-
1
-
-
84890581447
-
-
The well-known text is by Giovanni Pico della Mirandola, Oration on the Dignity of Man, trans. A. Robert Caponigri (Washington, D.C.: Regency Gateway, 1956)
-
The well-known text is by Giovanni Pico della Mirandola, Oration on the Dignity of Man, trans. A. Robert Caponigri (Washington, D.C.: Regency Gateway, 1956).
-
-
-
-
2
-
-
84890710630
-
-
But since the essays can also profitably be read separately and out of order, I leave intact a few minor redundancies in the argument, especially between chapters 1 and 8
-
But since the essays can also profitably be read separately and out of order, I leave intact a few minor redundancies in the argument, especially between chapters 1 and 8.
-
-
-
-
3
-
-
0009907154
-
Role Distance
-
See, in Encounters: Two Studies in the Sociology of Interaction, Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill
-
See Erving Goffman, "Role Distance," in Encounters: Two Studies in the Sociology of Interaction (Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1961), 83.
-
(1961)
, pp. 83
-
-
Goffman, E.1
-
4
-
-
0004136440
-
Community and Society
-
See, trans. and ed. C. P. Loomis, East Lansing: Michigan State University Press
-
See Ferdinand Tönnies, Community and Society, trans. and ed. C. P. Loomis (East Lansing: Michigan State University Press, 1957).
-
(1957)
-
-
Tönnies, F.1
-
5
-
-
0003639991
-
Being and Nothingness
-
This expression is borrowed from, trans. Hazel E. Barnes, New York: Simon and Schuster
-
This expression is borrowed from Jean-Paul Sartre, Being and Nothingness, trans. Hazel E. Barnes (New York: Simon and Schuster, 1966), 86.
-
(1966)
, pp. 86
-
-
Sartre, J.-P.1
-
6
-
-
84936068266
-
Law's Empire
-
Cambridge: Harvard University Press
-
Ronald M. Dworkin, Law's Empire (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1986).
-
(1986)
-
-
Dworkin, R.M.1
-
7
-
-
0001902326
-
Law as Interpretation
-
See, in The Politics of Interpretation, ed. W. J. T. Mitchell, Chicago: University of Chicago Press
-
See Ronald M. Dworkin, "Law as Interpretation," in The Politics of Interpretation, ed. W. J. T. Mitchell (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1983), 287.
-
(1983)
, pp. 287
-
-
Dworkin, R.M.1
-
8
-
-
0003527892
-
Communication and the Evolution of Society
-
See, trans. Thomas McCarthy, Boston: Beacon Press, chap. 1, and The Theory of Communicative Action, trans. Thomas McCarthy (Boston: Beacon Press, 1981), chap. 3
-
See Jürgen Habermas, Communication and the Evolution of Society, trans. Thomas McCarthy (Boston: Beacon Press, 1979), chap. 1, and The Theory of Communicative Action, trans. Thomas McCarthy (Boston: Beacon Press, 1981), chap. 3.
-
(1979)
-
-
Habermas, J.1
-
9
-
-
0004213898
-
Taking Rights Seriously
-
See, Cambridge: Harvard University Press, chap. 4; Dworkin, Law's Empire
-
See Ronald M. Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1977), chap. 4; Dworkin, Law's Empire.
-
(1977)
-
-
Dworkin, R.M.1
-
10
-
-
0004166519
-
Law's Empire
-
Dworkin, Law's Empire, 46-49.
-
-
-
Dworkin1
-
11
-
-
0004197812
-
Expression and Meaning
-
New York: Cambridge University Press
-
John R. Searle, Expression and Meaning (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1979), 4-5.
-
(1979)
, pp. 4-5
-
-
Searle, J.R.1
-
12
-
-
0041144970
-
Courts on Trial: Myth and Reality in American Justice
-
Such problems are discussed, for example, in, Princeton:Princeton University Press, chap. 6
-
Such problems are discussed, for example, in Jerome Frank, Courts on Trial: Myth and Reality in American Justice (Princeton:Princeton University Press, 1949), chap. 6.
-
(1949)
-
-
Frank, J.1
-
13
-
-
84919701548
-
The Phenomenology of Rights-Consciousness and the Pact of the Withdrawn Selves
-
For a similar conception of the state and its relation to the self see
-
For a similar conception of the state and its relation to the self see Peter Gabel, "The Phenomenology of Rights-Consciousness and the Pact of the Withdrawn Selves," Texas Law Review 62 (1984): 1563, at 1563.
-
(1984)
Texas Law Review
, vol.62
, pp. 1563
-
-
Gabel, P.1
-
14
-
-
0004191356
-
The Quest for Community
-
There is of course considerable literature warning against the fallacy and the danger of conceiving of the state in excessively communal terms. A well-known example is, New York: Oxford University Press
-
There is of course considerable literature warning against the fallacy and the danger of conceiving of the state in excessively communal terms. A well-known example is Robert Nisbet, The Quest for Community (New York: Oxford University Press, 1953).
-
(1953)
-
-
Nisbet, R.1
-
15
-
-
0009295451
-
The Supreme Court, 1978 Term-Foreword:The Forms of Justice
-
See
-
See Owen M. Fiss, "The Supreme Court, 1978 Term-Foreword:The Forms of Justice," Harvard Law Review 93 (1979): 1.
-
(1979)
Harvard Law Review
, vol.93
, pp. 1
-
-
Fiss, O.M.1
-
16
-
-
34250106199
-
Still Wrong after All These Years
-
Stanley Fish, "Still Wrong after All These Years," Law and Philosophy 6 (1987): 401, at 412.
-
(1987)
Law and Philosophy
, vol.6
, pp. 401
-
-
Fish, S.1
-
17
-
-
65349113191
-
It All Comes Out in the End: Judicial Rhetoric and the Strategy of Reassurance
-
Wojciech Sadurski, "It All Comes Out in the End: Judicial Rhetoric and the Strategy of Reassurance," Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 7 (1987): 258.
-
(1987)
Oxford Journal of Legal Studies
, vol.7
, pp. 258
-
-
Sadurski, W.1
-
18
-
-
84928222314
-
The Pathological Perspective and the First Amendment
-
(arguing that courts should interpret the First Amendment to provide maximum protection when intolerance of unorthodox ideas is prevalent and government is likely to stifle dissent)
-
Vincent Blasi, "The Pathological Perspective and the First Amendment," Columbia Law Review 85 (1985): 449 (arguing that courts should interpret the First Amendment to provide maximum protection when intolerance of unorthodox ideas is prevalent and government is likely to stifle dissent).
-
(1985)
Columbia Law Review
, vol.85
, pp. 449
-
-
Blasi, V.1
-
19
-
-
84890650163
-
Why the First Amendment Should Not Be Interpreted from the Pathological Perspective: A Response to Professor Blasi
-
(advocating that judges should consider legal argument, rather than a theory of societal good, in deciding cases)
-
George C. Christie, "Why the First Amendment Should Not Be Interpreted from the Pathological Perspective: A Response to Professor Blasi," Duke Law Journal 1986:683 (advocating that judges should consider legal argument, rather than a theory of societal good, in deciding cases);
-
(1986)
Duke Law Journal
, pp. 683
-
-
Christie, G.C.1
-
20
-
-
84890623813
-
The Role of Strategic Reasoning in Constitutional Interpretation: In Defense of the Pathological Perspective
-
(advocating the use of strategic reasoning to safeguard "core" constitutional commitments in First Amendment cases)
-
Vincent Blasi, "The Role of Strategic Reasoning in Constitutional Interpretation: In Defense of the Pathological Perspective," Duke Law Journal 1986:696 (advocating the use of strategic reasoning to safeguard "core" constitutional commitments in First Amendment cases).
-
(1986)
Duke Law Journal
, pp. 696
-
-
Blasi, V.1
-
21
-
-
0003323192
-
The Supreme Court, 1982-Foreword: Nomos and Narrative
-
For a compelling expression of a vision of law and of the judicial role that accentuates their coerciveness see, and "Violence and the Word," Yale Law Journal 95 (1986):
-
For a compelling expression of a vision of law and of the judicial role that accentuates their coerciveness see Robert M. Cover, "The Supreme Court, 1982-Foreword: Nomos and Narrative," Harvard Law Review 97 (1983): 4, and "Violence and the Word," Yale Law Journal 95 (1986): 1601.
-
(1983)
Harvard Law Review
, vol.97
, pp. 4
-
-
Cover, R.M.1
-
22
-
-
84935146771
-
Roll Over, Beethoven
-
Such a temptation is one of the themes in
-
Such a temptation is one of the themes in Peter Gabel and Duncan Kennedy, "Roll Over, Beethoven," Stanford Law Review 36 (1984): 1.
-
(1984)
Stanford Law Review
, vol.36
, pp. 1
-
-
Gabel, P.1
Kennedy, D.2
-
23
-
-
0004166519
-
Law's Empire
-
See
-
See Dworkin, Law's Empire, 228-38.
-
-
-
Dworkin1
-
24
-
-
0003516637
-
General Theory of Law and State
-
trans. Anders Wedberg, Cambridge: Harvard University Press
-
Hans Kelsen, General Theory of Law and State, trans. Anders Wedberg (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1945), 6.
-
(1945)
, pp. 6
-
-
Kelsen, H.1
-
25
-
-
0010278205
-
Directives and Norms
-
For a similar view see, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, and On Law and Justice (Berkeley and Los Angeles:University of California Press, 1959), 33
-
For a similar view see Alf Ross, Directives and Norms (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1968), 91, and On Law and Justice (Berkeley and Los Angeles:University of California Press, 1959), 33.
-
(1968)
, pp. 91
-
-
Ross, A.1
-
26
-
-
0004220262
-
The Concept of Law
-
Oxford: Clarendon Press
-
H. L. A. Hart, The Concept of Law (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1961), 39.
-
(1961)
, pp. 39
-
-
Hart, H.L.A.1
-
27
-
-
0004237063
-
Practical Reason and Norms
-
See, London: Hutchinson
-
See Joseph Raz, Practical Reason and Norms (London: Hutchinson, 1975), 50;
-
(1975)
, pp. 50
-
-
Raz, J.1
-
28
-
-
0010278205
-
Directives and Norms
-
Ross, Directives and Norms, 107;
-
-
-
Ross1
-
29
-
-
0004257139
-
Norm and Action
-
New York: Humanities
-
Georg H. Von Wright, Norm and Action (New York: Humanities, 1963), 70-92.
-
(1963)
, pp. 70-92
-
-
Von Wright, G.H.1
-
30
-
-
0004237063
-
Practical Reason and Norms
-
Compare Raz, Practical Reason and Norms, 105, 148;
-
, vol.105
, pp. 148
-
-
Raz, C.1
-
31
-
-
0010278205
-
Directives and Norms
-
Ross, Directives and Norms, 113.
-
-
-
Ross1
-
32
-
-
0004220262
-
The Concept of Law
-
But compare Hart, noting the ambiguity of the statement that a law is "addressed" to someone
-
But compare Hart, The Concept of Law, 21-22, noting the ambiguity of the statement that a law is "addressed" to someone.
-
-
-
-
33
-
-
0004287704
-
Pure Theory of Law
-
On practical conflict, see, Berkeley and Los Angeles University of California Press
-
On practical conflict, see Hans Kelsen, Pure Theory of Law (Berkeley and Los Angeles University of California Press, 1967), 25-26;
-
(1967)
, pp. 25-26
-
-
Kelsen, H.1
-
34
-
-
0004257139
-
Norm and Action
-
Von Wright, Norm and Action, 144-52.
-
-
-
Wright, V.1
-
35
-
-
0004057548
-
A History of the Criminal Law of England
-
London: Macmillan
-
James Fitzjames Stephen, A History of the Criminal Law of England (London: Macmillan, 1883), 2:107.
-
(1883)
, vol.2
, pp. 107
-
-
Stephen, J.F.1
-
36
-
-
84890643127
-
-
See Model Penal Code sec. 2.09 comment (Tent. Draft No. 10, 1960)
-
See Model Penal Code sec. 2.09 comment (Tent. Draft No. 10, 1960);
-
-
-
-
37
-
-
0004273012
-
Rethinking Criminal Law
-
Boston: Little, Brown, sec. 10.3
-
George P. Fletcher, Rethinking Criminal Law (Boston: Little, Brown, 1978), sec. 10.3;
-
(1978)
-
-
Fletcher, G.P.1
-
38
-
-
0006299267
-
Handbook on Criminal Law
-
St. Paul: West
-
Wayne R. LaFave and Austin W. Scott Jr., Handbook on Criminal Law (St. Paul: West, 1972), sec. 49.
-
(1972)
, pp. 49
-
-
LaFave, W.R.1
Scott Jr, A.W.2
-
39
-
-
84890581486
-
-
See infra 71-73
-
See infra 71-73.
-
-
-
-
40
-
-
84890736458
-
-
See infra 48-52
-
See infra 48-52.
-
-
-
-
41
-
-
38949102539
-
Differentiation of Society
-
Professor Niklas Luhmann believes that, in general, some mode of selective communication is essential to modern societies: "Under conditions [of size and complexity] that exclude the actual interaction between all members of the society, the communication system needs selective intensifiers."
-
Professor Niklas Luhmann believes that, in general, some mode of selective communication is essential to modern societies: "Under conditions [of size and complexity] that exclude the actual interaction between all members of the society, the communication system needs selective intensifiers." Niklas Luhmann, "Differentiation of Society," Canadian Journal of Sociology 2 (1977): 29, at 33.
-
(1977)
Canadian Journal of Sociology
, vol.2
, pp. 29
-
-
Luhmann, N.1
-
42
-
-
84890744660
-
-
For a discussion of specific strategies, see infra 48, 52-54, 57-62
-
For a discussion of specific strategies, see infra 48, 52-54, 57-62.
