메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 11, Issue 4, 2012, Pages 289-302

Expressing evaluative forensic science opinions in a court of law

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 84871338017     PISSN: 14708396     EISSN: 1470840X     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1093/lpr/mgs016     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (16)

References (50)
  • 1
    • 79958730872 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [2010] EWCA Crim 2439.
    • (2010) EWCA Crim , pp. 2439
  • 2
    • 85116950918 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Our attention is directed to what transpires, or should transpire, in court rather than to what forensic scientists should do in their investigations and how they should express conclusions in reports or in other contexts. See B. Found and G. Edmond, 'Reporting on the comparison and interpretation of pattern evidence: Recommendations for forensic specialists
    • Our attention is directed to what transpires, or should transpire, in court rather than to what forensic scientists should do in their investigations and how they should express conclusions in reports or in other contexts. See B. Found and G. Edmond, 'Reporting on the comparison and interpretation of pattern evidence: Recommendations for forensic specialists' (2012) 44 Australian J Forensic Sci 193-6.
    • (2012) Australian J Forensic Sci , pp. 193-6
  • 4
    • 84871266230 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Forensic science evidence cannot assist the jury if it is not reliable. Similarly, evidence that is likely to be overvaluedwill not assist the jury's decision-making responsibilities.
    • Forensic science evidence cannot assist the jury if it is not reliable. Similarly, evidence that is likely to be overvaluedwill not assist the jury's decision-making responsibilities.
  • 5
    • 84871299731 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See references at n 18 below.
    • See references at n 18 below.
  • 6
    • 84871277792 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Guest editorial, Expressing evaluative opinions: A position statement (2011) 51 Sci & Justice 1-2 (while a number of lawyers also joined as signatories to the editorial its instigation appears to lie with the forensic science community). See also G. Morrison, 'The likelihood-ratio framework and forensic evidence in court: A response to R v T' 16 Int J Evidence and Proof 1-29.
    • See Guest editorial, Expressing evaluative opinions: A position statement (2011) 51 Sci & Justice 1-2 (while a number of lawyers also joined as signatories to the editorial its instigation appears to lie with the forensic science community). See also G. Morrison, 'The likelihood-ratio framework and forensic evidence in court: A response to R v T' 16 Int J Evidence and Proof 1-29.2012
    • (2012)
  • 7
    • 84871307110 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • R v T EWCA Crim 2439 at [30].
    • R v T EWCA Crim 2439 at [30].2010
    • (2010)
  • 8
    • 49549090850 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • R v T [2010] EWCA Crim 2439 at [73], [96]. On juror understanding of forensic science terminologies see D. McQuiston-Surrett, and M.J. Saks, 'The testimony of forensic identification science: What expert witnesses say and what factfinders hear' (2009) 33 Law & Human Behavior 436 and D. McQuiston-Surrett and M. Saks, 'Communicating opinion evidence in the forensic identification sciences: accuracy and impact
    • R v T [2010] EWCA Crim 2439 at [73], [96]. On juror understanding of forensic science terminologies see D. McQuiston-Surrett, and M.J. Saks, 'The testimony of forensic identification science: What expert witnesses say and what factfinders hear' (2009) 33 Law & Human Behavior 436 and D. McQuiston-Surrett and M. Saks, 'Communicating opinion evidence in the forensic identification sciences: accuracy and impact' (2008) 59 Hastings Law J 1159
    • (2008) Hastings Law J , vol.59 , pp. 1159
  • 9
    • 84871263045 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • We emphasise that this essay is not intended as a defence of the present system.
    • We emphasise that this essay is not intended as a defence of the present system.
  • 10
    • 84871305957 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Guest Editorial, 'Expressing evaluative opinions': '1) The interpretation of scientific evidence invokes reasoning in the face of uncertainty. Probability theory provides the only coherent logical foundation for such reasoning.'
    • Guest Editorial, 'Expressing evaluative opinions': '1) The interpretation of scientific evidence invokes reasoning in the face of uncertainty. Probability theory provides the only coherent logical foundation for such reasoning.'
