-
1
-
-
79955826627
-
Welfare of bowman
-
See In re, 734 Wash, citing Thomas McCormick, Lecture on Judicial Decisions and Biomedical Ethics at the University of Washington School of Medicine Apr. 30, 1980 name misspelled McCormack in original "With the recent advancement of medical science, the traditional common law 'heart and lungs' definition is no longer adequate. Some of the specific factors compelling a more refined definition are: 1 modern medicine's technological ability to sustain life in the absence of spontaneous heartbeat or respiration, 2 the advent of successful organ transplantation capabilities which creates a demand for viable organs from recently deceased donors, 3 the enormous expenditure of resources potentially wasted if persons in fact dead are being treated medically as though they were alive, and 4 the need for a precise time of death so that persons who have died may be treated appropriately."
-
See In re Welfare of Bowman, 617 P.2d 731, 734 (Wash. 1980) (citing Thomas McCormick, Lecture on Judicial Decisions and Biomedical Ethics at the University of Washington School of Medicine (Apr. 30, 1980) (name misspelled McCormack in original)) ("With the recent advancement of medical science, the traditional common law 'heart and lungs' definition is no longer adequate. Some of the specific factors compelling a more refined definition are: (1) modern medicine's technological ability to sustain life in the absence of spontaneous heartbeat or respiration, (2) the advent of successful organ transplantation capabilities which creates a demand for viable organs from recently deceased donors, (3) the enormous expenditure of resources potentially wasted if persons in fact dead are being treated medically as though they were alive, and (4) the need for a precise time of death so that persons who have died may be treated appropriately.").
-
(1980)
P.2d
, vol.617
, pp. 731
-
-
-
2
-
-
49449100639
-
Pediatric heart transplantation after declaration of cardiocirculatory death
-
713
-
Mark M. Boucek et al., Pediatric Heart Transplantation After Declaration of Cardiocirculatory Death, 359 NEW ENG. J. MED. 709, 713 (2008).
-
(2008)
New Eng. J. Med.
, vol.359
, pp. 709
-
-
Boucek, M.M.1
-
3
-
-
65549091494
-
Brain death: Can it be resuscitated?
-
See, Mar.-Apr, at, 22 hereinafter Shewmon, Resuscitated
-
See D. Alan Shewmon, Brain Death: Can It Be Resuscitated?, HASTINGS CENTER REP., Mar.-Apr. 2009, at 18, 22 [hereinafter Shewmon, Resuscitated];
-
(2009)
Hastings Center Rep.
, pp. 18
-
-
Shewmon, D.A.1
-
4
-
-
0035183576
-
The brain and somatic integration: Insights into the standard biological rationale for equating "brain death" with death
-
468, hereinafter Shewmon, Somatic Integration
-
D. Alan Shewmon, The Brain and Somatic Integration: Insights into the Standard Biological Rationale for Equating "Brain Death" with Death, 26 J. MED. & PHIL. 457, 468 (2001) [hereinafter Shewmon, Somatic Integration].
-
(2001)
J. Med. & Phil.
, vol.26
, pp. 457
-
-
Shewmon, D.A.1
-
5
-
-
33745918143
-
-
See, e.g., Norton, explaining that people's fears of being buried alive, or "taphophobia, " rose significantly when cholera epidemics in Europe made it important to bury people very soon after the determination of death
-
See, e.g., JAN BONDENSON, BURIED ALIVE 31-32 (Norton 2002) (explaining that people's fears of being buried alive, or "taphophobia, " rose significantly when cholera epidemics in Europe made it important to bury people very soon after the determination of death);
-
(2002)
Buried Alive
, pp. 31-32
-
-
Bondenson, J.1
-
6
-
-
85038519290
-
-
UNUM Life Ins. Co. of Am. v. Craig, 512 Ariz, consulting the Uniform Simultaneous Death Act USDA, which is "a uniform statute originally drafted to apply in circumstances resulting in multiple related deaths where it is not possible to determine the order in which the deaths occurred, " to determine the beneficiary of insurance policies when a husband and wife were found to have died simultaneously in a car crash
-
UNUM Life Ins. Co. of Am. v. Craig, 26 P.3d 510, 512 (Ariz. 2001) (consulting the Uniform Simultaneous Death Act (USDA), which is "a uniform statute originally drafted to apply in circumstances resulting in multiple related deaths where it is not possible to determine the order in which the deaths occurred, " to determine the beneficiary of insurance policies when a husband and wife were found to have died simultaneously in a car crash).
-
(2001)
P.3d
, vol.26
, pp. 510
-
-
-
7
-
-
79955804075
-
-
People v. Eulo, 290 n. 1 N. Y
-
People v. Eulo, 472 N. E.2d 286, 290 n. 1 (N. Y. 1984)
-
(1984)
N. E.2d
, vol.472
, pp. 286
-
-
-
8
-
-
79952808891
-
-
superseded by statute, §§, McKinney
-
superseded by statute, N. Y. PUBLIC HEALTH LAW §§ 2964-67 (McKinney 2010)
-
(2010)
N. Y. Public Health Law
, pp. 2964-2967
-
-
-
9
-
-
84942004332
-
-
as recognized in In re Westchester Cnty. Med. Ctr., 611-12 n. 2, "While erecting death as a critical milepost in a person's legal life, the law has had little occasion to consider the precise point at which a person ceases to live."
-
as recognized in In re Westchester Cnty. Med. Ctr., 531 N. E.2d 607, 611-12 n. 2 (1988)) ("[W]hile erecting death as a critical milepost in a person's legal life, the law has had little occasion to consider the precise point at which a person ceases to live.").
-
(1988)
N. E.2d
, vol.531
, pp. 607
-
-
-
10
-
-
85038515417
-
-
Id. at 290
-
Id. at 290.
-
-
-
-
11
-
-
85038490897
-
-
Id. at 290-91
-
Id. at 290-91.
-
-
-
-
14
-
-
79955788852
-
-
supp, defining an anatomical gift as "a donation of all or part of a human body to take effect after the donor's death for the purpose of transplantation, therapy, research, or education" emphasis added
-
A U. L. A. 53 (supp. 2010) (defining an anatomical gift as "a donation of all or part of a human body to take effect after the donor's death for the purpose of transplantation, therapy, research, or education" (emphasis added));
-
(2010)
U. L. A.
, vol.8 A
, pp. 53
-
-
-
15
-
-
73449143856
-
The thin flat line: Redefining who is legally dead in organ donation after cardiac death
-
113
-
Maxine M. Harrington, The Thin Flat Line: Redefining Who Is Legally Dead in Organ Donation After Cardiac Death, 25 ISSUES L. AT MED. 95, 113
-
Issues L. at Med.
, vol.25
, pp. 95
-
-
Harrington, M.M.1
-
16
-
-
0002903570
-
The dead donor rule: Should we stretch it, bend it, or abandon it?
-
citing, &, in, Robert M. Arnold et al. eds.
-
(citing Robert M. Arnold & Stuart J. Youngner, The Dead Donor Rule: Should We Stretch It, Bend It, or Abandon It?, in PROCURING ORGANS FOR TRANSPLANT, THE DEBATE OVER NON-HEART-BEATING CADAVER PROTOCOLS 219, 220-21 (Robert M. Arnold et al. eds., 1995)).
-
(1995)
Procuring Organs for Transplant, the Debate Over Non-Heart-Beating Cadaver Protocols
, vol.219
, pp. 220-221
-
-
Arnold, R.M.1
Youngner, S.J.2
-
17
-
-
0014403727
-
A definition of irreversible coma
-
Ad Hoc Comm. of the Harvard Med. Sch. to Examine the Definition of Brain Death, 337-40
-
Ad Hoc Comm. of the Harvard Med. Sch. to Examine the Definition of Brain Death, A Definition of Irreversible Coma, 205 JAMA 337, 337-40 (1968).
-
(1968)
JAMA
, vol.205
, pp. 337
-
-
-
18
-
-
85038522624
-
-
Id. at 337
-
Id. at 337.
-
-
-
-
19
-
-
84944656537
-
Refinements in criteria/or the determination of death: An appraisal
-
Task Force on Death and Dying, Inst, of Soc'y, Ethics and the Life Scis., 51
-
Task Force on Death and Dying, Inst, of Soc'y, Ethics and the Life Scis., Refinements in Criteria/or the Determination of Death: An Appraisal, 221 JAMA 48, 51 (1972).
-
(1972)
JAMA
, vol.221
, pp. 48
-
-
-
20
-
-
6044253804
-
Abandon the dead donor rule or change the definition of death?
-
267
-
Robert M. Veatch, Abandon the Dead Donor Rule or Change the Definition of Death?, 14 KENNEDY INST. ETHICS J. 261, 267 (2004).
-
(2004)
Kennedy Inst. Ethics J.
, vol.14
, pp. 261
-
-
Veatch, R.M.1
-
22
-
-
85038512313
-
-
Id. at 33
-
Id. at 33.
-
-
-
-
23
-
-
85038501356
-
-
Id. at 1
-
Id. at 1.
-
-
-
-
24
-
-
79955816632
-
Unif. determination of death act
-
§ 1
-
UNIF. DETERMINATION OF DEATH ACT § 1, 12 A U. L. A. 781 (2008).
-
(2008)
U. L. A.
, vol.12 A
, pp. 781
-
-
-
25
-
-
85038502573
-
-
Id
-
Id.
-
-
-
-
26
-
-
85038491790
-
-
Vital organs are organs that are necessary for life, like the heart. Importantly, the law permits organ donation of non-vital organs from living donors, including kidney donation. However, this form of organ donation is unlikely to meet the needs of many of the people who are on waiting lists for vital organs
-
Vital organs are organs that are necessary for life, like the heart. Importantly, the law permits organ donation of non-vital organs from living donors, including kidney donation. However, this form of organ donation is unlikely to meet the needs of many of the people who are on waiting lists for vital organs.
-
-
-
-
27
-
-
79955789322
-
Wanted! dead and/or alive: Choosing among the not-so-uniform statutory definitions of death
-
See, 889-90, There are two notable exceptions of states that have made accommodations to neurological criteria for determining death for people with certain religious convictions-New York and New Jersey. New York's Department of Health issued regulations and guidance on the determination of death in 1987 and indicated the importance of "providing reasonable accommodation of an individual's religious or moral objection to use of the brain death standard to determine death."