-
-
-
-
43
-
-
0003626537
-
The History of Sexuality
-
See, trans. Robert Hurley, New York: Pantheon
-
See Michel Foucault, The History of Sexuality, trans. Robert Hurley (New York: Pantheon, 1978).
-
(1978)
-
-
Foucault, M.1
-
44
-
-
0003053720
-
Interpretation and the Sciences of Man
-
For an excellent exposition of the view that radically distinguishes the methodology and expectations of the natural sciences from those of the human sciences, as well as for a discussion of the role of interpretation in the latter, see
-
For an excellent exposition of the view that radically distinguishes the methodology and expectations of the natural sciences from those of the human sciences, as well as for a discussion of the role of interpretation in the latter, see Charles Taylor, "Interpretation and the Sciences of Man," Review of Metaphysics 25 (1971): 3
-
(1971)
Review of Metaphysics
, vol.25
, pp. 3
-
-
Taylor, C.1
-
45
-
-
0042923057
-
Understanding in Human Science
-
"Understanding in Human Science," Review of Metaphysics 34 (1980): 25.
-
(1980)
Review of Metaphysics
, vol.34
, pp. 25
-
-
-
46
-
-
0042376653
-
The Individualization of Excusing Conditions
-
See generally
-
See generally George P. Fletcher, "The Individualization of Excusing Conditions," Southern California Law Review 47 (1974): 25.
-
(1974)
Southern California Law Review
, vol.47
, pp. 25
-
-
Fletcher, G.P.1
-
47
-
-
84890672747
-
-
See infra 62-67
-
See infra 62-67.
-
-
-
-
48
-
-
84890681847
-
Discretion to Disobey
-
Kadish and Kadish, Discretion to Disobey, 125.
-
-
-
Kadish1
Kadish2
-
49
-
-
0004273012
-
Rethinking Criminal Law
-
sec. 7.5.1, arguing that vagueness of justification and excuse defenses is acceptable on the ground that actors rarely plan the conduct that gives rise to such defenses
-
Compare Fletcher, Rethinking Criminal Law, sec. 7.5.1, arguing that vagueness of justification and excuse defenses is acceptable on the ground that actors rarely plan the conduct that gives rise to such defenses.
-
-
-
Fletcher, C.1
-
50
-
-
84890598638
-
Ann. sec
-
This aspect of the strategy of selective transmission is most pronounced when the criminal code delegates the definition of defenses entirely to the courts. See, e.g, West
-
This aspect of the strategy of selective transmission is most pronounced when the criminal code delegates the definition of defenses entirely to the courts. See, e.g., N.J. Stat. Ann. sec. 2C:3-2 (West 1982);
-
(1982)
, vol.2 C
, pp. 3-2
-
-
Stat, N.J.1
-
51
-
-
84890607630
-
New Jersey Criminal Law Revision Commission, Final Report: The New Jersey Penal Code
-
New Jersey Criminal Law Revision Commission, Final Report: The New Jersey Penal Code (1971), 2:80.
-
(1971)
, vol.2
, pp. 80
-
-
-
52
-
-
0041676721
-
Intolerable Conditions as a Defense to Prison Escapes
-
See Note, at 1126-28
-
See Note, "Intolerable Conditions as a Defense to Prison Escapes," UCLA Law Review 26 (1979): 1126, at 1126-28.
-
(1979)
UCLA Law Review
, vol.26
, pp. 1126
-
-
-
53
-
-
84890676642
-
-
See, e.g., People v. Lovercamp, 43 Cal. App. 3d 823, 118 Cal. Rptr. 110 (1974)
-
See, e.g., People v. Lovercamp, 43 Cal. App. 3d 823, 118 Cal. Rptr. 110 (1974);
-
-
-
-
54
-
-
84890726943
-
-
Johnson v. State, 379 A.2d 1129 (Del. 1977)
-
Johnson v. State, 379 A.2d 1129 (Del. 1977);
-
-
-
-
55
-
-
84890695713
-
-
State v. Boleyn, 328 So. 2d 95 (La. 1976); People v. Hocquard, 64 Mich. App
-
State v. Boleyn, 328 So. 2d 95 (La. 1976); People v. Hocquard, 64 Mich. App.
-
-
-
-
56
-
-
84890670801
-
-
43 Cal. App. 3d 823, 118 Cal. Rptr. 110 (1974)
-
43 Cal. App. 3d 823, 118 Cal. Rptr. 110 (1974).
-
-
-
-
57
-
-
84890669323
-
-
52 Ill. 2d 231, 287 N.E.2d 670 (1972)
-
52 Ill. 2d 231, 287 N.E.2d 670 (1972).
-
-
-
-
58
-
-
84890671141
-
-
See, e.g., D'Aquino v. United States, 192 F.2d 338, 357-65 (9th Cir. 1951) (treason)
-
See, e.g., D'Aquino v. United States, 192 F.2d 338, 357-65 (9th Cir. 1951) (treason);
-
-
-
-
59
-
-
84890730412
-
-
Ross v. State, 169 Ind. 388, 82 N.E. 781 (1907) (arson)
-
Ross v. State, 169 Ind. 388, 82 N.E. 781 (1907) (arson);
-
-
-
-
60
-
-
84890680179
-
-
Nall v. Commonwealth, 208 Ky. 700, 271 S.W. 1059 (1925) (burglary)
-
Nall v. Commonwealth, 208 Ky. 700, 271 S.W. 1059 (1925) (burglary);
-
-
-
-
61
-
-
84890603830
-
-
State v. St. Clair, 262 S.W.2d 25 (Mo. 1953) (robbery)
-
State v. St. Clair, 262 S.W.2d 25 (Mo. 1953) (robbery);
-
-
-
-
62
-
-
84890675959
-
-
State v. Ellis, 232 Or. 70, 374 P.2d 461 (1962) (kidnapping)
-
State v. Ellis, 232 Or. 70, 374 P.2d 461 (1962) (kidnapping).
-
-
-
-
63
-
-
84890573995
-
-
Duress was, however, allowed as a defense to perjury in, for example, Hall v. State, 136 Fla. 644, 679-84, 187 So. 392, 407-9 (1939), and more recently in the English case of Regina v. Hudson, [1971] 2 All E.R. 244 (C.A.)
-
Duress was, however, allowed as a defense to perjury in, for example, Hall v. State, 136 Fla. 644, 679-84, 187 So. 392, 407-9 (1939), and more recently in the English case of Regina v. Hudson, [1971] 2 All E.R. 244 (C.A.).
-
-
-
-
64
-
-
84890603478
-
-
Commonwealth v. Chermansky, 430 Pa. 170, 174, 242 A.2d 237, 240 (1968), But compare Commonwealth v. Klein, 372 Mass. 823, 363 N.E.2d 1313 (1977), which declined to follow an act-at-yourperil rule
-
Commonwealth v. Chermansky, 430 Pa. 170, 174, 242 A.2d 237, 240 (1968). But compare Commonwealth v. Klein, 372 Mass. 823, 363 N.E.2d 1313 (1977), which declined to follow an act-at-yourperil rule.
-
-
-
-
65
-
-
84890631494
-
-
Model Penal Code sec. 3.06 comment 15 (Tent. Draft No. 8, 1958)
-
Model Penal Code sec. 3.06 comment 15 (Tent. Draft No. 8, 1958).
-
-
-
-
66
-
-
84890663574
-
-
12 Cal. 3d 470, 526 P.2d 241, 116 Cal. Rptr. 233 (1974)
-
12 Cal. 3d 470, 526 P.2d 241, 116 Cal. Rptr. 233 (1974).
-
-
-
-
67
-
-
84890727920
-
-
That society considers such an outcome beneficial is attested to by the considerable latitude given police in the use of deadly force against escaping felons and by the defense that ex hypothesi would have been available to Ceballos had he shot at the burglar himself
-
That society considers such an outcome beneficial is attested to by the considerable latitude given police in the use of deadly force against escaping felons and by the defense that ex hypothesi would have been available to Ceballos had he shot at the burglar himself.
-
-
-
-
68
-
-
84890710542
-
-
Ceballos, 12 Cal. 3d at 477, 526 P.2d at 244, 116 Cal. Rptr. at 236
-
Ceballos, 12 Cal. 3d at 477, 526 P.2d at 244, 116 Cal. Rptr. at 236.
-
-
-
-
69
-
-
84890618497
-
Almost the only knowledge of law possessed by many people is that ignorance of it is no excuse (ignorantia juris non excusat)
-
London: Stevens
-
"Almost the only knowledge of law possessed by many people is that ignorance of it is no excuse (ignorantia juris non excusat)." Glanville Williams, Textbook of Criminal Law (London: Stevens, 1978), 405.
-
(1978)
Textbook of Criminal Law
, pp. 405
-
-
-
70
-
-
84890644414
-
-
International Minerals, 402 U.S. at 564-65
-
International Minerals, 402 U.S. at 564-65;
-
-
-
-
71
-
-
84890646503
-
-
United States v. Freed, 401 U.S. 601, 609 (1970)
-
United States v. Freed, 401 U.S. 601, 609 (1970);
-
-
-
-
72
-
-
84890662766
-
-
Lambert v. California, 35 U.S. 225, 229 (1957)
-
Lambert v. California, 35 U.S. 225, 229 (1957);
-
-
-
-
73
-
-
84890697770
-
-
Reyes v. United States, 258 F.2d 774, 784 (9th Cir. 1958)
-
Reyes v. United States, 258 F.2d 774, 784 (9th Cir. 1958).
-
-
-
-
74
-
-
84890626171
-
-
Lambert, 355 U.S. at 229; Reyes, 258 F.2d at 784-85
-
Lambert, 355 U.S. at 229; Reyes, 258 F.2d at 784-85.
-
-
-
-
75
-
-
84890716633
-
-
State v. Sawyer, 95 Conn. 34, 110 A. 461 (1920)
-
State v. Sawyer, 95 Conn. 34, 110 A. 461 (1920);
-
-
-
-
76
-
-
84890703193
-
-
Long v. State, 44 Del. 262, 65 A.2d 489 (1949)
-
Long v. State, 44 Del. 262, 65 A.2d 489 (1949);
-
-
-
-
77
-
-
84890737090
-
-
State v. Collins, 15 Del. 536, 41 A. 144 (1894)
-
State v. Collins, 15 Del. 536, 41 A. 144 (1894).
-
-
-
-
78
-
-
84890603198
-
-
Hargrove v. United States, 67 F.2d 820 (5th Cir. 1933)
-
Hargrove v. United States, 67 F.2d 820 (5th Cir. 1933);
-
-
-
-
79
-
-
84890735574
-
-
Long, 44 Del. at 278-79, 65 A.2d at 497; Collins, 15 Del. at 539-40, 41 A. at 145
-
Long, 44 Del. at 278-79, 65 A.2d at 497; Collins, 15 Del. at 539-40, 41 A. at 145.
-
-
-
-
80
-
-
0003865211
-
Criminal Law-the General Part
-
For a detailed discussion of this distinction, see, 2d ed, London: Stevens
-
For a detailed discussion of this distinction, see Glanville L. Williams, Criminal Law-the General Part, 2d ed. (London: Stevens, 1961), secs. 106-17.
-
(1961)
, pp. 106-117
-
-
Williams, G.L.1
-
81
-
-
84890714882
-
-
Lambert v. California, 355 U.S. 225, 228-29 (1957)
-
Lambert v. California, 355 U.S. 225, 228-29 (1957);
-
-
-
-
82
-
-
84890592790
-
-
compare Hayes v. United States, 258 F.2d 774, 784 (8th Cir. 1958) (distinguishing Lambert on the ground, inter alia, that failure to register while crossing the border is not a mere omission)
-
compare Hayes v. United States, 258 F.2d 774, 784 (8th Cir. 1958) (distinguishing Lambert on the ground, inter alia, that failure to register while crossing the border is not a mere omission).
-
-
-
-
83
-
-
0004293083
-
A Fragment on Government
-
See
-
See Bentham, A Fragment on Government, 430.
-
-
-
Bentham1
-
84
-
-
84890743680
-
-
The possibility of conflict is eliminated, of course, only with respect to conventional morality or to whatever other moral system the law embodies
-
The possibility of conflict is eliminated, of course, only with respect to conventional morality or to whatever other moral system the law embodies.
-
-
-
-
85
-
-
0010548576
-
The Path of the Law
-
See, in Collected Legal Papers, New York: Harcourt Brace
-
See Oliver Wendell Holmes, "The Path of the Law," in Collected Legal Papers (New York: Harcourt Brace, 1920), 167, at 169-79.
-
(1920)
, vol.167
, pp. 169-179
-
-
Holmes, O.W.1
-
86
-
-
0004237063
-
Practical Reason and Norms
-
This analysis presupposes the view that the normativity of law does not depend on its coerciveness. For an example of this view, see, compare Finnis, Natural Law, 346-47, on the controversy that evolved in the Wfteenth through seventeenth centuries around the "purely penal law theory" of the nature of the obligation imposed by criminal law
-
This analysis presupposes the view that the normativity of law does not depend on its coerciveness. For an example of this view, see Raz, Practical Reason and Norms, 157-61; compare Finnis, Natural Law, 346-47, on the controversy that evolved in the Wfteenth through seventeenth centuries around the "purely penal law theory" of the nature of the obligation imposed by criminal law.
-
-
-
Raz1
-
87
-
-
84890724956
-
-
The safe-side principle makes sense only when the agent is confronted with a single moral duty that constrains the pursuit of her self-interest. It is obviously of no help in resolving a conflict between competing moral duties. The criminal law, however, typically deals with the former situation
-
The safe-side principle makes sense only when the agent is confronted with a single moral duty that constrains the pursuit of her self-interest. It is obviously of no help in resolving a conflict between competing moral duties. The criminal law, however, typically deals with the former situation.