  • 11
    • 84871321634 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Safety in Numbers? Deciding When DNA Alone is Enough to Convict' (2010) 85 NYU L Rev 1130 at 1162 quoting S. Cole and R. Diosa-Vila, 'CSI and Its Effects:Media, Juries, and the Burden of Proof
    • A. Roth, 'Safety in Numbers? Deciding When DNA Alone is Enough to Convict' (2010) 85 NYU L Rev 1130 at 1162 quoting S. Cole and R. Diosa-Vila, 'CSI and Its Effects:Media, Juries, and the Burden of Proof' (2007) 41 New Eng L Rev 435-468
    • (2007) New Eng L Rev , vol.41 , pp. 435-468
    • Roth, A.1
  • 12
    • 77957224507 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Articles rejecting the claimof forensic science evidence to uniqueness and individualization e.g. S. Cole, 'Forensic without uniqueness, conclusions without individualization: The new epistemology of forensic identification
    • Articles rejecting the claimof forensic science evidence to uniqueness and individualization e.g. S. Cole, 'Forensic without uniqueness, conclusions without individualization: The new epistemology of forensic identification' (2009) 8 Law, Probability Risk 233
    • (2009) Law, Probability Risk , vol.8 , pp. 233
  • 13
    • 41349097141 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Individualization Fallacy in Forensic Science Evidence
    • M. J. Saks and J.Koehler, The Individualization Fallacy in Forensic Science Evidence, (2008) 61 Vand L Rev 199
    • (2008) Vand L Rev , vol.61 , pp. 199
    • Saks, M.J.1    Koehler, J.2
  • 14
    • 82955191087 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Probability, Individualization and Uniqueness in Forensic Science Evidence
    • D. Kaye, 'Probability, Individualization and Uniqueness in Forensic Science Evidence' (200975 Brook L Rev 1163
    • (2009) Brook L Rev , vol.75 , pp. 1163
    • Kaye, D.1
  • 15
    • 84871343050 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The potential for problems in the chain of custody (i.e. continuity), laboratory and interpretational errors are not included in these estimates. See e.g. W. Thompson, 'The Potential for Error in ForensicDNATesting (andHowThatComplicates theUse of DNA Databases for Criminal Identification)
    • The potential for problems in the chain of custody (i.e. continuity), laboratory and interpretational errors are not included in these estimates. See e.g. W. Thompson, 'The Potential for Error in ForensicDNATesting (andHowThatComplicates theUse of DNA Databases for Criminal Identification)' (2008) www.gene-watch.org
    • (2008)
  • 16
    • 84893367474 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In Australia it is only the failure to explain matters peculiarly within the accused's knowledge that can be used by the jury, and then only to exclude doubts that might otherwise arise fromspeculating about that knowledge. See Azzopardi v R
    • In Australia it is only the failure to explain matters peculiarly within the accused's knowledge that can be used by the jury, and then only to exclude doubts that might otherwise arise fromspeculating about that knowledge. See Azzopardi v R (2001) 205 CLR 50.
    • (2001) CLR , vol.205 , pp. 50
  • 17
    • 84871278557 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Psychological research endorsing the general use of this heuristic includes R. Hastie, 'Juror Decision-Making Models: The Generalisation Gap' (1981) 89 Psychology Bull 246, 251, and 'Evidence Evaluation in Complex Decision Making' (1986) 51 J. Personality and Soc. Psychology
    • Psychological research endorsing the general use of this heuristic includes R. Hastie, 'Juror Decision-Making Models: The Generalisation Gap' (1981) 89 Psychology Bull 246, 251, and 'Evidence Evaluation in Complex Decision Making' (1986) 51 J. Personality and Soc. Psychology 242-244
  • 18
    • 0032927882 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Juror reactions to DNA evidence: Errors and expectancies
    • J. Schklar and S. Diamond, 'Juror reactions to DNA evidence: Errors and expectancies' (1999) 23 Law & Human Behavior 159
    • (1999) Law & Human Behavior , vol.23 , pp. 159
    • Schklar, J.1    Diamond, S.2
  • 19
    • 26944450538 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Juror understanding of DNA evidence: An empirical assessment of presentation formats for trace evidence with a relatively small random-match probability
    • D. Nance and S. Morris, 'Juror understanding of DNA evidence: An empirical assessment of presentation formats for trace evidence with a relatively small random-match probability' (2005) 34 J Legal Studies 395
    • (2005) J Legal Studies , vol.34 , pp. 395
    • Nance, D.1    Morris, S.2
  • 20
    • 23044529157 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Psychology of Numbers in the Courtroom: How to Make DNA-Match Statistics Seem Impressive or Insufficient
    • J. Koehler, 'The Psychology of Numbers in the Courtroom: How to Make DNA-Match Statistics Seem Impressive or Insufficient' (2001) 74 Cal L Rev 1299-1300
    • (2001) Cal L Rev , vol.74 , pp. 1299-1300
    • Koehler, J.1
  • 21
    • 84871323326 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Where Koehler concludes that: 'research indicates that people think heuristically rather than probabilistically. That is, when presented with quantitative information, we do not perform algebraic computations and arrive at solutions by using tenets of logic and probability theory. Instead, we evaluate quantitative evidence via mental shortcuts and other rules of thumb. In the case of DNA evidence, the ease with which we can imagine scenarios or examples of a match other than the suspect may be the heuristic of choice.' See also K. Martire, R. Kemp and B. Newell, 'The psychology of interpreting expert evaluative opinions', paper presented at the Impressions and Expressions conference, Sydney December
    • Where Koehler concludes that: 'research indicates that people think heuristically rather than probabilistically. That is, when presented with quantitative information, we do not perform algebraic computations and arrive at solutions by using tenets of logic and probability theory. Instead, we evaluate quantitative evidence via mental shortcuts and other rules of thumb. In the case of DNA evidence, the ease with which we can imagine scenarios or examples of a match other than the suspect may be the heuristic of choice.' See also K. Martire, R. Kemp and B. Newell, 'The psychology of interpreting expert evaluative opinions', paper presented at the Impressions and Expressions conference, Sydney December 2011.
