메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 33, Issue 2, 2013, Pages 379-400

Proceduralism, judicial review and the refusal of royal assent

Author keywords

Epistemic democracy; Judicial review; Legitimacy; Proceduralism

Indexed keywords


EID: 84878791139     PISSN: 01436503     EISSN: 14643820     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1093/ojls/gqt003     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (2)

References (85)
  • 1
    • 84869815112 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Between Judicial and Legislative Supremacy: A Cautious Defense of Constrained Judicial Review
    • A Harel and A Shinar, 'Between Judicial and Legislative Supremacy: A Cautious Defense of Constrained Judicial Review' (2012) 10 Int J Constitutional Law 950.
    • (2012) Int J Constitutional Law , vol.10 , pp. 950
    • Harel, A.1    Shinar, A.2
  • 2
    • 84878806337 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note.
    • for an overview of these three theories. I will concentrate on weak judicial review, but my arguments could also support other forms of constrained judicial review.
  • 3
    • 33645815488 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Core of the Case Against Judicial Review
    • J Waldron, 'The Core of the Case Against Judicial Review' (2006) 115 Yale LJ 1346, 1406.
    • (2006) Yale LJ , vol.115
    • Waldron, J.1
  • 4
    • 22744443155 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Democratic Disobedience'
    • D Markovits, 'Democratic Disobedience' (2005) 114 Yale LJ 1897, 1899.
    • (2005) Yale LJ , vol.114
    • Markovits, D.1
  • 7
    • 84924069240 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For the type of argument I have in mind: D Estlund, Democratic Authority: A Philosophical Framework (Princeton University Press)
    • For the type of argument I have in mind: D Estlund, Democratic Authority: A Philosophical Framework (Princeton University Press 2008).
    • (2008)
  • 8
    • 84909362717 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • F Peter
    • Routledge
    • F Peter, Democratic Legitimacy (Routledge 2009).
    • (2009) Democratic Legitimacy
  • 11
    • 0003363903 scopus 로고
    • Law and Democracy
    • J Laws, 'Law and Democracy' (1995) PL 72.
    • (1995) PL , pp. 72
    • Laws, J.1
  • 13
    • 84878803778 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Brettschneider (n 7)
    • Brettschneider (n 7) 137.
  • 14
    • 84878781540 scopus 로고
    • It is mainly with respect to these procedural failures that Ely defends judicial review. J Ely
    • Harvard University Press
    • It is mainly with respect to these procedural failures that Ely defends judicial review. J Ely, Democracy and Distrust: Theory of Judicial Review (Harvard University Press 1980).
    • (1980) Democracy and Distrust: Theory of Judicial Review
  • 15
    • 84878812169 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Markovits (n 3)
    • Markovits (n 3) 1921.
  • 16
    • 0035537730 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Activist Challenges to Deliberative Democracy'
    • IM Young, 'Activist Challenges to Deliberative Democracy' (2001) 29 Political Theory 670, 685-86.
    • (2001) Political Theory , vol.29
    • Young, I.M.1
  • 17
    • 84878796760 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Brettschneider (n 7)
    • Brettschneider (n 7) 145.
  • 18
    • 78751493660 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Proceduralism and Popular Threats to Democracy'
    • AS Kirshner, 'Proceduralism and Popular Threats to Democracy' (2010) 18 J Pol Phil 405, 410.
    • (2010) J Pol Phil , vol.18
    • Kirshner, A.S.1
  • 19
    • 84878791335 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note.
    • 'Pragmatists assess institution and politics in terms of their anticipated consequences, and they claim that those consequences are more likely to be normatively attractive to the extent that they reflect a diversity of perspectives. But they also insist that even consequences that emerge in circumstances of diversity must be further constrained by initial conditions of freedom and equality in both procedural and substantive terms. . . . They are insistent to the extent that pragmatists propose freedom and equality as necessary to the normative justification of democratic politics. But since pragmatists seek to dispense with foundationalist commitments, it is, on their interpretation, the commitment to democratic politics that animates their commitment to freedom and equality, rather than the reverse.' Knight and Johnson (n 6) 44-45.
  • 20
    • 84878776028 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Brettschneider (n 7).
