메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 119, Issue 1, 2008, Pages 57-95

Decisions, reasons, and rationality

(1)  Cullity, Garrett a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 69249160164     PISSN: 00141704     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1086/592585     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (23)

References (128)
  • 1
    • 0042578837 scopus 로고
    • Reasons for Action, Decisions and Norms
    • note
    • For the view that deciding is forming an intention after deliberation, or by reasoning, see Joseph Raz, "Reasons for Action, Decisions and Norms," Mind 84 (1975): 481-99, 488-89
    • (1975) Mind , vol.84
    • Raz, J.1
  • 2
    • 11944250996 scopus 로고
    • Intention and Means-End Reasoning
    • note
    • Michael E. Bratman, "Intention and Means-End Reasoning," Philosophical Review 90 (1981): 252-65, 252
    • (1981) Philosophical Review , vol.90 , pp. 252-265
    • Bratman, M.E.1
  • 6
    • 84920777265 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Intention, Belief, and Instrumental Rationality
    • note
    • As I read them, according to Bratman, the answer is the first; according to John Broome, the second; according to Hugh McCann, neither. For the disagreement between Bratman and Broome, see Michael E. Bratman, "Intention, Belief, and Instrumental Rationality," in Reasons for Action, ed. David Sobel and Steven Walls (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, forthcoming), sec. 5
    • Reasons for Action
    • Bratman, M.E.1
  • 7
    • 82755169450 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Unity of Reasoning?
    • note
    • John Broome, "The Unity of Reasoning?" in Spheres of Reason, ed. Simon Robertson, John Skorupski, and Jens Timmerman (Oxford: Oxford University Press, forthcoming), sec. 7.
    • Spheres of Reason
    • Broome, J.1
  • 8
    • 0010161256 scopus 로고
    • Settled Objectives and Rational Constraints
    • Hugh McCann, "Settled Objectives and Rational Constraints," American Philosophical Quarterly 28 (1991): 25-36.
    • (1991) American Philosophical Quarterly , vol.28 , pp. 25-36
    • McCann, H.1
  • 9
    • 34247182480 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Scope of Instrumental Reason
    • note
    • For example, Mark Schroeder, "The Scope of Instrumental Reason," Philosophical Perspectives 18 (2004): 337-64, 348.
    • (2004) Philosophical Perspectives , vol.18 , pp. 337-364
    • Schroeder, M.1
  • 14
    • 63849156585 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Brentano and the Buck-Passers
    • Sven Danielsson and Jonas Olson, "Brentano and the Buck-Passers," Mind 116 (2007): 511-22.
    • (2007) Mind , vol.116 , pp. 511-522
    • Danielsson, S.1    Olson, J.2
  • 15
    • 32144461232 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Allan Gibbard Thinking How to Live (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2003), 188-91.
    • (2003) Thinking How to Live , pp. 188-191
    • Gibbard, A.1
  • 16
    • 60949155950 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Reasons and Motivation
    • note
    • Noteworthy proposals for sharpening it up are made by Derek Parfit, "Reasons and Motivation,"Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, suppl. ser., 71 (1997): 99-130.
    • (1997) Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society , vol.71 , pp. 99-130
    • Parfit, D.1
  • 17
    • 85121654975 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rationality and Reasons
    • note
    • "Rationality and Reasons," in Exploring Practical Philosophy: From Action to Values, ed. Dan Egonsson, Jonas Josefsson, Bjorn Petersson, and Toni Ronnow-Rasmussen (Aldershot: Ashgate, 2001), 17-39, 25, 29
    • (2001) Exploring Practical Philosophy: From Action to Values , pp. 17-39
  • 19
    • 33845621322 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Explaining Normativity: On Rationality and the Justification of Reason
    • note
    • Joseph Raz, "Explaining Normativity: On Rationality and the Justification of Reason," in Engaging Reason: On the Theory of Value and Action (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999), 67-89, sec. 1
    • (1999) Engaging Reason: On the Theory of Value and Action , pp. 67-89
    • Raz, J.1
  • 20
    • 34247240971 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Why Be Rational?
    • note
    • Niko Kolodny, "Why Be Rational?" Mind 114 (2005): 509-63, sec. 5.