-
See Jason L. Goldsmith, Wanted! Dead and/or Alive: Choosing Among the Not-So-Uniform Statutory Definitions of Death, 61 U. MIAMI L. REV. 871, 889-90 (2007). There are two notable exceptions of states that have made accommodations to neurological criteria for determining death for people with certain religious convictions-New York and New Jersey. New York's Department of Health issued regulations and guidance on the determination of death in 1987 and indicated the importance of "providing reasonable accommodation of an individual's religious or moral objection to use of the brain death standard to determine death."
-
(2007)
U. Miami L. Rev.
, vol.61
, pp. 871
-
-
Goldsmith, J.L.1
-
28
-
-
85038496687
-
-
See, Dec, In 2005, a panel appointed by the Department of Health clarified in guidelines what policies of reasonable accommodation hospitals may adopt. They explained that, "policies may include specific accommodations, such as the continuation of artificial respiration under certain circumstances."
-
See N. Y. STATE DEP'T OF HEALTH, GUIDELINES FOR DETERMINING BRAIN DEATH 2 (Dec. 2005), http://www.health.state.ny.us/professionals/doctors/guidelines/ determination-of-brain-deat h/docs/determination-of-brain-death.pdf. In 2005, a panel appointed by the Department of Health clarified in guidelines what policies of reasonable accommodation hospitals may adopt. They explained that, "policies may include specific accommodations, such as the continuation of artificial respiration under certain circumstances."
-
(2005)
N. Y. State Dep't of Health, Guidelines for Determining Brain Death
, pp. 2
-
-
-
29
-
-
85038490139
-
-
Id. at 2-3. Interestingly enough, the panel explained that if a family disagrees with whole brain standard of death or is in psychological denial that an individual is dead, the hospital does not need to accommodate these views; it need only allow for religious or moral views
-
Id. at 2-3. Interestingly enough, the panel explained that if a family disagrees with whole brain standard of death (or is in psychological denial that an individual is dead), the hospital does not need to accommodate these views; it need only allow for religious or moral views.
-
-
-
-
30
-
-
85038482919
-
-
Id. at 3
-
Id. at 3;
-
-
-
-
31
-
-
67650733892
-
Accommodating religious and moral objections to neurological death
-
see also, 185-86, noting that some members of the Orthodox Jewish faith, communities in Japan, Roman Catholicism, evangelical Protestantism, Islam, and Native American communities have rejected a neurological standard of death on religious or moral grounds
-
see also Robert S. Olick et al., Accommodating Religious and Moral Objections to Neurological Death, 20 J. CLINICAL ETHICS 183, 185-86 (2009) (noting that some members of the Orthodox Jewish faith, communities in Japan, Roman Catholicism, evangelical Protestantism, Islam, and Native American communities have rejected a neurological standard of death on religious or moral grounds).
-
(2009)
J. Clinical Ethics
, vol.20
, pp. 183
-
-
Olick, R.S.1
-
32
-
-
85038505038
-
-
New Jersey not only allows hospitals to reasonably accommodate individual views about death, but also requires that insurance coverage continue during the period of accommodation-i.e., after a person could be declared dead under the whole brain death standard. See, §, West, "No health care practitioner or other health care provider, and no health service plan, insurer, or governmental authority, shall deny coverage or exclude from the benefits of service any individual solely because of that individual's personal religious beliefs regarding the application of neurological criteria for, declaring death."
-
New Jersey not only allows hospitals to reasonably accommodate individual views about death, but also requires that insurance coverage continue during the period of accommodation-i.e., after a person could be declared dead under the whole brain death standard. See N. J. STAT. ANN. § 26:6A-7 (West 2007) ("No health care practitioner or other health care provider, and no health service plan, insurer, or governmental authority, shall deny coverage or exclude from the benefits of service any individual solely because of that individual's personal religious beliefs regarding the application of neurological criteria for, declaring death.").
-
(2007)
N. J. Stat. Ann.
, vol.26
-
-
-
33
-
-
65549128062
-
Policies on donation after cardiac death at children's hospitals: A mixed-methods analysis of variation
-
Cf, 1902, "The persistent shortage of transplantable organs and requests from families generated renewed interest in DCD in the early 1990s."
-
Cf. Armand H. Matheny Antommaria et al., Policies on Donation After Cardiac Death at Children's Hospitals: A Mixed-Methods Analysis of Variation, 301 JAMA 1902, 1902 (2009) ("The persistent shortage of transplantable organs and requests from families generated renewed interest in DCD in the early 1990s.").
-
(2009)
JAMA
, vol.301
, pp. 1902
-
-
Matheny, A.H.1
Antommaria2
-
34
-
-
34447523753
-
Organ donation after cardiac death
-
See, 209
-
See Robert Steinbrook, Organ Donation After Cardiac Death, 357 NEW ENG. J. MED. 209, 209 (2007).
-
(2007)
New Eng. J. Med.
, vol.357
, pp. 209
-
-
Steinbrook, R.1
-
35
-
-
33846405623
-
Taking values seriously: Ethical challenges in organ donation and transplantation for critical care professionals
-
S95
-
Mark P. Aulisio et al., Taking Values Seriously: Ethical Challenges in Organ Donation and Transplantation for Critical Care Professionals, 35 CRITICAL CARE MED. S95, S95 (2007).
-
(2007)
Critical Care Med.
, vol.35
-
-
Aulisio, M.P.1
-
36
-
-
34250813058
-
Recovery of transplantable organs after cardiac or circulatory death: Transforming the paradigm for the ethics of organ donation
-
May, at, 1
-
Joseph L. Verheijde, Mohamed Y. Rady & Joan McGregor, Recovery of Transplantable Organs After Cardiac or Circulatory Death: Transforming the Paradigm for the Ethics of Organ Donation, 2 PHIL. ETHICS & HUMAN. MED., no. 8, May 2007 at 1, 1, http://www.pehmed.com/content/pdf/l747-5341-2-8.pdf.
-
(2007)
Phil. Ethics & Human. Med.
, vol.2
, Issue.8
, pp. 1
-
-
Verheijde, J.L.1
Rady, M.Y.2
McGregor, J.3
-
37
-
-
85038490367
-
-
Harrington, supra note 9, at 107-08
-
Harrington, supra note 9, at 107-08
-
-
-
-
38
-
-
0003620441
-
-
citing, &, available at
-
(citing ROGER HERDMAN & JOHN T. POTTS, INST, OF MED., NON-HEART-BEATING ORGAN TRANSPLANTATION: MEDICAL AND ETHICAL ISSUES IN PROCUREMENT 1 (1997), available at http://www.nap.edu/catalog.php?record-id= 6036);
-
(1997)
Inst, of Med., Non-Heart-Beating Organ Transplantation: Medical and Ethical Issues in Procurement
, pp. 1
-
-
Herdman, R.1
Potts, J.T.2
-
39
-
-
77249124847
-
The circulatory-respiratory determination of death in organ donation
-
see, 964
-
see James L. Bernat et al., The Circulatory-Respiratory Determination of Death in Organ Donation, 38 Critical Care Med. 963, 964 (2010).
-
(2010)
Critical Care Med.
, vol.38
, pp. 963
-
-
Bernat, J.L.1
-
40
-
-
85038511843
-
-
heart's inability to cause a pulse or circulate blood is known as asystole. Electrocardiagraphic activity may continue after asystole without interfering with the determination of death. See Steinbrook, supra note 22, at 910
-
The heart's inability to cause a pulse or circulate blood is known as asystole. Electrocardiagraphic activity may continue after asystole without interfering with the determination of death. See Steinbrook, supra note 22, at 910.
-
-
-
-
41
-
-
77953590871
-
Are DCD donors dead?
-
See, May-June, at, 24
-
See Don Marquis, Are DCD Donors Dead?, HASTINGS CENTER REP., May-June 2010, at 24, 24.
-
(2010)
Hastings Center Rep.
, pp. 24
-
-
Marquis, D.1
-
42
-
-
85038492665
-
-
See Steinbrook, supra note 22, at 210
-
See Steinbrook, supra note 22, at 210.
-
-
-
-
43
-
-
85038487327
-
-
See id. at 211-12
-
See id. at 211-12;
-
-
-
-
44
-
-
79955812076
-
-
see also United Network for Organ Sharing, at, Mar. 23, noting that the nextof-kin may consent to procedures that assist with organ donations like heparin, regitine, femoral line placement, lymph node excision, ECMO, and bronchoscopy
-
see also United Network for Organ Sharing, Attachment III to Appendix B of the UNOS Bylaws: Model Elements for Controlled DCD Recovery Protocols, at 1 (Mar. 23, 2007), http://www.unos.org/docs/Appendix-B-AttachIII.pdf (noting that the nextof-kin may consent to procedures that assist with organ donations like heparin, regitine, femoral line placement, lymph node excision, ECMO, and bronchoscopy).
-
(2007)
Attachment III to Appendix B. of the UNOS Bylaws: Model Elements for Controlled DCD Recovery Protocols
, pp. 1
-
-
-
45
-
-
85038520526
-
-
Steinbrook, supra note 22, at 209
-
Steinbrook, supra note 22, at 209.
-
-
-
-
46
-
-
85038513933
-
-
See id. at 211
-
See id. at 211.
-
-
-
-
49
-
-
85038511164
-
-
Id. at 145-46
-
Id. at 145-46.
-
-
-
-
50
-
-
0034841151
-
Recommendations for nonheartbeating organ donation
-
Ethics Comm., American Coll. of Critical Care Med., Society of Critical Care Med., 1826-31
-
Ethics Comm., American Coll. of Critical Care Med., Society of Critical Care Med., Recommendations for Nonheartbeating Organ Donation, 29 Critical Care Med. 1826, 1826-31 (2001);
-
(2001)
Critical Care Med.
, vol.29
, pp. 1826
-
-
-
51
-
-
33644930249
-
Report of a national conference on donation after cardiac death
-
see also, 281-82
-
see also J. L. Bernat et al., Report of a National Conference on Donation After Cardiac Death, 6 AM. J. TRANSPLANTATION 281, 281-82 (2006).
-
(2006)
Am. J. Transplantation
, vol.6
, pp. 281
-
-
Bernat, J.L.1
-
52
-
-
85038512969
-
-
Ethics Comm., American Coll. of Critical Care Med., Society of Critical Care Med., supra note 35, at 1827
-
Ethics Comm., American Coll. of Critical Care Med., Society of Critical Care Med., supra note 35, at 1827.
