메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn , Issue , 2008, Pages 175-205

Kantian ethics, exploitation, and multinational clinical trials

(1)  Siegel, Andrew W a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 84890610569     PISSN: None     EISSN: None     Source Type: Book    
DOI: None     Document Type: Chapter
Times cited : (6)

References (27)
  • 1
    • 12944267984 scopus 로고
    • On the Proverb: That May Be True in Theory, But Is of No Practical Use
    • in Perpetual Peace and Other Essays, trans.Ted Humphrey (Indianapolis: Hackett
    • Immanuel Kant, "On the Proverb: That May Be True in Theory, But Is of No Practical Use," in Perpetual Peace and Other Essays, trans.Ted Humphrey (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1992), 89.
    • (1992) , pp. 89
    • Kant, I.1
  • 2
    • 4644265447 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • fair benefits
    • This point is consistent with the, view, which, in dissent from the general consensus, holds that collateral health benefits from the conduct of research may suffice to prevent exploitation. See "Moral Standards for Research in Developing Countries: From 'Reasonable Availability' to 'Fair Benefits,'"
    • This point is consistent with the "fair benefits" view, which, in dissent from the general consensus, holds that collateral health benefits from the conduct of research may suffice to prevent exploitation. See "Moral Standards for Research in Developing Countries: From 'Reasonable Availability' to 'Fair Benefits,'" Hastings Center Report 34, no. 3 (2004): 17-27.
    • (2004) Hastings Center Report , vol.34 , Issue.3 , pp. 17-27
  • 3
    • 84967096043 scopus 로고
    • Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals, trans. J. W. Ellington
    • Indianapolis: Hackett
    • Immanuel Kant, Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals, trans. J. W. Ellington (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1993), 421.
    • (1993) , pp. 421
    • Kant, I.1
  • 4
    • 84890658141 scopus 로고
    • Kant on False Promises
    • Some Kant commentators have argued that we should view his conceptual contradiction test as strictly concerned with logical impossibility, while others have argued that it is practical impossibility that matters. For the former, see, Proceedings of the Third International Kant Congress, ed. L.W. Beck (Dordrecht: D. Reidel, for the latter
    • Some Kant commentators have argued that we should view his conceptual contradiction test as strictly concerned with logical impossibility, while others have argued that it is practical impossibility that matters. For the former, see A.Wood, "Kant on False Promises," Proceedings of the Third International Kant Congress, ed. L.W. Beck (Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 1972); for the latter
    • (1972)
    • Wood, A.1
  • 5
    • 0141710143 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kant's Formula of Universal Law
    • in Creating the Kingdom of Ends (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • see Christine Korsgaard, "Kant's Formula of Universal Law," in Creating the Kingdom of Ends (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996).
    • (1996)
    • Korsgaard, C.1
  • 6
    • 14644404471 scopus 로고
    • Murder and Mayhem
    • in The Practice of Moral Judgment (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • Barbara Herman, "Murder and Mayhem," in The Practice of Moral Judgment (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993).
    • (1993)
    • Herman, B.1
  • 7
    • 0009077238 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Moral Deliberation and the Derivation of Duties
    • in The Practice of Moral Judgment, 154. This idea is nicely captured in Philip Roth's Everyman, in a character's reflections on her husband's lies about an affair: "Lying is cheap, contemptible control over the other person. It's watching the other person acting on incomplete information-in other words, humiliating herself." Philip Roth, Everyman (New York: Houghton Mifflin
    • Barbara Herman, "Moral Deliberation and the Derivation of Duties," in The Practice of Moral Judgment, 154. This idea is nicely captured in Philip Roth's Everyman, in a character's reflections on her husband's lies about an affair: "Lying is cheap, contemptible control over the other person. It's watching the other person acting on incomplete information-in other words, humiliating herself." Philip Roth, Everyman (New York: Houghton Mifflin, 2006), 121.