    • (2005) Mind , vol.114 , pp. 509-563
    • Kolodny, N.1
  • 21
    • 84926330403 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • It is of course possible to think of rationality as proper functioning withoutmaking rationality explanatorily prior to reasons: see, e.g., Bratman, "Intention, Belief, and Instrumental Rationality," sec. 1
    • Intention, Belief, and Instrumental Rationality
    • Bratman1
  • 22
    • 38949166541 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Myth of Instrumental Rationality
    • note
    • Joseph Raz, "The Myth of Instrumental Rationality," Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy 1 (2005): 2-28, 15.
    • (2005) Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy , vol.1 , pp. 2-28
    • Raz, J.1
  • 23
    • 0003622275 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • For examples of the neo-Aristotelian view, see Philippa Foot, Natural Goodness (Oxford: Clarendon, 2001), esp. chap. 4
    • (2001) Natural Goodness
    • Foot, P.1
  • 24
    • 60949459008 scopus 로고
    • The Rationality of Morality
    • note
    • Gavin Lawrence, "The Rationality of Morality," in Virtue and Reasons, ed. Rosalind Hursthouse, Gavin Lawrence, and Warren Quinn (Oxford: Clarendon, 1995), 89-147.
    • (1995) Virtue and Reasons , pp. 89-147
    • Lawrence, G.1
  • 25
    • 0003343064 scopus 로고
    • Internal and External Reasons
    • note
    • Bernard Williams, "Internal and External Reasons," in Moral Luck (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981), 101-13
    • (1981) Moral Luck , pp. 101-113
    • Williams, B.1
  • 26
    • 0040202098 scopus 로고
    • Skepticism about Practical Reason
    • Christine M. Korsgaard, "Skepticism about Practical Reason," Journal of Philosophy 83 (1986): 5-25.
    • (1986) Journal of Philosophy , vol.83 , pp. 5-25
    • Korsgaard, C.M.1
  • 28
    • 0034164930 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On Acting Rationally against One's Best Judgment
    • For several helpfully detailed examples of this kind, see Nomy Arpaly, "On Acting Rationally against One's Best Judgment," Ethics 110 (2000): 488-513. See also Harry Frankfurt, "Rationality and the Unthinkable," in The Importance of WhatWe Care About (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988), 177-90
    • (2000) Ethics , vol.110 , pp. 488-513
    • Arpaly, N.1
  • 29
    • 0002039694 scopus 로고
    • Rationality and the Unthinkable
    • note
    • Harry Frankfurt, "Rationality and the Unthinkable," in The Importance of WhatWe Care About (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988), 177-90
    • (1988) The Importance of WhatWe Care About , pp. 177-190
    • Frankfurt, H.1
  • 30
    • 0002166149 scopus 로고
    • Is Akratic Action Always Irrational?
    • note
    • Alison McIntyre, "Is Akratic Action Always Irrational?" in Identity, Character and Morality, ed. Owen Flanagan and Amelie Rorty (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1993), 379-400
    • (1993) Identity, Character and Morality , pp. 379-400
    • McIntyre, A.1
  • 31
    • 0004083939 scopus 로고
    • note
    • Robert Nozick, The Nature of Rationality (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1993), chap. 4. The following formulation in Parfit also seems to imply that Huck is rational: "We are rational insofar as we respond to reasons, or apparent reasons. We have some apparent reason when we have some belief whose truth would give us that reason" (Parfit, "Rationality and Reasons," 25). My own use of the phrase "apparent reasons" in the text differs from Parfit's. As I use it, F is an apparent reason for you to X when it appears to you that F is a reason to X.
    • (1993) The Nature of Rationality
    • Nozick, R.1
  • 33
    • 84926349001 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • There is also the converse case. Suppose I truly believe that the drug will not cure me and that I have no reason to take it, but I then irrationally decide to take it. Now, if my decision is a reason, I have turned the second belief from true to false.
  • 35
    • 84926383912 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The reasoning of this paragraph would fail if, as the bad effects of the drug diminish, the strength of the alleged reason provided by the decision to take it also diminishes. But it is hard to see why that would be so.
  • 36
    • 84959761254 scopus 로고
    • The Toxin Puzzle
    • note
    • "In a case like this"-but not in unusual cases like Kavka's toxin puzzle, discussed in Gregory S. Kavka, "The Toxin Puzzle," Analysis 43 (1983): 33-36, sec. 4.
