메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 117, Issue 2, 2007, Pages 171-201

Responsibility incorporated

(1)  Pettit, Philip a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 33947662939     PISSN: 00141704     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1086/510695     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (354)

References (64)
  • 1
    • 33947649883 scopus 로고
    • Corporate Personality and Criminal Liability
    • Eric Colvin, "Corporate Personality and Criminal Liability," Criminal Law Forum 6 (1995): 17.
    • (1995) Criminal Law Forum , vol.6 , pp. 17
    • Colvin, E.1
  • 3
    • 0004075078 scopus 로고
    • The point of view that I defend is shared in broad outline, although not always on specific points, with a number of recent authors, in particular with Peter French. See, New York: Columbia University Press
    • The point of view that I defend is shared in broad outline, although not always on specific points, with a number of recent authors, in particular with Peter French. See Peter A. French, Collective and Corporate Responsibility (New York: Columbia University Press, 1984);
    • (1984) Collective and Corporate Responsibility
    • French, P.A.1
  • 6
    • 33947637516 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • But my argument is original, I think, and in any case the point of view taken remains a minority position. The modern contractualist analysis of the commercial corporation, so it appears, still treats it as little more than a collective noun for the web of contracts that link the various participants (Ross Grantham, The Doctrinal Basis of the Rights of Company Shareholders, Cambridge Law Journal 57 [1998]: 579).
    • But my argument is original, I think, and in any case the point of view taken remains a minority position. The modern contractualist analysis of the commercial corporation, so it appears, still treats it as little more than "a collective noun for the web of contracts that link the various participants" (Ross Grantham, "The Doctrinal Basis of the Rights of Company Shareholders," Cambridge Law Journal 57 [1998]: 579).
  • 7
    • 33947620392 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This analysis may take a number of forms, whether on the basis of identifying the corporate organization with its chief officers or treating the agent involved as a delegate or imputing vicarious or associative liability. See Peter Cane, Responsibility in Law and Morality (Oxford: Hart, 2002);
    • This analysis may take a number of forms, whether on the basis of identifying the corporate organization with its chief officers or treating the agent involved as a delegate or imputing vicarious or associative liability. See Peter Cane, Responsibility in Law and Morality (Oxford: Hart, 2002);
  • 9
    • 33947613419 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The classic source is P. F. Strawson, Freedom and Resentment, in Free Will, 2nd ed., ed. Gary Watson (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003), 72-93.
    • The classic source is P. F. Strawson, "Freedom and Resentment," in Free Will, 2nd ed., ed. Gary Watson (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003), 72-93.
  • 11
    • 33947625915 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Some of these conditions may be fulfilled without others, leading to familiar scenarios of partial responsibility
    • Some of these conditions may be fulfilled without others, leading to familiar scenarios of partial responsibility.
  • 12
    • 0037365072 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Are Ethical Judgments Intrinsically Motivational? Lessons from Acquired Sociopathy
    • Agents with acquired sociopathy may be in the category. See
    • Agents with acquired sociopathy may be in the category. See A. L. Roskies, "Are Ethical Judgments Intrinsically Motivational? Lessons from Acquired Sociopathy," Philosophical Psychology 16 (2003): 51-66.
    • (2003) Philosophical Psychology , vol.16 , pp. 51-66
    • Roskies, A.L.1
  • 13
    • 33947672721 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is important to recognize because discussions in the theory of criminal justice often run the two together, setting up a false contrast between a backward-looking retributivism and a forward-looking consequentialism. Retributivism should be seen as a doctrine that bears primarily on when someone is fit to be held responsible in criminal law; consequentialism, on how someone who is fit to be held responsible should be sanctioned
    • This is important to recognize because discussions in the theory of criminal justice often run the two together, setting up a false contrast between a backward-looking retributivism and a forward-looking consequentialism. Retributivism should be seen as a doctrine that bears primarily on when someone is fit to be held responsible in criminal law; consequentialism, on how someone who is fit to be held responsible should be sanctioned.
  • 14
    • 33947678549 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Colvin, Corporate Personality and Criminal Liability; W. S. Laufer, Corporate Bodies and Guilty Minds: The Failure of Corporate Criminal Liability (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2006).
    • See, e.g., Colvin, "Corporate Personality and Criminal Liability"; W. S. Laufer, Corporate Bodies and Guilty Minds: The Failure of Corporate Criminal Liability (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2006).
  • 17
    • 33744535363 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I do not assume that acting on a shared intention is essential for group agency, only that group agency normally involves it, and in any case, I shall concentrate on the cases where it is involved. The line I favor on the analysis of acting on a shared intention is developed further in Philip Pettit and David Schweikard, Joint Action and Group Agency, Philosophy of the Social Sciences 36 (2006): 18-39.