    • Brettschneider (n 7).
  • 21
    • 33645111286 scopus 로고
    • 'Foundations of Democracy'
    • H Kelsen, 'Foundations of Democracy' (1955) 66 Ethics 1, 4.
    • (1955) Ethics , vol.66
    • Kelsen, H.1
  • 22
    • 84878777917 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Peter defends a similar view (n 6)
    • Peter defends a similar view (n 6) 133-34.
  • 23
    • 84878806440 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note.
    • For instance, if a polity was to forbid same-sex marriage based on natural law arguments, such as those we find in Finnis, I would dare to claim that such a law is wrong. It is nonetheless possible that the polity arrived at such a decision rationally based on Finnis's arguments and that there was no procedural failure. This law would therefore be legitimate, though incorrect.
  • 24
    • 1842702196 scopus 로고
    • Law, Morality, and ''Sexual Orientation''
    • J Finnis, 'Law, Morality, and ''Sexual Orientation''' (1995) 9 Notre Dame JL 38.
    • (1995) Notre Dame JL , vol.9 , pp. 38
    • Finnis, J.1
  • 26
    • 84878775723 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This example is not meant to refer to statutory rape.
    • This example is not meant to refer to statutory rape.
  • 27
    • 84878812154 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note.
    • A similar argument can be found in Capustin: 'even in the circumstances of politics, we can reasonably maintain that there are moral limits to the law's authority, and that these limits can sometimes be known. In other words, reason may require us to accept as authoritative the results of fair democratic procedures unless they are known to be unjust.'
  • 28
    • 84878786617 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'The Authority of Law in the Circumstances of Politics'
    • M Capustin, 'The Authority of Law in the Circumstances of Politics' (2007) 20 Can J L Juris 297, 299.
    • (2007) Can J L Juris , vol.20
    • Capustin, M.1
  • 29
    • 84878778755 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For example Estlund's list of primary bads (n 6)
    • For example Estlund's list of primary bads (n 6) 163.
  • 30
    • 84878779646 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note.
    • Another way to formulate this is to say that views that support rape and slavery, for instance, are not reasonable.
  • 31
    • 21644480823 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Democracy, Rights, Disagreements and Judicial Review'
    • P Lenta, 'Democracy, Rights, Disagreements and Judicial Review' (2004) 20 S Afr J Human Rights 1, 7.
    • (2004) S Afr J Human Rights , vol.20
    • Lenta, P.1
  • 32
    • 84878798695 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I thank an anonymous referee for this objection.
    • I thank an anonymous referee for this objection.
  • 33
    • 84878772530 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Brettschneider (n 7)
    • Brettschneider (n 7) 9.
  • 34
    • 84878791432 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note.
    • In my first point, I discuss judicial review in the case of a 'breakdown' of a well-functioning democracy. My other points apply to procedures that are well-functioning and that meet similar requirements as those offered by Waldron, such as a general respect for law.
  • 36
    • 84878781822 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note.
    • I do not discuss judicial review with regard to clear procedural illegitimacy: if the government enacts a law that has not been voted by the legislature for instance. In such cases, what we face is a mistake as to the appropriate procedure to follow, not a disagreement on what the procedure ought to be.
  • 37
    • 84878799172 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Estlund (n 6)
    • Estlund (n 6) 111.
  • 38
    • 84878778547 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note.
    • A procedural right would be the right to vote. A non-procedural right would be a constitutional right to freedom of speech for instance. The distinction between procedure and substance is not rigid as disagreement about procedure can crumble into substantial disagreement.
  • 39
    • 84878782860 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ely (n 11).
    • Ely (n 11).
  • 41
    • 84878779804 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Gaus (n 4)
    • Gaus (n 4) 285.
  • 42
    • 84878783398 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Refining the Question about Judges' Moral Capacity
    • and the related articles in the symposium.
    • J Waldron, 'Refining the Question about Judges' Moral Capacity' (2009) 7 I_CON 1, and the related articles in the symposium.
    • (2009) I_CON , vol.7 , pp. 1
    • Waldron, J.1
  • 43
    • 84878780533 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Gaus (n 4)
    • Gaus (n 4) 185-87.
