메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn , Issue , 2010, Pages 13-28

Constitutional failure: Ultimately attitudinal

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 84867078312     PISSN: None     EISSN: None     Source Type: Book    
DOI: None     Document Type: Chapter
Times cited : (4)

References (69)
  • 2
    • 43849105344 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Oxford University Press 81-97
    • Sanford Levinson, Our Undemocratic Constitution (New York: Oxford University Press, 2006), 49-62, 81-97.
    • (2006) Our Undemocratic Constitution , pp. 49-62
    • Levinson, S.1
  • 5
    • 84884040047 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Adrian Vermeule challenged this proposition in the Princeton conference of February 2007, at which I presented a draft of this paper. He claims constitutional failure does not presuppose a notion of constitutional success because discussants can agree only on what counts as constitutional failure, not success. Professor Vermeule and I disagree across the board. First, I would expect little disagreement with a test of constitutional success described at a high level of abstraction, such as "adequa[cy] to the exigencies of government and the preservation of the Union," to borrow from Congress's charge of 1787 to the Philadelphia Convention, which Madison renders in Federalist No. 45 as adequacy "to the public good, the real welfare of the great body of the people." Second, I would not expect universal agreement on what counts as constitutional failure, perhaps short of a violent revolution. The founding generation reached no consensus on whether the Articles of Confederation had failed. Opposing the changes proposed by the Philadelphia Convention, some Antifederalists claimed that mere (Article XIII) amendments augmenting Congress's powers would suffice to correct the Confederation's deficiencies. Finally, and centrally, an outside observer like Professor Vermeule might contend that disagreement over whether the Constitution (government under the Constitution) is adequate to "the people's welfare" is disagreement either about nothing at all or about something that does not admit of truly better or worse understandings. But should the disagreeing parties themselves reach either conclusion, they would cease to be disagreeing parties. The mere fact of disagreement about either constitutional success or failure would hardly indicate either that there's nothing to disagree about, or that no one answer is better than any other, or that discussants should not seek the better answer, or that they should not reflect on what they are looking for before they start the quest.
  • 7
    • 84883901879 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Liberalism: Old and New, ed. Ellen Frankel Paul, Fred D. Miller, and Jeffrey Paul (New York: Cambridge University Press)
    • Michael P. Zuckert, "On Constitutional Welfare Liberalism: An Old-Liberal Perspective," in Liberalism: Old and New, ed. Ellen Frankel Paul, Fred D. Miller, and Jeffrey Paul (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2007), 313-15.
    • (2007) On Constitutional Welfare Liberalism: An Old-Liberal Perspective , pp. 313-315
    • Zuckert, M.P.1
  • 8
    • 0004279652 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Harvard University Press
    • John Hart Ely, Democracy and Distrust (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1980), 88-101.
    • (1980) Democracy and Distrust , pp. 88-101
    • Ely, J.H.1
  • 11
    • 33745960206 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New Haven: Yale University Press 70-83
    • Lawrence Sager, Justice in Plain Clothes (New Haven: Yale University Press, 2004), 5-10, 70-83.
    • (2004) Justice in Plain Clothes , pp. 5-10
    • Sager, L.1
  • 14
    • 84883944423 scopus 로고
    • The Federalist, ed. Jacob E. Cooke (Middletown, CT: Wesleyan University Press)
    • Alexander Hamilton, James Madison, and John Jay, The Federalist, ed. Jacob E. Cooke (Middletown, CT: Wesleyan University Press, 1961), No. 45, 309.
    • (1961) , Issue.45 , pp. 309
    • Hamilton, A.1    Madison, J.2    Jay, J.3
  • 15
    • 84883926248 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Princeton: Princeton University Press 92-100
    • See Sotirios A. Barber, Welfare and the Constitution (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2003), 8-22, 92-100.
    • (2003) Welfare and the Constitution , pp. 8-22
    • Barber, A.1
  • 16
    • 84922776662 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a defense of Ronald Dworkin's approach to constitutional interpretation, see Sotirios A. Barber and James E. Fleming, Constitutional Interpretation: The Basic Questions (New York: Oxford University Press, 2007), 155-70. Dworkin's original theory was set forth in Ronald Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1971), 132-37.
  • 18
    • 33846180030 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Fallacies of Negative Constitutionalism
    • Sotirios A. Barber, "Fallacies of Negative Constitutionalism," Fordham Law Review 75 (2006): 653-57.
    • (2006) Fordham Law Review , vol.75 , pp. 653-657
    • Barber, S.A.1
  • 19
    • 84884049122 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Federalist No. 51, 349.
  • 20
    • 84883908115 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Levinson, Undemocratic Constitution, 4.
  • 21
    • 84884028302 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Federalist No. 63, 423-25.
  • 22
    • 84883916445 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and No. 71, 482-83.
  • 23
    • 84884083259 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Barber, Welfare and the Constitution, chaps. 2-4.
  • 25
    • 84884080163 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Welfare and the Constitution
    • Barber, Welfare and the Constitution, 55-64.
    • Barber1
  • 26
    • 84883913500 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Federalist Nos. 44-53.
  • 29
    • 84884032940 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Welfare and the Constitution
    • Barber, Welfare and the Constitution, 100-106.
    • Barber1
  • 30
    • 84884046772 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Pessimism is justified in view of conditions of the large commercial republic beyond the immediate conditions specified above. These broader conditions include inexhaustible natural resources, nations that peacefully accept the cultural convergence that comes with the unlimited economic expansion of one member or group (i.e., cultures that walk quietly to their deaths), prospects for economic fairness within the expanding member and its partners, prospects for economic fairness within some nations without war (instead of trade) with other nations, the rationality of nuclear war, and technological advance that doesn't create more vulnerabilities than it can compensate for.