-
-
-
-
53
-
-
85038483897
-
-
See Boucek et al., supra note 2, at 711 citing two instances in which donations were performed after an observation period of seventy-five seconds
-
See Boucek et al., supra note 2, at 711 (citing two instances in which donations were performed after an observation period of seventy-five seconds).
-
-
-
-
57
-
-
33747494876
-
Dusk, dawn, and defining death: Legal classifications and biological categories
-
E.g., in, Stuart J. Youngner, Robert M. Arnold & Renie Schapiro eds.
-
E.g., R. Alta Charo, Dusk, Dawn, and Defining Death: Legal Classifications and Biological Categories, in THE DEFINITION OF DEATH: CONTEMPORARY CONTROVERSIES 277 (Stuart J. Youngner, Robert M. Arnold & Renie Schapiro eds., 1999).
-
(1999)
The Definition of Death: Contemporary Controversies
, pp. 277
-
-
Charo, R.A.1
-
58
-
-
79955816632
-
Unif. determination of death act
-
§ 1
-
Unif. Determination of Death Act § 1, 12 A U. L. A. 781 (2008).
-
(2008)
U. L. A.
, vol.12 A
, pp. 781
-
-
-
60
-
-
0037387545
-
Extended somatic support for pregnant women after brain death
-
1241-42
-
David J. Powner & Ira M. Bernstein, Extended Somatic Support for Pregnant Women After Brain Death, 31 CRITICAL CARE MED. 1241, 1241-42 (2003).
-
(2003)
Critical Care Med.
, vol.31
, pp. 1241
-
-
Powner, D.J.1
Bernstein, I.M.2
-
61
-
-
85038515886
-
-
Id.
-
Id.
-
-
-
-
62
-
-
33646558958
-
The prolongation of somatic support in a pregnant woman with brain-death: A case report
-
see also, Apr
-
see also João P. Souza et al, The Prolongation of Somatic Support in a Pregnant Woman with Brain-Death: A Case Report, 3 REPRODUCTIVE HEALTH, no. 3, Apr. 2006 at 1, http://www.reproductive-health-journal.eom/content/3/l/3;
-
(2006)
Reproductive Health
, vol.3
, Issue.3
, pp. 1
-
-
Souza, J.P.1
-
63
-
-
47349121324
-
Extended somatic support for a pregnant woman with brain death from metastatic malignant melanoma: A case report
-
Patrick Yeung Jr., Christopher McManus & Jean-Gilles Tchabo, Extended Somatic Support for a Pregnant Woman with Brain Death from Metastatic Malignant Melanoma: A Case Report, 21 J. MATERNAL-FETAL & NEONATAL MED. 509 (2008).
-
(2008)
J. Maternal-Fetal & Neonatal Med.
, vol.21
, pp. 509
-
-
Yeung Jr., P.1
McManus, C.2
Tchabo, J.-G.3
-
65
-
-
85038519442
-
-
Somatic integration simply means some coordination of organ function so the body works together as a whole. See id. at 458
-
Somatic integration simply means some coordination of organ function so the body works together as a whole. See id. at 458.
-
-
-
-
66
-
-
85038496640
-
-
Id. at 466
-
Id. at 466.
-
-
-
-
67
-
-
85038489359
-
-
President's Council on Bioethics, supra note 8, at 40
-
The President's Council on Bioethics, supra note 8, at 40.
-
-
-
-
68
-
-
85038512895
-
-
note
-
The Council qualifies its definition of total brain failure by explaining that it does not preclude the existence of islands of brain tissue that may be damaged but not completely deteriorated. Additionally, some functionality is retained in some patients diagnosed with "brain death"-they continue to secrete anti-diuretic hormone, a process that is mediated by the brain. Id. at 37-38. Thus, even in the relatively uncontroversial part of interpreting whether a patient has irreversible cessation of neurological functions, there remains some, perhaps very minimal, brain function. This might be a fudging of the law, or a way that the procedural component of the law (i.e., that physicians are to make the determination of death in accordance with accepted medical standards) interprets the law slightly differently than the strict meaning of the language would suggest. Notably, this is different from the question of whether whole brain death can be considered death. That is not a fudge, but an outright fiction.
-
-
-
-
69
-
-
85038497412
-
-
Notably, they explain elsewhere that if total brain failure cannot support a definition of death, they would not endorse abandoning the dead donor rule and allowing organ transplantation to proceed. Id. at 12. They also explain that total brain failure does not necessarily mean complete failure-there may yet be isolated parts of the brain that function. They claim that the relevant question, however, is the following: "Is the organism as a whole still present?"
-
Notably, they explain elsewhere that if total brain failure cannot support a definition of death, they would not endorse abandoning the dead donor rule and allowing organ transplantation to proceed. Id. at 12. They also explain that total brain failure does not necessarily mean complete failure-there may yet be isolated parts of the brain that function. They claim that the relevant question, however, is the following: "Is the organism as a whole still present?"
-
-
-
-
70
-
-
85038521747
-
-
Id. at 37-38
-
Id. at 37-38.
-
-
-
-
71
-
-
85038510107
-
-
Id. at 58
-
Id. at 58;
-
-
-
-
72
-
-
85038519709
-
-
cf. id. at 95 Personal Statement of Alfonso Gomez-Lobo, Dr. Phil acknowledging the majority position but supporting the first position
-
cf. id. at 95 (Personal Statement of Alfonso Gomez-Lobo, Dr. Phil) (acknowledging the majority position but supporting the first position).
-
-
-
-
73
-
-
85038526556
-
-
Id. at 60
-
Id. at 60.
-
-
-
-
74
-
-
85038506556
-
-
Id. at 61
-
Id. at 61.
-
-
-
-
75
-
-
85038510587
-
-
Id. at 64-65
-
Id. at 64-65.
-
-
-
-
80
-
-
85038499052
-
-
Id. at 64-65
-
Id. at 64-65.
-
-
-
-
81
-
-
85038527727
-
-
Id. at 50
-
Id. at 50.
-
-
-
-
82
-
-
68149172757
-
The incoherence of determining death by neurological criteria: A commentary on controversies in the determination of death, a white paper by the president's council on bioethics
-
187-88
-
See Franklin G. Miller & Robert D. Truog, The Incoherence of Determining Death by Neurological Criteria: A Commentary on Controversies in the Determination of Death, A White Paper by the President's Council on Bioethics, 19 KENNEDY INST. ETHICS J. 185, 187-88 (2009).
-
(2009)
Kennedy Inst. Ethics J.
, vol.19
, pp. 185
-
-
Miller, F.G.1
Truog, R.D.2
-
83
-
-
0035189661
-
Beyond brain death?
-
496
-
Amir Halevy, Beyond Brain Death?, 26 J. MED. & PHIL. 493, 496 (2001).
-
(2001)
J. Med. & Phil.
, vol.26
, pp. 493
-
-
Halevy, A.1
-
84
-
-
34548577430
-
"Non-heart-beating," or "cardiac death," organ donation: Why we should care
-
332
-
Mohamed Y. Rady et al., "Non-Heart-Beating, " or "Cardiac Death, " Organ Donation: Why We Should Care, 2 J. HOSP. MED. 324, 332 (2007).
-
(2007)
J. Hosp. Med.
, vol.2
, pp. 324
-
-
Rady, M.Y.1
-
85
-
-
85038516383
-
-
Harrington, supra note 9, at 127-29
-
Harrington, supra note 9, at 127-29.
-
-
-
-
86
-
-
69249208816
-
Policies of children's - Hospitals on donation after cardiac death
-
Letter to the Editor, 844
-
Yorick J. de Groot & Erwin J. O. Kompanje, Letter to the Editor, Policies of Children's - Hospitals on Donation After Cardiac Death, 302 JAMA 844, 844 (2009);
-
(2009)
JAMA
, vol.302
, pp. 844
-
-
De Groot, Y.J.1
Kompanje, E.J.O.2
-
87
-
-
75649138307
-
Irreversibility: Cardiac death versus brain death
-
201, "The cardiorespiratory definition of death does not assure irreversibility, because CPR, extracorporeal circulation, etc., allow recovery of heartbeat after prolonged periods of asystole."
-
see also Calixto Machado & Julius Korein, Irreversibility: Cardiac Death Versus Brain Death, 20 REVS. NEUROSCIENCES 199, 201 (2009) ("[T]he cardiorespiratory definition of death does not assure irreversibility, because CPR, extracorporeal circulation, etc., allow recovery of heartbeat after prolonged periods of asystole.").
-
(2009)
Revs. Neurosciences
, vol.20
, pp. 199
-
-
Machado, C.1
Korein, J.2
-
88
-
-
34547492414
-
Seeking an ethical and legal way of procuring transplantable organs from the dying without further attempts to redefine human death
-
June
-
David Wainwright Evans, Seeking an Ethical and Legal Way of Procuring Transplantable Organs from the Dying Without Further Attempts to Redefine Human Death, 2 PHIL. ETHICS & HUMAN. MED., no. 11, June 2007 at 2, http://www.pehmed.com/content/pdf/1747-5341-2-ll.pdf.
-
(2007)
Phil. Ethics & Human. Med.
, vol.2
, Issue.11
, pp. 2
-
-
Evans, D.W.1
-
89
-
-
77951620347
-
A systematic review of autoresuscitation after cardiac arrest
-
1248
-
K. Hornby, L. Hornby & S. D. Shemie, A Systematic Review of Autoresuscitation After Cardiac Arrest, 38 CRITICAL CARE MED. 1246, 1248 (2010).
-
(2010)
Critical Care Med.
, vol.38
, pp. 1246
-
-
Hornby, K.1
Hornby, L.2
Shemie, S.D.3
-
90
-
-
85038497156
-
-
Id
-
Id.
-
-
-
-
91
-
-
85038494954
-
-
Id
-
Id.
-
-
-
-
92
-
-
70350135959
-
Eligibility for organ donation: A medico-legal perspective on defining and determining death
-
858
-
Jocelyn Downie et al., Eligibility for Organ Donation: A Medico-legal Perspective on Defining and Determining Death, 56 CANADIAN J. ANESTHESIA 851, 858 (2009);
-
(2009)
Canadian J. Anesthesia
, vol.56
, pp. 851
-
-
Downie, J.1
-
93
-
-
38849208500
-
The lazarus phenomenon
-
552, defining the Lazarus Phenomenon as "delayed return of spontaneous circulation ROSC after cessation of cardiopulmonary resuscitation CPR " and noting that it is a rare, but real, phenomenon
-
Vedamurthy Adhiyaman et al., The Lazarus Phenomenon, 100 J. ROYAL SOCY MED. 552, 552 (2007) (defining the Lazarus Phenomenon as "delayed return of spontaneous circulation (ROSC) after cessation of cardiopulmonary resuscitation (CPR) " and noting that it is a rare, but real, phenomenon).
