메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 22, Issue 1, 2012, Pages 73-88

Erratum: Time, rationality, and self-governance (Nous-Supplement: Philosophical Issues 22 (73-88) DOI: 10.1111/j.1533-6077.2012.00219.x);Time, rationality, and self-governance

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 84873392546     PISSN: 15336077     EISSN: 17582237     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1111/phis.12021     Document Type: Erratum
Times cited : (56)

References (29)
  • 1
    • 0003975273 scopus 로고
    • Harvard University Press reissued by CSLI Press, 1999) at 82. As indicated there, I owe this phrase to John Etchemendy.
    • Michael E. Bratman, Intention, Plans, and Practical Reason (Harvard University Press, 1987; reissued by CSLI Press, 1999) at 82. As indicated there, I owe this phrase to John Etchemendy.
    • (1987) Intention, Plans, and Practical Reason
    • Bratman, M.E.1
  • 2
    • 84873391589 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is pretty much where I left this matter in Intention, Plans, and Practical Reason.
    • This is pretty much where I left this matter in Intention, Plans, and Practical Reason.
  • 3
    • 43249137952 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Wide or Narrow Scope?
    • See e.g., John Broome, "Wide or Narrow Scope?" Mind 116 (2007): 359-70.
    • (2007) Mind , vol.116 , pp. 359-370
    • Broome, J.1
  • 4
    • 82055199199 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Instrumental Rationality, Symmetry, and Scope
    • also highlights a distinction between local and overall rationality in his at 129-30.
    • John Brunero also highlights a distinction between local and overall rationality in his "Instrumental Rationality, Symmetry, and Scope," Philosophical Studies 157 (2012): 125-140, at 129-30.
    • (2012) Philosophical Studies , vol.157 , pp. 125-140
    • Brunero, J.1
  • 5
    • 0003867020 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Harvard University Press For different but related ideas see Pamela Hieronymi, "The Wrong Kind of Reason," Journal of Philosophy 102 (2005): 437-57, and John Broome, Rationality Through Reasoning (unpublishedMS, version of July, 2011, "complete26"), Chap. 3. [My references to this manuscript below will be to this as yet unpublished manuscript.] But these are complexities we can safely ignore here.
    • T. M. Scanlon, What We Owe to Each Other (Harvard University Press, 1998), p. 17. For different but related ideas see Pamela Hieronymi, "The Wrong Kind of Reason," Journal of Philosophy 102 (2005): 437-57, and John Broome, Rationality Through Reasoning (unpublishedMS, version of July, 2011, "complete26"), Chap. 3. [My references to this manuscript below will be to this as yet unpublished manuscript.] But these are complexities we can safely ignore here.
    • (1998) What We Owe to Each Other , pp. 17
    • Scanlon, T.M.1
  • 6
    • 0003343064 scopus 로고
    • Internal and External Reasons
    • Cambridge University Press
    • Bernard Williams, "Internal and External Reasons", in his Moral Luck (Cambridge University Press, 1981), 101-113.
    • (1981) Moral Luck , pp. 101-113
    • Williams, B.1
  • 7
    • 0039610491 scopus 로고
    • Internal Reasons and the Obscurity of Blame
    • Cambridge University Press at 36.
    • Bernard Williams, "Internal Reasons and the Obscurity of Blame", in his Making Sense of Humanity (Cambridge University Press, 1981), 35-45, at 36.
    • (1981) His Making Sense of Humanity , pp. 35-45
    • Williams, B.1
  • 8
    • 0003541293 scopus 로고
    • Harvard University Press And see also Simon Blackburn, Ruling Passions: A Theory of Practical Reasoning (Oxford University Press, 1998).
    • See Allan Gibbard, Wise Choices, Apt Feelings (Harvard University Press, 1990) at 163. And see also Simon Blackburn, Ruling Passions: A Theory of Practical Reasoning (Oxford University Press, 1998).
    • (1990) Wise Choices, Apt Feelings , pp. 163
    • Gibbard, A.1
  • 9
    • 84861917736 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a recent, trenchant discussion see unpublished manuscript
    • For a recent, trenchant discussion see Niko Kolodny, "Instrumental Reasons," unpublished manuscript.
    • Instrumental Reasons
    • Kolodny, N.1
  • 10
    • 84873378038 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A more precise formulation would refer to the need, by a certain time, for an intention to M if one is to M.
    • A more precise formulation would refer to the need, by a certain time, for an intention to M if one is to M.
  • 11
    • 84873387297 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In his "The Requirements of Rationality," (unpublished manuscript version 2.4; August 2007) Nadeem Hussain emphasizes the relevance of a method of reflective equilibrium to our assessment of such claims about rationality.
    • In his "The Requirements of Rationality," (unpublished manuscript version 2.4; August 2007) Nadeem Hussain emphasizes the relevance of a method of reflective equilibrium to our assessment of such claims about rationality.