-
-
-
-
88
-
-
0004057243
-
Private Property and the Constitution
-
On the broad implications of the distinction between ordinary and specialized language in the law, see, New Haven: Yale University Press
-
On the broad implications of the distinction between ordinary and specialized language in the law, see Bruce Ackerman, Private Property and the Constitution (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1977), 10-20 and passim.
-
(1977)
, pp. 10-20
-
-
Ackerman, B.1
-
89
-
-
84890653175
-
-
2 L.R.-Cr. Cas. Res. 154 (1875)
-
2 L.R.-Cr. Cas. Res. 154 (1875).
-
-
-
-
90
-
-
84890778281
-
-
Offences Against the Person Act, 1861, 24 and 25 Vict., chap. 100, sec. 55
-
Offences Against the Person Act, 1861, 24 and 25 Vict., chap. 100, sec. 55.
-
-
-
-
91
-
-
33645559809
-
An Inquiry into Criminal Guilt
-
See, e.g, London:Sweet and Maxwell
-
See, e.g., Peter Brett, An Inquiry into Criminal Guilt (London:Sweet and Maxwell, 1963), 149;
-
(1963)
, pp. 149
-
-
Brett, P.1
-
92
-
-
11744345131
-
Mens Rea in Statutory Offences
-
London: Macmillan
-
J. Edwards, Mens Rea in Statutory Offences (London: Macmillan, 1955), 58-63;
-
(1955)
, pp. 58-63
-
-
Edwards, J.1
-
93
-
-
0004273012
-
Rethinking Criminal Law
-
sec. 9.3.3
-
Fletcher, Rethinking Criminal Law, sec. 9.3.3, pp. 723-27;
-
-
-
Fletcher1
-
94
-
-
84890779181
-
Criminal Law-the General Part
-
Wil1liams, Criminal Law-the General Part, sec. 69, pp. 185-99.
-
, vol.69
, pp. 185-199
-
-
Wil1liams1
-
95
-
-
84890713818
-
-
2 L.R.-Cr. Cas. Res. at 174-75
-
2 L.R.-Cr. Cas. Res. at 174-75.
-
-
-
-
96
-
-
84890598692
-
Criminal Law-the General Part
-
Williams, Criminal Law-the General Part, sec. 83, p. 241.
-
, vol.83
, pp. 241
-
-
Williams1
-
97
-
-
26444572832
-
Criminal Responsibility
-
(book review)
-
Graham Hughes, "Criminal Responsibility" (book review), Stanford Law Review 16 (1964): 470, 480-81.
-
(1964)
Stanford Law Review
, vol.16
, Issue.470
, pp. 480-481
-
-
Hughes, G.1
-
98
-
-
84890763275
-
-
61 Cal. 2d 529, 393 P.2d 673, 39 Cal. Rptr. 361 (1964)
-
61 Cal. 2d 529, 393 P.2d 673, 39 Cal. Rptr. 361 (1964).
-
-
-
-
99
-
-
84890577300
-
-
Lanzetta v. New Jersey, 306 U.S. 451, 453 (1939)
-
Lanzetta v. New Jersey, 306 U.S. 451, 453 (1939).
-
-
-
-
100
-
-
84890592076
-
-
Giacco v. Pennsylvania, 38 U.S. 399, 402-3 (1966)
-
Giacco v. Pennsylvania, 38 U.S. 399, 402-3 (1966).
-
-
-
-
101
-
-
84890635839
-
-
Winters v. New York, 333 U.S. 507, 517-20 (1948)
-
Winters v. New York, 333 U.S. 507, 517-20 (1948);
-
-
-
-
102
-
-
84890641830
-
-
Fox v. Washington, 236 U.S. 273 (1915)
-
Fox v. Washington, 236 U.S. 273 (1915).
-
-
-
-
103
-
-
84890740840
-
-
United States v. National Dairy Prods. Corp., 372 U.S. 29, 36-37 (1963)
-
United States v. National Dairy Prods. Corp., 372 U.S. 29, 36-37 (1963);
-
-
-
-
104
-
-
84890644740
-
-
Boyce Motor Lines v. United States, 342 U.S. 337, 342 (1952)
-
Boyce Motor Lines v. United States, 342 U.S. 337, 342 (1952).
-
-
-
-
105
-
-
84890737747
-
Void-for-Vagueness Doctrine
-
See Rose v. Locke, 423 U.S. 48, 54-55 (1975) (Brennan, J., dissenting); Franklin v. State, 257 So. 2d 21, 23 (Fla. 1971)
-
See Rose v. Locke, 423 U.S. 48, 54-55 (1975) (Brennan, J., dissenting); Franklin v. State, 257 So. 2d 21, 23 (Fla. 1971); "Void-for-Vagueness Doctrine," 73-74.
-
-
-
-
106
-
-
84890612901
-
Handbook on Criminal Law
-
(footnotes omitted). For similar criticisms of the reliance on scienter to cure vagueness, see Boyce Motor Lines v. United States, 342 U.S. 337, 345 (Jackson, J., dissenting)
-
LaFave and Scott, Handbook on Criminal Law, sec. 11, p. 86 (footnotes omitted). For similar criticisms of the reliance on scienter to cure vagueness, see Boyce Motor Lines v. United States, 342 U.S. 337, 345 (1952) (Jackson, J., dissenting);
-
(1952)
, vol.11
, pp. 86
-
-
LaFave1
Scott2
-
107
-
-
78649528665
-
Unconstitutional Uncertainty-an Appraisal
-
Rex Collings, "Unconstitutional Uncertainty-an Appraisal," Cornell Law Quarterly 40 (1955): 195, 227-31.
-
(1955)
Cornell Law Quarterly
, vol.40
, Issue.195
, pp. 227-231
-
-
Collings, R.1
-
108
-
-
84890728690
-
-
See, e.g., Boyce Motor Lines v. United States, 34 U.S. 337, 345 (1957) (Jackson, J., dissenting): "[T]he knowledge requisite to knowing violation of a statute is factual knowledge as distinguished from knowledge of the law." 102. Rose v. Locke, 423 U.S. 48, 50 (1975)
-
See, e.g., Boyce Motor Lines v. United States, 34 U.S. 337, 345 (1957) (Jackson, J., dissenting): "[T]he knowledge requisite to knowing violation of a statute is factual knowledge as distinguished from knowledge of the law." 102. Rose v. Locke, 423 U.S. 48, 50 (1975).
-
-
-
-
109
-
-
84890607482
-
-
Franklin v. State, 257 So. 2d 21 (Fla. 1971)
-
Franklin v. State, 257 So. 2d 21 (Fla. 1971).
-
-
-
-
110
-
-
0040390944
-
Ruthlessness in Public Life
-
See, in Mortal Questions, New York: Cambridge University Press
-
See Thomas Nagel, "Ruthlessness in Public Life," in Mortal Questions (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1979), 75;
-
(1979)
, pp. 75
-
-
Nagel, T.1
-
111
-
-
84882786545
-
Moral Luck
-
Williams, "Moral Luck," 547;
-
-
-
Williams1
-
112
-
-
7444256978
-
Political Action: The Problem of Dirty Hands
-
in War and Moral Responsibility, ed. Marshall Cohen, Thomas Nagel, and Thomas Scanlon, Princeton: Princeton University Press
-
Walzer, "Political Action: The Problem of Dirty Hands," in War and Moral Responsibility, ed. Marshall Cohen, Thomas Nagel, and Thomas Scanlon (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1974), 62;
-
(1974)
, pp. 62
-
-
Walzer1
-
113
-
-
0009211086
-
Truth and Politics
-
see also, in Philosophy, Politics, and Society, ed. P. Laslett and W. Runcirnan, 3d ser, New York:Barnes and Noble
-
see also Hannah Arendt, "Truth and Politics," in Philosophy, Politics, and Society, ed. P. Laslett and W. Runcirnan, 3d ser. (New York:Barnes and Noble, 1967), 104;
-
(1967)
, pp. 104
-
-
Arendt, H.1
-
114
-
-
0001845081
-
Politics as a Vocation
-
in From Max Weber: Essays in Sociology, ed. and trans. H. H. Gerth and C. Wright Mills, New York: Oxford University Press, Dirty Hands is the title of Sartre's play that deals with this moral issue. See Jean-Paul Sartre, No Exit and Three Other Plays, trans. L. Abel (New York: Vintage, 1956)
-
Max Weber, "Politics as a Vocation," in From Max Weber: Essays in Sociology, ed. and trans. H. H. Gerth and C. Wright Mills (New York: Oxford University Press, 1946), 77. Dirty Hands is the title of Sartre's play that deals with this moral issue. See Jean-Paul Sartre, No Exit and Three Other Plays, trans. L. Abel (New York: Vintage, 1956).
-
(1946)
, pp. 77
-
-
Weber, M.1
-
115
-
-
84890617566
-
The Rule of Law and Its Virtue
-
in The Authority of Law (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1979), 214. In the following discussion, I rely primarily on the excellent analysis in this essay. Other valuable philosophical treatments of the rule of law can be found in Finnis
-
Joseph Raz, "The Rule of Law and Its Virtue," in The Authority of Law (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1979), 214. In the following discussion, I rely primarily on the excellent analysis in this essay. Other valuable philosophical treatments of the rule of law can be found in Finnis, Natural Law, 270-76;
-
Natural Law
, pp. 270-276
-
-
Raz, J.1
-
116
-
-
0004273196
-
The Morality of Law
-
New Haven: Yale University Press
-
Lon L. Fuller, The Morality of Law (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1964), 33-94;
-
(1964)
, pp. 33-94
-
-
Fuller, L.L.1
-
117
-
-
1842650613
-
The Principles of Politics
-
Oxford: Clarendon Press
-
J. R. Lucas, The Principles of Politics (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1966), 106-17;
-
(1966)
, pp. 106-117
-
-
Lucas, J.R.1
-
118
-
-
0004048289
-
A Theory of Justice
-
Cambridge: Harvard University Press
-
John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1971), 235-43.
-
(1971)
, pp. 235-243
-
-
Rawls, J.1
-
119
-
-
84890689307
-
Rule of Law
-
See
-
See Raz, "Rule of Law," 226.
-
-
-
Raz1
-
120
-
-
0004273196
-
The Morality of Law
-
See
-
See Fuller, The Morality of Law, 33-41;.
-
-
-
Fuller1
-
121
-
-
84924766916
-
A General View of a Complete Code of Laws
-
in The Works of Jeremy Bentham, J. Bowring, ed, Edinburgh:W. Tait
-
Jeremy Bentham, "A General View of a Complete Code of Laws," in The Works of Jeremy Bentham, J. Bowring, ed. (Edinburgh:W. Tait, 1843), 3:155, 161.
-
(1843)
, vol.3
-
-
Bentham, J.1
-
122
-
-
0003466894
-
Rationale of Judicial Evidence
-
in Works
-
Jeremy Bentham, "Rationale of Judicial Evidence," in Works, 6:191, 508.
-
, vol.6
-
-
Bentham, J.1
-
123
-
-
84890577546
-
An Essay on Political Tactics
-
In addition to insisting on the clarity and simplicity of all laws, Bentham argued for the publicity of legislative proceedings. See, in Works, and of judicial proceedings, see "Bentham's Draught for the Organization of Judicial Establishments," in Works, 4:305, 316-18
-
In addition to insisting on the clarity and simplicity of all laws, Bentham argued for the publicity of legislative proceedings. See "An Essay on Political Tactics," in Works, 2:299, 310-17, and of judicial proceedings, see "Bentham's Draught for the Organization of Judicial Establishments," in Works, 4:305, 316-18.
-
, vol.2
, Issue.299
, pp. 310-317
-
-
-
124
-
-
84890689307
-
Rule of Law
-
Raz, "Rule of Law," 220.
-
-
-
Raz1
-
125
-
-
0003996038
-
The Road to Serfdom
-
For this group of arguments, see especially, Chicago: University of Chicago Press
-
For this group of arguments, see especially Friedrich A. von Hayek, The Road to Serfdom (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1944), 72-87;
-
(1944)
, pp. 72-87
-
-
Von Hayek, F.A.1
-
126
-
-
84871647310
-
A Theory of Justice
-
Rawls, A Theory of Justice, 235-36;
-
-
-
Rawls1
-
127
-
-
84890689307
-
Rule of Law
-
Raz, "Rule of Law," 220-22.
-
-
-
Raz1
-
128
-
-
84890689307
-
Rule of Law
-
Raz uses the image of entrapment in this context. See
-
Raz uses the image of entrapment in this context. See Raz, "Rule of Law," 222.
-
-
-
Raz1
-
129
-
-
0004273012
-
Rethinking Criminal Law
-
See, sec. 10.3
-
See Fletcher, Rethinking Criminal Law, sec. 10.3, pp. 811-12.
-
-
-
Fletcher1
-
130
-
-
0004305896
-
Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals
-
See, trans. H. J. Paton, London: Hutchinson
-
See Immanuel Kant, Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals, trans. H. J. Paton (London: Hutchinson, 1948), 62-66, 99-95.
-
(1948)
-
-
Kant, I.1
-
131
-
-
84890746141
-
-
These duties include the moral duty to obey the law, whenever such a duty exists
-
These duties include the moral duty to obey the law, whenever such a duty exists.
-
-
-
-
132
-
-
84871647310
-
A Theory of Justice
-
arguing that because the value of the rule of law is related to liberty, the rule of law can be curtailed, when necessary, on liberty's behalf
-
Compare Rawls, A Theory of Justice, 242, arguing that because the value of the rule of law is related to liberty, the rule of law can be curtailed, when necessary, on liberty's behalf.
-
-
-
Rawls, C.1
-
133
-
-
84890689307
-
Rule of Law
-
Raz, "Rule of Law," 213-14.
-
-
-
Raz1
-
134
-
-
0004273196
-
The Morality of Law
-
See
-
See Fuller, The Morality of Law, passim 129.