-
(2007)
J. Royal SoCy Med.
, vol.100
, pp. 552
-
-
Adhiyaman, V.1
-
94
-
-
85038525400
-
-
Hornby, Hornby & Shemie, supra note 68, at 1248
-
Hornby, Hornby & Shemie, supra note 68, at 1248.
-
-
-
-
95
-
-
85038507740
-
-
Id. at 1251 "The existing data are of insufficient quality to support or refute the recommended waiting period to determine death after a cardiac arrest in the context of DCD."
-
Id. at 1251 ("The existing data are of insufficient quality to support or refute the recommended waiting period to determine death after a cardiac arrest in the context of DCD.").
-
-
-
-
96
-
-
49449107323
-
Donating hearts after cardiac death-reversing the irreversible
-
See, 672
-
See Robert Veatch, Donating Hearts After Cardiac Death-Reversing the Irreversible, 359 NEW ENG. J. MED. 672, 672 (2008).
-
(2008)
New Eng. J. Med.
, vol.359
, pp. 672
-
-
Veatch, R.1
-
97
-
-
4243535647
-
The role of the public in public policy on the definition of death
-
supra note 41, at, 298
-
Dan W. Brock, The Role of the Public in Public Policy on the Definition of Death, in THE DEFINITION OF DEATH: CONTEMPORARY CONTROVERSIES, supra note 41, at 293, 298.
-
The Definition of Death: Contemporary Controversies
, pp. 293
-
-
Brock, D.W.1
-
98
-
-
79955876925
-
-
E.g., §, West, "A determination of death must be made in accordance with accepted medical standards; provided however all reasonable attempts to restore spontaneous circulatory or respiratory functions shall first be made...." emphasis added
-
E.g., OKLA. STAT. ANN. tit. 63, § 3122 (West 2004) ("A determination of death must be made in accordance with accepted medical standards; provided however all reasonable attempts to restore spontaneous circulatory or respiratory functions shall first be made....") (emphasis added);
-
(2004)
Okla. Stat. Ann. Tit
, vol.63
, pp. 3122
-
-
-
99
-
-
77950406003
-
-
§, A 1, "In the opinion of a physician duly authorized to practice medicine in this Commonwealth, based on the ordinary standards of medical practice, there is the absence of spontaneous respiratory and spontaneous cardiac functions and, because of the disease or condition which directly or indirectly caused these functions to cease, or because of the passage of time since these functions ceased, attempts at resuscitation would not, in the opinion of such physician, be successful in restoring spontaneous life-sustaining functions, and, in such event, death shall be deemed to have occurred at the time these functions ceased." emphasis added
-
VA. CODE ANN. § 54.1-2972 (A) (1) (2009) ("In the opinion of a physician duly authorized to practice medicine in this Commonwealth, based on the ordinary standards of medical practice, there is the absence of spontaneous respiratory and spontaneous cardiac functions and, because of the disease or condition which directly or indirectly caused these functions to cease, or because of the passage of time since these functions ceased, attempts at resuscitation would not, in the opinion of such physician, be successful in restoring spontaneous life-sustaining functions, and, in such event, death shall be deemed to have occurred at the time these functions ceased....") (emphasis added).
-
(2009)
Va. Code Ann.
, pp. 541-2972
-
-
-
100
-
-
85038491227
-
-
*, Conn. Super. Ct. Feb. 19, The court rejected the defendant's claim that because he had three heart attacks and was resuscitated each time, his marriage had ended by death. Referring to the state statute with language from the Uniform Definition of Death Act, the court found that "the defendant's alleged 'deaths' were neither permanent nor irreversible."
-
* 3 (Conn. Super. Ct. Feb. 19, 2008) (The court rejected the defendant's claim that because he had three heart attacks and was resuscitated each time, his marriage had ended by death. Referring to the state statute with language from the Uniform Definition of Death Act, the court found that "[t]he defendant's alleged 'deaths' were neither permanent nor irreversible.");
-
(2008)
Conn. Super. LEXIS 426
, vol.2008
, pp. 3
-
-
-
101
-
-
85038499653
-
-
Jefferson Cnty. v. E. Idaho Reg'l Med. Ctr., 1087 Idaho Ct. App, In a dispute over whether a county fund had to pay a hospital for resuscitation efforts on a particular indigent woman, the court concluded that a woman could not be declared dead by a layperson or by a posthumous review of her medical records, but only after resuscitative efforts had been tried and had failed.
-
Jefferson Cnty. v. E. Idaho Reg'l Med. Ctr., 883 P.2d 1084, 1087 (Idaho Ct. App. 1994) (In a dispute over whether a county fund had to pay a hospital for resuscitation efforts on a particular indigent woman, the court concluded that a woman could not be declared dead by a layperson or by a posthumous review of her medical records, but only after resuscitative efforts had been tried and had failed.);
-
(1994)
P.2d
, vol.883
, pp. 1084
-
-
-
102
-
-
85038522842
-
-
People v. Selwa, 322-23 Mich. Ct. App, finding that a man was properly bonded for trial on a negligent homicide charge when a six and a half week old fetus was born without a heartbeat but was resuscitated and appeared to have lived for a few hours
-
People v. Selwa, 543 N. W.2d 321, 322-23 (Mich. Ct. App. 1995) (finding that a man was properly bonded for trial on a negligent homicide charge when a six and a half week old fetus was born without a heartbeat but was resuscitated and appeared to have lived for a few hours).
-
(1995)
N. W.2d
, vol.543
, pp. 321
-
-
-
103
-
-
41549084671
-
Death, organ transplantation, and medical practice
-
Feb, at, 3
-
Thomas Huddle, Michael A. Schwartz, F. Amos Bailey & Michael A. Bos, Death, Organ Transplantation, and Medical Practice, 3 PHIL. ETHICS & HUMAN. MED., no. 5, Feb. 2008 at 1, 3, http://www.peh-med.com/content/pdf/l747-5341-3- 5.pdf;
-
(2008)
Phil. Ethics & Human. Med.
, vol.3
, Issue.5
, pp. 1
-
-
Huddle, T.1
Schwartz, M.A.2
Bailey, F.A.3
Bos, M.A.4
-
104
-
-
0037789453
-
Defining death in non-heart beating organ donors
-
182
-
N. Zamperetti, Defining Death in Non-Heart Beating Organ Donors, 29 J. MED. ETHICS 182, 182 (2003).
-
(2003)
J. Med. Ethics
, vol.29
, pp. 182
-
-
Zamperetti, N.1
-
105
-
-
85038522731
-
-
Marquis, supra note 27, at 27
-
Marquis, supra note 27, at 27
-
-
-
-
106
-
-
85038508551
-
-
Brock, supra note 75, at 298-99
-
Brock, supra note 75, at 298-99;
-
-
-
-
107
-
-
85038519630
-
-
see Machado & Korein, supra note 66, at 200
-
see Machado & Korein, supra note 66, at 200.
-
-
-
-
108
-
-
49449103301
-
The boundaries of organ donation after circulatory death
-
670
-
James L. Bernat, The Boundaries of Organ Donation After Circulatory Death, 359 NEW ENG. J. MED. 669, 670 (2008).
-
(2008)
New Eng. J. Med.
, vol.359
, pp. 669
-
-
Bernat, J.L.1
-
109
-
-
85038511058
-
-
Id. at 670-71
-
Id. at 670-71.
-
-
-
-
110
-
-
85038499298
-
-
Id
-
Id.
-
-
-
-
111
-
-
85038512943
-
-
Marquis, supra note 27, at 26
-
Marquis, supra note 27, at 26.
-
-
-
-
113
-
-
33845895457
-
Cognitive consequences of forced compliance
-
209, concluding that "if a person is induced to do or say something which is contrary to his private opinion, there will be a tendency for him to change his opinion so as to bring it into correspondence with what he has done or said"
-
See Leon Festinger & James M. Carlsmith, Cognitive Consequences of Forced Compliance, 58 J. ABNORMAL SOC. PSYCH. 203, 209 (1959) (concluding that "[i]f a person is induced to do or say something which is contrary to his private opinion, there will be a tendency for him to change his opinion so as to bring it into correspondence with what he has done or said").
-
(1959)
J. Abnormal Soc. Psych
, vol.58
, pp. 203
-
-
Festinger, L.1
Carlsmith, J.M.2
-
114
-
-
0007201781
-
What courts do in fact
-
See, 655, noting that judges arrive at their decisions by "hunches" that come from "the effect of innumerable stimuli on what is loosely termed 'the personality of the judge'"
-
See Jerome Frank, What Courts Do in Fact, 26 ILL. L. REV. 645, 655 (1931) (noting that judges arrive at their decisions by "hunches" that come from "[t]he effect of innumerable stimuli on what is loosely termed 'the personality of the judge'").
-
(1931)
ILL. L. Rev.
, vol.26
, pp. 645
-
-
Frank, J.1
-
116
-
-
0025501057
-
Falling off the vine: Legal fictions and the doctrine of substituted judgment
-
see also, 14-16
-
see also Louise Harmon, Falling Off the Vine: Legal Fictions and the Doctrine of Substituted Judgment, 100 YALE L. J. 1, 14-16 (1990).
-
(1990)
Yale L. J.
, vol.100
, pp. 1
-
-
Harmon, L.1
-
117
-
-
85038505664
-
-
FULLER, supra note 88, at 9
-
FULLER, supra note 88, at 9.
-
-
-
-
118
-
-
85038497539
-
-
Id. at 12-14
-
Id. at 12-14.
-
-
-
-
119
-
-
85038517485
-
-
Id. at 92
-
Id. at 92.
-
-
-
-
120
-
-
79955859704
-
-
J. H. Burns & H. L. A. Hart eds., Oxford Univ. Press 1977, describing a legal fiction as a "willful falsehood, having for its object the stealing legislative power, by and for hands, which could not, or durst not, openly claim it, and, but for the delusion thus produced, could not exercise it"
-
JEREMY BENTHAM, THE COLLECTED WORKS OF JEREMY BENTHAM: A COMMENT ON THE COMMENTARIES AND A FRAGMENT OF GOVERNMENT 509 (J. H. Burns & H. L. A. Hart eds., Oxford Univ. Press 1977) (1838) (describing a legal fiction as a "willful falsehood, having for its object the stealing legislative power, by and for hands, which could not, or durst not, openly claim it, and, but for the delusion thus produced, could not exercise it").