  • 12
    • 69249160164 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Decisions, Reasons, and Rationality
    • In putting the question this way I am following at 82.
    • In putting the question this way I am following Garret Cullity, "Decisions, Reasons, and Rationality," Ethics 119 (2008): 57-95, at 82.
    • (2008) Ethics , vol.119 , pp. 57-95
    • Cullity, G.1
  • 13
    • 38949143560 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For the first idea see my Intention, Plans, and Practical Reason (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1987; reissued by CSLI Publications 1999). For the connections to sociality see the essays on shared agency in my Faces of Intention (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1999), and my manuscript-in-progress, Shared Agency. For the connections to self-governance see the essays in my New York; Oxford University Press
    • For the first idea see my Intention, Plans, and Practical Reason (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1987; reissued by CSLI Publications 1999). For the connections to sociality see the essays on shared agency in my Faces of Intention (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1999), and my manuscript-in-progress, Shared Agency. For the connections to self-governance see the essays in my Structures of Agency: Essays (New York; Oxford University Press, 2007).
    • (2007) Structures of Agency: Essays
  • 14
    • 53249100535 scopus 로고
    • Extreme and Restricted Utilitarianism
    • Philippa Foot, ed. Oxford University Press For some complications see my "The Interplay of Intention and Reason," unpublished manuscript.
    • J.J.C. Smart, "Extreme and Restricted Utilitarianism," in Philippa Foot, ed., Theories of Ethics (Oxford University Press, 1967). For some complications see my "The Interplay of Intention and Reason," unpublished manuscript.
    • (1967) Theories of Ethics
    • Smart, J.J.C.1
  • 15
    • 69249098886 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Intention. Practical Rationality, and Self-Governance
    • See my
    • See my "Intention. Practical Rationality, and Self-Governance," Ethics 119 (2009): 411-443.
    • (2009) Ethics , vol.119 , pp. 411-443
  • 16
    • 84873332672 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Which is not to deny that we also sometimes want to give up control over aspects of our lives.
    • Which is not to deny that we also sometimes want to give up control over aspects of our lives.
  • 17
    • 84873403740 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I defend this thought further in section 6.
    • I defend this thought further in section 6.
  • 18
    • 0001862709 scopus 로고
    • Identification and Wholeheartedness
    • For talk of where the person stands see as reprinted in his Cambridge University Press at 166.
    • For talk of where the person stands see Harry Frankfurt, "Identification and Wholeheartedness," as reprinted in his The Importance of What We Care About (Cambridge University Press, 1987): 159-76, at 166.
    • (1987) The Importance of What We Care about , pp. 159-176
    • Frankfurt, H.1
  • 19
    • 84873366745 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • One challenge concerns cases in which, while the end is attainable, the agent will in fact not performall of the other necessary means or constitutive elements. [For a version of this challenge that concerns "ought" see John Broome, Rationality Through Reasoning, at p. 207.] Now, I grant that even if you ought to E (where E is attainable by you) and M is a necessary means to or constitutive element of E, if in fact you are not going to perform other necessary means to E then it does not follow that you ought to M. But it seems to me that reasons work differently than "ought" in such cases.
    • One challenge concerns cases in which, while the end is attainable, the agent will in fact not performall of the other necessary means or constitutive elements. [For a version of this challenge that concerns "ought" see John Broome, Rationality Through Reasoning, at p. 207.] Now, I grant that even if you ought to E (where E is attainable by you) and M is a necessary means to or constitutive element of E, if in fact you are not going to perform other necessary means to E then it does not follow that you ought to M. But it seems to me that reasons work differently than "ought" in such cases.
  • 20
    • 84873397818 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I limit my attention here to cases in which grounds support an intention to X by supporting X; and I also put to one side cases in which the agent's relevant thinking about her grounds is itself distorted in some way.
    • I limit my attention here to cases in which grounds support an intention to X by supporting X; and I also put to one side cases in which the agent's relevant thinking about her grounds is itself distorted in some way.
  • 21
    • 77950751301 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Unifying the Requirements of Rationality
    • at 250. And John Broome notes that the fixity of the past supports what he calls "necessary detachment". (John Broome, Rationality Through Reasoning, at pp. 130, 145.)
    • See Andrew Reisner,"Unifying the Requirements of Rationality," Philosophical Explorations 12 (2009): 243-60, at 250. And John Broome notes that the fixity of the past supports what he calls "necessary detachment". (John Broome, Rationality Through Reasoning, at pp. 130, 145.)
    • (2009) Philosophical Explorations , vol.12 , pp. 243-260
    • Reisner, A.1
  • 22
    • 77950258040 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Reply to Critics
    • I borrow the terminology of "incomparable" from at 735-7.
    • I borrow the terminology of "incomparable" from Allan Gibbard, "Reply to Critics," Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 72 (2006): 729-744, at 735-7.