    • (1983) Analysis , vol.43 , pp. 33-36
    • Kavka, G.S.1
  • 37
    • 0003975273 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Michael Bratman sharply identifies the problem and gives it this label in Bratman, "Intention and Means-End Reasoning," sec. 1-see also Bratman, Intention, Plans, and Practical Reason, 24-27.
    • Intention, Plans, and Practical Reason , pp. 24-27
    • Bratman, M.1
  • 38
    • 0242289341 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Are Intentions Reasons? And How Should We Cope with Incommensurable Values?
    • note
    • John Broome, "Are Intentions Reasons? And How Should We Cope with Incommensurable Values?" in Practical Rationality and Preference: Essays for David Gauthier, ed. Christopher W. Morris and Arthur Ripstein (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001), 98-120, 98-100
    • (2001) Practical Rationality and Preference: Essays for David Gauthier , pp. 98-120
    • Broome, J.1
  • 39
    • 56949106401 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rational Resolve
    • Richard Holton, "Rational Resolve," Philosophical Review 113 (2004): 507-35
    • (2004) Philosophical Review , vol.113 , pp. 507-535
    • Holton, R.1
  • 41
  • 44
    • 84926388862 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I do not think this is a convincing argument that decisions do not make this kind of difference to reasons; I am suggesting that we need a better argument for thinking that they do.
  • 45
    • 70349525768 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The same point can apply in situations where there is no mistake-e.g., when one chooses one of a range of long-term activities, none of which is worse than any other. See Raz, "Myth of Instrumental Rationality," 21-22.
    • Myth of Instrumental Rationality , pp. 21-22
    • Raz1
  • 46
    • 60949115923 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Reasons: A Puzzling Duality?
    • note
    • In his discussion of these cases, T. M. Scanlon, "Reasons: A Puzzling Duality?" in Wallace et al., Reason and Value, 237, also argues that decisions are second-order reasons. However, his conclusion is not that reasons are subtracted, and I disagree with one of the premises of his argument-as I explain in Sec. VII below.
    • Reason and Value , pp. 237
    • Scanlon, T.M.1
  • 47
    • 61149290110 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Public Goods and Fairness
    • note
    • I offer a defense of those claims about fairness in Garrett Cullity, "Public Goods and Fairness," Australasian Journal of Philosophy 86 (2008): 1-21.
    • (2008) Australasian Journal of Philosophy , vol.86 , pp. 1-21
    • Cullity, G.1
  • 48
    • 36749009731 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Normative Requirements
    • See John Broome, "Normative Requirements," Ratio 12 (1999): 398-419
    • (1999) Ratio , vol.12 , pp. 398-419
    • Broome, J.1
  • 51
    • 0039088207 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is my own rendering of a claim that Broome formulates slightly differently in various places. See Broome, "Normative Requirements," 410.
    • Normative Requirements , pp. 410
    • Broome1
  • 59
    • 84926294822 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Kavka, "Toxin Puzzle." In Kavka's example there is a different requirement-I must, at midnight, intend to drink the toxin tomorrow afternoon-and no pharmacologist.
    • Toxin Puzzle
    • Kavka1
  • 60
    • 4544369123 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Some will want to resist this example by granting that you have a reason to get yourself into that state but not a reason to be in that state. (This is a distinction suggested, e.g., by Parfit, "Rationality and Reasons," 24.) But Broome himself would, I think, want to reject that distinction, and it looks problematic here. The only reasons you have for getting yourself into that state are the advantages of being in that state, and those advantages might in some circumstances not be reasons for getting yourself into that state (suppose you will be fed the pill in your sleep).
    • Rationality and Reasons , pp. 24
    • Parfit1
  • 61
    • 46349094112 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Does Rationality Give Us Reasons?
    • On this point, see John Broome, "Does Rationality Give Us Reasons?" Philosophical Issues 15 (2005): 321-37.
    • (2005) Philosophical Issues , vol.15 , pp. 321-337
    • Broome, J.1
  • 63
    • 62449144035 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Have We Reason to Do as Rationality Requires?-a Comment on Raz
    • See John Broome, "Have We Reason to Do as Rationality Requires?-a Comment on Raz," Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy 1 (2005): 1-8 n. 5.