    • I do not assume that acting on a shared intention is essential for group agency, only that group agency normally involves it, and in any case, I shall concentrate on the cases where it is involved. The line I favor on the analysis of acting on a shared intention is developed further in Philip Pettit and David Schweikard, "Joint Action and Group Agency," Philosophy of the Social Sciences 36 (2006): 18-39.
  • 18
    • 33947686305 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Broadly, it follows Michael Bratman, Faces of Intention: Selected Essays on Intention and Agency (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999).
    • Broadly, it follows Michael Bratman, Faces of Intention: Selected Essays on Intention and Agency (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999).
  • 19
    • 0038608416 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Collective Preferences, Obligations, and Rational Choice
    • For other influential approaches see
    • For other influential approaches see Margaret Gilbert, "Collective Preferences, Obligations, and Rational Choice," Economics and Philosophy 17 (2001): 109-20;
    • (2001) Economics and Philosophy , vol.17 , pp. 109-120
    • Gilbert, M.1
  • 20
    • 0040811434 scopus 로고
    • Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press
    • Raimo Tuomela, The Importance of Us (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1995).
    • (1995) The Importance of Us
    • Tuomela, R.1
  • 21
    • 60949263499 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This applies to the explicit processes of belief formation that must figure in any mental life. Some propositions will have to receive the assent of the group, however, by way of being presupposed in other more explicit patterns. That, in effect, is the lesson of Lewis Carroll, What the Tortoise Said to Achilles, Mind 4 1895, 278-80
    • This applies to the explicit processes of belief formation that must figure in any mental life. Some propositions will have to receive the assent of the group, however, by way of being presupposed in other more explicit patterns. That, in effect, is the lesson of Lewis Carroll, "What the Tortoise Said to Achilles," Mind 4 (1895): 278-80.
  • 22
    • 33947614510 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • While the propositions endorsed may be probabilistic, the possibility ruled out is that members might put degrees of belief and desire together, mainlining one another's minds and generating a system of probability and utility for the group as a whole. Assuming that people do each have fine-grained degrees of belief and desire, it is not clear how they could even know what they are, let alone communicate them to one another in the mainlining fashion; such degrees will show up in behavior, particularly in dispositions to accept various gambles, but need not be available to introspection. See Gilbert Harman, Change in View Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1986
    • While the propositions endorsed may be probabilistic, the possibility ruled out is that members might put degrees of belief and desire together, mainlining one another's minds and generating a system of probability and utility for the group as a whole. Assuming that people do each have fine-grained degrees of belief and desire, it is not clear how they could even know what they are, let alone communicate them to one another in the mainlining fashion; such degrees will show up in behavior, particularly in dispositions to accept various gambles, but need not be available to introspection. See Gilbert Harman, Change in View (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1986).
  • 25
    • 33947658752 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and Groups with Minds of Their Own, in Socializing Metaphysics, ed. Frederick F. Schmitt (New York: Rowan & Littlefield, 2003), 129-66.
    • and "Groups with Minds of Their Own," in Socializing Metaphysics, ed. Frederick F. Schmitt (New York: Rowan & Littlefield, 2003), 129-66.
  • 26
    • 60949086046 scopus 로고
    • The One and the Many: Adjudication in Collegial Courts
    • The idea of the discursive dilemma is a generalization of the legal idea of a doctrinal paradox. See
    • The idea of the discursive dilemma is a generalization of the legal idea of a doctrinal paradox. See L. A. Kernhauser and L. G. Sager, "The One and the Many: Adjudication in Collegial Courts," California Law Review 81 (1993): 1-59.
    • (1993) California Law Review , vol.81 , pp. 1-59
    • Kernhauser, L.A.1    Sager, L.G.2
  • 27
    • 33644764311 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Discursive Dilemma and Public Reason
    • For an overview of the topic and of other issues, see
    • For an overview of the topic and of other issues, see Christian List, "The Discursive Dilemma and Public Reason," Ethics 116 (2006): 362-402.
    • (2006) Ethics , vol.116 , pp. 362-402
    • List, C.1
  • 29
    • 33947669223 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • When to Defer to a Majority - and When
    • Philip Pettit, "When to Defer to a Majority - and When Not," Analysis 66 (2006): 179-87.
    • (2006) Analysis , vol.66 , pp. 179-187
    • Pettit, P.1
  • 30
    • 33947666980 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The initial theorem, explicitly focused on generalizing the discursive dilemma, is proved in Christian List and Philip Pettit, Aggregating Sets of Judgments: An Impossibility Result, Economics and Philosophy 18 (2002): 89-110.