    • (2006) , pp. 121
    • Herman, B.1
  • 8
    • 84890721710 scopus 로고
    • Mutual Aid and Respect for Persons," in The Practice of Moral Judgment; and Onora O'Neil, "Universal Laws and Ends-in-Themselves
    • in Contructions of Reason (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • See Herman, "Mutual Aid and Respect for Persons," in The Practice of Moral Judgment; and Onora O'Neil, "Universal Laws and Ends-in-Themselves," in Contructions of Reason (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989).
    • (1989)
    • Herman1
  • 9
    • 84890689542 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is in fundamental opposition to consequentialist and modern decision-theoretic accounts, which view rational choice as serving a merely instrumental role in producing valuable states of affairs
    • This is in fundamental opposition to consequentialist and modern decision-theoretic accounts, which view rational choice as serving a merely instrumental role in producing valuable states of affairs.
  • 10
    • 24944457403 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kant's Formula of Humanity
    • in Creating the Kingdom of Ends
    • Christine Korsgaard, "Kant's Formula of Humanity," in Creating the Kingdom of Ends.
    • Korsgaard, C.1
  • 11
    • 0009993153 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kant's Ethical Thought
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Allen Wood, Kant's Ethical Thought (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999), 130.
    • (1999) , pp. 130
    • Wood, A.1
  • 12
    • 84890783755 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As Korsgaard argues, the deceiver treats persons as mere means because he treats an agent's reason "as a mediate rather than a first cause." Korsgaard, "The Right to Lie," in Creating the Kingdom of Ends, 141
    • As Korsgaard argues, the deceiver treats persons as mere means because he treats an agent's reason "as a mediate rather than a first cause." Korsgaard, "The Right to Lie," in Creating the Kingdom of Ends, 141.
  • 13
    • 0041854992 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Metaphysics of Morals, trans. and ed. Mary Gregor
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Immanuel Kant, The Metaphysics of Morals, trans. and ed. Mary Gregor (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), 463, 465.
    • (1996) , vol.463 , pp. 465
    • Kant, I.1
  • 14
    • 84890636539 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Council for International Organizations of Medical Sciences (CIOMS), International Ethical Guidelines for Biomedical Research Involving Human Subjects (1993), Commentary on Guideline 8, at 25
    • Council for International Organizations of Medical Sciences (CIOMS), International Ethical Guidelines for Biomedical Research Involving Human Subjects (1993), Commentary on Guideline 8, at 25.
  • 15
    • 0031875308 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Human Rights and Maternal-Fetal HIV Transmission Prevention Trials in Africa
    • at 562
    • George Annas and Michael Grodin, "Human Rights and Maternal-Fetal HIV Transmission Prevention Trials in Africa," American Journal of Public Health 88 (1998): 560-63, at 562.
    • (1998) American Journal of Public Health , vol.88 , pp. 560-563
    • Annas, G.1    Grodin, M.2
  • 16
    • 78049527131 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Exploitation
    • in Exploitation, ed. K.Neilsen and R.Ware (New York: Humanities Press, at 15
    • Allen Wood, "Exploitation," in Exploitation, ed. K.Neilsen and R.Ware (New York: Humanities Press, 1997), 2-26, at 15.
    • (1997) , pp. 2-26
    • Wood, A.1
  • 17
    • 84890697109 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The standard view has been that Kant supports only a minimalist state, which is limited to protecting individuals from interferences with their freedom. For some recent challenges to this view, see Alexander Kaufman,Welfare in the Kantian State (Oxford:Oxford University Press, 1999); and Allen Rosen, Kant's Theory of Justice (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1993)
    • The standard view has been that Kant supports only a minimalist state, which is limited to protecting individuals from interferences with their freedom. For some recent challenges to this view, see Alexander Kaufman,Welfare in the Kantian State (Oxford:Oxford University Press, 1999); and Allen Rosen, Kant's Theory of Justice (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1993).
  • 18
    • 40949103702 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Does Global Inequality Matter?
    • in Global Justice, ed. Thomas Pogge (Oxford: Blackwell
    • C. R. Beitz, "Does Global Inequality Matter?" in Global Justice, ed. Thomas Pogge (Oxford: Blackwell, 2001), 115.