    • (2005) Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy , vol.1 , pp. 1-8
    • Broome, J.1
  • 65
    • 58749112498 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • For the debate over the normativity of requirements of rationality, see Kolodny, "Why Be Rational?".
    • Why Be Rational?
    • Kolodny1
  • 66
    • 43249137952 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Wide or Narrow Scope?
    • John Broome, "Wide or Narrow Scope?" Mind 116 (2007): 359-70
    • (2007) Mind , vol.116 , pp. 359-370
    • Broome, J.1
  • 67
    • 43249133964 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • State or Process Requirements?
    • Niko Kolodny, "State or Process Requirements?" Mind 116 (2007): 371-85
    • (2007) Mind , vol.116 , pp. 371-385
    • Kolodny, N.1
  • 70
    • 4544248465 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Normativity, Commitment, and Instrumental Reason
    • I adapt an example from R. Jay Wallace, "Normativity, Commitment, and Instrumental Reason," Philosophers' Imprint 1 (2001): 24.
    • (2001) Philosophers' Imprint , vol.1 , pp. 24
    • Jay Wallace, R.1
  • 71
    • 0003975273 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The only potential counterexample I can think of depends on the claim that a person can rationally intend E while believing E will not happen. Suppose I am jailed and credibly assured that I will be released if I betray my best friend. It could be rational to refuse to betray my friend and spend my time pursuing ways of getting out of jail that I know are very unlikely to succeed (filing the bars, perhaps). Here, we might think that I to-intend to get out of jail-that is the goal toward which my action is orchestrated-but believe that I will only in fact get out of jail if I betray my friend. However, the claim on which this depends is controversial: see, e.g., Bratman, Intention, Plans, and Practical Reason, 35-42. Notice that although, if the controversial claim is correct, this is a counterexample to 3, it is not a counterexample to 4. Betraying my friend is not a suitable way of getting out of jail.
    • Intention, Plans, and Practical Reason , pp. 35-42
    • Bratman1
  • 72
    • 0008990999 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I offer no definition of 'means'. These are usually thought of as temporally prior causes of the attainment of ends and therefore distinguished from ways of attaining an end that constitute its attainment-see, e.g., Williams, "Internal and External Reasons," 104.
    • Internal and External Reasons , pp. 104
    • Williams1
  • 74
    • 84926311784 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • It might be translated as "a sufficiently good means"-but only if that is interpreted in line with the stipulation I go on to give in the text.
  • 75
    • 84926319519 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Suppose I intend to go to a concert. Actually, the music will be bad, and I don't have a sufficient reason to go. If I did have a sufficient reason to go, the music would be good. And if the music was good, a lot more tickets would have been sold by now, and the only available seats would be at the back of the auditorium. Suppose I believe all of that but akratically decide to go anyway. Surely that does not mean that in order to avoid instrumental irrationality I must buy a seat at the back.
  • 76
    • 84926293414 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This properly allows for considerable vagueness. If I think I need to pick a marriage partner by middle age, the indeterminacy surrounding whether I have reached middle age will be reflected as time passes in a changing degree of belief whether I have done so and a corresponding variation in the extent to which it is irrational for me not to have done so yet. That seems a plausible result.
  • 77
    • 84926322449 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Suppose I form a spur-of-the-moment decision to contact my confessor immediately, I believe that in order to do so I must pick up the phone, and straight away I form the intention to pick up the phone. Then I do satisfy a version of 4-I. The relevant period is the very short period between making the former decision and forming the latter intention; "immediately" is the substitution for "by t."
  • 78
    • 84926394156 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • If there is more than one suitable means, the disjunction of them can be substituted for M.
  • 79
  • 82
    • 67349234179 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Intention, Belief, Practical, Theoretical
    • note
    • Michael E. Bratman, "Intention, Belief, Practical, Theoretical," in Robertson, Skorupski, and Timmerman, Spheres of Reason, sec. 4.
    • Spheres of Reason
    • Bratman, M.E.1
  • 83
    • 84926285667 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is a common theme among critics of Broome-style wide-scope requirements: it is often expressed as a worry about the "symmetry" of the different possible ways of complying with them. See Schroeder, "Scope of Instrumental Reason," 339
    • Scope of Instrumental Reason , pp. 339
    • Schroeder1
  • 85
    • 60949115963 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Structural Irrationality
    • note
    • T. M. Scanlon, "Structural Irrationality," in Common Minds: Themes from the Philosophy of Philip Pettit, ed. Geoffrey Brennan, Robery Goodin, Frank Jackson, and Michael Smith (New York: OxfordUniversity Press, 2007), 84-103.
