메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 7, Issue 3, 2001, Pages 307-340

Is it wrong to do right when others do wrong?: A Critique of American Tort Law

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 84882824173     PISSN: 13523252     EISSN: 14698048     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1017/s1352325201073050     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (12)

References (40)
  • 2
    • 85022408897 scopus 로고
    • L; and the burden [of precautions necessary to avert L], B; liability depends upon whether B is less than L multiplied by P: i.e., whether B [is less than] PL.” United States v. Carroll Towing Co., 159 F.2d 169, 173 (2d Cir. ).
    • “[I]f the probability [of a foreseeable plaintiff's injury] be called P; the injury, L; and the burden [of precautions necessary to avert L], B; liability depends upon whether B is less than L multiplied by P: i.e., whether B [is less than] PL.” United States v. Carroll Towing Co., 159 F.2d 169, 173 (2d Cir. 1947).
    • (1947) “[I]f the probability [of a foreseeable plaintiff's injury] be called P; the injury
  • 3
    • 0030530625 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see Richard W. Wright, The Standards of Care in Negligence Law, in PHILOSOPHICAL FOUNDATIONS, 250. For a deontological account of tort law's use of the Hand Formula, see Heidi M. Hurd, The Deontology of Negligence, 76 B. U. L. REV.
    • For a denial of the prominence of economic analysis in doctrinal explanation, see Richard W. Wright, The Standards of Care in Negligence Law, in PHILOSOPHICAL FOUNDATIONS, 249-75, 250. For a deontological account of tort law's use of the Hand Formula, see Heidi M. Hurd, The Deontology of Negligence, 76 B. U. L. REV. 249-72 (1996).
    • (1996) For a denial of the prominence of economic analysis in doctrinal explanation , pp. 249
  • 5
    • 75449111545 scopus 로고
    • 551 P.2d 389 (Cal. ).
    • See, e.g., Landeros v. Flood, 551 P.2d 389 (Cal. 1976).
    • (1976) Landeros v. Flood
  • 7
    • 85022370194 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In his view, the content of the concept of corrective justice is given, in part, by the practices in which the concept of corrective justice functions-the principal one being tort law. Since tort doctrines broadly reflect the principle that persons do wrong not to anticipate and avert others’ wrongs, Coleman might argue that this is good reason to believe that corrective justice is compatible with such a principle. See Jules L. Coleman, The Practice of Corrective Justice, in PHILOSOPHICAL FOUNDATIONS, at 53-72. One might think, however, that tort law's requirement that we suspend our activities in anticipation of others’ wrongdoing significantly undercuts Coleman's initial premise that tort law is a practice of corrective justice. If so, it does not follow from the fact that tort law embodies such a commitment that such a commitment is compatible with corrective justice.
    • Jules Coleman might issue a caution here. In his view, the content of the concept of corrective justice is given, in part, by the practices in which the concept of corrective justice functions-the principal one being tort law. Since tort doctrines broadly reflect the principle that persons do wrong not to anticipate and avert others’ wrongs, Coleman might argue that this is good reason to believe that corrective justice is compatible with such a principle. See Jules L. Coleman, The Practice of Corrective Justice, in PHILOSOPHICAL FOUNDATIONS, at 53-72. One might think, however, that tort law's requirement that we suspend our activities in anticipation of others’ wrongdoing significantly undercuts Coleman's initial premise that tort law is a practice of corrective justice. If so, it does not follow from the fact that tort law embodies such a commitment that such a commitment is compatible with corrective justice.
    • Jules Coleman might issue a caution here.
  • 9
    • 0003687747 scopus 로고
    • 2733-83 (Cambridge University Press 1989); RONALD DWORKIN, LAW'S EMPIRE 292-93 (Harvard University Press 1986); JOHN RAWLS, A THEORY OF JUSTICE (Harvard University Press ).
    • See DAVID O. BRINK, MORAL REALISM AND THE FOUNDATIONS OF ETHICS 264-68, 2733-83 (Cambridge University Press 1989); RONALD DWORKIN, LAW'S EMPIRE 292-93 (Harvard University Press 1986); JOHN RAWLS, A THEORY OF JUSTICE (Harvard University Press 1971).