-
-
-
Fuller1
-
135
-
-
84890775446
-
The Institutional Nature of Law
-
in The Authority of Law
-
Joseph Raz, "The Institutional Nature of Law," in The Authority of Law, 103, at 112.
-
, vol.103
, pp. 112
-
-
Raz, J.1
-
136
-
-
0004289733
-
Tragic Choices
-
See also, New York: Norton, 78-79, 95, describing situations in which the value of honesty competes against and sometimes loses to other values in what the authors call "tragic" social contexts
-
See also Guido Calabresi and Philip Bobbitt, Tragic Choices (New York: Norton, 1978), 24-26, 78-79, 95, describing situations in which the value of honesty competes against and sometimes loses to other values in what the authors call "tragic" social contexts.
-
(1978)
, pp. 24-26
-
-
Calabresi, G.1
Bobbitt, P.2
-
137
-
-
84890668532
-
Political Action
-
Walzer, "Political Action," 64, 65.
-
, vol.64
, pp. 65
-
-
Walzer1
-
138
-
-
84890758458
-
-
Obviously, many other pertinent and important issues are not even raised here. Prominent examples would be the complex and crucial role played by lawyers in regard to acoustic separation, and the relation of selective transmission to various theories of democracy
-
Obviously, many other pertinent and important issues are not even raised here. Prominent examples would be the complex and crucial role played by lawyers in regard to acoustic separation, and the relation of selective transmission to various theories of democracy.
-
-
-
-
139
-
-
0004255702
-
The Province of Jurisprudence Determined
-
New York: Noonday Press
-
John Austin, The Province of Jurisprudence Determined (New York: Noonday Press, 1954).
-
(1954)
-
-
Austin, J.1
-
140
-
-
0004220262
-
The Concept of Law
-
Oxford: Clarendon Press
-
H. L. A. Hart, The Concept of Law (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1961), 38.
-
(1961)
, pp. 38
-
-
Hart, H.L.A.1
-
141
-
-
0004048651
-
The Authority of the State
-
Oxford: Clarendon Press, "Definition" may overstate what Green's formulation provides, but it is sufficient for my purpose that it focuses on some central characteristics of authority
-
Leslie Green, The Authority of the State (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1988), 41-42. "Definition" may overstate what Green's formulation provides, but it is sufficient for my purpose that it focuses on some central characteristics of authority.
-
(1988)
, pp. 41-42
-
-
Green, L.1
-
142
-
-
84890673530
-
-
I do not consider the possible use by authority of noncoercive spurs or inducements, though I believe that some of my arguments would apply, with variable force, to such milder means as well
-
I do not consider the possible use by authority of noncoercive spurs or inducements, though I believe that some of my arguments would apply, with variable force, to such milder means as well.
-
-
-
-
144
-
-
84925931177
-
Political Authority and Political Obligation
-
Rolf Sartorius, "Political Authority and Political Obligation," Virginia Law Review 67 (1981): 3.
-
(1981)
Virginia Law Review
, vol.67
, pp. 3
-
-
Sartorius, R.1
-
145
-
-
84890731818
-
Political Coercion and Political Obligation
-
For a view that the coerciveness of political regimes does not vitiate the consent necessary for political obligation, see, in Nomos 14: Coercion, ed. J. Roland Pennock and John Chapman, Chicago: Aldine
-
For a view that the coerciveness of political regimes does not vitiate the consent necessary for political obligation, see Alan Wertheimer, "Political Coercion and Political Obligation," in Nomos 14: Coercion, ed. J. Roland Pennock and John Chapman (Chicago: Aldine, 1972), 213.
-
(1972)
, pp. 213
-
-
Wertheimer, A.1
-
146
-
-
0003956640
-
The Morality of Freedom
-
Oxford: Clarendon Press
-
Joseph Raz, The Morality of Freedom (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986), 38-69.
-
(1986)
, pp. 38-69
-
-
Raz, J.1
-
147
-
-
80053470518
-
Legitimate Authority
-
in The Authority of Law, Oxford: Clarendon Press
-
Joseph Raz, "Legitimate Authority," in The Authority of Law (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1979), 24-25.
-
(1979)
, pp. 24-25
-
-
Raz, J.1
-
148
-
-
0004048289
-
A Theory of Justice
-
See, Cambridge: Harvard University Press
-
See John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1971), 334.
-
(1971)
, pp. 334
-
-
Rawls, J.1
-
149
-
-
84890580955
-
-
College Dictionary, rev. ed, New York: Random House, The idea of "deference" has also been traditionally prominent in discussions of authority in political philosophy. See Friedman, "Concept of Authority," 64ff
-
College Dictionary, rev. ed. (New York: Random House, 1988). The idea of "deference" has also been traditionally prominent in discussions of authority in political philosophy. See Friedman, "Concept of Authority," 64ff.
-
(1988)
-
-
-
150
-
-
0003890812
-
Moral Principles and Political Obligations
-
See e.g, Princeton: Princeton University Press
-
See e.g. A. J. Simmons, Moral Principles and Political Obligations (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1979), 163.
-
(1979)
, pp. 163
-
-
Simmons, A.J.1
-
151
-
-
84890642781
-
Respect for Law
-
Raz connects the latter two: obeying the law is a matter of identification with one's society because it expresses trust in its institutions. See, in The Authority of Law
-
Raz connects the latter two: obeying the law is a matter of identification with one's society because it expresses trust in its institutions. See "Respect for Law," in The Authority of Law, 260-61.
-
-
-
-
152
-
-
84890647874
-
Perspectives on Authority
-
For a similar point see, in Raz, Authority
-
For a similar point see Steven Lukes, "Perspectives on Authority," in Raz, Authority, 213-14.
-
-
-
Lukes, S.1
-
153
-
-
0003880778
-
The Authority of Law
-
Raz, The Authority of Law, 255.
-
-
-
Raz1
-
154
-
-
84890590713
-
-
The view of sanctions as having only an "ancillary" function in the law's guidance of behavior is emphasized by Hart in The Concept of Law, 38
-
The view of sanctions as having only an "ancillary" function in the law's guidance of behavior is emphasized by Hart in The Concept of Law, 38.
-
-
-
-
155
-
-
0004237063
-
Practical Reason and Norms
-
The concept of exclusionary reasons is elaborated in, London: Hutchinson
-
The concept of exclusionary reasons is elaborated in Joseph Raz, Practical Reason and Norms (London: Hutchinson, 1975).
-
(1975)
-
-
Raz, J.1
-
156
-
-
0003880778
-
The Authority of Law
-
Raz, The Authority of Law, 22-24.
-
-
-
Raz1
-
157
-
-
0004305896
-
Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals
-
trans. H. J. Paton, London: Hutchinson
-
Kant, Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals, trans. H. J. Paton (London: Hutchinson, 1948).
-
(1948)
-
-
Kant1
-
158
-
-
84890719769
-
-
We often experience threats as a challenge or a dare. The present account helps make sense of this reaction
-
We often experience threats as a challenge or a dare. The present account helps make sense of this reaction.
-
-
-
-
159
-
-
0003516637
-
General Theory of Law and State
-
New York:Russell and Russell, and Pure Theory of Law, 2d ed. (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1967)
-
Hans Kelsen, General Theory of Law and State (New York:Russell and Russell, 1961) and Pure Theory of Law, 2d ed. (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1967).
-
(1961)
-
-
Kelsen, H.1
-
160
-
-
0000516383
-
Is There a Prima Facie Obligation to Obey the Law?
-
which maintains that whether we recognize a general moral duty to obey the law makes little practical difference
-
Compare M. B. E. Smith, "Is There a Prima Facie Obligation to Obey the Law?" Yale Law Journal 82 (1973): 950, which maintains that whether we recognize a general moral duty to obey the law makes little practical difference.
-
(1973)
Yale Law Journal
, vol.82
, pp. 950
-
-
Smith, M.B.E.1
-
161
-
-
0003880778
-
The Authority of Law
-
Raz, The Authority of Law, 25.
-
-
-
Raz1
-
162
-
-
0003768818
-
Judgment under Uncertainty
-
The best-known lines of attack are respectively represented by, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
The best-known lines of attack are respectively represented by D. Kahneman, P. Slovic, and A. Tversky, eds., Judgment under Uncertainty (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982);
-
(1982)
-
-
Kahneman, D.1
Slovic, P.2
Tversky, A.3
-
163
-
-
0004077471
-
Models of Bounded Rationality
-
Cambridge: MIT Press
-
Herbert Simon, Models of Bounded Rationality (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1982).
-
(1982)
-
-
Simon, H.1
-
164
-
-
84984003626
-
Is More Choice Better Than Less?
-
A recent exception that takes a more normative view is
-
A recent exception that takes a more normative view is Gerald Dworkin, "Is More Choice Better Than Less?" Midwest Studies in Philosophy 7 (1982): 47.
-
(1982)
Midwest Studies in Philosophy
, vol.7
, pp. 47
-
-
Dworkin, G.1
-
165
-
-
0004195469
-
Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy
-
Cambridge:Harvard University Press
-
Bernard Williams, Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy (Cambridge:Harvard University Press, 1985), 57.
-
(1985)
, pp. 57
-
-
Williams, B.1
-
167
-
-
84890630159
-
-
This of course is a feature of Kant's theory of moral autonomy as well: no one, not even the agent, can ever be sure that a moral action was autonomously motivated
-
This of course is a feature of Kant's theory of moral autonomy as well: no one, not even the agent, can ever be sure that a moral action was autonomously motivated.
-
-
-
-
168
-
-
84972277428
-
Autonomy
-
For choice as constitutive of autonomy in recent writing see e.g
-
For choice as constitutive of autonomy in recent writing see e.g. R. S. Downie and Elizabeth Telfer, "Autonomy," Philosophy 46 (1971):293;
-
(1971)
Philosophy
, vol.46
, pp. 293
-
-
Downie, R.S.1
Telfer, E.2
-
169
-
-
0004238267
-
The Theory and Practice of Autonomy
-
Cambridge:Cambridge University Press
-
Gerald Dworkin, The Theory and Practice of Autonomy (Cambridge:Cambridge University Press, 1988);
-
(1988)
-
-
Dworkin, G.1
-
171
-
-
0003956640
-
The Morality of Freedom
-
Raz, The Morality of Freedom, 370.
-
-
-
Raz1
-
172
-
-
84890600698
-
-
The variation is meant to accommodate different views of the exact manner in which one's life is essential to one's identity, e.g., by forging a character that is a constituent of the self's identity
-
The variation is meant to accommodate different views of the exact manner in which one's life is essential to one's identity, e.g., by forging a character that is a constituent of the self's identity.
-
-
-
-
173
-
-
0004281423
-
Problems of the Self
-
On some of the complications that attend this view, and which cannot be considered here, see, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, essays 3 and 4; and Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity (Oxford: Blackwell, 1980)
-
On some of the complications that attend this view, and which cannot be considered here, see Bernard Williams, Problems of the Self (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), essays 3 and 4; and Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity (Oxford: Blackwell, 1980).
-
(1973)
-
-
Williams, B.1
-
174
-
-
84890637718
-
-
Examples of the general approach to autonomy I have in mind are Dworkin, Theory and Practice; and Robert Young, Personal Autonomy:Beyond Positive and Negative Liberty (London: Croom Helm, 1986)
-
Examples of the general approach to autonomy I have in mind are Dworkin, Theory and Practice; and Robert Young, Personal Autonomy:Beyond Positive and Negative Liberty (London: Croom Helm, 1986).
-
-
-
-
175
-
-
84925905118
-
Picking and Choosing
-
On the problem of tie-breaking in the case of choosing, see
-
On the problem of tie-breaking in the case of choosing, see Edna Ullmann-Margalit and Sidney Morgenbesser, "Picking and Choosing," Social Research 44 (1977): 757.
-
(1977)
Social Research
, vol.44
, pp. 757
-
-
Ullmann-Margalit, E.1
Morgenbesser, S.2
-
176
-
-
0003793334
-
Four Essays on Liberty
-
Oxford: Oxford University Press, li-lii, who overlooks this dificulty
-
Compare Isaiah Berlin, Four Essays on Liberty (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1969), li-lii, who overlooks this dificulty.
-
(1969)
-
-
Berlin, I.1
-
177
-
-
84890718243
-
-
Even if successful in its own terms, the suggestion I explore would leave out some contested zones of morality, and correspondingly of criminality, such as those concerning the treatment of animals and the environment. I do not touch on these issues, but it should be noted that the harm principle does not directly engage them either
-
Even if successful in its own terms, the suggestion I explore would leave out some contested zones of morality, and correspondingly of criminality, such as those concerning the treatment of animals and the environment. I do not touch on these issues, but it should be noted that the harm principle does not directly engage them either.
-
-
-
-
178
-
-
84890752851
-
Liberty, Representative Government
-
Specifically at the hands of, in On Liberty, in Utilitarianism, Everyman edition
-
Specifically at the hands of John Stuart Mill, in On Liberty, in Utilitarianism, Liberty, Representative Government (Everyman edition), 158.
-
-
-
Mill, J.S.1
-
179
-
-
84860630622
-
Human Dignity and its Impact on German Substantive Criminal Law and Criminal Procedure
-
The idea of human dignity plays a central role in German criminal jurisprudence, though not quite the same role I explore here. For a recent survey see
-
The idea of human dignity plays a central role in German criminal jurisprudence, though not quite the same role I explore here. For a recent survey see Otto Lagodny, "Human Dignity and its Impact on German Substantive Criminal Law and Criminal Procedure," Israel Law Review 33 (1999): 575.
-
(1999)
Israel Law Review
, vol.33
, pp. 575
-
-
Lagodny, O.1
-
180
-
-
0003506798
-
The Moral Limits of the Criminal Law
-
The most comprehensive exploration and critique of the principle is by, in his four-volume magnum opus, New York: Oxford University Press
-
The most comprehensive exploration and critique of the principle is by Joel Feinberg, in his four-volume magnum opus, The Moral Limits of the Criminal Law (New York: Oxford University Press, 1984-88).
