메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 27, Issue 2, 2010, Pages 181-205

Making room for options: Moral reasons, imperfect duties, and choice

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 79251644691     PISSN: 02650525     EISSN: 14716437     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1017/S0265052509990203     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (21)

References (42)
  • 1
    • 79251647612 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ed. Thomas E. Hill, Jr., trans. Arnulf Zweig (Oxford: Oxford University Press, esp., (Akademie edition, 421n, Below I note some departures from Kant's account, along with other interpretations of imperfect obligation
    • Immanuel Kant, Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals (1785), ed. Thomas E. Hill, Jr., trans. Arnulf Zweig (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002), esp. p. 222n. (Akademie edition, vol. 4: 421n.). Below I note some departures from Kant's account, along with other interpretations of imperfect obligation.
    • (2002) Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals (1785) , vol.4 , pp. 222
    • Kant, I.1
  • 2
    • 79251647207 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This view emerges in, elsewhere in this volume
    • This view emerges in Charles Larmore, "Reflection and Morality," elsewhere in this volume.
    • Reflection and Morality
    • Larmore, C.1
  • 3
    • 0347491070 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Three conceptions of rational agency
    • Cf. also the "motivation requirement" put forth as a widely accepted starting-point in , at pp. 217-18
    • Cf. also the "motivation requirement" put forth as a widely accepted starting-point in R. Jay Wallace, "Three Conceptions of Rational Agency," Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 2, no. 3 (1999): 217-42, at pp. 217-18
    • (1999) Ethical Theory and Moral Practice , vol.2 , Issue.3 , pp. 217-242
    • Wallace, R.J.1
  • 4
    • 0042842133 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Introduction
    • and the account of a similar view as granted by all parties to the current debate about reasons, in, in Cullity and Gaut, eds., (Oxford: Clarendon Press, at p. 3
    • and the account of a similar view as granted by all parties to the current debate about reasons, in Garrett Cullity and Berys Gaut, "Introduction," in Cullity and Gaut, eds., Ethics and Practical Reason (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1997), 1-27, at p. 3.
    • (1997) Ethics and Practical Reason , pp. 1-27
    • Cullity, G.1    Gaut, B.2
  • 5
    • 0006937830 scopus 로고
    • Vindicating reason
    • Note that "critical," as I use the term, implies no reference to Kant's Critiques; cf. the notion of a "critical conception of practical reason," in, in Paul Guyer, ed., (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Note that "critical," as I use the term, implies no reference to Kant's Critiques; cf. the notion of a "critical conception of practical reason," in Onora O'Neill, "Vindicating Reason," in Paul Guyer, ed., A Cambridge Companion to Kant (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992).
    • (1992) A Cambridge Companion to Kant
    • O'Neill, O.1
  • 6
    • 79251637331 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • My plural term "practical reasons" refers to particular considerations for or against action, whereas "practical reason" in the singular, without the indefinite article, refers to a faculty of the mind or a system of norms (sometimes capitalized as "Reason
    • My plural term "practical reasons" refers to particular considerations for or against action, whereas "practical reason" in the singular, without the indefinite article, refers to a faculty of the mind or a system of norms (sometimes capitalized as "Reason").
  • 7
    • 77950244670 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Practical reasons and moral 'ought'
    • See my, in Russ Schafer-Landau, ed., (Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • See my "Practical Reasons and Moral 'Ought'," in Russ Schafer-Landau, ed., Oxford Studies in Metaethics, vol. 2 (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007), 172-94.
    • (2007) Oxford Studies in Metaethics , vol.2 , pp. 172-194
  • 8
    • 0003485498 scopus 로고
    • "Discounting" is sometimes used more broadly, to cover any reduction in the weight assigned to a reason, on the model of the temporal "discount rate" for value, as in, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, As I use the term, discounting might be seen as the limiting case of this broader notion, with weight reduced to zero
    • "Discounting" is sometimes used more broadly, to cover any reduction in the weight assigned to a reason, on the model of the temporal "discount rate" for value, as in George Ainslie, Picoeconomics: The Strategic Interaction of Successive Motivational States within the Person (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992). As I use the term, discounting might be seen as the limiting case of this broader notion, with weight reduced to zero.
    • (1992) Picoeconomics: The Strategic Interaction of Successive Motivational States within the Person
    • Ainslie, G.1
  • 9
    • 85052248588 scopus 로고
    • Famine, affluence, and morality
    • For utilitarian arguments requiring maximal contribution to famine relief, see esp.