    • (1971) MORAL REALISM AND THE FOUNDATIONS OF ETHICS 264-68
    • BRINK, D.O.1
  • 10
    • 85022355591 scopus 로고
    • 308 N.E.2d 467 (ass. ) (eliminating the distinctions between invitees, licensees, and “trapped, imperiled and helpless trespasser[s]”).
    • See, e.g., Pridgen v. Boston Housing Authority, 308 N.E.2d 467 (ass. 1974) (eliminating the distinctions between invitees, licensees, and “trapped, imperiled and helpless trespasser[s]”).
    • (1974) Pridgen v. Boston Housing Authority
  • 11
    • 85022366445 scopus 로고
    • 439 F.2d 477 (D.C. Cir. 1970) (holding that it was actionable negligence on the part of a landlord not to protect its tenants from third-party criminal assaults); Tarasoff v. Regents of University of California, 551 P.2d 334 (Cal. ) (recognizing a cause of action against a psychologist who failed to warn a woman of his patient's desire to kill her).
    • See, e.g., Kline v. 1500 Massachusetts Avenue Apartment Corp., 439 F.2d 477 (D.C. Cir. 1970) (holding that it was actionable negligence on the part of a landlord not to protect its tenants from third-party criminal assaults); Tarasoff v. Regents of University of California, 551 P.2d 334 (Cal. 1976) (recognizing a cause of action against a psychologist who failed to warn a woman of his patient's desire to kill her).
    • (1976) Kline v. 1500 Massachusetts Avenue Apartment Corp.
  • 14
    • 85022358496 scopus 로고
    • In Weirum. v. RKO General Inc., 539 P.2d 36 (Cal. ), the Court held that a radio station could be held liable for the death of a driver who was killed by two teenagers while they were racing to intercept the station's disk jockey after he announced that he had “bread to spread” to the first person who made it to his location. The court found that the station posed “an unreasonable risk of harm to [the plaintiff]” by hosting an event in which contestants would foreseeably engage in “competitive pursuits on public streets.” In Bigbee v. Pacific Telephone and Telegraph Co., the Court held that a telephone company could be held liable for injuries sustained by a plaintiff who was hit by a drunk driver while in a telephone booth. The Court held that in light of the foreseeability of reckless drivers, the company could be found to have negligently placed its booth within fifteen feet of a major thoroughfare (where outdoor booths are commonly located).
    • Consider only two of the many cases in which the classic tests of breach have been thought to generate the conclusion that defendants have been negligent for failing to anticipate and avert others’ negligence. In Weirum. v. RKO General Inc., 539 P.2d 36 (Cal. 1975), the Court held that a radio station could be held liable for the death of a driver who was killed by two teenagers while they were racing to intercept the station's disk jockey after he announced that he had “bread to spread” to the first person who made it to his location. The court found that the station posed “an unreasonable risk of harm to [the plaintiff]” by hosting an event in which contestants would foreseeably engage in “competitive pursuits on public streets.” In Bigbee v. Pacific Telephone and Telegraph Co., the Court held that a telephone company could be held liable for injuries sustained by a plaintiff who was hit by a drunk driver while in a telephone booth. The Court held that in light of the foreseeability of reckless drivers, the company could be found to have negligently placed its booth within fifteen feet of a major thoroughfare (where outdoor booths are commonly located).
    • (1975) Consider only two of the many cases in which the classic tests of breach have been thought to generate the conclusion that defendants have been negligent for failing to anticipate and avert others’ negligence.
  • 15
    • 85022387063 scopus 로고
    • Watson v. Kentucky & Indiana Bridge & Ry. Co., 126 S.W. 146, 151 (Ky. ) (holding that a railroad proximately caused an arsonist's fire when it failed to prevent the arsonist from tossing a match onto a tanker gas spill). Courts uncomfortable with this result have simply declared that third-party wrongdoing is unforeseeable. “[I]f the intervening agency is something so unexpected or extraordinary as that [the defendant] could not or ought not to have anticipated it, he will not be liable and certainly he is not bound to anticipate the criminal acts of others by which damage is inflicted, and hence is not liable therefore.” Watson, 126 S.W. at 146 (emphasis added).