    • The initial theorem, explicitly focused on generalizing the discursive dilemma, is proved in Christian List and Philip Pettit, "Aggregating Sets of Judgments: An Impossibility Result," Economics and Philosophy 18 (2002): 89-110.
  • 31
    • 34250878024 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Arrow's Theorem in Judgment Aggregation
    • For a more recent theorem see, forthcoming
    • For a more recent theorem see Franz Dietrich and Christian List, "Arrow's Theorem in Judgment Aggregation," Social Choice and Welfare (forthcoming);
    • Social Choice and Welfare
    • Dietrich, F.1    List, C.2
  • 32
    • 33947635943 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • this relates closely to results in Marc Pauly and Martin Van Hees, Logical Constraints on Judgment Aggregation, Journal of Philosophical Logic (forthcoming).
    • this relates closely to results in Marc Pauly and Martin Van Hees, "Logical Constraints on Judgment Aggregation," Journal of Philosophical Logic (forthcoming).
  • 33
    • 33947682577 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is the Dietrich-List result. The List-Pettit result varies a little. Assume that a group of individuals has to find a procedure for deriving a set of judgments on propositions that are logically connected, although in a slightly different sense from that in the other case. Take any procedure that treats every individual voter equally (anonymity, giving no one the status of a dictator; that is designed to work for any consistent sets of input judgments universal domain, and that enables a group to produce complete and consistent judgments over ranges of connected issues. No procedure that satisfies conditions of roughly these kinds will identify a rule or function, majoritarian or nonmajoritarian, whereby the corporate judgment on every issue can be derived from the votes and judgments of members on that issue
    • This is the Dietrich-List result. The List-Pettit result varies a little. Assume that a group of individuals has to find a procedure for deriving a set of judgments on propositions that are logically connected, although in a slightly different sense from that in the other case. Take any procedure that treats every individual voter equally (anonymity), giving no one the status of a dictator; that is designed to work for any consistent sets of input judgments (universal domain); and that enables a group to produce complete and consistent judgments over ranges of connected issues. No procedure that satisfies conditions of roughly these kinds will identify a rule or function - majoritarian or nonmajoritarian - whereby the corporate judgment on every issue can be derived from the votes and judgments of members on that issue.
  • 34
    • 43749125127 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Christian List and Philip Pettit, Group Agency and Supervenience, Southern Journal of Philosophy, suppl., ed. Murray Spindel 44 (2006): 85-104.
    • Christian List and Philip Pettit, "Group Agency and Supervenience," Southern Journal of Philosophy, suppl., ed. Murray Spindel 44 (2006): 85-104.
  • 35
    • 33947698202 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Personal and Sub-personal Reason: The Case of Groups
    • forthcoming. For an argument that the attitudes of reliable group agents cannot be generated without group-level reasoning, so that autonomy is supported in yet a stronger fashion, see
    • For an argument that the attitudes of reliable group agents cannot be generated without group-level reasoning, so that autonomy is supported in yet a stronger fashion, see Philip Pettit, "Personal and Sub-personal Reason: The Case of Groups," Dialectica 61 (2007), forthcoming.
    • (2007) Dialectica , vol.61
    • Pettit, P.1
  • 36
    • 54949121671 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • We sometimes judge that ignorance of evidence was invincible and blameless; sometimes, that it was not: we rule that, however ignorant, the agent still had access to the evidence. While it is hard to say what principles should govern such judgments of evidential access, we need not dwell on the question here, since it arises in the individual case as well as in the case of group agents. See G. Rosen, Scepticism about Moral Responsibility, Philosophical Perspectives 18 (2004): 295-313.
    • We sometimes judge that ignorance of evidence was invincible and blameless; sometimes, that it was not: we rule that, however ignorant, the agent still had access to the evidence. While it is hard to say what principles should govern such judgments of evidential access, we need not dwell on the question here, since it arises in the individual case as well as in the case of group agents. See G. Rosen, "Scepticism about Moral Responsibility," Philosophical Perspectives 18 (2004): 295-313.
  • 37
    • 33947683095 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Philip Pettit, The Common Mind: An Essay on Psychology, Society, and Politics (1993; repr., New York: Oxford University Press, 1996), chap. 2.
    • Philip Pettit, The Common Mind: An Essay on Psychology, Society, and Politics (1993; repr., New York: Oxford University Press, 1996), chap. 2.