-
(1838)
The Collected Works of Jeremy Bentham: A Comment on the Commentaries and A Fragment of Government
, pp. 509
-
-
Bentham, J.1
-
121
-
-
85038494928
-
-
Fuller, supra note 88, at 90 "In accordance with the notion that the legislator 'commands' or is 'all-powerful, ' it is often assumed that if fictions are found in legislation they are to be construed as expository devices-mere conveniences of expression."
-
FULLER, supra note 88, at 90 ("In accordance with the notion that the legislator 'commands' or is 'all-powerful, ' it is often assumed that if fictions are found in legislation they are to be construed as expository devices-mere conveniences of expression. ").
-
-
-
-
122
-
-
85038482349
-
-
Louise Harmon, supra note 88, at 9
-
Louise Harmon, supra note 88, at 9
-
-
-
-
124
-
-
85038497057
-
-
As Fuller explains, "the use of the word 'fiction' does not always imply that the author of the statement positively disbelieved it. It may rather imply the opinion that the author of the statement in question was or would have been had he seen its full implication aware of its inadequacy or partial untruth, although he may have believed it in the sense that he could think of no better way of expressing the idea he had in mind." Fuller, supra note 88, at 8
-
As Fuller explains, "[t]he use of the word 'fiction' does not always imply that the author of the statement positively disbelieved it. It may rather imply the opinion that the author of the statement in question was (or would have been had he seen its full implication) aware of its inadequacy or partial untruth, although he may have believed it in the sense that he could think of no better way of expressing the idea he had in mind." FULLER, supra note 88, at 8.
-
-
-
-
125
-
-
34547344511
-
New legal fictions
-
1437
-
Peter J. Smith, New Legal Fictions, 95 GEO. L. J. 1435, 1437 (2007).
-
(2007)
Geo. L. J.
, vol.95
, pp. 1435
-
-
Smith, P.J.1
-
126
-
-
85038509735
-
-
Id. at 1452-53, 1453 n. 80
-
Id. at 1452-53, 1453 n. 80.
-
-
-
-
127
-
-
85038513907
-
-
Id. at 1453-54
-
Id. at 1453-54.
-
-
-
-
128
-
-
79955795943
-
Legal fictions and juristic truth
-
19-20, Some might conflate this discussion of legal fictions with the more fundamental legal realist critiques that the way we understand the process and procedures of making law is fictitious. This confusion may arise from the fact that Lon Fuller was an early legal realist who contributed a great deal to our understanding of legal fictions
-
Nancy J. Knauer, Legal Fictions and Juristic Truth, 23 St. THOMAS L. REV. 1, 19-20 (2010). Some might conflate this discussion of legal fictions with the more fundamental legal realist critiques that the way we understand the process and procedures of making law is fictitious. This confusion may arise from the fact that Lon Fuller was an early legal realist who contributed a great deal to our understanding of legal fictions.
-
(2010)
St. Thomas L. Rev.
, vol.23
, pp. 1
-
-
Knauer, N.J.1
-
129
-
-
4644255389
-
The useful, dangerous fiction of grand jury independence
-
5
-
Niki Kuckes, The Useful, Dangerous Fiction of Grand Jury Independence, 41 AM. CRIM. L. REV. 1, 5 (2004)
-
(2004)
Am. Crim. L. Rev.
, vol.41
, pp. 1
-
-
Kuckes, N.1
-
130
-
-
26444464162
-
American legal realism
-
citing, 443, &, noting that Lon Fuller was one of the early realists. However, legal fictions should be understood as heuristic devices that transparently extend the law. Because of their transparency, they are distinct from the practices that legal realists seek to understand, like the notion that judges merely find the facts and apply the law to them
-
(citing Lon L. Fuller, American Legal Realism, 82 U. PA. L. REV. 429, 443 & n. 31 (1934)) (noting that Lon Fuller was one of the early realists). However, legal fictions should be understood as heuristic devices that transparently extend the law. Because of their transparency, they are distinct from the practices that legal realists seek to understand, like the notion that judges merely find the facts and apply the law to them.
-
(1934)
U. Pa. L. Rev.
, vol.82
, Issue.31
, pp. 429
-
-
Fuller, L.L.1
-
131
-
-
85038493189
-
-
Cf. Frank, supra note 87, at 655 describing the influence of "the personality of the judge"
-
Cf. Frank, supra note 87, at 655 (describing the influence of "the personality of the judge").
-
-
-
-
132
-
-
85038501404
-
-
Two commentators have developed the beginnings of a typology for legal fictions. See, e.g., Smith, supra note 96, at 1437
-
Two commentators have developed the beginnings of a typology for legal fictions. See, e.g., Smith, supra note 96, at 1437;
-
-
-
-
133
-
-
0036619891
-
Lessons from abroad: Mathematical, poetic, and literary fictions in the law
-
Note, 2240-44, Others have made some helpful distinctions about types of fictions and the harms of using them
-
Note, Lessons From Abroad: Mathematical, Poetic, and Literary Fictions in the Law, 115 HARV. L. REV. 2228, 2240-44 (2002). Others have made some helpful distinctions about types of fictions and the harms of using them.
-
(2002)
Harv. L. Rev.
, vol.115
, pp. 2228
-
-
-
134
-
-
70350542943
-
Legal fiction and forfeiture: An historical analysis of the civil asset forfeiture reform act
-
81-84, The important work that remains to be done is the development of a thorough typology of the different types of heuristic devices employed by different legal fictions and the advantages and disadvantages of different categories of fictions
-
Todd Barnet, Legal Fiction and Forfeiture: An Historical Analysis of the Civil Asset Forfeiture Reform Act, 40 DUQ. L. REV. 77, 81-84 (2001). The important work that remains to be done is the development of a thorough typology of the different types of heuristic devices employed by different legal fictions and the advantages and disadvantages of different categories of fictions.
-
(2001)
Duq. L. Rev.
, vol.40
, pp. 77
-
-
Barnet, T.1
-
135
-
-
85038502849
-
-
Charo, supra note 41, at 277
-
Charo, supra note 41, at 277.
-
-
-
-
138
-
-
85038483350
-
-
id. at 103 Personal Statement of Gilbert C. Meilaender
-
id. at 103 (Personal Statement of Gilbert C. Meilaender).
-
-
-
-
139
-
-
85038527794
-
-
See supra Part II. A
-
See supra Part II. A.
-
-
-
-
140
-
-
27744592831
-
Whose body is it anyway? An updated model of healthcare decision-making rights for adolescents
-
256
-
Kimberly M. Mutcherson, Whose Body Is It Anyway? An Updated Model of Healthcare Decision-making Rights for Adolescents, 14 CORNELL J. L. & PUB. POL'Y 251, 256 (2005).
-
(2005)
Cornell. J. L. & Pub. Pol'y
, vol.14
, pp. 251
-
-
Mutcherson, K.M.1
-
141
-
-
0345878991
-
Standards, rules, and social norms
-
distinctions between rules and standards are well-covered in the literature. In general, rules are easier and less costly to apply. See, 102-03, explaining that "a person can more cheaply inform himself of a rule than inform himself of a standard... given that the person or his lawyer merely consults the legislative code in order to determine the content of a rule, whereas he would have to study and interpret a body of case law in order to predict how a court would apply a standard"
-
The distinctions between rules and standards are well-covered in the literature. In general, rules are easier and less costly to apply. See Erik A. Posner, Standards, Rules, and Social Norms, 21 HARV. J. L. & PUB. POL'Y 101, 102-03 (1997) (explaining that "a person can more cheaply inform himself of a rule than inform himself of a standard... given that the person (or his lawyer) merely consults the legislative code in order to determine the content of a rule, whereas he would have to study and interpret a body of case law in order to predict how a court would apply a standard").
-
(1997)
Harv. J. L. & Pub. Pol'y
, vol.21
, pp. 101
-
-
Posner, E.A.1
-
142
-
-
85038517450
-
-
Id
-
Id.
-
-
-
-
143
-
-
85038496287
-
-
Olick et al., supra note 20, at 183
-
Olick et al., supra note 20, at 183.
-
-
-
-
144
-
-
85038504035
-
-
See supra Part II. A
-
See supra Part II. A.
-
-
-
-
145
-
-
0042938203
-
Preventing internal exile: The need for restrictions on collateral sentencing consequences
-
Surprisingly enough, treating people who are not dead as if they were dead has some precedent. The historic use of "civil death" was the way that European countries once decided how to treat ex-convicts, and was also used in the United States to a lesser degree. Someone who had been convicted of a serious offense was treated as if he had died and was no longer a member of society. In fact, "until the 1960s consequences of criminal convictions in the United States included the automatic dissolution of marriage, the denial of licenses ranging from employment to fishing permits, and the inability to enter into contracts or to engage in civil litigation. ", 154-55, It is not clear whether the fact that people who have been convicted of felonies still lose the right to vote is a holdover from this now antiquated legal fiction
-
Surprisingly enough, treating people who are not dead as if they were dead has some precedent. The historic use of "civil death" was the way that European countries once decided how to treat ex-convicts, and was also used in the United States to a lesser degree. Someone who had been convicted of a serious offense was treated as if he had died and was no longer a member of society. In fact, "until the 1960s consequences of criminal convictions in the United States included the automatic dissolution of marriage, the denial of licenses ranging from employment to fishing permits, and the inability to enter into contracts or to engage in civil litigation. " Nora V. Demleitner, Preventing Internal Exile: The Need for Restrictions on Collateral Sentencing Consequences, 11 STAN. L. & POL'Y REV. 153, 154-55 (1999). It is not clear whether the fact that people who have been convicted of felonies still lose the right to vote is a holdover from this now antiquated legal fiction.
-
(1999)
Stan. L. & Pol'y Rev.
, vol.11
, pp. 153
-
-
Demleitner, N.V.1
-
146
-
-
85038512630
-
-
Marquis, supra note 27, at 25, 30
-
Marquis, supra note 27, at 25, 30.
-
-
-
-
147
-
-
85038490447
-
-
Importantly, these patients might not be treated as dead in a detrimental way, as we explain infra Part V. A
-
Importantly, these patients might not be treated as dead in a detrimental way, as we explain infra Part V. A.