    • See, e.g., Watson v. Kentucky & Indiana Bridge & Ry. Co., 126 S.W. 146, 151 (Ky. 1910) (holding that a railroad proximately caused an arsonist's fire when it failed to prevent the arsonist from tossing a match onto a tanker gas spill). Courts uncomfortable with this result have simply declared that third-party wrongdoing is unforeseeable. “[I]f the intervening agency is something so unexpected or extraordinary as that [the defendant] could not or ought not to have anticipated it, he will not be liable and certainly he is not bound to anticipate the criminal acts of others by which damage is inflicted, and hence is not liable therefore.” Watson, 126 S.W. at 146 (emphasis added). Of course, what this really means is that persons ought not to have to foresee third-party intentional wrongdoing, not that they cannot foresee it.
    • (1910) Of course, what this really means is that persons ought not to have to foresee third-party intentional wrongdoing, not that they cannot foresee it.
  • 16
    • 85022350709 scopus 로고
    • see H. L. A. HART&TONY HONORE, CAUSATION IN THE LAW 68-81 (2nd ed., Oxford University Press ).
    • For the classic articulation of the direct cause test of proximacy, see H. L. A. HART&TONY HONORE, CAUSATION IN THE LAW 68-81 (2nd ed., Oxford University Press 1985).
    • (1985) For the classic articulation of the direct cause test of proximacy
  • 17
    • 85022440885 scopus 로고
    • HART, “The general principle of the traditional doctrine is that the free, deliberate and informed act or omission of a human being, intended to exploit the situation created by the defendant, negatives any causal connection.” note 18, at 138. Similarly, when a pedestrian who is injured by a negligent driver is further injured by a negligent ambulance driver, the original driver is deemed a proximate cause of the entire set of injuries sustained by the pedestrian. See, e.g., Atherton v. Devine, 602 P.2d 634 (Okla. ).
    • HART, “The general principle of the traditional doctrine is that the free, deliberate and informed act or omission of a human being, intended to exploit the situation created by the defendant, negatives any causal connection.” note 18, at 138. Thus, while an arsonist will break the causal chain between a railroad's negligent gas spill and a resulting fire, a passerby who carelessly tosses a lighted cigarette into the spill will not. Similarly, when a pedestrian who is injured by a negligent driver is further injured by a negligent ambulance driver, the original driver is deemed a proximate cause of the entire set of injuries sustained by the pedestrian. See, e.g., Atherton v. Devine, 602 P.2d 634 (Okla. 1979).
    • (1979) Thus, while an arsonist will break the causal chain between a railroad's negligent gas spill and a resulting fire, a passerby who carelessly tosses a lighted cigarette into the spill will not.
  • 19
    • 85022408410 scopus 로고
    • As one court declared in a case in which the defendant violated such an ordinance: “Since it is a safety measure, its violation was negligence. This negligence created the hazard and thereby brought about the harm which the ordinance was intended to prevent. It was therefore a legal or ‘proximate’ cause of the harm.” Ross v. Hartman, 139 F.2d 14, 15 (D.C. Cir. ) (emphasis added).
    • Some jurisdictions treat such enactments as statutory torts; others allow plaintiffs to use them to establish per se negligence; and still others invoke them to make car owners “per se proximate causes” of any harms caused by fleeing car thieves. As one court declared in a case in which the defendant violated such an ordinance: “Since it is a safety measure, its violation was negligence. This negligence created the hazard and thereby brought about the harm which the ordinance was intended to prevent. It was therefore a legal or ‘proximate’ cause of the harm.” Ross v. Hartman, 139 F.2d 14, 15 (D.C. Cir. 1943) (emphasis added).
    • (1943) Some jurisdictions treat such enactments as statutory torts; others allow plaintiffs to use them to establish per se negligence; and still others invoke them to make car owners “per se proximate causes” of any harms caused by fleeing car thieves.
  • 20
    • 85022396532 scopus 로고
    • see Heidi M. Hurd, Will State's High Court Reform the Tort Laws that Burden Society? SAN DIEGO UNION August 18, (Editorial).