  • 38
    • 0001981679 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Freedom in Belief and Desire
    • Philip Pettit and Michael Smith, "Freedom in Belief and Desire," Journal of Philosophy 93 (1996): 429-49,
    • (1996) Journal of Philosophy , vol.93 , pp. 429-449
    • Pettit, P.1    Smith, M.2
  • 39
    • 33947639351 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • reprinted in Frank Jackson, Philip Pettit, and Michael Smith, Mind, Morality, and Explanation (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004);
    • reprinted in Frank Jackson, Philip Pettit, and Michael Smith, Mind, Morality, and Explanation (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004);
  • 42
    • 33947711065 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Th. Eschmann, Studies on the Notion of Society in St. Thomas Aquinas: St. Thomas and the Decretal of Innocent IV, Romana Ecclesia; Ceterum, Medieval Studies 8 (1946): 35. On Aquinas's argument, see 11.
    • Th. Eschmann, "Studies on the Notion of Society in St. Thomas Aquinas: St. Thomas and the Decretal of Innocent IV, Romana Ecclesia; Ceterum," Medieval Studies 8 (1946): 35. On Aquinas's argument, see 11.
  • 43
    • 0038520251 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Decision Making in Superorganisms: How Collective Wisdom Arises from the Poorly Informed Masses
    • ed. Gerd Gigerenzer and Reinhard Selten Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
    • T. D. Seeley, "Decision Making in Superorganisms: How Collective Wisdom Arises from the Poorly Informed Masses," in Bounded Rationality: The Adaptive Toolbox, ed. Gerd Gigerenzer and Reinhard Selten (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2001).
    • (2001) Bounded Rationality: The Adaptive Toolbox
    • Seeley, T.D.1
  • 44
    • 85174221240 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Group-Level Cognition
    • For background see
    • For background see R. A. Wilson, "Group-Level Cognition," Philosophy of Science 68 (2001): 262-73.
    • (2001) Philosophy of Science , vol.68 , pp. 262-273
    • Wilson, R.A.1
  • 46
    • 0000875904 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Frank Jackson and Philip Pettit, Functionalism and Broad Content, Mind 97 (1988): 381-400, and Program Explanation: A General Perspective, Analysis 50 (1990): 107-17.
    • Frank Jackson and Philip Pettit, "Functionalism and Broad Content," Mind 97 (1988): 381-400, and "Program Explanation: A General Perspective," Analysis 50 (1990): 107-17.
  • 47
    • 33947680555 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Both are reprinted in Jackson, Pettit, and Smith, Mind, Morality, and Explanation.
    • Both are reprinted in Jackson, Pettit, and Smith, Mind, Morality, and Explanation.
  • 49
    • 0011358101 scopus 로고
    • Morality, Individuals, and Collectives
    • See, ed. J. D. G. Evans Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • See Keith Graham, "Morality, Individuals, and Collectives," in Moral Philosophy and Contemporary Problems, ed. J. D. G. Evans (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1987), 12.
    • (1987) Moral Philosophy and Contemporary Problems , pp. 12
    • Graham, K.1
  • 50
    • 33947682061 scopus 로고
    • But see, Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • But see Derek Parfit, Reasons and Persons (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1984), pt. 1.
    • (1984) Reasons and Persons , Issue.PART. 1
    • Parfit, D.1
  • 51
    • 33947711064 scopus 로고
    • Group Morality
    • ed. Philip Pettit, Richard Sylvan, and Jean Norman Oxford: Blackwell, In the firing-squad case, there is a weak suboptimal equilibrium from which no one can unilaterally depart with moral benefit. In the speeding-car case, there is a strong suboptimal moral equilibrium from which no one can unilaterally depart without doing moral harm
    • Frank Jackson, "Group Morality," in Metaphysics and Morality: Essays in Honour of J.J. C. Smart, ed. Philip Pettit, Richard Sylvan, and Jean Norman (Oxford: Blackwell, 1987), 91-110, In the firing-squad case, there is a weak suboptimal equilibrium from which no one can unilaterally depart with moral benefit. In the speeding-car case, there is a strong suboptimal moral equilibrium from which no one can unilaterally depart without doing moral harm.
    • (1987) Metaphysics and Morality: Essays in Honour of J.J. C. Smart , pp. 91-110
    • Jackson, F.1
  • 52
    • 33947657740 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Corporate Responsibility
    • ed. H. LaFolette Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • P. A. Werhane and R. E. Freeman, "Corporate Responsibility," in The Oxford Handbook of Practical Ethics, ed. H. LaFolette (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003), 523-24.
    • (2003) The Oxford Handbook of Practical Ethics , pp. 523-524
    • Werhane, P.A.1    Freeman, R.E.2
  • 53
    • 0345186562 scopus 로고
    • Can a Random Collection of Individuals Be Morally Responsible?