-
(1984)
-
-
Feinberg, J.1
-
181
-
-
0004243670
-
Liberty, Equality, Fraternity
-
ed. R. J. White, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
James Fitzjames Stephens, Liberty, Equality, Fraternity, ed. R. J. White (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1873, 1967).
-
(1873)
-
-
Stephens, J.F.1
-
182
-
-
84890629958
-
The Crisis of Overcriminalization
-
in Sanford H. Kadish, Blame and Punishment: Essays in the Criminal Law, New York: Macmillan
-
"The Crisis of Overcriminalization," in Sanford H. Kadish, Blame and Punishment: Essays in the Criminal Law (New York: Macmillan, 1987), 21.
-
(1987)
, pp. 21
-
-
-
184
-
-
84890737643
-
-
204 Cal. App. 2d 832; 23 Cal. Rptr. 92 (1962)
-
204 Cal. App. 2d 832; 23 Cal. Rptr. 92 (1962).
-
-
-
-
185
-
-
84890576883
-
-
326 S.E. 2d 410 (S.C. 1985). The eponymous defendant in this case is Brown; I refer to the case by the name of the second defendant (Braxton) to avoid confusion with the other case entitled State v. Brown I discuss next
-
326 S.E. 2d 410 (S.C. 1985). The eponymous defendant in this case is Brown; I refer to the case by the name of the second defendant (Braxton) to avoid confusion with the other case entitled State v. Brown I discuss next.
-
-
-
-
186
-
-
84890758400
-
-
All the court says in explaining withholding the option of castration is that such punishment would be in violation of the state's constitutional prohibition against cruel and unusual punishment. No mention is made of the possible relevance of the defendants' preference in the matter
-
All the court says in explaining withholding the option of castration is that such punishment would be in violation of the state's constitutional prohibition against cruel and unusual punishment. No mention is made of the possible relevance of the defendants' preference in the matter.
-
-
-
-
187
-
-
84890727413
-
-
364 A.2d 27 (N.J. Super. Ct. Law Div. 1976), aff'd, 381 A.2d 1231 (N.J. Super. Ct. App. Div. 1977)
-
364 A.2d 27 (N.J. Super. Ct. Law Div. 1976), aff'd, 381 A.2d 1231 (N.J. Super. Ct. App. Div. 1977).
-
-
-
-
188
-
-
84890673241
-
-
For a related discussion of puzzles to which victims' consent can give rise see Leo Katz, Ill-Gotten Gains: Evasion, Blackmail, Fraud, and Kindred Puzzles of the Law (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1996), 145-57
-
For a related discussion of puzzles to which victims' consent can give rise see Leo Katz, Ill-Gotten Gains: Evasion, Blackmail, Fraud, and Kindred Puzzles of the Law (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1996), 145-57.
-
-
-
-
189
-
-
84902690703
-
What Is Wrong with Slavery
-
See, e.g
-
See, e.g., R. M. Hare, "What Is Wrong with Slavery," Philosophy and Public Affairs 8 (1979): 103.
-
(1979)
Philosophy and Public Affairs
, vol.8
, pp. 103
-
-
Hare, R.M.1
-
190
-
-
0005424391
-
Happy Slaves: A Critique of Consent Theory
-
Chicago: University of Chicago Press, preface, where the author raises some of these issues, but eschews the use of the kinds of thought experiments I indulge in favor of an historical study of the idea of consent in liberal theory
-
Compare Don Herzog, Happy Slaves: A Critique of Consent Theory (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1989), preface, where the author raises some of these issues, but eschews the use of the kinds of thought experiments I indulge in favor of an historical study of the idea of consent in liberal theory.
-
(1989)
-
-
Herzog, D.1
-
191
-
-
0004226063
-
Mill on Liberty
-
The locus classicus of this discussion is in John Stuart Mill, On Liberty. For a critical commentary of Mill's argument, see, New York: Oxford University Press
-
The locus classicus of this discussion is in John Stuart Mill, On Liberty. For a critical commentary of Mill's argument, see Chin Liew Ten, Mill on Liberty (New York: Oxford University Press, 1980), 117-23.
-
(1980)
, pp. 117-123
-
-
Ten, C.L.1
-
192
-
-
20344402904
-
The Constitution of Rights: Human Dignity and American Values
-
There is a rapidly growing literature on dignity as a legal value. Some important essays are collected in, Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press
-
There is a rapidly growing literature on dignity as a legal value. Some important essays are collected in Michael Meyer and W. A. Parent, eds., The Constitution of Rights: Human Dignity and American Values (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1992).
-
(1992)
-
-
Meyer, M.1
Parent, W.A.2
-
193
-
-
84925931735
-
The Political Theories of Choice and Dignity
-
But the tradition has not gone unchallenged. On the independence of dignity from the value of choice, see
-
But the tradition has not gone unchallenged. On the independence of dignity from the value of choice, see Robert Goodin, "The Political Theories of Choice and Dignity," American Philosophical Quarterly 18 (1981): 91;
-
(1981)
American Philosophical Quarterly
, vol.18
, pp. 91
-
-
Goodin, R.1
-
194
-
-
84901230990
-
Consenting Adults: The Problem of Enhancing Human Dignity Non-Coercively
-
on the independence of dignity from consent, see
-
on the independence of dignity from consent, see R. George Wright, "Consenting Adults: The Problem of Enhancing Human Dignity Non-Coercively," Boston University Law Review 75 (1995): 1397.
-
(1995)
Boston University Law Review
, vol.75
, pp. 1397
-
-
George Wright, R.1
-
195
-
-
84890714986
-
-
Though the court recognizes that the participants' consent is a defense in the case of sports such as football, boxing, or wrestling, no convincing explanation is given as to what distinguishes these cases from the instant case
-
Though the court recognizes that the participants' consent is a defense in the case of sports such as football, boxing, or wrestling, no convincing explanation is given as to what distinguishes these cases from the instant case.
-
-
-
-
196
-
-
84890781313
-
-
The "our" here simply refers to those who subscribe to the morality of dignity to which I allude
-
The "our" here simply refers to those who subscribe to the morality of dignity to which I allude.
-
-
-
-
197
-
-
84882036840
-
Basic Respect and Cultural Diversity
-
For a suggestion along similar lines see, in Respect, Pluralism, and Justice:Kantian Perspectives (New York: Oxford University Press
-
For a suggestion along similar lines see Thomas E. Hill Jr., "Basic Respect and Cultural Diversity," in Respect, Pluralism, and Justice:Kantian Perspectives (New York: Oxford University Press, 2000), 59.
-
(2000)
, pp. 59
-
-
Hill Jr, T.E.1
-
198
-
-
0041320538
-
-
E.g., People v. Chen, no.87-774 (N.Y. Sup. Ct. Dec. 2, 1988); cited in Doriane Lambelet Coleman, "Individualizing Justice through Multiculturalism: The Liberals' Dilemma," Columbia Law Review 96 (1996): 1093, at 1102-3
-
E.g., People v. Chen, no.87-774 (N.Y. Sup. Ct. Dec. 2, 1988); cited in Doriane Lambelet Coleman, "Individualizing Justice through Multiculturalism: The Liberals' Dilemma," Columbia Law Review 96 (1996): 1093, at 1102-3.
-
-
-
-
199
-
-
84890666541
-
Individualizing Justice through Multiculturalism
-
And becomes highly charged. For one heated exchange see
-
And becomes highly charged. For one heated exchange see Coleman, "Individualizing Justice through Multiculturalism," at 1098
-
-
-
Coleman1
-
200
-
-
0347306242
-
Talking 'Culture': Gender, Race, Nation, and the Politics of Multiculturalism
-
esp. at
-
Leti Volpp, "Talking 'Culture': Gender, Race, Nation, and the Politics of Multiculturalism," Columbia Law Review 96 (1996): 1573, esp. at 1594-1600.
-
(1996)
Columbia Law Review
, vol.96
-
-
Volpp, L.1
-
201
-
-
0043085015
-
Punishment for Thoughts
-
in On Guilt and Innocence (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press
-
Herbert Morris, "Punishment for Thoughts," in On Guilt and Innocence (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1976), 1-29.
-
(1976)
, pp. 1-29
-
-
Morris, H.1
-
202
-
-
0041675563
-
Philosophy of Criminal Law
-
For some further reflections on this theme see, Totowa, N.J.: Rowman and Littlefield
-
For some further reflections on this theme see Douglas Husak, Philosophy of Criminal Law (Totowa, N.J.: Rowman and Littlefield, 1987), 97-99, 103-5.
-
(1987)
-
-
Husak, D.1
-
203
-
-
0003991395
-
Criminal Attempts
-
For an explicit statement of this assumption, see, e.g, Oxford: Clarendon Press, "even practical thought [deliberation, intention-formation, choice] does not, by itself, impinge on the world: it must be translated into action; and we can say that it is by action (as distinct from mere thought) that agents impinge on or make a difference to the world." 4. See, for example, Joseph Tussman, Government and the Mind (New York: Oxford University Press, 1977), 88
-
For an explicit statement of this assumption, see, e.g., R. A. Duff, Criminal Attempts (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1996), 313-14: "even practical thought [deliberation, intention-formation, choice] does not, by itself, impinge on the world: it must be translated into action; and we can say that it is by action (as distinct from mere thought) that agents impinge on or make a difference to the world." 4. See, for example, Joseph Tussman, Government and the Mind (New York: Oxford University Press, 1977), 88.
-
(1996)
, pp. 313-314
-
-
Duff, R.A.1
-
204
-
-
0004157494
-
Harmless Wrongdoing
-
See e.g, New York: Oxford University Press
-
See e.g. Joel Feinberg, Harmless Wrongdoing (New York: Oxford University Press, 1988), 23-24;
-
(1988)
, pp. 23-24
-
-
Feinberg, J.1
-
205
-
-
0041675563
-
Philosophy of Criminal Law
-
Husak, Philosophy of Criminal Law, 105;
-
-
-
Husak1
-
206
-
-
0003991395
-
Criminal Attempts
-
Duff, Criminal Attempts, 314.
-
-
-
Duff1
-
207
-
-
0003799915
-
Word and Object
-
See, e.g, Cambridge:MIT Press, chaps. 1-2
-
See, e.g., Willard Van Orman Quine, Word and Object (Cambridge:MIT Press, 1960), chaps. 1-2.
-
(1960)
-
-
Quine, W.V.O.1
-
208
-
-
0004220928
-
The Principles of Morals and Legislation
-
New York: Hafner Press
-
Jeremy Bentham, The Principles of Morals and Legislation (New York: Hafner Press, 1948), 1.
-
(1948)
, pp. 1
-
-
Bentham, J.1
-
209
-
-
0004273805
-
Anarchy, State, and Utopia
-
New York: Basic Books
-
Robert Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopia (New York: Basic Books, 1974), 42-45.
-
(1974)
, pp. 42-45
-
-
Nozick, R.1
-
210
-
-
84890737656
-
-
352 U.S. 432 (1956)
-
352 U.S. 432 (1956).
-
-
-
-
211
-
-
84890778824
-
-
204 Cal. App. 2d 832; 23 Cal. Rptr. 92 (1962), discussed in chapter 5
-
204 Cal. App. 2d 832; 23 Cal. Rptr. 92 (1962), discussed in chapter 5.
-
-
-
-
212
-
-
0001466690
-
The Misfortunes of the Dead
-
The example is discussed by
-
The example is discussed by George Pitcher in "The Misfortunes of the Dead," American Philosophical Quarterly 21 (1984): 183;
-
(1984)
American Philosophical Quarterly
, vol.21
, pp. 183
-
-
Pitcher, G.1
-
213
-
-
0003439620
-
Harm to Others
-
New York: Oxford University Press
-
Joel Feinberg, Harm to Others (New York: Oxford University Press, 1984), 90-91.
-
(1984)
, pp. 90-91
-
-
Feinberg, J.1
-
214
-
-
84890708286
-
-
Pitcher, "Misfortunes of the Dead," diagnoses the problem this case poses in similar terms. I propose a different solution from his, though the two, I think, are consistent. Mine, however, leads more directly to the claim I seek to establish concerning the extrapersonal effects of thoughts
-
Pitcher, "Misfortunes of the Dead," diagnoses the problem this case poses in similar terms. I propose a different solution from his, though the two, I think, are consistent. Mine, however, leads more directly to the claim I seek to establish concerning the extrapersonal effects of thoughts.
-
-
-
-
215
-
-
84890664689
-
-
For a discussion of "vicarious harms" along such lines see Feinberg, Harm to Others, at 70-79
-
For a discussion of "vicarious harms" along such lines see Feinberg, Harm to Others, at 70-79.
-
-
-
-
216
-
-
84890594808
-
-
Guy de Maupassant famously stated that the tower was his favorite lunch place in Paris, being the one place from which the tower could not be seen; he is also said to have left Paris permanently to avoid looking at the tower
-
Guy de Maupassant famously stated that the tower was his favorite lunch place in Paris, being the one place from which the tower could not be seen; he is also said to have left Paris permanently to avoid looking at the tower.
-
-
-
-
217
-
-
84890720682
-
-
So I do not mean to raise the separate question whether there is a useful logical or ontological sense that would admit the "properties" ordinary speech implicitly excludes, or, for that matter, exclude "properties" that the latter takes for granted
-
So I do not mean to raise the separate question whether there is a useful logical or ontological sense that would admit the "properties" ordinary speech implicitly excludes, or, for that matter, exclude "properties" that the latter takes for granted.
-
-
-
-
218
-
-
0038014282
-
Two Conceptions of Happiness
-
Cases of this kind are also sometimes discussed in connection with the concept of happiness. See, for example
-
Cases of this kind are also sometimes discussed in connection with the concept of happiness. See, for example, Richard Kraut, "Two Conceptions of Happiness," Philosophical Review 88 (1979): 167-97.