    • (2007) Common Minds: Themes from the Philosophy of Philip Pettit , pp. 84-103
    • Scanlon, T.M.1
  • 86
    • 84926319029 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • A further worry: suppose you have tried some means to your end but failed. It still seems irrational for you to retain your intention without making any further effort to implement it. Does 4-T fail to capture the irrationality of this kind of case? I think not. For now you have entered a new stretch of time-the one commencing with the failure of your first effort-and 4-T can be reapplied.
  • 87
    • 84888652731 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Broome is one leading proponent of this cognitivist strategy: see esp. Broome, "Practical Reasoning," secs. 1-3.
    • Practical Reasoning
    • Broome1
  • 89
    • 60949351040 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Practical Reasoning
    • note
    • Gilbert Harman, "Practical Reasoning," in Reasoning, Meaning, and Mind (New York:Oxford University Press, 1999), 46-74
    • (1999) Reasoning, Meaning, and Mind , pp. 46-74
    • Harman, G.1
  • 91
    • 35348873961 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cognitivism about Instrumental Reason
    • Kieran Setiya, "Cognitivism about Instrumental Reason," Ethics 117 (2007): 649-73.
    • (2007) Ethics , vol.117 , pp. 649-673
    • Setiya, K.1
  • 93
    • 61149185961 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Two Approaches to Instrumental Rationality and Belief Consistency
    • John Brunero, "Two Approaches to Instrumental Rationality and Belief Consistency," Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy 1 (2005): 1-20.
    • (2005) Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy , vol.1 , pp. 1-20
    • Brunero, J.1
  • 96
    • 84926314803 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Even if we could list them all, meeting all of them would not be sufficient to make you rational. Your meeting them would need to be guided in the right way. The crucial question of how to explain this guidance condition is not one I try to answer here.
  • 97
    • 84926327611 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Compare Broome, "Unity of Reasoning?" sec. 2. Broome's own favored enkrasia requirement is formulated in terms of beliefs about ought rather than decisive reasons. The other difference is my addition of the clause, "and you have had time to form the intention to X." If getting from a belief that you have a decisive reason to X to an intention to X is a transition between different states, it will take time-although perhaps not very long. Without the addition of this clause, 5-P would carry the false implication that at the first moment you hold the two beliefs, but before the process of forming the intention is complete, the state you are in is a state of irrationality. As Broome points out, the occurrences of 'you' within the scope of the beliefs have to be read as "reflexive" pronouns- i.e., you must know who you are.
    • Unity of Reasoning?
    • Broome1
  • 98
    • 84926355193 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • If there are no good reasons for a belief that are not pieces of evidence for its truth, then the second clause is redundant. I include it to sidestep the controversy over that.
  • 99
  • 102
    • 84926285667 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Schroeder, "Scope of Instrumental Reason," goes as far as defending a narrow-scope treatment of requirements of instrumental rationality.
    • Scope of Instrumental Reason
    • Schroeder1
  • 103
    • 84926319615 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Another way to avoid being classified by 4 as irrational is simply to stop intending E. Doing that when nothing in your situation has changed could be irrational. So it looks as though there is also an intention-constancy requirement of rationality on the inputs to your thinking about the means to your ends.
  • 108
    • 60949115923 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • It might seem better to resort to the weaker claim that "adopting a goal gives rise to a difference in what an agent must, in so far as he has that goal and is not irrational, see as reasons" (Scanlon, "Reasons: A Puzzling Duality?" 235). This claims that failing to see oneself as having reasons to take what one believes to be the means to one's intended ends is not impossible but irrational. But now this claim is too weak to explain the instrumental irrationality of the akratic incompetent. It implies that I am irrational in not seeing my means as reasons. But it does not explain the difference between two akratic agents, both of whom deny that they have reasons to take the suitable means, but one of whom is instrumentally incompetent while the other is not.