-
-
-
-
148
-
-
85008346767
-
-
Combs v. Int'l Ins. Co., 599 6th Cir, "It has always been the law that where a party deliberately incapacitates himself or renders performance of his contract impossible, his act amounts to an injury to the other party, which gives the other party a cause of action for breach of contract."
-
Combs v. Int'l Ins. Co., 354 F.3d 568, 599 (6th Cir. 2004) ("[I]t has always been the law that where a party deliberately incapacitates himself or renders performance of his contract impossible, his act amounts to an injury to the other party, which gives the other party a cause of action for breach of contract."
-
(2004)
F.3d
, vol.354
, pp. 568
-
-
-
149
-
-
79955839098
-
-
quoting Roehm v. Horst, 18
-
(quoting Roehm v. Horst, 178 U. S. 1, 18 (1900)));
-
(1900)
U. S.
, vol.178
, pp. 1
-
-
-
150
-
-
85038497940
-
-
Wis. Power & Light Co. v. Century Indem. Co., 793 7th Cir, "The disclaimer of a contractual duty is a breach of contract even if the time specified in the contract for performing the duty has not yet arrived. It is what is called anticipatory breach."
-
Wis. Power & Light Co. v. Century Indem. Co., 130 F.3d 787, 793 (7th Cir. 1997) ("The disclaimer of a contractual duty is a breach of contract even if the time specified in the contract for performing the duty has not yet arrived. It is what is called anticipatory breach.").
-
(1997)
F.3d
, vol.130
, pp. 787
-
-
-
151
-
-
85038508668
-
The declaratory judgment act's actual controversy requirement: Should a patent owner's promise not to sue deprive the court of jurisdiction?
-
Super Sack Mfg. Corp. v. Chase Packaging Corp., 580-82
-
Michael G. Munsell, The Declaratory Judgment Act's Actual Controversy Requirement: Should a Patent Owner's Promise Not to Sue Deprive the Court of Jurisdiction?: Super Sack Mfg. Corp. v. Chase Packaging Corp., 62 Mo. L. REV. 573, 580-82 (1997)
-
(1997)
Mo. L. Rev.
, vol.62
, pp. 573
-
-
Munsell, M.G.1
-
152
-
-
85038504243
-
-
citing Air-vend, Inc. v. Thorne Indus., Inc, 1125 D. Minn
-
(citing Air-vend, Inc. v. Thorne Indus., Inc. 625 F. Supp. 1123, 1125 (D. Minn. 1985)
-
(1985)
F. Supp
, vol.625
, pp. 1123
-
-
-
153
-
-
85038483287
-
-
aff'd, Fed. Cir, unpublished opinion
-
aff'd, 831 F.2d 306 (Fed. Cir. 1987) (unpublished opinion)).
-
(1987)
F.2d
, vol.831
, pp. 306
-
-
-
154
-
-
85038496309
-
-
Machado & Korein, supra note 66, at 201
-
Machado & Korein, supra note 66, at 201.
-
-
-
-
155
-
-
33746861655
-
Victims of cardiac arrest occurring outside the hospital: A source of transplantable kidneys
-
157
-
Ana L. Sanchez-Fructuouso et al., Victims of Cardiac Arrest Occurring Outside the Hospital: A Source of Transplantable Kidneys, 145 ANN. INT. MED. 157, 157 (2006).
-
(2006)
Ann. Int. Med.
, vol.145
, pp. 157
-
-
Sanchez-Fructuouso, A.L.1
-
156
-
-
0003293917
-
The bifurcated legal standard of determining death: Does it work?
-
supra note 41, at, 130
-
Alex M. Capron, The Bifurcated Legal Standard of Determining Death: Does It Work?, in THE DEFINITION OF DEATH: CONTEMPORARY CONTROVERSIES, supra note 41, at 117, 130.
-
The Definition of Death: Contemporary Controversies
, pp. 117
-
-
Capron, A.M.1
-
157
-
-
85038505767
-
Organ donation: Don't let these myths confuse you
-
See, e.g., Apr. 3, conflating a false determination of death with the possibility of being restored to a fully functioning life
-
See, e.g., Mayo Clinic Staff, Organ Donation: Don't Let These Myths Confuse You, MAYOCLINIC. COM (Apr. 3, 2010), http://www.mayoclinic.com/health/ organdonation/FL00077 (conflating a false determination of death with the possibility of being restored to a fully functioning life).
-
(2010)
MayoClinic. Com
-
-
Staff, M.C.1
-
158
-
-
85038492710
-
Natasha richardson brain dead, family gathered (update: She has died)
-
Mar. 17, 11:00 PM
-
Katherine Thomson, Natasha Richardson Brain Dead, Family Gathered (Update: She Has Died), HUFFINGTON POST (Mar. 17, 2009, 11:00 PM), http://www.huffingtonpost.com/2009/03/i7/natasha-richardson-brain-n-175764.html.
-
(2009)
Huffington Post
-
-
Thomson, K.1
-
159
-
-
85038480502
-
-
An individual with PVS is in a state of unconsciousness that has persisted for some time, where the chance of returning to a conscious state is deemed highly unlikely. However, whether individuals with PVS truly lack awareness has recently come under scrutiny, as will be discussed supra in Part IV. A
-
An individual with PVS is in a state of unconsciousness that has persisted for some time, where the chance of returning to a conscious state is deemed highly unlikely. However, whether individuals with PVS truly lack awareness has recently come under scrutiny, as will be discussed supra in Part IV. A.
-
-
-
-
160
-
-
4644356460
-
Death and organ procurement: Public beliefs and attitudes
-
2332
-
Laura A. Siminoff, Christopher Burant & Stuart J. Youngner, Death and Organ Procurement: Public Beliefs and Attitudes, 59 SOC. SCI. & MED. 2325, 2332 (2004).
-
(2004)
Soc. Sci. & Med.
, vol.59
, pp. 2325
-
-
Siminoff, L.A.1
Burant, C.2
Youngner, S.J.3
-
161
-
-
77952189827
-
-
supra note 8, at, "If indeed it is the case that there is no solid scientific or philosophical rationale for the current 'whole brain standard, ' then the only ethical course is to stop procuring organs from heart-beating individuals. Organ transplantation could continue, but with exclusive reliance on donors whose death is determined by the cardiopulmonary standard under a controlled DCD protocol....". Notably, we have argued that controlled DCDD as currently practiced also involves a legal fiction
-
PRESIDENT'S COUNCIL ON BIOETHICS, supra note 8, at 12 ("If indeed it is the case that there is no solid scientific or philosophical rationale for the current 'whole brain standard, ' then the only ethical course is to stop procuring organs from heart-beating individuals. Organ transplantation could continue, but with exclusive reliance on donors whose death is determined by the cardiopulmonary standard under a controlled DCD protocol...."). Notably, we have argued that controlled DCDD as currently practiced also involves a legal fiction.
-
President's Council on Bioethics
, pp. 12
-
-
-
162
-
-
85038521596
-
-
higher brain standard is also problematic because there is reason to doubt consciousness is seated in the neocortex, which suggests that a conscious individual could be declared dead under the higher brain standard. See Machado & Korein, supra note 66, at 200-01
-
The higher brain standard is also problematic because there is reason to doubt consciousness is seated in the neocortex, which suggests that a conscious individual could be declared dead under the higher brain standard. See Machado & Korein, supra note 66, at 200-01.
-
-
-
-
163
-
-
0003506798
-
-
defining a "harm" as a setback to the interests of a person or being. This four volume treatise provides a widely-cited and influential account of harm to individuals. However, Feinberg's account of harm has been subject to some criticism. As David Shoemaker notes, although this account has been criticized for not establishing the necessary conditions for harm, even these critics recognize that Feinberg's criteria are sufficient to establish harm
-
1 JOEL FEINBERG, THE MORAL LIMITS OF THE CRIMINAL LAW: HARM TO OTHERS 31-64 (1984) (defining a "harm" as a setback to the interests of a person or being). This four volume treatise provides a widely-cited and influential account of harm to individuals. However, Feinberg's account of harm has been subject to some criticism. As David Shoemaker notes, although this account has been criticized for not establishing the necessary conditions for harm, even these critics recognize that Feinberg's criteria are sufficient to establish harm.
-
(1984)
The Moral Limits of the Criminal Law: Harm to Others
, vol.1
, pp. 31-64
-
-
Feinberg, J.1
-
164
-
-
0034558751
-
"Dirty words" and the offense principle
-
547, Those who favor another conception of harm may need to apply alternative conceptions to the analysis of whether a "brain dead" person or a person who has decided to withdraw therapy can be harmed or wronged
-
David W. Shoemaker, "Dirty Words" and the Offense Principle, 19 L. & PHIL. 545, 547 n. 5 (2000). Those who favor another conception of harm may need to apply alternative conceptions to the analysis of whether a "brain dead" person or a person who has decided to withdraw therapy can be harmed or wronged.
-
(2000)
L. & Phil.
, vol.19
, Issue.5
, pp. 545
-
-
Shoemaker, D.W.1
-
165
-
-
85038526668
-
-
See, e.g., Miller & Truog, supra note 62, at 188-90
-
See, e.g., Miller & Truog, supra note 62, at 188-90;
-
-
-
-
166
-
-
70449632942
-
Death and organ donation: Back to the future
-
618-19
-
Franklin G. Miller, Death and Organ Donation: Back to the Future, 35 J. MED. ETHICS 616, 618-19 (2009).
-
(2009)
J. Med. Ethics
, vol.35
, pp. 616
-
-
Miller, F.G.1
-
167
-
-
84866323261
-
The definition of death
-
Oct. 26
-
David De Grazia, The Definition of Death, STANFORD ENCYCLOPEDIA OF PHILOSOPHY (Oct. 26, 2007), http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/death-definition/.
-
(2007)
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
-
-
De Grazia, D.1
-
168
-
-
77149167629
-
Willful modulation of brain activity in disorders of consciousness
-
PVS patients were asked questions and asked to visualize themselves engaged in a motor activity like swinging a tennis racket or in a spatial activity like walking around observing objects in a room. Patients would indicate a yes or no response to the questions asked by visualizing either the motor activity or the spatial activity. Functional Magnetic Resonance Imaging fMRI was used to see which areas of the brain were activated in response to a series of yes or no questions. Five patients appeared to get the answers right to a series of personal questions
-
Martin M. Monti et al., Willful Modulation of Brain Activity in Disorders of Consciousness, 362 NEW ENG. J. MED. 579 (2010). PVS patients were asked questions and asked to visualize themselves engaged in a motor activity like swinging a tennis racket or in a spatial activity like walking around observing objects in a room. Patients would indicate a yes or no response to the questions asked by visualizing either the motor activity or the spatial activity. Functional Magnetic Resonance Imaging (fMRI) was used to see which areas of the brain were activated in response to a series of yes or no questions. Five patients appeared to get the answers right to a series of personal questions.