-
(1979)
Philosophical Review
, vol.88
, pp. 167-197
-
-
Kraut, R.1
-
219
-
-
84890662300
-
-
These two categories are not exhaustive: physical objects, such as geographic locations, can also play the part of a relational term. They are however irrelevant to our present concerns
-
These two categories are not exhaustive: physical objects, such as geographic locations, can also play the part of a relational term. They are however irrelevant to our present concerns.
-
-
-
-
220
-
-
84890669325
-
Of the Dignity and Meanness of Human Nature
-
in Political Essays, ed. Charles W. Hendel, Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill
-
Compare David Hume, "Of the Dignity and Meanness of Human Nature," in Political Essays, ed. Charles W. Hendel (Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1953).
-
(1953)
-
-
Hume, D.1
-
221
-
-
85080838551
-
Concealment and Exposure
-
Hence, the examples recently adduced by Thomas Nagel to demonstrate the perils of excessive candor in social interactions fall outside the purview of my argument. See his
-
Hence, the examples recently adduced by Thomas Nagel to demonstrate the perils of excessive candor in social interactions fall outside the purview of my argument. See his "Concealment and Exposure," Philosophy and Public Affairs 27 (1998): 3, 10-17.
-
(1998)
Philosophy and Public Affairs
, vol.27
, Issue.3
, pp. 10-17
-
-
-
222
-
-
0000692309
-
The Meaning of 'Meaning,'
-
The main papers are, in Philosophical Papers, London: Cambridge University Press
-
The main papers are Hilary Putnam, "The Meaning of 'Meaning,'" in Philosophical Papers (London: Cambridge University Press, 1975), 2:215;
-
(1975)
, vol.2
, pp. 215
-
-
Putnam, H.1
-
223
-
-
84985362811
-
Individualism and the Mental
-
and "Other Bodies," in Thought and Object, ed. Andrew Woodfield (New York: Oxford University Press, 1982), 97
-
Tyler Burge, "Individualism and the Mental," Midwest Studies in Philosophy 4 (1979): 73-121, and "Other Bodies," in Thought and Object, ed. Andrew Woodfield (New York: Oxford University Press, 1982), 97.
-
(1979)
Midwest Studies in Philosophy
, vol.4
, pp. 73-121
-
-
Burge, T.1
-
224
-
-
0004200551
-
The Limits of the Criminal Sanction
-
Consider Professor Packer's blunt move to short-circuit the whole issue: "Very simply, the law treats man's conduct as autonomous and willed, not because it is, but because it is desirable to proceed as if it were.", Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press
-
Consider Professor Packer's blunt move to short-circuit the whole issue: "Very simply, the law treats man's conduct as autonomous and willed, not because it is, but because it is desirable to proceed as if it were." Herbert L. Packer, The Limits of the Criminal Sanction (Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press, 1968), 74-75.
-
(1968)
, pp. 74-75
-
-
Packer, H.L.1
-
225
-
-
84976114120
-
Choice, Character, and Excuse
-
See, e.g
-
See, e.g., Michael S. Moore, "Choice, Character, and Excuse," Social Philosophy and Policy 7 (1990): 29;
-
(1990)
Social Philosophy and Policy
, vol.7
, pp. 29
-
-
Moore, M.S.1
-
226
-
-
84972438169
-
Character, Choice, and Moral Agency: The Relevance of Character to Our Moral Culpability Judgments
-
Peter Arenella, "Character, Choice, and Moral Agency: The Relevance of Character to Our Moral Culpability Judgments," Social Philosophy and Policy 7 (1990): 59.
-
(1990)
Social Philosophy and Policy
, vol.7
, pp. 59
-
-
Arenella, P.1
-
227
-
-
0004253960
-
Liberalism and the Limits of Justice
-
Notable recent examples include, New York: Cambridge University Press
-
Notable recent examples include Michael J. Sandel, Liberalism and the Limits of Justice (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1982);
-
(1982)
-
-
Sandel, M.J.1
-
228
-
-
0642318814
-
Passion
-
New York: Free Press, For a related criticism of legal scholarship for its failure to consider the lawcreating subject, see Pierre Schlag, "The Problem of the Subject," Texas Law Review 69 (1991): 1627
-
Roberto M. Unger, Passion (New York: Free Press, 1984). For a related criticism of legal scholarship for its failure to consider the lawcreating subject, see Pierre Schlag, "The Problem of the Subject," Texas Law Review 69 (1991): 1627.
-
(1984)
-
-
Unger, R.M.1
-
229
-
-
0004244925
-
Punishment and Responsibility
-
H. L. A. Hart draws attention to the ambiguity of responsibility statements, although he construes it quite differently. See, Oxford: Clarendon Press
-
H. L. A. Hart draws attention to the ambiguity of responsibility statements, although he construes it quite differently. See H. L. A. Hart, Punishment and Responsibility (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1968), 186, 196-97.
-
(1968)
, vol.186
, pp. 196-197
-
-
Hart, H.L.A.1
-
230
-
-
1542692426
-
Collective Responsibility
-
A sense of responsibility that corresponds to what I call subjectresponsibility is suggested in, in Doing and Deserving, Princeton: Princeton University Press
-
A sense of responsibility that corresponds to what I call subjectresponsibility is suggested in Joel Feinberg, "Collective Responsibility," in Doing and Deserving (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1970), 222, 250-51;
-
(1970)
, vol.222
, pp. 250-251
-
-
Feinberg, J.1
-
231
-
-
34447187763
-
Why We Are Responsible for Our Emotions
-
Eugene Schlossberger, "Why We Are Responsible for Our Emotions," Mind 95 (1986): 37.
-
(1986)
Mind
, vol.95
, pp. 37
-
-
Schlossberger, E.1
-
232
-
-
0040414208
-
Responsibility of Persons for Their Emotions
-
An account of responsibility for emotions that is based on what I call object-responsibility may be found in
-
An account of responsibility for emotions that is based on what I call object-responsibility may be found in Edward Sankowski, "Responsibility of Persons for Their Emotions," Canadian Journal of Philosophy 7 (1977): 829.
-
(1977)
Canadian Journal of Philosophy
, vol.7
, pp. 829
-
-
Sankowski, E.1
-
233
-
-
0003967815
-
Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity
-
See, e.g, Cambridge:Cambridge University Press, esp. chap. 2
-
See, e.g., Richard Rorty, Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity (Cambridge:Cambridge University Press, 1989), esp. chap. 2.
-
(1989)
-
-
Rorty, R.1
-
234
-
-
84898384961
-
Meditations on First Philosophy, in The Philosophical Writings of Descartes
-
trans. John Cottingham, Robert Stoothoff, and Dugald Murdoch, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
René Descartes, Meditations on First Philosophy, in The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, trans. John Cottingham, Robert Stoothoff, and Dugald Murdoch (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1984), 2:1.
-
(1984)
, vol.2
, pp. 1
-
-
Descartes, R.1
-
235
-
-
84890585678
-
-
Most prominently in Being and Nothingness
-
Most prominently in Being and Nothingness.
-
-
-
-
236
-
-
0003952877
-
Identification and Externality" and "Identification and Wholeheartedness
-
See, both in The Importance of What We Care About, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
See Henry G. Frankfurt, "Identification and Externality" and "Identification and Wholeheartedness," both in The Importance of What We Care About (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988), 58, 167.
-
(1988)
, vol.58
, pp. 167
-
-
Frankfurt, H.G.1
-
237
-
-
0003702370
-
Encounters
-
Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill
-
Erving Goffman, Encounters (Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1961), 85-152;
-
(1961)
, pp. 85-152
-
-
Goffman, E.1
-
238
-
-
33645740472
-
The Underlife of a Public Institution: A Study of Ways of Making Out in a Mental Hospital
-
in Asylums: Essays on the Social Situation of Mental Patients and Other Inmates, Garden City, N.Y.:Anchor
-
"The Underlife of a Public Institution: A Study of Ways of Making Out in a Mental Hospital," in Asylums: Essays on the Social Situation of Mental Patients and Other Inmates (Garden City, N.Y.:Anchor, 1961), 171, 318-20.
-
(1961)
, vol.171
, pp. 318-320
-
-
-
239
-
-
0003891615
-
Mind, Self, and Society
-
The primary modern text on the social origins of the self is, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, For a more recent statement, see Peter L. Berger and Thomas Luckmann, The Social Construction of Reality (Garden City, N.Y.:Doubleday, 1966), 173-80
-
The primary modern text on the social origins of the self is George H. Mead, Mind, Self, and Society (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1934). For a more recent statement, see Peter L. Berger and Thomas Luckmann, The Social Construction of Reality (Garden City, N.Y.:Doubleday, 1966), 173-80.
-
(1934)
-
-
Mead, G.H.1
-
240
-
-
0003740191
-
Reasons and Persons
-
Oxford: Clarendon Press, part 3, esp
-
Derek Parfit, Reasons and Persons (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984), part 3, esp. 199-306.
-
(1984)
, pp. 199-306
-
-
Parfit, D.1
-
241
-
-
84890664234
-
-
The occurrence of such an aberrant reaction, however, may assume different significance over time. For example, if such "aberrations" recur, they may have to be incorporated into the ever revisable picture of the self and thus change its constitution
-
The occurrence of such an aberrant reaction, however, may assume different significance over time. For example, if such "aberrations" recur, they may have to be incorporated into the ever revisable picture of the self and thus change its constitution.
-
-
-
-
242
-
-
84890606153
-
-
Obviously, an experience of shame is not a sufficient condition for responsibility when the experience results from a factual mistake: as it turns out, it was not really me who overturned the vase; it was the wind, or someone else
-
Obviously, an experience of shame is not a sufficient condition for responsibility when the experience results from a factual mistake: as it turns out, it was not really me who overturned the vase; it was the wind, or someone else.
-
-
-
-
243
-
-
84890702332
-
-
Here again, the simplest case is one that involves a factual mistake:I did not notice at Wrst that it was my hand that overturned the vase
-
Here again, the simplest case is one that involves a factual mistake:I did not notice at Wrst that it was my hand that overturned the vase.
-
-
-
-
244
-
-
84890729163
-
-
As in the corresponding situation mentioned in note 19 above, persistent failure to assume a responsible stance under similar circumstances will eventually be incorporated in the composition of the self and will suggest a revision of its boundaries
-
As in the corresponding situation mentioned in note 19 above, persistent failure to assume a responsible stance under similar circumstances will eventually be incorporated in the composition of the self and will suggest a revision of its boundaries.
-
-
-
-
245
-
-
0003986649
-
Nicomachean Ethics
-
See, book 3, chap. 5
-
See Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, book 3, chap. 5.
-
-
-
Aristotle1
-
246
-
-
0009269009
-
Reason and Responsibility in Aristotle
-
For an interpretation (or rather a reconstruction) of Aristotle's theory of moral responsibility that tries to avoid this problem, see, in Essays on Aristotle's Ethics, ed. Amelie O. Rorty (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press
-
For an interpretation (or rather a reconstruction) of Aristotle's theory of moral responsibility that tries to avoid this problem, see T. H. Irwin, "Reason and Responsibility in Aristotle," in Essays on Aristotle's Ethics, ed. Amelie O. Rorty (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1981), 117, 126-44.
-
(1981)
, vol.117
, pp. 126-144
-
-
Irwin, T.H.1
-
247
-
-
0004305896
-
Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals
-
This is in one sense Kant's own solution; roughly, we are responsible not because we "will our will" but because we are our will as noumenal selves. See, trans. H. J. Paton, London: Hutchinson
-
This is in one sense Kant's own solution; roughly, we are responsible not because we "will our will" but because we are our will as noumenal selves. See Immanuel Kant, Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals, trans. H. J. Paton (London: Hutchinson, 1948), 101-2;
-
(1948)
, pp. 101-102
-
-
Kant, I.1
-
248
-
-
0040278949
-
Kant's Compatibilism
-
see also, in Self and Nature in Kant's Philosophy, ed. Allen W. Wood, Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press
-
see also Allen W. Wood, "Kant's Compatibilism," in Self and Nature in Kant's Philosophy, ed. Allen W. Wood (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1984), 73.
-
(1984)
, pp. 73
-
-
Wood, A.W.1
-
249
-
-
33746175929
-
Freedom and Necessity
-
See, e.g, in Philosophical Essays, New York: St. Martin's Press
-
See, e.g., Alfred J. Ayer, "Freedom and Necessity," in Philosophical Essays (New York: St. Martin's Press, 1954), 271;
-
(1954)
, pp. 271
-
-
Ayer, A.J.1
-
250
-
-
12944273077
-
The Compatibility of Free Will and Determinism
-
John V. Canfield, "The Compatibility of Free Will and Determinism," Philosophical Review 71 (1962): 352.
-
(1962)
Philosophical Review
, vol.71
, pp. 352
-
-
Canfield, J.V.1
-
251
-
-
0012218613
-
Responsibility for Self
-
in Free Will, ed. Gary Watson, New York: Oxford University Press
-
Charles Taylor, "Responsibility for Self," in Free Will, ed. Gary Watson (New York: Oxford University Press, 1982), 111, 112.
-
(1982)
, vol.111
, pp. 112
-
-
Taylor, C.1
-
252
-
-
84890578789
-
-
These "dimensions" should not be reified and rigidly separated. They are merely heuristic aids meant to facilitate a mental grip on the unitary category of the self. As explained below, the same phenomena can sometimes be explained by reference to different dimensions of the self
-
These "dimensions" should not be reified and rigidly separated. They are merely heuristic aids meant to facilitate a mental grip on the unitary category of the self. As explained below, the same phenomena can sometimes be explained by reference to different dimensions of the self.