    • For utilitarian arguments requiring maximal contribution to famine relief, see esp. Peter Singer, "Famine, Affluence, and Morality," Philosophy and Public Affairs 1, no. 1 (1972): 229-43
    • (1972) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.1 , Issue.1 , pp. 229-243
    • Singer, P.1
  • 11
    • 84875681578 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kant's insistence on doing as much as we can surfaces, e.g., in his application of the formula of humanity to the duty to aid those in need (see, [4: 430]). The point of imperfect duties, on his account, is apparently just to eliminate the possibility of conflicting obligations
    • Kant's insistence on doing as much as we can surfaces, e.g., in his application of the formula of humanity to the duty to aid those in need (see Kant, Groundwork, 231 [4: 430]). The point of imperfect duties, on his account, is apparently just to eliminate the possibility of conflicting obligations.
    • Groundwork , pp. 231
    • Kant1
  • 12
    • 28644441464 scopus 로고
    • Supererogation and offense: A conceptual scheme for ethics
    • Cf.
    • Cf. Roderick M. Chisholm, "Supererogation and Offense: A Conceptual Scheme for Ethics," Ratio 5, no. 1 (1963): 1-14.
    • (1963) Ratio , vol.5 , Issue.1 , pp. 1-14
    • Chisholm, R.M.1
  • 13
    • 0242437647 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For some other attempts to capture optional reasons, see, (Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • For some other attempts to capture optional reasons, see Joseph Raz, Engaging Reason: On the Theory of Value and Action (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999), 90-117
    • (1999) Engaging Reason: On the Theory of Value and Action , pp. 90-117
    • Raz, J.1
  • 14
    • 38949083687 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Enticing reasons
    • in R. J. Wallace, P. Pettit, S. Scheffler, and M. Smith, eds., (Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • Jonathan Dancy, "Enticing Reasons," in R. J. Wallace, P. Pettit, S. Scheffler, and M. Smith, eds., Reason and Value: Themes from the Moral Philosophy of Joseph Raz (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004), 91-118
    • (2004) Reason and Value: Themes from the Moral Philosophy of Joseph Raz , pp. 91-118
    • Dancy, J.1
  • 16
    • 0004237063 scopus 로고
    • (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, though Raz's own account of optional reasons in Engaging Reason rests, instead, on appeal to the incommensurability of first-order reasons
    • Cf. Joseph Raz, Practical Reason and Norms (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1990)-though Raz's own account of optional reasons in Engaging Reason rests, instead, on appeal to the incommensurability of first-order reasons.
    • (1990) Practical Reason and Norms
    • Raz, J.1
  • 17
    • 0003867020 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • See T. M. Scanlon, What We Owe to Each Other (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1998), 50-55.
    • (1998) What We Owe to Each Other , pp. 50-55
    • Scanlon, T.M.1
  • 20
    • 79251645201 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It also might be said to confer merit on the act, and thereby on the agent, to accommodate the notion of supererogation on the kind of account offered by, elsewhere in this volume
    • It also might be said to confer merit on the act, and thereby on the agent, to accommodate the notion of supererogation on the kind of account offered by Terry Horgan and Mark Timmons, "Untying a Knot from the Inside Out: Reflections on the 'Paradox' of Supererogation," elsewhere in this volume.
    • Untying a Knot from the Inside Out: Reflections on the 'Paradox' of Supererogation
    • Horgan, T.1    Timmons, M.2
  • 21
    • 79251645693 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • One might think my reason for action in such a case would offer a criticism of failure to act, e.g., that a certain potential aid recipient will suffer unless I aid him. But note that this criticism is not really applicable unless no one else is in a position to alleviate the suffering in question. Strictly, the criticism applies to the surrounding community, or to some collective body including myself, which may indeed be subject to requirements in such cases, as will be evident in my later discussion of political issues
    • One might think my reason for action in such a case would offer a criticism of failure to act, e.g., that a certain potential aid recipient will suffer unless I aid him. But note that this criticism is not really applicable unless no one else is in a position to alleviate the suffering in question. Strictly, the criticism applies to the surrounding community, or to some collective body including myself, which may indeed be subject to requirements in such cases, as will be evident in my later discussion of political issues.
  • 23
    • 79251644013 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • both elsewhere in this volume. But I would not make the link to emotional blame or other reactive attitudes an explicit part of the definition of moral obligation, if pinning down the relevant sort of practical criticism can do the job. It is essentially criticism that tends to make one unworthy of others' personal regard, or of relationship with others
    • and Stephen Darwall, "'But It Would Be Wrong'," both elsewhere in this volume. But I would not make the link to emotional blame or other reactive attitudes an explicit part of the definition of moral obligation, if pinning down the relevant sort of practical criticism can do the job. It is essentially criticism that tends to make one unworthy of others' personal regard, or of relationship with others.