    • Reasons: A Puzzling Duality? , pp. 235
    • Scanlon1
  • 110
    • 33644775245 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • How Truth Governs Belief
    • Nishi Shah, "How Truth Governs Belief," Philosophical Review 112 (2003): 447-82
    • (2003) Philosophical Review , vol.112 , pp. 447-482
    • Shah, N.1
  • 111
    • 46349092647 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Doxastic Deliberation
    • Nishi Shah and David Velleman, "Doxastic Deliberation," Philosophical Review 114 (2005): 497-534.
    • (2005) Philosophical Review , vol.114 , pp. 497-534
    • Shah, N.1    Velleman, D.2
  • 112
    • 84881773411 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • What Good Is a Will?
    • note
    • See J. David Velleman, "What Good Is a Will?" in Action in Context, ed. Anton Leist and Holger Baumann (Berlin: de Gruyter, 2007), 193-215.
    • (2007) Action in Context , pp. 193-215
    • David Velleman, J.1
  • 116
    • 84926300658 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I take "failing to exercise a disposition" to span failing to have it at all and having it but not exercising it.
  • 117
    • 84926300437 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Notice the way in which my view differs from the "two-tier" account of such cases recommended by Holton, "Rational Resolve." On that account, the rationality of forming and holding a resolution confers rationality on its exercise. My different suggestion is that the dispositions we have decisive reasons to support fix the standards for rationality. To illustrate the difference, suppose you are convincingly taught from a young age that the natural selectionist theories you will be taught in school are the work of the devil and that you should shut your ears to the seductive arguments that will be used in their favor. It might then be rational for you to resolve not to listen to them. As I read it, a two-tier account carries the implication that it is therefore rational to go ahead and ignore the evidence for natural selection. On my view, this is irrational since your disposition, even if it is rationally acquired, is one which violates the standards for evidence sensitivity that we have decisive reasons to uphold.
    • Rational Resolve
    • Holton1
  • 119
    • 84926330011 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Perhaps I will perform better in a Schelling case if I am oblivious to my own irrationality. But perhaps not.
  • 120
    • 84926282885 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Another corollary is that our practice of evaluation in terms of rationality and irrationality only makes sense on the assumption that we are similar enough to give us reasons to have the same dispositions in thinking about reasons. But that sounds correct too.
  • 121
    • 84926319253 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Nor are they inconsistent with such claims. If beliefs and intentions have constitutive aims, then it is plausible that our reasons to have those states will give us reasons to be disposed to meet the standards that fit them to being the states they are.
  • 122
    • 0003975273 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • My remarks have some close affinities with those made by other writers. For example, Bratman writes: "In assessing the rationality of an agent for some intention or intentional action our concern is to determine the extent to which the agent has come up to relevant standards of rational agency. A failure on the agent's part to come up to such standards makes that agent guilty of a form of criticizable irrationality. In reaching such assessments our concern is with the actual processes that lead to the intention and action and with the underlying habits, dispositions and patterns of thinking and reasoning which are manifested in those processes. Our concern is with the extent to which these processes-and the underlying habits, dispositions, and patterns they manifest-come up to appropriate standards of rationality" (Bratman, Intention, Plans, and Practical Reason, 51).
    • Intention, Plans, and Practical Reason , pp. 51
    • Bratman1
  • 124
    • 84991289779 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I would not want to suggest that a completely unquestioning obedience to military superiors is ever (actually) what there is a sufficient reason to have. See Jessica Wolfendale, Torture and the Military Profession (New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2007).
    • (2007) Torture and the Military Profession
    • Wolfendale, J.1
  • 125
    • 0003975273 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Whether a state counts as a to-intention is settled by whether it is a commitment to which this requirement properly applies. Thus, merely orchestrating your action toward the achievement of a goal is not sufficient for a to-intention since it may be rational for you to aim at A and at the same time to aim at B, even though achieving both is undesirable. See Bratman's video game example in Bratman, Intention, Plans, and Practical Reason, chap. 8, for illustration and discussion.
    • Intention, Plans, and Practical Reason
    • Bratman1
  • 126
    • 84926316296 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I present what follows as an explanation of why these applications of 4 are requirements of rationality. Unlike Broome, I offer no cognitivist explanation of the correctness of practical reasoning.
  • 127
    • 84926309836 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Note that in doing so, this goes beyond 4-I, which does not imply (although of course it does not deny) that this combination of states is irrational.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.