    • (2011)
  • 22
    • 84859090090 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Death of the American Trial
    • University of Chicago Press
    • R. Burns, The Death of the American Trial (University of Chicago Press, 2009).
    • (2009)
    • Burns, R.1
  • 23
    • 0002469974 scopus 로고
    • The Inference to the Best Explanation
    • G.Harman, 'The Inference to the Best Explanation' (1965) 74 The Philosophical Rev 88
    • (1965) The Philosophical Rev , vol.74 , pp. 88
    • Harman, G.1
  • 24
    • 0000479181 scopus 로고
    • TheNature of Juridical Proof
    • R.Allen, 'TheNature of Juridical Proof' (1991) 13 Cardozo L. R. 373
    • (1991) Cardozo L. R. , vol.13 , pp. 373
    • Allen, R.1
  • 25
    • 41449101021 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Juridical Proof and the Best Explanation
    • M. Pardo and R. Allen, 'Juridical Proof and the Best Explanation' (2008) 27 Law & Philosophy 223.
    • (2008) Law & Philosophy , vol.27 , pp. 223
    • Pardo, M.1    Allen, R.2
  • 26
    • 0004266879 scopus 로고
    • The Probable and the Provable
    • Oxford University Press, Oxford
    • J. Cohen, The Probable and the Provable (Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1977).
    • (1977)
    • Cohen, J.1
  • 27
    • 84871345879 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • We accept that some types of scientific inquiries (e.g. some areas of theoretical physics) may not be readily susceptible to experimental research. Such constraints are inapplicable to the vast majority of the forensic sciences. Revealingly, the reliability of many types of forensic science, particularly those involving subjective comparisons and pattern matching, remains uncertain. See e.g. National Research Council of the National Academy of Science, Strengthening Forensic Science in the United States: A Path Forward (Washington, DC: National Academies Press
    • We accept that some types of scientific inquiries (e.g. some areas of theoretical physics) may not be readily susceptible to experimental research. Such constraints are inapplicable to the vast majority of the forensic sciences. Revealingly, the reliability of many types of forensic science, particularly those involving subjective comparisons and pattern matching, remains uncertain. See e.g. National Research Council of the National Academy of Science, Strengthening Forensic Science in the United States: A Path Forward (Washington, DC: National Academies Press, 2009)
    • (2009)
  • 28
    • 23244453289 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The coming paradigm shift in forensic identification science
    • M. Saks and J. Koehler, 'The coming paradigm shift in forensic identification science' (2005) 309 Science 892
    • (2005) Science , vol.309 , pp. 892
    • Saks, M.1    Koehler, J.2
  • 29
    • 57649198439 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Failed forensics: How forensic science lost its way and how it might yet find it
    • M. Saks and D. Faigman, 'Failed forensics: How forensic science lost its way and how it might yet find it' (2008) 4 Annual Rev Law & Social Sci 149.