-
(2010)
New Eng. J. Med.
, vol.362
, pp. 579
-
-
Monti, M.M.1
-
169
-
-
85038497908
-
-
Machado & Korein, supra note 66, at 201
-
Machado & Korein, supra note 66, at 201.
-
-
-
-
170
-
-
85038524488
-
-
note
-
Is the dead donor rule itself a legal fiction? From one point of view, the answer is yes. As applied, the dead donor rule takes on the color of a legal fiction because the underlying determination of death rests on fictions. From another standpoint, however, the dead donor rule simply places constraints on what physicians can and cannot do. The determination of when death occurs is found elsewhere in the law and happens to involve legal fictions. Similarly, a statute that places constraints on the campaign donations of persons is not fictitious, even though the fiction that a corporation is a person under the eyes of the law means that the statute will apply to corporations and generate a Active outcome. Nothing much depends on whether we conceive of the dead donor rule as a second-order legal fiction or whether we think of the underlying determinations of death as legal fictions. For this reason, and because we have found analyzing the different legal fictions involved in the determinations of death to more directly take us to conceptually rich issues, we have not considered the dead donor rule to be a legal fiction in this Article.
-
-
-
-
171
-
-
85038499086
-
-
U. S. Dep't of Health & Human Servs., Step 1: Transplant; Step 2: Deceased Donor Transplants by State last visited Oct. 13, 2010
-
U. S. DEP'T OF HEALTH & HUMAN SERVS., ORGAN PROCUREMENT & TRANSPLANTATION NETWORK, DECEASED DONOR TRANSPLANTS IN U. S. BY STATE, http://optn. transplant.hrsa.gov/latestData/step2.asp (Step 1: Transplant; Step 2: Deceased Donor Transplants by State) (last visited Oct. 13, 2010).
-
Organ Procurement & Transplantation Network, Deceased Donor Transplants in U. S. by State
-
-
-
172
-
-
57849108174
-
Rethinking the ethics of vital organ donations
-
Nov.-Dec, at, 41. To be valid, consent would have to include informing patients that this type of donation is not donation after death, because the whole brain criterion does not correspond to death. Here, we are again relying upon Feinberg's account that a harm sets back a person's interests
-
Franklin G. Miller & Robert D. Truog, Rethinking the Ethics of Vital Organ Donations, 38 HASTINGS CENTER REP., Nov.-Dec. 2008, at 38, 41. To be valid, consent would have to include informing patients that this type of donation is not donation after death, because the whole brain criterion does not correspond to death. Here, we are again relying upon Feinberg's account that a harm sets back a person's interests.
-
(2008)
Hastings Center Rep.
, vol.38
, pp. 38
-
-
Miller, F.G.1
Truog, R.D.2
-
173
-
-
85038523326
-
-
See FEINBERG, supra note 123
-
See FEINBERG, supra note 123.
-
-
-
-
174
-
-
0013101271
-
As good as dead
-
Aug. 13
-
Gary Greenberg, As Good as Dead, NEW YORKER, Aug. 13, 2001, http://www.newyorker.com/archive/2001/08/l3/010813fa-FACT.
-
(2001)
New Yorker
-
-
Greenberg, G.1
-
175
-
-
0032047774
-
The future of euthanasia and physician-assisted suicide: Beyond rights talk to informed public policy
-
See generally Ezekiel J. Emanuel, The Future of Euthanasia and Physician-Assisted Suicide: Beyond Rights Talk to Informed Public Policy, 82 MINN. L. REV. 983, 1003-10 (1998) (discussing benefits and dangers of physician-assisted suicide and euthanasia). (Pubitemid 128402275)
-
(1998)
Minnesota Law Review
, vol.82
, Issue.4
, pp. 983
-
-
Emanuel, E.J.1
-
176
-
-
33749064305
-
-
Cruzan v. Director, Mo. Dep't of Health, 270
-
Cruzan v. Director, Mo. Dep't of Health, 497 U. S. 261, 270 (1990).
-
(1990)
U. S.
, vol.497
, pp. 261
-
-
-
177
-
-
85038488536
-
-
Miller & Truog, supra note 130
-
Miller & Truog, supra note 130.
-
-
-
-
178
-
-
1842295516
-
-
re, 670 N. J
-
In re Quinlan, 355 A.2d 647, 670 (N. J. 1976).
-
(1976)
A.2d
, vol.355
, pp. 647
-
-
Quinlan1
-
179
-
-
85038501052
-
-
Id
-
Id.
-
-
-
-
180
-
-
85038520004
-
-
Id
-
Id.
-
-
-
-
181
-
-
33947433798
-
-
citing Eisenstadt v. Baird, 445-46
-
(citing Eisenstadt v. Baird, 405 U. S. 438, 445-46 (1972);
-
(1972)
U. S.
, vol.405
, pp. 438
-
-
-
182
-
-
15744361838
-
-
Griswold v. Connecticut, 481
-
Griswold v. Connecticut, 381 U. S. 479, 481 (1965)).
-
(1965)
U. S.
, vol.381
, pp. 479
-
-
-
183
-
-
84964346583
-
-
Abigail Alliance v. Von Eschenbach, D. C. Cir, One major concern about allowing a constitutional right to save one's life is that it may have many other implications-such as allowing patients to obtain access to experimental
-
Abigail Alliance v. Von Eschenbach, 495 F.3d 695 (D. C. Cir. 2007). One major concern about allowing a constitutional right to save one's life is that it may have many other implications-such as allowing patients to obtain access to experimental drugs with highly uncertain safety and efficacy and with minimal oversight-and the courts have rightly been cautious about expanding fundamental constitutional rights for this reason.
-
(2007)
F.3d
, vol.495
, pp. 695
-
-
-
184
-
-
85038496080
-
Responding to eugene volokh, medical self-defense, prohibited experimental therapies, and payment for organs
-
See, 35, Though there might be a legitimate distinction between experimental therapy that has some unknown and likely low probability of prolonging life, and organ transplantation, which is known to save lives, judicial reluctance to expand the set of fundamental constitutional rights more generally suggests that this strategy is unlikely to succeed
-
See Richard M. Cooper, Responding to Eugene Volokh, Medical Self-Defense, Prohibited Experimental Therapies, and Payment for Organs, 121 HARV. L. REV. F. 31, 35 (2007). Though there might be a legitimate distinction between experimental therapy that has some unknown and likely low probability of prolonging life, and organ transplantation, which is known to save lives, judicial reluctance to expand the set of fundamental constitutional rights more generally suggests that this strategy is unlikely to succeed.
-
(2007)
Harv. L. Rev. F.
, vol.121
, pp. 31
-
-
Cooper, R.M.1
-
185
-
-
84964346583
-
Abigail alliance
-
See
-
See Abigail Alliance, 495 F.3d 695.
-
F.3d
, vol.495
, pp. 695
-
-
-
186
-
-
48049084323
-
Do donation after cardiac death protocols violate criminal homicide statutes?
-
See, 245, Of course, lesser offenses might also be grounds for physician liability, such as third-degree murder, manslaughter, or battery
-
See Joan McGregor et al., Do Donation After Cardiac Death Protocols Violate Criminal Homicide Statutes?, 27 MED. & L. 241, 245 (2008). Of course, lesser offenses might also be grounds for physician liability, such as third-degree murder, manslaughter, or battery.
-
(2008)
Med. & L.
, vol.27
, pp. 241
-
-
McGregor, J.1
-
187
-
-
79955818021
-
-
§, 1, 1
-
MODEL PENAL CODE § 210. 1 (1) (2009).
-
(2009)
Model Penal Code
, pp. 210
-
-
-
188
-
-
85038519497
-
-
State v. BeBee, 747 Utah, murderer was still liable even though he had shot a dying victim
-
State v. BeBee, 195 P.2d 746, 747 (Utah 1948) (murderer was still liable even though he had shot a dying victim).
-
(1948)
P.2d
, vol.195
, pp. 746
-
-
-
189
-
-
0006190237
-
Controversy erupts over organ removals
-
Apr. 13, at, explaining that the protocol included the administration of Heparin to prevent blood clotting and Regitine to widen blood vessels and increase blood flow to organs
-
Gina Kolata, Controversy Erupts over Organ Removals, N. Y. TIMES, Apr. 13, 1997, at A28 (explaining that the protocol included the administration of Heparin to prevent blood clotting and Regitine to widen blood vessels and increase blood flow to organs).
-
(1997)
N. Y. Times
-
-
Kolata, G.1
-
190
-
-
85038481822
-
-
Harrington, supra note 9, at 108
-
Harrington, supra note 9, at 108.
-
-
-
-
191
-
-
85038481006
-
-
Unif. Law Comm'rs, last visited Oct. 11
-
UNIF. LAW COMM'RS, A Few Facts About the Uniform Definition of Death Act, http://www.nccusl.org/nccusl/uniformact-factsheets/uniformacts-fs-udda.asp (last visited Oct. 11, 2010).
-
(2010)
A Few Facts About the Uniform Definition of Death Act
-
-
-
192
-
-
85038510885
-
Unif. definition of death act
-
prefatory note
-
UNIF. DEFINITION OF DEATH ACT, 12 A U. L. A. 779 prefatory note (2008).
-
(2008)
U. L. A.
, vol.12 A
, pp. 779
-
-
-
193
-
-
85038502230
-
-
Conferring immunity to physicians in this manner could also protect physicians from liability for lesser-included offenses like manslaughter or battery
-
Conferring immunity to physicians in this manner could also protect physicians from liability for lesser-included offenses like manslaughter or battery.
-
-
-
-
194
-
-
0347936732
-
-
See, e.g., §, b West, Westlaw through, Legis. Sess.
-
See, e.g., CAL. PENAL CODE § 187 (b) (West, Westlaw through 2009 Legis. Sess.).
-
(2009)
Cal. Penal Code
, pp. 187
-
-
-
195
-
-
85038514488
-
-
See id. § 196. This appears to be permitted either because it is considered a "lawful" killing, or because it is justifiable homicide when a public official acts to kill another "in obedience to any judgment of a competent court."