    • But It Would Be Wrong
    • Darwall, S.1
  • 24
    • 0002025908 scopus 로고
    • Moral luck
    • For less everyday examples, cf. esp. the case of Paul Gauguin's pursuit of his art by leaving his family and moving to Tahiti, discussed in, in Williams, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • For less everyday examples, cf. esp. the case of Paul Gauguin's pursuit of his art by leaving his family and moving to Tahiti, discussed in Bernard Williams, "Moral Luck," in Williams, Moral Luck (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982), 20-39
    • (1982) Moral Luck , pp. 20-39
    • Williams, B.1
  • 26
    • 79251619063 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I owe this suggestion to Michael Weber
    • I owe this suggestion to Michael Weber.
  • 27
    • 0003363646 scopus 로고
    • Freedom and resentment
    • Cf. Darwall's account of what he calls "impersonal" reasons in "'But It Would Be Wrong'." The term derives from P. F. Strawson's treatment of reactive attitudes in, where it indicates that an attitude is not a reaction just to a slight to oneself. In application to standpoints of criticism, however, "impersonal" suggests independence of persons generally. I want to distinguish moral reasons from others, such as aesthetic reasons, that might be thought to rest on criticism from an impersonal standpoint. "Interpersonal," in any case, seems a better fit with the interpretation of moral obligation in terms of "second-personal" demands that Darwall advocates, in an account with which I am broadly in sympathy
    • Cf. Darwall's account of what he calls "impersonal" reasons in "'But It Would Be Wrong'." The term derives from P. F. Strawson's treatment of reactive attitudes in Strawson, "Freedom and Resentment," Proceedings of the British Academy 48 (1962): 1-25, where it indicates that an attitude is not a reaction just to a slight to oneself. In application to standpoints of criticism, however, "impersonal" suggests independence of persons generally. I want to distinguish moral reasons from others, such as aesthetic reasons, that might be thought to rest on criticism from an impersonal standpoint. "Interpersonal," in any case, seems a better fit with the interpretation of moral obligation in terms of "second-personal" demands that Darwall advocates, in an account with which I am broadly in sympathy.
    • (1962) Proceedings of the British Academy , vol.48 , pp. 1-25
    • Strawson1
  • 28
    • 0012492956 scopus 로고
    • See , trans. Mary Gregor (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, for the treatment of imperfect duties as requiring direct concern for the beneficiary (which for Kant does not entail undergoing a feeling, but just the adoption of an end). I note that John Rawls also holds that duties of virtue include perfect duties that require action for the right reasons
    • See Immanuel Kant, The Metaphysics of Morals (1797), trans. Mary Gregor (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), for the treatment of imperfect duties as requiring direct concern for the beneficiary (which for Kant does not entail undergoing a feeling, but just the adoption of an end). I note that John Rawls also holds that duties of virtue include perfect duties that require action for the right reasons
    • (1991) The Metaphysics of Morals (1797
    • Kant, I.1
  • 30
    • 0038911441 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, (Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • See John Stuart Mill, Utilitarianism (1863) (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998), 94.
    • (1998) Utilitarianism (1863 , pp. 94
    • Mill, J.S.1
  • 31
    • 0008809643 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Justice and nature
    • See , I should note that my ensuing remarks were written before the various economic disasters of September 2008. I am reminded of a fortune cookie I once got: "Today's philosophy is tomorrow's common sense
    • See Thomas Nagel, "Justice and Nature," Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 17, no. 2 (1998): 303-21. I should note that my ensuing remarks were written before the various economic disasters of September 2008. I am reminded of a fortune cookie I once got: "Today's philosophy is tomorrow's common sense.
    • (1998) Oxford Journal of Legal Studies , vol.17 , Issue.2 , pp. 303-321
    • Nagel, T.1
  • 32
    • 33947662939 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Responsibility incorporated
    • Philip Pettit has done systematic work along these lines. See, e.g.
    • Philip Pettit has done systematic work along these lines. See, e.g., Pettit, "Responsibility Incorporated," Ethics 117, no. 1 (2007): 171-201.