    • See
    • See Virginia Held, "Can a Random Collection of Individuals Be Morally Responsible?" Journal of Philosophy 67 (1970): 471-81.
    • (1970) Journal of Philosophy , vol.67 , pp. 471-481
    • Held, V.1
  • 54
    • 33947651989 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Matthew Braham and M. J. Holler (Distributing Causal Responsibility in Collectivities, in their Economics, Rational Choice, and Normative Philosophy [London: Routledge, 2007]) argue that it is always possible to distribute causal responsibility among the members of a collectivity who together bring about some result. That may be so, but my concern here is with moral responsibility, not causal.
    • Matthew Braham and M. J. Holler ("Distributing Causal Responsibility in Collectivities," in their Economics, Rational Choice, and Normative Philosophy [London: Routledge, 2007]) argue that it is always possible to distribute causal responsibility among the members of a collectivity who together bring about some result. That may be so, but my concern here is with moral responsibility, not causal.
  • 55
    • 33947642949 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Erin Kelly (The Burdens of Collective Liability, in Ethics and Foreign Intervention, ed. D. K. Chatterjee and D. E. Scheid [Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003]) suggests that many theorists emphasize corporate responsibility at a cost to individual enactor responsibility; I hope it is clear that my line is very different.
    • Erin Kelly ("The Burdens of Collective Liability," in Ethics and Foreign Intervention, ed. D. K. Chatterjee and D. E. Scheid [Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003]) suggests that many theorists emphasize corporate responsibility at a cost to individual enactor responsibility; I hope it is clear that my line is very different.
  • 57
    • 84971135884 scopus 로고
    • Moral Responsibility of Public Officials: The Problem of Many Hands
    • There is a problem of no hands, we might say, rather than the more familiar problem of many hands. See
    • There is a problem of no hands, we might say, rather than the more familiar problem of many hands. See D. F. Thompson, "Moral Responsibility of Public Officials: The Problem of Many Hands," American Political Science Review 74 (1980): 905-16,
    • (1980) American Political Science Review , vol.74 , pp. 905-916
    • Thompson, D.F.1
  • 58
    • 33947676175 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and Political Ethics and Public Office (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1987);
    • and Political Ethics and Public Office (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1987);
  • 60
    • 4544360946 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Institutional Responsibility for Global Problems
    • For a distinct but congenial lesson about corporate responsibility, to the effect that the greater powers of institutional agents may occasion more serious obligations in spheres such as that of global justice, see
    • For a distinct but congenial lesson about corporate responsibility, to the effect that the greater powers of institutional agents may occasion more serious obligations in spheres such as that of global justice, see M. J. Green, "Institutional Responsibility for Global Problems," Philosophical Topics 30 (2002): 79-95.
    • (2002) Philosophical Topics , vol.30 , pp. 79-95
    • Green, M.J.1
  • 61
    • 0007344719 scopus 로고
    • For a sampling of the literature on this topic, see Larry May and Stacey Hoffman, eds, Savage, MD: Rowman & Littlefield
    • For a sampling of the literature on this topic, see Larry May and Stacey Hoffman, eds., Collective Responsibility: Five Decades of Debate in Theoretical and Applied Ethics (Savage, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, 1991).
    • (1991) Collective Responsibility: Five Decades of Debate in Theoretical and Applied Ethics
  • 62
    • 33947641916 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Participant Reactive Attitudes and Collective Responsibility
    • See
    • See D. P. Tollefsen, "Participant Reactive Attitudes and Collective Responsibility," Philosophical Explorations 6 (2003): 227.
    • (2003) Philosophical Explorations , vol.6 , pp. 227
    • Tollefsen, D.P.1
  • 63
    • 0942278828 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Compare D. J. Levinson, Collective Sanctions, Stanford Law Review 56 (2003): 345-428, for an argument about the beneficial effects of imposing sanctions on all the members of a collection to motivate them to identify the guilty individuals in their midst (348).
    • Compare D. J. Levinson, "Collective Sanctions," Stanford Law Review 56 (2003): 345-428, for an argument about the beneficial effects of imposing sanctions on all the members of a collection "to motivate them to identify the guilty individuals in their midst" (348).
  • 64
    • 33947675101 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For an argument that corporations can be made more reactive to internal fault and shortfall in this fashion, see Brent Fisse and John Braithwaite, Corporations, Crime, and Accountability Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993
    • For an argument that corporations can be made more reactive to internal fault and shortfall in this fashion, see Brent Fisse and John Braithwaite, Corporations, Crime, and Accountability (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993).


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.