-
See id. § 196. This appears to be permitted either because it is considered a "lawful" killing, or because it is justifiable homicide when a public official acts to kill another "[i]n obedience to any judgment of a competent court."
-
-
-
-
196
-
-
85038510731
-
-
Id
-
Id.
-
-
-
-
197
-
-
85038494317
-
-
Kolata, supra note 142 explaining that the Cleveland Clinic contemplated revising their DCDD protocol and abandoned this proposal after a prosecutor began investigating the situation
-
Kolata, supra note 142 (explaining that the Cleveland Clinic contemplated revising their DCDD protocol and abandoned this proposal after a prosecutor began investigating the situation).
-
-
-
-
198
-
-
85038492963
-
-
This approach may raise difficulties for the "check box" method of choosing to be an organ donor well in advance, such as when people make the choice to be an organ donor as they receive their drivers' licenses. Unless there was sufficient public transparency about the nature of brain death, individuals would have to be given information about the choice they are making at the time they are asked
-
This approach may raise difficulties for the "check box" method of choosing to be an organ donor well in advance, such as when people make the choice to be an organ donor as they receive their drivers' licenses. Unless there was sufficient public transparency about the nature of brain death, individuals would have to be given information about the choice they are making at the time they are asked.
-
-
-
-
199
-
-
85038520860
-
-
FULLER, supra note 88, at 70
-
FULLER, supra note 88, at 70.
-
-
-
-
200
-
-
85038483959
-
-
Harmon, supra note 88, at 13
-
Harmon, supra note 88, at 13.
-
-
-
-
201
-
-
0642312201
-
Does the public support organ donation using higher brain-death criteria?
-
33
-
See James M. Dubois & Tracy Schmidt, Does the Public Support Organ Donation Using Higher Brain-Death Criteria?, 14 J. CLINICAL ETHICS 26, 33 (2003).
-
(2003)
J. Clinical Ethics
, vol.14
, pp. 26
-
-
Dubois, J.M.1
Schmidt, T.2
-
202
-
-
85038513125
-
-
Again, consent for organ donation would have to be informed about the legal fiction operating in DCDD for such consent to be valid, and this may complicate the way that consent is currently obtained
-
Again, consent for organ donation would have to be informed about the legal fiction operating in DCDD for such consent to be valid, and this may complicate the way that consent is currently obtained.
-
-
-
-
203
-
-
0031061254
-
Recovery from "brain death": A neurologist's apologia
-
42
-
D. Alan Shewmon, Recovery from "Brain Death": A Neurologist's Apologia, 64 LINACRE Q. 30, 42 (1997).
-
(1997)
Linacre Q.
, vol.64
, pp. 30
-
-
Shewmon, D.A.1
-
204
-
-
79955796413
-
Designating health care decisionmakers for patients without advance directives: A psychological critique
-
There may be cases in which individuals have not previously expressed their preferences in writing through an advance directive, and it is not immediately apparent what the patient's preferences would be. Although states vary on whether surrogates, without evidence of the patient's wishes, should use the substituted judgment standard or best interests standard or some combination of the two, the Uniform Health Care Decisions Act provides that a surrogate should make decisions based on the patient's instructions or expressed wishes. Barring that, the surrogate should consider the patient's best interests, which includes considering the patient's values. See, &, 986-87, To the extent that our suggested approach relies heavily on the donor's consent to withdraw treatment and recover organs, it may require using relatively high evidentiary standards for surrogate decision-making based on the patient's values and preferences
-
There may be cases in which individuals have not previously expressed their preferences in writing through an advance directive, and it is not immediately apparent what the patient's preferences would be. Although states vary on whether surrogates, without evidence of the patient's wishes, should use the substituted judgment standard or best interests standard (or some combination of the two), the Uniform Health Care Decisions Act provides that a surrogate should make decisions based on the patient's instructions or expressed wishes. Barring that, the surrogate should consider the patient's best interests, which includes considering the patient's values. See Nina A. Kohn & Jeremy A. Blumenthal, Designating Health Care Decisionmakers for Patients Without Advance Directives: A Psychological Critique, 42 GA. L. REV. 979, 986-87 (2008). To the extent that our suggested approach relies heavily on the donor's consent to withdraw treatment and recover organs, it may require using relatively high evidentiary standards for surrogate decision-making based on the patient's values and preferences.
-
(2008)
Ga. L. Rev.
, vol.42
, pp. 979
-
-
Kohn, N.A.1
Blumenthal, J.A.2
-
205
-
-
85038490774
-
-
See FULLER, supra note 88, at 69-70
-
See FULLER, supra note 88, at 69-70.
-
-
-
-
206
-
-
85038514342
-
-
Bix, supra note 85, at 20
-
Bix, supra note 85, at 20.
-
-
-
-
207
-
-
85038513701
-
-
Harmon, supra note 88, at 63
-
Harmon, supra note 88, at 63.
-
-
-
-
208
-
-
85038497172
-
-
See id. at 63
-
See id. at 63.
-
-
-
-
209
-
-
84865136792
-
-
Citizens United v. Fed. Election Comm'n, 913
-
Citizens United v. Fed. Election Comm'n, 130 S. Ct. 876, 913 (2010).
-
(2010)
S. Ct.
, vol.130
, pp. 876
-
-
-
210
-
-
77952557645
-
Roberts versus roberts
-
See, e.g., Mar. 11
-
See, e.g., Jeffrey Rosen, Roberts Versus Roberts, NEW REPUBLIC, Mar. 11, 2010, at 17;
-
(2010)
New Republic
, pp. 17
-
-
Rosen, J.1
-
211
-
-
79951614646
-
The "devastating" decision
-
Feb. 25
-
Ronald Dworkin, The "Devastating" Decision, N. Y. REVIEW OF BOOKS (Feb. 25, 2010), http://www.nybooks.com/articles/archives/2010/feb/25/the- devastating-decision/;
-
(2010)
N. Y. Review of Books
-
-
Dworkin, R.1
-
212
-
-
85038518332
-
-
President Barack Obama, State of the Union Address Jan. 10, 2010, available at
-
President Barack Obama, State of the Union Address (Jan. 10, 2010), available at http://www.whitehouse.gov/the-press-office/remarks-president-state- union-address.
-
-
-
-
213
-
-
79955805068
-
The high court's shoddy scholarship
-
See, Jan. 23, at, with regard to the use of the legal fiction by the majority, stating only that "in the face of logic and history, the majority acted as if there could be no constitutional distinction between a corporation and a human being. Untrue. The Supreme Court has long held that corporations are considered 'persons' under the Constitution and are therefore entitled to its protections. For more than a century, Congress has barred corporations from making direct contributions to political candidates, with no suggestion that it must treat corporate persons the same as real ones; that prohibition stands, at least for now."
-
See Ruth Marcus, The High Court's Shoddy Scholarship, WASH. POST, Jan. 23, 2010, at A13 (with regard to the use of the legal fiction by the majority, stating only that "in the face of logic and history, the majority acted as if there could be no constitutional distinction between a corporation and a human being. Untrue. The Supreme Court has long held that corporations are considered 'persons' under the Constitution and are therefore entitled to its protections. For more than a century, Congress has barred corporations from making direct contributions to political candidates, with no suggestion that it must treat corporate persons the same as real ones; that prohibition stands, at least for now.").
-
(2010)
Wash. Post
-
-
Marcus, R.1
-
214
-
-
85038492460
-
-
See Citizens United, at, 899-900
-
See Citizens United, 130 S. Ct. at 896-97, 899-900.
-
S. Ct.
, vol.130
, pp. 896-897
-
-
-
215
-
-
77954532194
-
-
See First Natl Bank of Bos. v. Bellotti, 804-05, White, J., dissenting "What some have considered to be the principal function of the First Amendment, the use of communication as a means of self-expression, self-realization, and self-fulfillment, is not at all furthered by corporate speech.... Shareholders in such entities do not share a common set of political or social views...."
-
See First Natl Bank of Bos. v. Bellotti, 435 U. S. 765, 804-05 (1978) (White, J., dissenting) ("[W]hat some have considered to be the principal function of the First Amendment, the use of communication as a means of self-expression, self-realization, and self-fulfillment, is not at all furthered by corporate speech.... Shareholders in such entities do not share a common set of political or social views....").
-
(1978)
U. S.
, vol.435
, pp. 765
-
-
-
216
-
-
79851474610
-
Citizens united
-
at, Stevens, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part
-
Citizens United, 130 S. Ct. at 947-48 (Stevens, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part).
-
S. Ct.
, vol.130
, pp. 947-948
-
-
-
217
-
-
85038502109
-
-
Id. at 908. How a corporation thinks, exactly, is not clear
-
Id. at 908. How a corporation thinks, exactly, is not clear.
-
-
-
-
218
-
-
85038492918
-
Bellotti
-
at, White, J., dissenting
-
Bellotti, 435 U. S. at 804-05 (White, J., dissenting).
-
U. S.
, vol.435
, pp. 804-805
-
-
-
219
-
-
79955814519
-
Taking exception to the new corporate discharge exceptions
-
759
-
Ralph Brubaker, Taking Exception to the New Corporate Discharge Exceptions, 13 AM. BANKR. INST. L. REV. 757, 759 (2005).
-
(2005)
Am. Bankr. Inst. L. Rev.
, vol.13
, pp. 757
-
-
Brubaker, R.1
-
220
-
-
85038485985
-
-
See supra Part II. A
-
See supra Part II. A.
-
-
-
-
221
-
-
85038491900
-
-
See supra Parts II. B, III. C
-
See supra Parts II. B, III. C.
-
-
-
-
222
-
-
85038496100
-
-
See supra Part II. B
-
See supra Part II. B.
-
-
-
-
223
-
-
85038483129
-
-
See N. Y. STATE DEP'T OF HEALTH, supra note 20
-
See N. Y. STATE DEP'T OF HEALTH, supra note 20.
-
-
-
-
224
-
-
85038505038
-
-
See, §, West
-
See N. J. STAT. ANN. § 26:6A-7 (West 2007).
-
(2007)
N. J. Stat. Ann.
, vol.26
-
-
-
225
-
-
80053034384
-
Lighting a fuse for rebellion on the right
-
Feb. 16
-
David Barstow, Lighting a Fuse for Rebellion on the Right, N. Y. TIMES, Feb. 16, 2010, at A1.
-
(2010)
N. Y. Times
-
-
Barstow, D.1
|