  • 31
    • 84884058231 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Constitutional Democracy
    • Murphy, Constitutional Democracy, 131-32.
    • Murphy1
  • 32
    • 84884096274 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Federalist No. 51, 349.
  • 33
    • 84883990290 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Federalist No. 49, 340-41.
  • 34
    • 0004224477 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press 233
    • Ernest Barker, The Politics of Aristotle (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1970), 110, 233.
    • (1970) The Politics of Aristotle , pp. 110
    • Barker, E.1
  • 36
    • 84884082017 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Federalist No. 84, 580.
  • 37
    • 84883994160 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Diamond, As Far as Republican Principles Will Admit, 337-68.
  • 39
    • 0039207584 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Harvard University Press
    • Stephen Macedo, Diversity and Distrust (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2000).
    • (2000) Diversity and Distrust
    • Macedo, S.1
  • 42
    • 84883942389 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Reconstructing the Commercial Republic
    • Elkin, Reconstructing the Commercial Republic.
    • Elkin1
  • 44
    • 84883951530 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Taking Rights Seriously
    • Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously, 134-37.
    • Dworkin1
  • 45
    • 0039233113 scopus 로고
    • A Natural Law Theory of Interpretation
    • Michael S. Moore, "A Natural Law Theory of Interpretation," Southern California Law Review 58 (1985): 277-398.
    • (1985) Southern California Law Review , vol.58 , pp. 277-398
    • Moore, M.S.1
  • 46
    • 84883975404 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Constitutional Interpretation
    • See also, Barber and Fleming, Constitutional Interpretation, 155-70.
    • Barber1    Fleming2
  • 47
    • 84883911471 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • More generally, and pace The Federalist, the rule of law cannot substitute for the rule of human beings where law represents and flows from a commitment to public reasonableness, a virtue.
  • 48
    • 84884080491 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For an argument that public reasonableness is essential to liberalism, see Stephen Macedo, Liberal Virtues: Citizenship, Virtue, and Community in Liberal Constitutionalism (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1990), 40-45.
  • 50
    • 84884060397 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 74 U.S. (7 Wall.) 506 (1869).
  • 51
    • 84884098207 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dismissing the negative-rights model of the Constitution as a whole does not mean dismissing the value of negative rights, for, as already observed, some negative rights are functional to the pursuit of real ends.
  • 52
    • 84884103206 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Barber, Welfare and the Constitution, 100-106.
  • 53
    • 84884039845 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Federalist No. 45, 309.
  • 54
    • 84884063966 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Federalist No. 51, 352.
  • 55
    • 84883936235 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Barber, Welfare and the Constitution, 103.
  • 57
    • 84898135152 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Barber and Fleming, Constitutional Interpretation, 117-33. This generalization would not hold for what could be the institutional notions of "reason" and "public reasonableness," for one cannot have a reason for rejecting reason or a public reason for rejecting public reasonableness. (One person or a few persons could of course have reasons for restricting the circle of persons to whom they give reasons.) Reservations in reason's behalf could in turn favor some institutional theories over others. An example might be national federalism over dual federalism. I argue to this effect in a work in progress, borrowing from my previous writings and from recent works like Malcolm M. Feeley and Edward Rubin, Federalism: Political Identity and Tragic Compromises (Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 2008), esp. 103-23.
  • 58
    • 84883903570 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Federalist No. 40, 258-60, 263.
  • 59
    • 84883999324 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Congress and Responsible Government
    • Sotirios A. Barber, "Congress and Responsible Government," Boston University Law Review 89 (2009): 702-3.
    • (2009) Boston University Law Review , vol.89 , pp. 702-703
    • Barber, S.A.1
  • 60
    • 84884094629 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I defend this view of constitutional obligation in On What the Constitution Means (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1984), chap. 3.
  • 61
    • 84883937941 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Federalist No. 40, 265 (emphasis in original).
  • 62
    • 84883959799 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Federalist No. 1, 3.
  • 63
    • 84884021026 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and No. 15, 93.
  • 64
    • 84884122303 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Constitutional Democracy, 15-16, 522-36.
    • Murphy, Constitutional Democracy, 15-16, 522-36.
    • Murphy1
  • 65
    • 84884113424 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • elfare and the Constitution
    • Barber, Welfare and the Constitution, 122-26.
    • Barber1
  • 66
    • 84884059189 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Borrowing from Macedo on "public reasonableness" (Liberal Virtues, 41-45) and Diamond's view (from Aristotle) that "each political order is literally constituted by the kind of human character it aims. to form" (As Far as Republican Principles Will Admit, 340). I argue to this effect in "Congress and Responsible Government," 698-703.
  • 67
    • 84884048073 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Federalist No. 1, 3.
  • 68
    • 84884006361 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Federalist No. 40, 265 (emphasis in original).
  • 69
    • 84883989892 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Federalist No. 49, 340-41.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.