-
-
-
-
253
-
-
84890614155
-
-
This is not to say that people are responsible for all the effects traceable to their bodies. In part 3, I illustrate some of the ways in which one can try to avoid responsibility by distancing oneself from certain aspects of one's bodily existence
-
This is not to say that people are responsible for all the effects traceable to their bodies. In part 3, I illustrate some of the ways in which one can try to avoid responsibility by distancing oneself from certain aspects of one's bodily existence.
-
-
-
-
254
-
-
84890679935
-
-
See part 4
-
See part 4.
-
-
-
-
255
-
-
84890607047
-
-
See Rylands v. Fletcher, 3 L.R-E. & I. App. 330 (H.L. 1868)
-
See Rylands v. Fletcher, 3 L.R-E. & I. App. 330 (H.L. 1868).
-
-
-
-
256
-
-
84890657433
-
-
See Page v. Hollingsworth, 7 Ind. 317 (1855)
-
See Page v. Hollingsworth, 7 Ind. 317 (1855).
-
-
-
-
257
-
-
0000542896
-
Property and Personhood
-
For a succinct statement see Rudolph von Jhering, The Struggle for Law, 2d ed., trans. John J. Lalor (Chicago: Callaghan and Company, 1915), 59: "Property is but the periphery of my person extended to things." For a recent exposition of this perspective, see, I elaborate my own version of such a theory in chapter 9
-
For a succinct statement see Rudolph von Jhering, The Struggle for Law, 2d ed., trans. John J. Lalor (Chicago: Callaghan and Company, 1915), 59: "Property is but the periphery of my person extended to things." For a recent exposition of this perspective, see Margaret J. Radin, "Property and Personhood," Stanford Law Review 34 (1982):957, 959. I elaborate my own version of such a theory in chapter 9.
-
(1982)
Stanford Law Review
, vol.34
-
-
Radin, M.J.1
-
258
-
-
84890600361
-
Vicarious Parental Liability in Connecticut: Is It Effective?
-
See Merleau-Ponty, Phenomenology of Perception, 143. In chapter 9 I propose a more elaborate picture, in which identification with the body and other objects is not based directly on the phenomenology described here, but is linguistically mediated by the use of the concept "I." 38. Although the common law does not generally recognize parents' vicarious liability, many jurisdictions have statutory provisions to this effect. For a survey, see Note
-
See Merleau-Ponty, Phenomenology of Perception, 143. In chapter 9 I propose a more elaborate picture, in which identification with the body and other objects is not based directly on the phenomenology described here, but is linguistically mediated by the use of the concept "I." 38. Although the common law does not generally recognize parents' vicarious liability, many jurisdictions have statutory provisions to this effect. For a survey, see Note, Emogene C. Wilhelm, "Vicarious Parental Liability in Connecticut: Is It Effective?" University of Bridgeport Law Review 7 (1986): 99, 121-24.
-
(1986)
University of Bridgeport Law Review
, vol.7
-
-
Wilhelm, E.C.1
-
259
-
-
0004273012
-
Rethinking Criminal Law
-
For one commentator's testimony of the difficulties encountered in this area, see, Boston:Little, Brown, "Tort scholars have been puzzled for decades to explain the tort rule in employer liability cases." 40. For a comprehensive examination and rejection of the different arguments that might uphold the relevance of actual harm
-
For one commentator's testimony of the difficulties encountered in this area, see George P. Fletcher, Rethinking Criminal Law (Boston:Little, Brown, 1978), sec. 8.5, p. 649: "Tort scholars have been puzzled for decades to explain the tort rule in employer liability cases." 40. For a comprehensive examination and rejection of the different arguments that might uphold the relevance of actual harm
-
(1978)
, pp. 649
-
-
Fletcher, G.P.1
-
260
-
-
0041374777
-
Harm and Punishment: A Critique of Emphasis on the Results of Conduct in the Criminal Law
-
see
-
see Stephen J. Schulhofer, "Harm and Punishment: A Critique of Emphasis on the Results of Conduct in the Criminal Law," University of Pennsylvania Law Review 122 (1974): 1497.
-
(1974)
University of Pennsylvania Law Review
, vol.122
, pp. 1497
-
-
Schulhofer, S.J.1
-
261
-
-
84895628507
-
Moral Luck
-
See, e.g, in Mortal Questions, New York: Cambridge University Press
-
See, e.g., Thomas Nagel, "Moral Luck," in Mortal Questions (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1979), 24;
-
(1979)
, pp. 24
-
-
Nage, T.1
-
262
-
-
0004231635
-
Moral Luck
-
in Moral Luck, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
Bernard Williams, "Moral Luck," in Moral Luck (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981), 20.
-
(1981)
, pp. 20
-
-
Williams, B.1
-
263
-
-
84882786545
-
Moral Luck
-
See
-
See Williams, "Moral Luck," 20-22.
-
-
-
Williams1
-
264
-
-
62449122587
-
Collective Responsibility
-
See, e.g
-
See, e.g., Feinberg, "Collective Responsibility," 248-51;
-
-
-
Feinberg1
-
265
-
-
84890745141
-
Collective Responsibility and Obedience to the Law
-
Thomas R. Flynn, "Collective Responsibility and Obedience to the Law," Georgia Law Review 18 (1984): 845, 846-52;
-
(1984)
Georgia Law Review
, vol.18
-
-
Flynn, T.R.1
-
266
-
-
84890781066
-
Moral Responsibility and Collective Action
-
in Individual and Collective Responsibility, ed. Peter A. French, Cambridge, Mass.: Schenkman
-
Virginia Held, "Moral Responsibility and Collective Action," in Individual and Collective Responsibility, ed. Peter A. French (Cambridge, Mass.: Schenkman, 1972), 101, 108-9.
-
(1972)
-
-
Held, V.1
-
267
-
-
62449122587
-
Collective Responsibility
-
See, e.g
-
See, e.g., Feinberg, "Collective Responsibility," 233.
-
-
-
Feinberg1
-
268
-
-
84890627790
-
-
"From our attribution of an action, and moral responsibility, to a collectivity, it does not follow that the collectivity's members are morally responsible for the action of the collectivity." Held, "Moral Responsibility," 109 (footnote omitted)
-
"From our attribution of an action, and moral responsibility, to a collectivity, it does not follow that the collectivity's members are morally responsible for the action of the collectivity." Held, "Moral Responsibility," 109 (footnote omitted).
-
-
-
-
269
-
-
0004130035
-
Self and Society: A Symbolic Interactionist Social Psychology
-
See, e.g, Boston: Allyn and Bacon
-
See, e.g., John P. Hewitt, Self and Society: A Symbolic Interactionist Social Psychology (Boston: Allyn and Bacon, 1976), 91-95.
-
(1976)
, pp. 91-95
-
-
Hewitt, J.P.1
-
270
-
-
84890580206
-
-
My discussion focuses on the social or cultural meaning of "American identity," not on the formal meaning, as with citizenship requirements
-
My discussion focuses on the social or cultural meaning of "American identity," not on the formal meaning, as with citizenship requirements.
-
-
-
-
271
-
-
84890587072
-
My Lai and Vietnam: The Issues of Responsibility
-
See, in French, Individual and Collective Responsibility
-
See Stanley Bates, "My Lai and Vietnam: The Issues of Responsibility," in French, Individual and Collective Responsibility, 145, 155-57, 161-63.
-
, vol.145
-
-
Bates, S.1
-
272
-
-
77952424958
-
Criminal Responsibility for the Acts of Another
-
"[I]t is of the very essence of our deep-rooted notions of criminal liability that guilt be personal and individual."
-
"[I]t is of the very essence of our deep-rooted notions of criminal liability that guilt be personal and individual." Francis B. Sayre, "Criminal Responsibility for the Acts of Another," Harvard Law Review 43 (1943): 689, 717.
-
(1943)
Harvard Law Review
, vol.43
-
-
Sayre, F.B.1
-
273
-
-
0006299267
-
Handbook of Criminal Law
-
2d ed, St. Paul: West
-
Wayne R. LaFave and Austin W. Scott Jr., Handbook of Criminal Law, 2d ed. (St. Paul: West, 1986), sec. 6.8, p. 588 (footnote omitted).
-
(1986)
, pp. 588
-
-
LaFave, W.R.1
Scott Jr, A.W.2
-
274
-
-
33846379390
-
The Unnecessary Crime of Conspiracy
-
See, e.g
-
See, e.g., Phillip E. Johnson, "The Unnecessary Crime of Conspiracy," California Law Review 61 (1973): 1137.
-
(1973)
California Law Review
, vol.61
, pp. 1137
-
-
Johnson, P.E.1
-
275
-
-
84890591484
-
-
People v. Kessler, 315 N.E.2d 29, 30-31 (Ill. 1974)
-
People v. Kessler, 315 N.E.2d 29, 30-31 (Ill. 1974).
-
-
-
-
276
-
-
84890743643
-
-
This does not amount to an endorsement of the decision or the doctrine. Responsibility, in the sense discussed here, is a necessary but not a sufficient ground for criminal liability; the latter also requires blame. The conclusion that the defendant is not responsible for an offense precludes liability, but Wnding responsibility does not by itself authorize criminal punishment. Further conditions of blameworthiness must be satisfied, but they fall outside my present topic
-
This does not amount to an endorsement of the decision or the doctrine. Responsibility, in the sense discussed here, is a necessary but not a sufficient ground for criminal liability; the latter also requires blame. The conclusion that the defendant is not responsible for an offense precludes liability, but Wnding responsibility does not by itself authorize criminal punishment. Further conditions of blameworthiness must be satisfied, but they fall outside my present topic.
-
-
-
-
277
-
-
84890587864
-
-
1 W.L.R. 317 (1955)
-
1 W.L.R. 317 (1955).
-
-
-
-
278
-
-
5644303072
-
Freedom and Responsibility
-
Criminal law theory casts this issue as a dispute over the adequate definition of "act"-that is, whether the definition should include a reference to the element of voluntariness. See, e.g, Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press
-
Criminal law theory casts this issue as a dispute over the adequate definition of "act"-that is, whether the definition should include a reference to the element of voluntariness. See, e.g., Herbert Morris, Freedom and Responsibility (Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press, 1961), 105-7.
-
(1961)
, pp. 105-107
-
-
Morris, H.1
-
279
-
-
84890661979
-
-
There are in fact references in the decision to the impairment of Charlson's self-control as a result of the tumor. See Charlson, 1 W.L.R. at 320-22
-
There are in fact references in the decision to the impairment of Charlson's self-control as a result of the tumor. See Charlson, 1 W.L.R. at 320-22.
-
-
-
-
280
-
-
1542402744
-
Innovations in the Prosecution of Child Sexual Abuse Cases
-
For data concerning the treatment of child molesters in a number of jurisdictions see, Washington, D.C.: American Bar Association
-
For data concerning the treatment of child molesters in a number of jurisdictions see Josephine Bulkley, ed., Innovations in the Prosecution of Child Sexual Abuse Cases (Washington, D.C.: American Bar Association, 1981), 9-134.
-
(1981)
, pp. 9-134
-
-
Bulkley, J.1
-
281
-
-
84890599377
-
-
2 All E.R. 801 (H.L. 1952)
-
2 All E.R. 801 (H.L. 1952).
-
-
-
-
282
-
-
84890609457
-
-
Model Penal Code, sec. 210.3(1)(b) (Proposed Official Draft 1962)
-
Model Penal Code, sec. 210.3(1)(b) (Proposed Official Draft 1962).
-
-
-
-
283
-
-
84890773551
-
-
Model Penal Code and Commentaries, part II, sec. 210.3, at 56 (Official Draft and Revised Comments 1980)
-
Model Penal Code and Commentaries, part II, sec. 210.3, at 56 (Official Draft and Revised Comments 1980).
-
-
-
-
284
-
-
84890730598
-
-
Royal Commission on Capital Punishment, 1949-1953, Report (London: Her Majesty's Stationery Office, 1953), 52-53
-
Royal Commission on Capital Punishment, 1949-1953, Report (London: Her Majesty's Stationery Office, 1953), 52-53.
-
-
-
-
285
-
-
0004199169
-
Textbook of Criminal Law
-
2d ed, London: Stevens
-
Glanville L. Williams, Textbook of Criminal Law, 2d ed. (London: Stevens, 1983), 548.
-
(1983)
, pp. 548
-
-
Williams, G.L.1
-
286
-
-
84890728373
-
-
Fletcher, Rethinking Criminal Law; the quotations are from sec. 4.2, pp. 247 and 249, and sec. 6.8, pp. 513-14
-
Fletcher, Rethinking Criminal Law; the quotations are from sec. 4.2, pp. 247 and 249, and sec. 6.8, pp. 513-14.
-
-
-
-
287
-
-
84890596360
-
-
The ordinary use of these terms only roughly approximates the conceptual distinction I want to make
-
The ordinary use of these terms only roughly approximates the conceptual distinction I want to make.
-
-
-
-
288
-
-
0004228374
-
Being-in-the-World
-
For the centrality of the notion of "coping" in Heidegger's conception of the self, see, Cambridge: MIT Press
-
For the centrality of the notion of "coping" in Heidegger's conception of the self, see Hubert L. Dreyfus, Being-in-the-World (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1991), 67-75.
-
(1991)
, pp. 67-75
-
-
Dreyfus, H.L.1
-
289
-
-
84890750873
-
-
These two interpretations of duress are elaborated in Fletcher, Rethinking Criminal Law, secs. 10.3-10.3.4, pp. 798-810
-
These two interpretations of duress are elaborated in Fletcher, Rethinking Criminal Law, secs. 10.3-10.3.4, pp. 798-810.
-
-
-
-
290
-
-
84890636384
-
-
378 A.2d 755 (N.J. 1977). Dr. Toscano, a chiropractor, was charged with aiding the preparation of a fraudulent insurance claim by making out a false medical report and was convicted of conspiring to obtain money by false pretenses. Toscano claimed that he had been under threats to his own and his wife's safety. The conviction was reversed on appeal
-
378 A.2d 755 (N.J. 1977). Dr. Toscano, a chiropractor, was charged with aiding the preparation of a fraudulent insurance claim by making out a false medical report and was convicted of conspiring to obtain money by false pretenses. Toscano claimed that he had been under threats to his own and his wife's safety. The conviction was reversed on appeal.