    • For a short critique of this doctrinal collapse, see Heidi M. Hurd, Will State's High Court Reform the Tort Laws that Burden Society? SAN DIEGO UNION August 18, 1991 (Editorial).
    • (1991) For a short critique of this doctrinal collapse
  • 23
    • 77952045341 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (SECOND) OF TORTS § 85.
    • RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS § 85.
    • RESTATEMENT
  • 25
    • 85022448135 scopus 로고
    • In LeBouef v. Goodyear Tire and Rubber Co., 623 F.2d 985, 989 (5th Cir. 1980), a drunk driver was killed when he drove his new Mercury Cougar at over 100 miles per hour on tires that had been tested for safety only for speeds up to 85 miles per hour. While the owner's manual stated that “[c]ontinuous driving over 90 mph requires using high-speed-capability tires,” the court found that it was “to be readily expected” that high-speed driving without such specialty tires would occur, and it ruled that Ford had a “duty either to provide an adequate warning of the specific danger of tread separation at such high speeds or to ameliorate the danger in some other way. In Jackson v. Coast Paint and Lacquer Co., 499 F.2d 809 (9th Cir. ), a paint manufacturer had supplied the following warnings with its paints: “Keep away from heat, sparks, and open flame. USE WITH ADEQUATE VENTILATION. Avoid prolonged contact with skin and breath of spray mist. Close container after each use. KEEP OUT OF REACH OF CHILDREN.” The plaintiff was allowed to reach the jury on the argument that the warning was inadequate because it permitted him to assume that the danger of unventilated use was breathing the toxic fumes, not an explosion-which is how he was injured by his unventilated use of the product.
    • Consider two choice illustrations. In LeBouef v. Goodyear Tire and Rubber Co., 623 F.2d 985, 989 (5th Cir. 1980), a drunk driver was killed when he drove his new Mercury Cougar at over 100 miles per hour on tires that had been tested for safety only for speeds up to 85 miles per hour. While the owner's manual stated that “[c]ontinuous driving over 90 mph requires using high-speed-capability tires,” the court found that it was “to be readily expected” that high-speed driving without such specialty tires would occur, and it ruled that Ford had a “duty either to provide an adequate warning of the specific danger of tread separation at such high speeds or to ameliorate the danger in some other way. In Jackson v. Coast Paint and Lacquer Co., 499 F.2d 809 (9th Cir. 1974), a paint manufacturer had supplied the following warnings with its paints: “Keep away from heat, sparks, and open flame. USE WITH ADEQUATE VENTILATION. Avoid prolonged contact with skin and breath of spray mist. Close container after each use. KEEP OUT OF REACH OF CHILDREN.” The plaintiff was allowed to reach the jury on the argument that the warning was inadequate because it permitted him to assume that the danger of unventilated use was breathing the toxic fumes, not an explosion-which is how he was injured by his unventilated use of the product.
    • (1974) Consider two choice illustrations.
  • 27
    • 85022375032 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Efficiency must be pursued within a morally defensible framework; so we must ask, and ask first, what aims it is morally desirable and defensible to pursue by imposing tort liability.” Tony Honore, The Morality of Tort Law-Questions and Answers, in PHILOSOPHICAL FOUNDATIONS, at 73-95
    • Thus, as Tony Honore argues: “Tort law, like the rest of law, must satisfy several values, of which efficiency in pursuing worthwhile objectives is only one. Efficiency must be pursued within a morally defensible framework; so we must ask, and ask first, what aims it is morally desirable and defensible to pursue by imposing tort liability.” Tony Honore, The Morality of Tort Law-Questions and Answers, in PHILOSOPHICAL FOUNDATIONS, at 73-95, 74.
    • Thus, as Tony Honore argues: “Tort law, like the rest of law, must satisfy several values, of which efficiency in pursuing worthwhile objectives is only one. , pp. 74
  • 29
    • 85022398795 scopus 로고
    • Inc., 155 A.2d 90 (N.J. 1959). See also Murphy v. Steeplechase Amusement Co., 166 N.E. 173 (N.Y. ) (court invoked assumption of risk doctrine to bar a plaintiff's recovery after he boarded a Coney Island ride seeing clearly that its point-however negligently conceived-was to toss persons around).
