons are, ipso facto, rules. note 5, at 187. The power to overrule is even more limited in operation.
    • My understanding is that Raz claims that rules are general protected reasons, not that all general protected reasons are, ipso facto, rules. note 3
    • RAZ1
  • 31
    • 85022390182 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This may help to explain the phenomenon of “jagged” development in common-law doctrine discussed by EISENBERG, My understanding is that Raz claims that rules are general protected reasons, not that all general protected reasons are, ipso facto, rules. note 3 note 3, at
    • Of course, courts sometimes rationalize a distinction with arguments they would not give were there not a precedent blocking their preferred argument. This may help to explain the phenomenon of “jagged” development in common-law doctrine discussed by EISENBERG, My understanding is that Raz claims that rules are general protected reasons, not that all general protected reasons are, ipso facto, rules. note 3 note 3, at 70-74.
    • Of course, courts sometimes rationalize a distinction with arguments they would not give were there not a precedent blocking their preferred argument , pp. 70-74
  • 32
    • 85022401332 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • cf. Alexander, Of course, courts sometimes rationalize a distinction with arguments they would not give were there not a precedent blocking their preferred argument. note 5, at 34-37. They determine the strength of the reason provided by the ratio that has to be defeated and consider whether a purported distinction provides either (a) a better reason than one already rejected, or (b) a different type of reason.
    • This explains how later courts can make decisions on the merits of distinguishing even when they disagree with the outcome of the precedent case; cf. Alexander, Of course, courts sometimes rationalize a distinction with arguments they would not give were there not a precedent blocking their preferred argument. note 5, at 34-37. They determine the strength of the reason provided by the ratio that has to be defeated and consider whether a purported distinction provides either (a) a better reason than one already rejected, or (b) a different type of reason.
    • This explains how later courts can make decisions on the merits of distinguishing even when they disagree with the outcome of the precedent case
  • 34
    • 85022363041 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Historically, some areas of the common law have also become more rule-like due to the authority of certain texts, such as Hale's Pleas of the Crown, being used in preference to the (relatively inaccessible) cases. note 14, and G. Postema, Philosophy of the Common Law, in OXFORD HANDBOOK OF JURISPRUDENCE AND PHILOSOPHY OF LAW (Coleman & Shapiro, eds., ). Simpson's suggestion, Historically, some areas of the common law have also become more rule-like due to the authority of certain texts, such as Hale's Pleas of the Crown, being used in preference to the (relatively inaccessible) cases. note 14, at 373-376, that the common law was a system of customary law, however, is open to criticism if it is taken to mean that the common law was based on convention; see Perry, Historically, some areas of the common law have also become more rule-like due to the authority of certain texts, such as Hale's Pleas of the Crown, being used in preference to the (relatively inaccessible) cases. note 1, at
    • As has been emphasized by Simpson, Historically, some areas of the common law have also become more rule-like due to the authority of certain texts, such as Hale's Pleas of the Crown, being used in preference to the (relatively inaccessible) cases. note 14, and G. Postema, Philosophy of the Common Law, in OXFORD HANDBOOK OF JURISPRUDENCE AND PHILOSOPHY OF LAW (Coleman & Shapiro, eds., 2002). Simpson's suggestion, Historically, some areas of the common law have also become more rule-like due to the authority of certain texts, such as Hale's Pleas of the Crown, being used in preference to the (relatively inaccessible) cases. note 14, at 373-376, that the common law was a system of customary law, however, is open to criticism if it is taken to mean that the common law was based on convention; see Perry, Historically, some areas of the common law have also become more rule-like due to the authority of certain texts, such as Hale's Pleas of the Crown, being used in preference to the (relatively inaccessible) cases. note 1, at 253-254.
    • (2002) As has been emphasized by Simpson , pp. 253-254
  • 36
    • 85022373540 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Prior to the Renaissance and the rise of printing, the consensus seems to have been based on the profession's collective understanding of the law; later, it became the profession's collective understanding of the extant case law. note 7, at
    • This aspect of normative powers is highlighted by RAZ, Prior to the Renaissance and the rise of printing, the consensus seems to have been based on the profession's collective understanding of the law; later, it became the profession's collective understanding of the extant case law. note 7, at 98-104.
    • This aspect of normative powers is highlighted by RAZ , pp. 98-104


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.