    • (2001) , pp. 115
    • Beitz, C.R.1
  • 19
    • 52849123202 scopus 로고
    • Kant on Imperfect Duty and Supererogation
    • in Dignity and Practical Reason in Kant's Moral Philosophy (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press
    • Thomas Hill, "Kant on Imperfect Duty and Supererogation," in Dignity and Practical Reason in Kant's Moral Philosophy (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1992), 147-73.
    • (1992) , pp. 147-173
    • Hill, T.1
  • 20
    • 84890572658 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • One might argue that even the person who falsely believes that all relief organizations are ineffective displays indifference. For one who makes an effort at educating oneself about relief organizations would learn that many are quite effective; and a person who adopted the maxim of beneficence would presumably wish to educate herself about such matters
    • One might argue that even the person who falsely believes that all relief organizations are ineffective displays indifference. For one who makes an effort at educating oneself about relief organizations would learn that many are quite effective; and a person who adopted the maxim of beneficence would presumably wish to educate herself about such matters.
  • 21
    • 84890743867 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The only exception would be in the very rare instance that even the most minimal contribution would undermine one's being well-off
    • The only exception would be in the very rare instance that even the most minimal contribution would undermine one's being well-off.
  • 22
    • 84890727359 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • GlaxoSmithKline 2001 Annual Report
    • GlaxoSmithKline 2001 Annual Report.
  • 23
    • 0030229913 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Placebo Orthodoxy in Clinical Research II: Ethical, Legal, and Regulatory Myths
    • at 253;World Medical Association, "Declaration of Helsinki: Ethical Principles for Medical Research Involving Human Subjects," Journal of the American Medical Association 284 (2000): 3043- 45
    • See, e.g., Benjamin Freedman, K. C. Glass, and Charles Weijer, "Placebo Orthodoxy in Clinical Research II: Ethical, Legal, and Regulatory Myths," Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 24 (1996): 252-59, at 253;World Medical Association, "Declaration of Helsinki: Ethical Principles for Medical Research Involving Human Subjects," Journal of the American Medical Association 284 (2000): 3043- 45.
    • (1996) Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics , vol.24 , pp. 252-259
    • Freedman, B.1    Glass, K.C.2    Weijer, C.3
  • 24
    • 0032199232 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Science in the Service of Healing
    • at 36
    • See, e.g., C. Grady, "Science in the Service of Healing," Hastings Center Report 28, no. 6 (1998): 34-38, at 36;
    • (1998) Hastings Center Report , vol.28 , Issue.6 , pp. 34-38
    • Grady, C.1
  • 25
    • 0031873862 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Placebo Controls in HIV Perinatal Transmission Trials: A South African's Viewpoint
    • at 565
    • S. Salim and K. Abdool, "Placebo Controls in HIV Perinatal Transmission Trials: A South African's Viewpoint," American Journal of Public Health 88 (1998): 564-66, at 565.
    • (1998) American Journal of Public Health , vol.88 , pp. 564-566
    • Salim, S.1    Abdool, K.2
  • 26
    • 0036510817 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • What Makes Placebo-Controlled Trials Unethical?
    • at 4
    • Franklin Miller and Howard Brody, "What Makes Placebo-Controlled Trials Unethical?" American Journal of Bioethics 2, no. 2 (2002): 3-9, at 4.
    • (2002) American Journal of Bioethics , vol.2 , Issue.2 , pp. 3-9
    • Miller, F.1    Brody, H.2
  • 27
    • 84890768781 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In the Surfaxin trial, it is possible that considerations of cost were not trivial. The cost for surfactant treatments is $1,100 to $2,400 per newborn. In a trial with several hundred individuals receiving the treatment, the cost could be significant, especially if the biotech company is a small one. This is not to deny that there is an obligation to provide the existing treatment as the control in the Surfaxin case. But it is not as clear-cut a case as Case 1 is
    • In the Surfaxin trial, it is possible that considerations of cost were not trivial. The cost for surfactant treatments is $1,100 to $2,400 per newborn. In a trial with several hundred individuals receiving the treatment, the cost could be significant, especially if the biotech company is a small one. This is not to deny that there is an obligation to provide the existing treatment as the control in the Surfaxin case. But it is not as clear-cut a case as Case 1 is.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.