    • (2006) Philosophy and Phenomenological Research , vol.72 , pp. 729-744
    • Gibbard, A.1
  • 23
    • 84865827843 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Decisions, Diachronic Autonomy, and the Division of Deliberative Labor
    • Here I am in disagreement with Luca Ferrero. See his "Decisions, Diachronic Autonomy, and the Division of Deliberative Labor," Philosophers' Imprint 10:2 (2010), 1-23, section 6. This rational default status also goes beyond John Broome's proposed principle of "persistence of intention". According to Broome's proposal (in its "special form"), "rationality requires of N that, if N intends at t1 to F, and no canceling event occurs between t1 and t2, then either N intends at t2 to F, or N considers at t2 whether to F." (See John Broome, Rationality Through Reasoning, at p. 185. For a related discussion of the case of Abraham and Isaac, see John Broome, "Are Intentions Reasons? And How Should We Cope with Incommensurable Values?" in Christopher W. Morris and Arthur Ripstein, eds., Practical Rationality and Preference: Essays for David Gauthier (Cambridge University Press, 2001): 98-120, esp. 114-119.) Without going into the details, it suffices here to note that, having so intended at t1, one satisfies Broome's requirement simply by reconsidering that intention at t2, at which point the cited principle describes no further rational pressure to retain that intention. (In this respect, Broome's approach here is similar in spirit to the approach I took in Intention, Plans, and Practical Reason.) According to (D), in contrast, even when one reconsiders one's prior intention it remains, in the absence of a relevant change in assessment, a rational default.
    • (2010) Philosophers' Imprint , vol.10 , Issue.2 , pp. 1-23
    • Ferrero, L.1
  • 24
    • 33750857210 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Yale University Press part II; and see J. David Velleman's appeal to "diachronic autonomy" in his "Deciding How to Decide," as reprinted in his The Possibility of Practical Reason (Oxford University Press, 2000): 221-243, at 238-40.
    • See Jed Rubenfeld, Freedom and Time (Yale University Press, 2001) part II; and see J. David Velleman's appeal to "diachronic autonomy" in his "Deciding How to Decide," as reprinted in his The Possibility of Practical Reason (Oxford University Press, 2000): 221-243, at 238-40.
    • (2001) Freedom and Time
    • Rubenfeld, J.1
  • 25
    • 0003740191 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • Derek Parfit, Reasons and Persons (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1984).
    • (1984) Reasons and Persons
    • Parfit, D.1
  • 26
    • 84873392411 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Agency, Time, and Sociality
    • This is a development of a view I discuss in my Structures of Agency, and in my "Agency, Time, and Sociality," Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 84:2 (2010): 7-26.
    • (2010) Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association , vol.84 , Issue.2 , pp. 7-26
  • 27
    • 0010142928 scopus 로고
    • Personal Identity
    • Sydney Shoemaker and Richard Swinburne Oxford: Basil Blackwell
    • Sydney Shoemaker, "Personal Identity," in Sydney Shoemaker and Richard Swinburne, Personal Identity (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1984) at 95.
    • (1984) Personal Identity , pp. 95
    • Shoemaker, S.1
  • 29
    • 84857849767 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Recall Broome's principle of persistence of intention (in its special form): "rationality requires of N that, if N intends at t1 to F, and no canceling event occurs between t1 and t2, then either N intends at t2 to F, or N considers at t2 whether to F" (emphasis added). Note that Broome's principle also highlights a second disjunct, though a different second disjunct from the one to which I am here appealing. (The second disjunct implicit in (D) involves relevant change in assessment of grounds for X, not just reconsidering whether to X.) Both Broome and I aim to avoid in this way an implication from the fixity of one's past formation of the intention at t1, directly and simply to a reason later to retain and act on that intention at t2. But, as indicated in note 24, the combination of (D) and (R) does this in a way that provides for a stronger diachronic constraint than does Broome's principle of intention persistence. (See
    • Recall Broome's principle of persistence of intention (in its special form): "rationality requires of N that, if N intends at t1 to F, and no canceling event occurs between t1 and t2, then either N intends at t2 to F, or N considers at t2 whether to F" (emphasis added). Note that Broome's principle also highlights a second disjunct, though a different second disjunct from the one to which I am here appealing. (The second disjunct implicit in (D) involves relevant change in assessment of grounds for X, not just reconsidering whether to X.) Both Broome and I aim to avoid in this way an implication from the fixity of one's past formation of the intention at t1, directly and simply to a reason later to retain and act on that intention at t2. But, as indicated in note 24, the combination of (D) and (R) does this in a way that provides for a stronger diachronic constraint than does Broome's principle of intention persistence. (See John Broome, Rationality Through Reasoning, pp. 184-190.)
    • Rationality Through Reasoning , pp. 184-190
    • Broome, J.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.