    • See, e.g., Meistrich v. Casino Arena Attractions, Inc., 155 A.2d 90 (N.J. 1959). See also Murphy v. Steeplechase Amusement Co., 166 N.E. 173 (N.Y. 1929) (court invoked assumption of risk doctrine to bar a plaintiff's recovery after he boarded a Coney Island ride seeing clearly that its point-however negligently conceived-was to toss persons around).
    • (1929) Meistrich v. Casino Arena Attractions
  • 31
    • 85022395990 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • After all, by definition there can be nothing unduly ‘self-serving’ about his ranking of some of his own interests over other of his own interests.” Simons, Contributory Negligence, at
    • As Ken Simons asks, why not permit a person “to rank his own interests however he likes, since he will suffer the harm? After all, by definition there can be nothing unduly ‘self-serving’ about his ranking of some of his own interests over other of his own interests.” Simons, Contributory Negligence, at 471.
    • As Ken Simons asks, why not permit a person “to rank his own interests however he likes, since he will suffer the harm? , pp. 471
  • 33
    • 0039382353 scopus 로고
    • 5 J. CONTEMP. LEGAL ISSUES 157-216 Hurd, The Deontology of Negligence, John Attanasio has defended what he calls the “principle of aggregate autonomy,” according to which one must “act to protect [others] against severe constrictions of life plans whenever such protection requires de minimis wealth-related interference with one's own life plans.” note 4, at 262-65. Stephen Perry articulates a similar argument in defending the thesis that to risk others is not, by itself, to harm them. Stephen Perry, Risk, Harm, and Responsibility, in PHILOSOPHICAL FOUNDATIONS, at 321-46. See also Honore, The Morality of Tort Law, in PHILOSOPHICAL FOUNDATIONS, at 80-81, 88-91 (arguing that wrongs must be analyzed separately from fault, even if fault is a necessary limit on the pursuit of corrective justice).
    • See Heidi M. Hurd, What in the World Is Wrong?, 5 J. CONTEMP. LEGAL ISSUES 157-216 (1994); Hurd, The Deontology of Negligence, John Attanasio has defended what he calls the “principle of aggregate autonomy,” according to which one must “act to protect [others] against severe constrictions of life plans whenever such protection requires de minimis wealth-related interference with one's own life plans.” note 4, at 262-65. Stephen Perry articulates a similar argument in defending the thesis that to risk others is not, by itself, to harm them. Stephen Perry, Risk, Harm, and Responsibility, in PHILOSOPHICAL FOUNDATIONS, at 321-46. See also Honore, The Morality of Tort Law, in PHILOSOPHICAL FOUNDATIONS, at 80-81, 88-91 (arguing that wrongs must be analyzed separately from fault, even if fault is a necessary limit on the pursuit of corrective justice).
    • (1994) What in the World Is Wrong?
    • Hurd, H.M.1
  • 34
    • 85022443564 scopus 로고
    • see Commonwealth v. Feinberg, 433 Pa. 558, 253 A.2d 636
    • For a criminal case on point, see Commonwealth v. Feinberg, 433 Pa. 558, 253 A.2d 636 (1969).
    • (1969) For a criminal case on point
  • 36
    • 85022370277 scopus 로고
    • As E. M. Forster famously wrote: “I hate the idea of causes, and if I had to choose between betraying my country and betraying my friend, I hope I should have the guts to betray my country.” E. M. FORSTER, TWO CHEERS FOR DEMOCRACY 68 (Harcourt Brace ).
    • Perhaps we might go so far as to say that it is true of friends. As E. M. Forster famously wrote: “I hate the idea of causes, and if I had to choose between betraying my country and betraying my friend, I hope I should have the guts to betray my country.” E. M. FORSTER, TWO CHEERS FOR DEMOCRACY 68 (Harcourt Brace 1951).
    • (1951) Perhaps we might go so far as to say that it is true of friends.
  • 38
    • 85022362012 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Wright, Right, Justice and Tort Law, in PHILOSOPHICAL FOUNDATIONS, at 164. Wright's Kantian conception of virtue is not mine, but Wright's point about that conception nevertheless serves as an important reminder that law may be too blunt an instrument to affect the cultivation of virtue, however it is conceived. I exploit just such an argument in a paper that reluctantly rejects a perfectionist theory of law in favor of a liberal theory. See Heidi M. Hurd, Liberalism by Default (unpublished manuscript available from author).