  • 44
    • 84878778319 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Alon Harel pointed out this imprecision.
    • Alon Harel pointed out this imprecision.
  • 45
    • 84878792160 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Brettschneider's discussion of the benevolent dictatorship (n 7)
    • Brettschneider's discussion of the benevolent dictatorship (n 7) 157.
  • 46
    • 84878789595 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Laws (n 8).
    • Laws (n 8).
  • 47
    • 33750523806 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Right to Judicial Review
    • Y Eylon and A Harel, 'The Right to Judicial Review' (2006) 92 Va L Rev 991.
    • (2006) Va L Rev , vol.92 , pp. 991
    • Eylon, Y.1    Harel, A.2
  • 48
    • 79957897071 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Easy Core Case for Judicial Review
    • A Harel and T Kahana, 'The Easy Core Case for Judicial Review' (2010) 2 J Legal Analysis 227.
    • (2010) J Legal Analysis , vol.2 , pp. 227
    • Harel, A.1    Kahana, T.2
  • 49
    • 84878798805 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Harel and Shinar (n 1).
    • Harel and Shinar (n 1).
  • 50
    • 84878800879 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kirshner (n 17)
    • Kirshner (n 17) 417.
  • 51
    • 84878780439 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note.
    • 'To have a moral justification for attempting to achieve a certain outcome X does not entail that one must always be doing something to achieve X. Parents have a moral justification to try to get their children to be decent human beings. But there are many times when it is best to stand back and hope for the best. A captive has a right that the police do what they can to extract him safely. But there will be circumstances where the police ought to do nothing lest the captor kill the captive. The captive does not thereby lose the right against the police to be free. In the circumstances, there is at least always moral justification for thinking about how best to achieve the outcome and then pursuing a course of action if it is a plausible one.'
  • 52
    • 79960407126 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'An Instrumental Argument for a Human Right to Democracy'
    • T Christiano, 'An Instrumental Argument for a Human Right to Democracy' (2011) 39 P&PA 142, 169.
    • (2011) P&PA , vol.39
    • Christiano, T.1
  • 53
    • 84878777187 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kirshner (n 17)
    • Kirshner (n 17) 422.
  • 54
    • 84878789490 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Christiano argues that such a reason is the protection of human rights (n 45) ; see also Allan (n 9) 95.
    • Christiano argues that such a reason is the protection of human rights (n 45) 161; see also Allan (n 9) 95.
  • 55
    • 84878795169 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • cf Allan (n 9) for whom disobedience and strong judicial review can be seen as serving fidelity to law.
    • cf Allan (n 9) for whom disobedience and strong judicial review can be seen as serving fidelity to law.
  • 56
    • 84878789639 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This claim is highly compatible with theories of constrained judicial review like popular constitutionalism and departmentalism. Harel and Shinar (n 1).
    • This claim is highly compatible with theories of constrained judicial review like popular constitutionalism and departmentalism. Harel and Shinar (n 1).
  • 57
    • 0000351211 scopus 로고
    • The Negotiable Constitution: On the Limitation of Rights (CUP 2009) 210, citing JB Thayer, 'The Origin and Scope of the American Doctrine of Constitutional Law'
    • GC Webber, The Negotiable Constitution: On the Limitation of Rights (CUP 2009) 210, citing JB Thayer, 'The Origin and Scope of the American Doctrine of Constitutional Law' (1893) 7 Harv L Rev 129, 144.
    • (1893) Harv L Rev , vol.7
    • Webber, G.C.1
  • 59
    • 84878787869 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Allan (n 9)
    • Allan (n 9) 206.
  • 60
    • 84878812621 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note.
    • Perry claims that this can and has been the case, ibid 171. In my view, in a well-functioning democracy, the reasonableness of the claim is precisely what we disagree about and it is presumptuous-in practice, though, not in principle-to suppose the unreasonableness of the other views.
  • 61
    • 84878801076 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As exemplified by Waldron
    • As exemplified by Waldron, 'The Core of the Case Against' (n 2) 1406.
    • 'The Core of the Case Against' , vol.2 , pp. 1406
  • 62
    • 84878771780 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • cf Allan (n 9)
    • cf Allan (n 9) 220.
  • 63
    • 84878775454 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I thank an anonymous referee for this objection.