    • (2008) Annual Rev Law & Social Sci , vol.4 , pp. 149
    • Saks, M.1    Faigman, D.2
  • 30
    • 84871290116 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The effectiveness of these adversarial protections are strongly doubted by empirical research. For an overview see G. Edmond and A. Roberts, 'Principles of evidence law and their implications for forensic science and medicine, (2011) 33 Sydney L Rev 359, and, more generally, B. Garrett, Convicting the innocent: Where criminal prosecutions go wrong (Harvard University Press, 2011). See also Law Commission of England andWales, Expert Evidence in Criminal Proceedings in England and Wales (HMSO
    • The effectiveness of these adversarial protections are strongly doubted by empirical research. For an overview see G. Edmond and A. Roberts, 'Principles of evidence law and their implications for forensic science and medicine, (2011) 33 Sydney L Rev 359, and, more generally, B. Garrett, Convicting the innocent: Where criminal prosecutions go wrong (Harvard University Press, 2011). See also Law Commission of England andWales, Expert Evidence in Criminal Proceedings in England and Wales (HMSO, 2011) at 20-21
    • (2011) , pp. 20-21
  • 32
    • 84871278704 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Otway v R [2011] EWCA Crim 3 (gait analysis). For criticism see G. Edmond, R. Kemp, G. Porter, D. Hamer, M. Burton, K. Biber and M. San Roque, 'Atkins v The Emperor: The 'cautious' use of unreliable 'expert' opinion
    • Otway v R [2011] EWCA Crim 3 (gait analysis). For criticism see G. Edmond, R. Kemp, G. Porter, D. Hamer, M. Burton, K. Biber and M. San Roque, 'Atkins v The Emperor: The 'cautious' use of unreliable 'expert' opinion' (2010) 14
    • (2010) , pp. 14
  • 33
    • 84899265672 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This consensus was not easily achieved, see J. Aronson, GeneticWitness: Science, Law, and Controversy in theMaking of DNA Profiling (Rutgers University Press
    • This consensus was not easily achieved, see J. Aronson, GeneticWitness: Science, Law, and Controversy in theMaking of DNA Profiling (Rutgers University Press, 2007
    • (2007)
  • 34
    • 84871311153 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See for example in Australia: R v Karger [2002] SASC 294 at [148]-[150] (Gray J) and Forbes v The Queen ACTCA 10 at [29], [40]
    • See for example in Australia: R v Karger [2002] SASC 294 at [148]-[150] (Gray J) and Forbes v The Queen ACTCA 10 at [29], [40]2009
    • (2009)
  • 35
    • 84871264323 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • HCATrans 120 and in England and Wales: R v T [2010] EWCA Crim 2439 at
    • [2010] HCATrans 120 and in England and Wales: R v T [2010] EWCA Crim 2439 at 88-91
    • (2010) , pp. 88-91
  • 36
    • 79958730872 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [2010] EWCA Crim 2439
    • (2010) EWCA Crim , pp. 2439
  • 37
    • 84871288542 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • EWCA Crim
    • [2009] EWCA Crim 1876.
    • (2009) , pp. 1876
  • 38
    • 84871268451 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • EWCA Crim 2439 at [93]-[94]. In Atkins the expert's opinion was expressed in terms from a graded series-also used in R v T-but the use of the particular terms was based on non-systematic experience rather than empirical study or statistical information drawn from a relevant dataset or database. For criticism see G. Edmond, R. Kemp, G. Porter, D. Hamer, M. Burton, K. Biber andM. San Roque, 'Atkins v The Emperor: The 'cautious' use of unreliable 'expert' opinion' (2010) 14E& P 146.
    • [2010] EWCA Crim 2439 at [93]-[94]. In Atkins the expert's opinion was expressed in terms from a graded series-also used in R v T-but the use of the particular terms was based on non-systematic experience rather than empirical study or statistical information drawn from a relevant dataset or database. For criticism see G. Edmond, R. Kemp, G. Porter, D. Hamer, M. Burton, K. Biber andM. San Roque, 'Atkins v The Emperor: The 'cautious' use of unreliable 'expert' opinion' (2010) 14E& P 146.
    • (2010)
  • 39
    • 84871338844 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [2011] EWCA Crim 3
    • (2011) EWCA Crim , pp. 3
  • 40
    • 84871302608 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Where such a conclusion is obvious such 'supplementary' opinions may be legally irrelevant, that is, without genuine assistance to the jury.
    • Where such a conclusion is obvious such 'supplementary' opinions may be legally irrelevant, that is, without genuine assistance to the jury.
  • 41
    • 84871258914 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See references in n 23 above
    • See references in n 23 above
  • 42
    • 84871321355 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See R v T [2010] EWCA Crim 2439 at [31], [54], [56], [58], [60].