-
-
-
-
291
-
-
0039231164
-
The Morality of the Criminal Law
-
Judge Bazelon has argued for an expanded insanity defense that extends to extreme social deprivation. See
-
Judge Bazelon has argued for an expanded insanity defense that extends to extreme social deprivation. See David L. Bazelon, "The Morality of the Criminal Law," Southern California Law Review 49 (1976): 385, 394-98;
-
(1976)
Southern California Law Review
, vol.49
-
-
Bazelon, D.L.1
-
292
-
-
0010506431
-
Rotten Social Background: Should the Criminal Law Recognize a Defense of Severe Environmental Deprivation?
-
see also
-
see also Richard Delgado, "Rotten Social Background: Should the Criminal Law Recognize a Defense of Severe Environmental Deprivation?" Law and Inequality Journal 3 (1985): 9, 12.
-
(1985)
Law and Inequality Journal
, vol.3
-
-
Delgado, R.1
-
293
-
-
0000109958
-
Interpretive Construction in the Substantive Criminal Law
-
See
-
See Mark Kelman, "Interpretive Construction in the Substantive Criminal Law," Stanford Law Review 33 (1981): 591, 643-44.
-
(1981)
Stanford Law Review
, vol.33
-
-
Kelman, M.1
-
294
-
-
0004071845
-
Commentaries on the Laws of England
-
Blackstone, for example, lists the execution of condemned criminals as the Wrst item in his discussion of justified homicide; self-defense appears later in that discussion. See, London: T. Cadell
-
Blackstone, for example, lists the execution of condemned criminals as the Wrst item in his discussion of justified homicide; self-defense appears later in that discussion. See William Blackstone, Commentaries on the Laws of England (London: T. Cadell, 1791), 4:178.
-
(1791)
, vol.4
, pp. 178
-
-
Blackstone, W.1
-
295
-
-
0040390944
-
Ruthlessness in Public Life
-
in Mortal Questions
-
Compare Nagel, "Ruthlessness in Public Life," in Mortal Questions, 75;
-
-
-
Nagel, C.1
-
296
-
-
0039500616
-
Politics and Moral Character
-
in Moral Luck
-
Williams, "Politics and Moral Character," in Moral Luck, 54;
-
-
-
Williams1
-
297
-
-
7444256978
-
Political Action: The Problem of Dirty Hands
-
in War and Moral Responsibility, ed. Marshall Cohen, Thomas Nagel, and Thomas Scanlon, Princeton: Princeton University Press
-
Michael Walzer, "Political Action: The Problem of Dirty Hands," in War and Moral Responsibility, ed. Marshall Cohen, Thomas Nagel, and Thomas Scanlon (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1974), 62.
-
(1974)
, pp. 62
-
-
Walzer, M.1
-
298
-
-
84890594655
-
Handbook of Criminal Law
-
See generally, sec. 3.3
-
See generally LaFave and Scott, Handbook of Criminal Law, sec. 3.3, pp. 211-12.
-
-
-
LaFave1
Scott2
-
299
-
-
84860625940
-
Human Rights and the Moral Foundations of Substantive Criminal Law
-
For a Kantian interpretation of criminal law's main doctrines, see
-
For a Kantian interpretation of criminal law's main doctrines, see David Richards, "Human Rights and the Moral Foundations of Substantive Criminal Law," Georgia Law Review 13 (1979): 1395.
-
(1979)
Georgia Law Review
, vol.13
, pp. 1395
-
-
Richards, D.1
-
300
-
-
84890682115
-
-
Throughout this essay I use intention broadly and interchangeably with mental state to include such things as beliefs, emotions, and desires
-
Throughout this essay I use intention broadly and interchangeably with mental state to include such things as beliefs, emotions, and desires.
-
-
-
-
301
-
-
0004097793
-
Speech Acts
-
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, and Expression and Meaning, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
John R. Searle, Speech Acts (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1969), 60-65, and Expression and Meaning (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1979), 4-5.
-
(1969)
-
-
Searle, J.R.1
-
302
-
-
84890683089
-
-
For the sake of this example I simply stipulate a majority rule for the jury's decision rather than a requirement of unanimity. Nothing substantive in my argument depends on this stipulation
-
For the sake of this example I simply stipulate a majority rule for the jury's decision rather than a requirement of unanimity. Nothing substantive in my argument depends on this stipulation.
-
-
-
-
303
-
-
14544303435
-
Identification and Externality
-
and "Identification and Wholeheartedness," in The Importance of What We Care About (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
Harry G. Frankfurt, "Identification and Externality" and "Identification and Wholeheartedness," in The Importance of What We Care About (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1977), 50 and 159.
-
(1977)
-
-
Frankfurt, H.G.1
-
304
-
-
84890709998
-
-
I do not mean to suggest that these benefits provide the main reasons or explanations for the theater, but only that they can be usefully extrapolated from the theater example in order to illuminate the nature of official roles
-
I do not mean to suggest that these benefits provide the main reasons or explanations for the theater, but only that they can be usefully extrapolated from the theater example in order to illuminate the nature of official roles.
-
-
-
-
305
-
-
80054445940
-
Theatricality: A Study of Convention in Theater and in Social Life
-
On the use by sociologists of the theater analogy to explore the nature of social roles, New York: Harper and Row
-
On the use by sociologists of the theater analogy to explore the nature of social roles, compare E. Burns, Theatricality: A Study of Convention in Theater and in Social Life (New York: Harper and Row, 1972).
-
(1972)
-
-
Burns, E.1
-
306
-
-
0003740191
-
Reasons and Persons
-
A similarly scalar conception of self is argued for by, Oxford: Clarendon Press, part 3
-
A similarly scalar conception of self is argued for by Derek Parfit, Reasons and Persons (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984), part 3.
-
(1984)
-
-
Parfit, D.1
-
307
-
-
0348046485
-
Legislative Intent
-
G. C. MacCallum Jr., "Legislative Intent," Yale Law Journal 75 (1966): 745, 773.
-
(1966)
, vol.75
-
-
MacCallum Jr, G.C.1
-
308
-
-
84890599905
-
-
See e.g. New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U.S. 254 (1964)
-
See e.g. New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U.S. 254 (1964).
-
-
-
-
309
-
-
84890587514
-
-
Compare the increased First Amendment protection given to abusive language directed to police officers as reflecting and encouraging an increased role distance in their case. See Lewis v. New Orleans, 408 U.S. 913 (1972)
-
Compare the increased First Amendment protection given to abusive language directed to police officers as reflecting and encouraging an increased role distance in their case. See Lewis v. New Orleans, 408 U.S. 913 (1972).
-
-
-
-
310
-
-
0003956640
-
The Morality of Freedom
-
Probably the best statement of this approach is in, Oxford: Clarendon Press
-
Probably the best statement of this approach is in Joseph Raz, The Morality of Freedom (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986), chap. 7.
-
(1986)
-
-
Raz, J.1
-
311
-
-
84890580726
-
-
My discussion is limited to the ownership by an individual owner of physical objects. This leaves out, among many things, important forms of wealth such as ownership of stock, collective ownership of various kinds, etc. Though my discussion bears indirectly on these kinds of property, I do not deal with them here
-
My discussion is limited to the ownership by an individual owner of physical objects. This leaves out, among many things, important forms of wealth such as ownership of stock, collective ownership of various kinds, etc. Though my discussion bears indirectly on these kinds of property, I do not deal with them here.
-
-
-
-
312
-
-
84890629769
-
-
Exchange value, such as that of money, is obviously parasitic on such primary advantages as those I list. However, the concept of object value and the analysis based on it pertain to objects with such secondary value as well
-
Exchange value, such as that of money, is obviously parasitic on such primary advantages as those I list. However, the concept of object value and the analysis based on it pertain to objects with such secondary value as well.
-
-
-
-
313
-
-
0002953848
-
Some Fundamental Legal Conceptions as Applied in Judicial Reasoning
-
See
-
See Wesley Hohfeld, "Some Fundamental Legal Conceptions as Applied in Judicial Reasoning," Yale Law Journal 23 (1913): 16;
-
(1913)
Yale Law Journal
, vol.23
, pp. 16
-
-
Hohfeld, W.1
-
314
-
-
0002398287
-
Ownership
-
in Oxford Essays in Jurisprudence (Wrst series), ed. A. G. Guest, Oxford: Clarendon Press
-
A. M. Honoré, "Ownership," in Oxford Essays in Jurisprudence (Wrst series), ed. A. G. Guest (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1961), 107;
-
(1961)
, pp. 107
-
-
Honoré, A.M.1
-
316
-
-
0005034284
-
The Disintegration of Property
-
Property, ed. J. Roland Pennock and John W. Chapman (New York: New York University Press
-
Thomas Grey, "The Disintegration of Property," Nomos 22: Property, ed. J. Roland Pennock and John W. Chapman (New York: New York University Press, 1980), 69-85;
-
(1980)
Nomos
-
-
Grey, T.1
-
317
-
-
0004273160
-
A Theory of Property
-
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
Stephen Munzer, A Theory of Property (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990), 22-23.
-
(1990)
, pp. 22-23
-
-
Munzer, S.1
-
318
-
-
84890769124
-
-
Wooley v. Maynard, 430 U.S. 705 (1976)
-
Wooley v. Maynard, 430 U.S. 705 (1976).
-
-
-
-
319
-
-
0003489804
-
The Blue and Brown Books
-
Immunity to such error is associated with the use of I "as subject," in Wittgenstein's terminology. See, New York: Oxford University Press
-
Immunity to such error is associated with the use of I "as subject," in Wittgenstein's terminology. See The Blue and Brown Books (New York: Oxford University Press, 1958), 66-67.
-
(1958)
, pp. 66-67
-
-
-
320
-
-
0000694249
-
Self-reference and Self-Awareness
-
For a clear statement of the issues involved see
-
For a clear statement of the issues involved see Sydney Shoemaker, "Self-reference and Self-Awareness," Journal of Philosophy 65 (1968): 555.
-
(1968)
Journal of Philosophy
, vol.65
, pp. 555
-
-
Shoemaker, S.1
-
321
-
-
34250468539
-
The Reference of 'I,'
-
The problem of drawing the boundaries of the entity to which I refers is also raised in Michael Woods, "Reference and Self-Identification," Journal of Philosophy 65 (1968): 568
-
Cf. Eddy Zemach, "The Reference of 'I,'" Philosophical Studies 23 (1972): 68. The problem of drawing the boundaries of the entity to which I refers is also raised in Michael Woods, "Reference and Self-Identification," Journal of Philosophy 65 (1968): 568.
-
(1972)
Philosophical Studies
, vol.23
, pp. 68
-
-
Zemach, E.1
-
322
-
-
0004289648
-
The Construction of Social Reality
-
These comments draw heavily on, New York: Free Press
-
These comments draw heavily on John R. Searle, The Construction of Social Reality (New York: Free Press, 1995);
-
(1995)
-
-
Searle, J.R.1
-
323
-
-
0004262394
-
On Social Facts
-
see also, Princeton: Princeton University Press
-
see also Margaret Gilbert, On Social Facts (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1992).
-
(1992)
-
-
Gilbert, M.1
-
324
-
-
84890586537
-
-
Cf. the view of self-ownership as stated in 1646 by the Leveller Richard Overton, in An Arrow against all Tyrants: "for every one as he is himselfe, so he hath a selfe propriety, else could he not be himselfe." (Cited in Day, "Locke on Property," at 219.)
-
Cf. the view of self-ownership as stated in 1646 by the Leveller Richard Overton, in An Arrow against all Tyrants: "for every one as he is himselfe, so he hath a selfe propriety, else could he not be himselfe." (Cited in Day, "Locke on Property," at 219.)
-
-
-
-
325
-
-
84890677681
-
-
See sources cited in note 22
-
See sources cited in note 22.
-
-
-
-
326
-
-
84890714212
-
-
See for example Blackstone's classical definition of ownership as "the sole and despotic dominion which one man claims and exercises over the external things of the world, in total exclusion of the right of any other individual in the universe." William Blackstone, Commentaries on the Laws of England, 11th ed. (London: T. Cadell, 1791), 2:2
-
See for example Blackstone's classical definition of ownership as "the sole and despotic dominion which one man claims and exercises over the external things of the world, in total exclusion of the right of any other individual in the universe." William Blackstone, Commentaries on the Laws of England, 11th ed. (London: T. Cadell, 1791), 2:2.
-
-
-
-
327
-
-
0003740191
-
Reasons and Persons
-
Oxford: Clarendon Press
-
Derek Parfit, Reasons and Persons (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984), part 3.
-
(1984)
, pp. 3
-
-
Parfit, D.1
-
328
-
-
84890662348
-
-
Breithaupt v. Abram, 352 U.S. 432 (1956)
-
Breithaupt v. Abram, 352 U.S. 432 (1956).
-
-
-
-
329
-
-
0003740191
-
Reasons and Persons
-
Oxford: Clarendon Press
-
Derek Parfit, Reasons and Persons (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984), part 3.
-
(1984)
, pp. 3
-
-
Parfit, D.1
-
330
-
-
84890598384
-
-
Breithaupt v. Abram, 352 U.S. 432 (1956)
-
Breithaupt v. Abram, 352 U.S. 432 (1956).
-
-
-
-
331
-
-
0004305896
-
Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals
-
The most influential source of the modern secular conception of dignity is, trans. H. J. Paton, London: Hutchinson
-
The most influential source of the modern secular conception of dignity is Immanuel Kant, Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals, trans. H. J. Paton (London: Hutchinson, 1948), 96-97.
-
(1948)
, pp. 96-97
-
-
Kant, I.1
|