    • I thank an anonymous referee for this objection.
  • 65
    • 84878785147 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Allan (n 9)
    • Allan (n 9) 213.
  • 66
    • 0036420988 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Deliberative Democracy and Constitutional Review'
    • CF Zurn, 'Deliberative Democracy and Constitutional Review' (2002) 21 L and Phil 467, 468.
    • (2002) L and Phil , vol.21
    • Zurn, C.F.1
  • 67
    • 3543018518 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'New Constitutional Ideas: Can New Parliamentary Models Resist Judicial Dominance when Interpreting Rights?'
    • JL Hiebert, 'New Constitutional Ideas: Can New Parliamentary Models Resist Judicial Dominance when Interpreting Rights?' (2004) 82 Texas L Rev 1963, 1977.
    • (2004) Texas L Rev , vol.82
    • Hiebert, J.L.1
  • 68
    • 84878794467 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note.
    • A notwithstanding clause does not imply that the legislature will be able to authorize clear violations of rights. As Allan argues: courts have to interpret the statutes following the idea 'that Parliament intends the rule of law' and this should prevent '[e]ven the most egregious violation of fundamental rights, if sanctioned by a ''literal'' construction' (n 9) 207.
  • 69
    • 84878786066 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note.
    • This is maybe where the rule of the clear mistake would come in handy. But then my point is still valid: the set of cases where it applies is almost empty.
  • 70
    • 84878781884 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Gaus (n 4)
    • Gaus (n 4) 282.
  • 71
    • 84878780953 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note.
    • To prevent a Dworkinian objection here, I only have to claim that rather than objecting with an argument from scepticism to the role of judges in interpreting the law, I am in fact relying on an epistemic argument according to which the legislature is in a better position to perform judgments involving moral principles than the courts. Hence, Hercules would not be in the courts but in Parliament.
  • 73
    • 77249104912 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'The Role of the Courts in the Political Constitution'
    • A Tomkins, 'The Role of the Courts in the Political Constitution' (2010) 60 U Toronto LJ 1, 10.
    • (2010) U Toronto LJ , vol.60
    • Tomkins, A.1
  • 74
    • 84878774397 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note.
    • As Tomkins explains: 'Judicially enforceable substantive rights may be deemed compatible with political constitutionalism when they are narrowly defined and absolute. An absolute ban on torture, for example, is a rule that can and ought to be a rule of law enforceable by the courts. It is those qualified political claims that are elevated to the status of substantive rights that are problematic.'
  • 75
    • 84878803089 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Gaus (n 4) 280; see also Allan (n 9)
    • Gaus (n 4) 280; see also Allan (n 9) 189.
  • 76
    • 4544313629 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'The Horizontal Effect of Constitutional Rights'
    • S Gardbaum, 'The Horizontal Effect of Constitutional Rights' (2003) 102 Michigan L Rev 387, 405.
    • (2003) Michigan L Rev , vol.102
    • Gardbaum, S.1
  • 77
    • 84878778070 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hiebert (n 60) 1964.
    • , vol.60 , pp. 1964
    • Hiebert1
  • 79
    • 84878772758 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Eylon and Harel (n 42)
    • Eylon and Harel (n 42)
  • 80
    • 84878785354 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Harel and Kahana (n 42)
    • Harel and Kahana (n 42)
  • 81
    • 84878772246 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Harel and Shinar (n 1)
    • Harel and Shinar (n 1)
  • 82
    • 84878780543 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • cf Allan (n 9)
    • cf Allan (n 9) 9.
  • 83
    • 84878770636 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hiebert (n 60)
    • Hiebert (n 60) 1985.
  • 84
    • 84878791695 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Political Constitutionalism and Judicial Review
    • accessed 13 August 2012.
    • PP Craig, 'Political Constitutionalism and Judicial Review' (2009) Oxford Legal Studies Research Paper 58/2009, 10 < http://ssrn.com/abstract=1503505> accessed 13 August 2012.
    • (2009) Oxford Legal Studies Research Paper 58/2009 , pp. 10
    • Craig, P.P.1
  • 85
    • 84878799238 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Perry (n 51)
    • Perry (n 51) 162.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.