    • See R v T [2010] EWCA Crim 2439 at [31], [54], [56], [58], [60].
  • 43
    • 65449135740 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Truth Machine: The contentious history of DNA fingerprinting
    • University of Chicago Press
    • M. Lynch, S. Cole, R. McNally, K. Jordan, Truth Machine: The contentious history of DNA fingerprinting (University of Chicago Press, 2008) 207-219.
    • (2008) , pp. 207-219
    • Lynch, M.1    Cole, S.2    McNally, R.3    Jordan, K.4
  • 44
    • 84871300472 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This much greater degree of likelihood can be seen in the figures referred to in R v T at [31] and advocated by forensic scientists as appropriate benchmarks underlying verbal expressions of likelihood. The scale's lowest supporting point is 'weak or limited support' which means it is up to 10 times more likely the evidence would exist if the prosecution's contentions are true, 'moderate support' 10 to 100 times more likely, 'moderately strong support', 100 to 1000 times more likely, 'strong support' 1000 to 10000 times more likely, 'very strong support' 10 000 to 10 00 000 times more likely, 'extremely strong support' greater than 10 00 000 times more likely. Once revealed to explain the verbally expressed likelihood ratio these figures may become irresistibly compelling to a jury. For an example of a case where such figures were revealed to a jury see Forbes v The Queen ACTCA 10.
    • This much greater degree of likelihood can be seen in the figures referred to in R v T at [31] and advocated by forensic scientists as appropriate benchmarks underlying verbal expressions of likelihood. The scale's lowest supporting point is 'weak or limited support' which means it is up to 10 times more likely the evidence would exist if the prosecution's contentions are true, 'moderate support' 10 to 100 times more likely, 'moderately strong support', 100 to 1000 times more likely, 'strong support' 1000 to 10000 times more likely, 'very strong support' 10 000 to 10 00 000 times more likely, 'extremely strong support' greater than 10 00 000 times more likely. Once revealed to explain the verbally expressed likelihood ratio these figures may become irresistibly compelling to a jury. For an example of a case where such figures were revealed to a jury see Forbes v The Queen ACTCA 10.2009
    • (2009)
  • 45
    • 84871263714 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SASCFC 82 at [94]-[96].
    • [2010] SASCFC 82 at [94]-[96].
    • (2010)
  • 46
    • 84871263837 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • And here, in a case dependant upon DNA evidence, the non-trivial issues of handling and laboratory errorsmight also have a role to play. See e.g. F.Vincent, Report: Inquiry into the Circumstances that Led to the Conviction of Mr Farah Abdulkadir Jama (Victorian Government Printer
    • And here, in a case dependant upon DNA evidence, the non-trivial issues of handling and laboratory errorsmight also have a role to play. See e.g. F.Vincent, Report: Inquiry into the Circumstances that Led to the Conviction of Mr Farah Abdulkadir Jama (Victorian Government Printer, 2010
    • (2010)
  • 47
    • 84871295070 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • C.f. approach by Sulan J in R v CarrollSASC 156 at [59].
    • C.f. approach by Sulan J in R v CarrollSASC 156 at [59].2010
    • (2010)
  • 48
    • 84871318711 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The forensic scientists suggest that '9) It is regrettable that the judgement confuses the Bayesian approach with the use of Bayes' Theorem. The Bayesian approach does not necessarily involve the use of Bayes' Theorem.' The problem is howelse can the evidential effect of a likelihood ratio be computed? One can explain the Theorem in terms of simpler logic but it is much more convenient to use the formula to calculate evidential effec
    • The forensic scientists suggest that '9) It is regrettable that the judgement confuses the Bayesian approach with the use of Bayes' Theorem. The Bayesian approach does not necessarily involve the use of Bayes' Theorem.' The problem is howelse can the evidential effect of a likelihood ratio be computed? One can explain the Theorem in terms of simpler logic but it is much more convenient to use the formula to calculate evidential effec
  • 49
    • 84871265887 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Can DNA Evidence Alone Convict an Accused?
    • A. Ligertwood, 'Can DNA Evidence Alone Convict an Accused?' (2011) 33 Sydney L Rev 487.
    • (2011) Sydney L Rev , vol.33 , pp. 487
    • Ligertwood, A.1
  • 50
    • 84871260176 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • We recognize that this is an empirical issue, though one not particularly susceptible to investigation or analysis in the ecology of the trial
    • We recognize that this is an empirical issue, though one not particularly susceptible to investigation or analysis in the ecology of the trial


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.