    • Richard Wright argues that aretaic obligations to cultivate certain virtues, if conceived of in Kant's terms as obligations to “subject the maxim of one's actions to the condition of qualifying as universal law,” simply “cannot be coerced by another.” Wright, Right, Justice and Tort Law, in PHILOSOPHICAL FOUNDATIONS, at 164. Wright's Kantian conception of virtue is not mine, but Wright's point about that conception nevertheless serves as an important reminder that law may be too blunt an instrument to affect the cultivation of virtue, however it is conceived. I exploit just such an argument in a paper that reluctantly rejects a perfectionist theory of law in favor of a liberal theory. See Heidi M. Hurd, Liberalism by Default (unpublished manuscript available from author).
    • Richard Wright argues that aretaic obligations to cultivate certain virtues, if conceived of in Kant's terms as obligations to “subject the maxim of one's actions to the condition of qualifying as universal law,” simply “cannot be coerced by another.”
  • 39
    • 85022391495 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Notwithstanding Richard Posner's spirited claims to the contrary, a utilitarian theory of liability cannot-necessarily cannot-protect rights. Liberals cash out the fundamental tenets of liberalism as claims of right just because they fear that the majority may not prefer them (and so will refuse to honor fundamental protections of liberty and equality). Liberals therefore cannot find adequate status for their most basic principles in a theory that insists on giving themonly as much weight as the majority prefers. Thus Posner's claim that there is “a consilience” between a wealth maximizer's approach to tort law and that of an Aristotelian, a Kantian, an egalitarian, and a consent-based liberal reflects, at best, wishful thinking and, at worst, grave confusion about the implications of such non-utilitarian theories. See Richard A. Posner, Wealth Maximization and Tort Law: A Philosophical Inquiry, in PHILOSOPHICAL FOUNDATIONS, at
    • This promise is, of course, a philosophically false one. Notwithstanding Richard Posner's spirited claims to the contrary, a utilitarian theory of liability cannot-necessarily cannot-protect rights. Liberals cash out the fundamental tenets of liberalism as claims of right just because they fear that the majority may not prefer them (and so will refuse to honor fundamental protections of liberty and equality). Liberals therefore cannot find adequate status for their most basic principles in a theory that insists on giving themonly as much weight as the majority prefers. Thus Posner's claim that there is “a consilience” between a wealth maximizer's approach to tort law and that of an Aristotelian, a Kantian, an egalitarian, and a consent-based liberal reflects, at best, wishful thinking and, at worst, grave confusion about the implications of such non-utilitarian theories. See Richard A. Posner, Wealth Maximization and Tort Law: A Philosophical Inquiry, in PHILOSOPHICAL FOUNDATIONS, at 99-111.
    • This promise is, of course, a philosophically false one. , pp. 99-111
  • 40
    • 85022401345 scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Marc A. Franklin, Replacing the Negligence Lottery: Compensation and Selective Reimbursement, 53 VA. L. REV. 774-814 (1967); Stephen D. Sugarman, Doing Away with Tort Law, 73 CAL. L. REV. 555-664 Jeremy Waldron, Moments of Carelessness and Massive Loss, in PHILOSOPHICAL FOUNDATIONS at
    • Of course there are those who would do away with tort law altogether, being neither utilitarians nor believers that corrective justice demands liability in the circumstances in which tort law imposes it. See, e.g., Marc A. Franklin, Replacing the Negligence Lottery: Compensation and Selective Reimbursement, 53 VA. L. REV. 774-814 (1967); Stephen D. Sugarman, Doing Away with Tort Law, 73 CAL. L. REV. 555-664 (1985); Jeremy Waldron, Moments of Carelessness and Massive Loss, in PHILOSOPHICAL FOUNDATIONS at 387-408.
    • (1985) Of course there are those who would do away with tort law altogether, being neither utilitarians nor believers that corrective justice demands liability in the circumstances in which tort law imposes it. , pp. 387-408


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.