    • (2007) Ethics , vol.117 , Issue.1 , pp. 171-201
    • Pettit1
  • 33
    • 0345826082 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Proximity affects the stringency of duty, including imperfect duty, in part by helping to set a threshold of minimally adequate virtue: unresponsiveness to perceptible suffering on the part of others is, in general, a worse trait than ignoring distant suffering. Cf., which denies the relevance of distance, along with degrees of bindingness of obligation
    • Proximity affects the stringency of duty, including imperfect duty, in part by helping to set a threshold of minimally adequate virtue: unresponsiveness to perceptible suffering on the part of others is, in general, a worse trait than ignoring distant suffering. Cf. Singer, "Famine, Affluence, and Morality," which denies the relevance of distance, along with degrees of bindingness of obligation.
    • Famine, Affluence, and Morality
    • Singer1
  • 34
    • 79251635741 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is my restatement of a suggestion made by Christopher Morris, to whom I owe the analogy that follows
    • This is my restatement of a suggestion made by Christopher Morris, to whom I owe the analogy that follows.
  • 35
    • 79251614840 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In addition to my own account here in terms of optional reasons, see the argument in, (unpublished) that the "strong latitude" involved in imperfect obligations is essential to selfdefinition and responsible moral agency
    • In addition to my own account here in terms of optional reasons, see the argument in Lauren Fleming, "Imperfect Duties, Moral Latitude, and ConstructingMoral Agency" (unpublished) that the "strong latitude" involved in imperfect obligations is essential to selfdefinition and responsible moral agency.
    • "Imperfect Duties, Moral Latitude, and ConstructingMoral Agency
    • Fleming, L.1
  • 36
    • 79251622016 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Raz
    • Cf. Raz, Engaging Reason, 102-4
    • Engaging Reason , pp. 102-104
  • 37
    • 35649025886 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Normative strength and the balance of reasons
    • for alternative arguments based on comparison of the two reasons in terms of a univocal measure of strength
    • and Joshua Gert, "Normative Strength and the Balance of Reasons," Philosophical Review 116, no. 4 (2007): 533-62, for alternative arguments based on comparison of the two reasons in terms of a univocal measure of strength.
    • (2007) Philosophical Review , vol.116 , Issue.4 , pp. 533-562
    • Gert, J.1
  • 38
    • 16644392635 scopus 로고
    • See esp. my , (Oxford: Oxford University Press, Let me thank Bruce Langtry for pressing this objection in discussion
    • See esp. my Practical Guilt (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995). Let me thank Bruce Langtry for pressing this objection in discussion.
    • (1995) Practical Guilt
  • 39
    • 79251615360 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Craving the right: Emotions and moral reasons
    • I argue this in terms of discounting in my essay, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, forthcoming
    • I argue this in terms of discounting in my essay "Craving the Right: Emotions and Moral Reasons," in C. Bagnoli, ed., Morality and the Emotions (Oxford: Oxford University Press, forthcoming).
    • Morality and the Emotions
    • Bagnoli, C.1
  • 40
    • 79957880473 scopus 로고
    • Guilt and virtue
    • See my
    • See my "Guilt and Virtue," Journal of Philosophy 91, no. 2 (1994): 57-70.
    • (1994) Journal of Philosophy , vol.91 , Issue.2 , pp. 57-70
  • 41
    • 0034165032 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Emotional strategies and rationality
    • Acting on a requirement to feel an emotion would depend on some degree of control over what we feel, but on that point see my
    • Acting on a requirement to feel an emotion would depend on some degree of control over what we feel, but on that point see my "Emotional Strategies and Rationality," Ethics 110, no. 3 (2000): 469-87.
    • (2000) Ethics , vol.110 , Issue.3 , pp. 469-487
  • 42
    • 79251620170 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note that not everything we refer to as "setting priorities" involves the sort of discounting of competing concerns that is at issue in my account. Sometimes, "prioritizing" a particular concern just amounts to assigning it priority in our plans to reflect its pre-given weight or importance. I take it that ordinary talk in political contexts of setting social priorities fits this mold and hence is unproblematic on the common conception of reasons as prima facie requirements. In allowing for priority-setting in light of optional reasons, my own account is also meant to accommodate decisions to modify the pre-given weight of one's reasons. I discuss this in application to free will issues in, (unpublished
    • Note that not everything we refer to as "setting priorities" involves the sort of discounting of competing concerns that is at issue in my account. Sometimes, "prioritizing" a particular concern just amounts to assigning it priority in our plans to reflect its pre-given weight or importance. I take it that ordinary talk in political contexts of setting social priorities fits this mold and hence is unproblematic on the common conception of reasons as prima facie requirements. In allowing for priority-setting in light of optional reasons, my own account is also meant to accommodate decisions to modify the pre-given weight of one's reasons. I discuss this in application to free will issues in "Reasons, Decisions, and Free Will" (unpublished).
    • Reasons, Decisions, and Free Will


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.