메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 27, Issue 2, 2010, Pages 29-63

Untying a knot from the inside out: Reflections on the "paradox" of supererogation

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 79251643008     PISSN: 02650525     EISSN: 14716437     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1017/S026505250999015X     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (69)

References (87)
  • 1
    • 0039171704 scopus 로고
    • Saints and heroes
    • in A. I. Melden, ed., (Seattle and London: University of Washington Press)
    • J. O. Urmson, "Saints and Heroes," in A. I. Melden, ed., Essays in Moral Philosophy (Seattle and London: University of Washington Press, 1958), 198-216.
    • (1958) Essays in Moral Philosophy , pp. 198-216
    • Urmson, J.O.1
  • 2
    • 79251603977 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See the works by Gert cited in note 37 below. Practical reasons concern all sorts of considerations that (as reasons) bear on choice and actions, and thus include nonmoral as well as moral reasons. Gert introduces the requiring/justifying distinction with respect to roles bearing on the rationality of action, and hence with regard to practical reasons generally
    • See the works by Gert cited in note 37 below. Practical reasons concern all sorts of considerations that (as reasons) bear on choice and actions, and thus include nonmoral as well as moral reasons. Gert introduces the requiring/justifying distinction with respect to roles bearing on the rationality of action, and hence with regard to practical reasons generally.
  • 3
    • 79251640455 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Moral reasons too, as a species of practical reasons, may play either a requiring or a justifying role. In Sections VI and VII, we explain and illustrate the idea of roles that practical reasons in general, and moral reasons in particular, may play
    • Moral reasons too, as a species of practical reasons, may play either a requiring or a justifying role. In Sections VI and VII, we explain and illustrate the idea of roles that practical reasons in general, and moral reasons in particular, may play.
  • 4
    • 79251638868 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Deontic concepts are used to morally evaluate actions and practices, and such concepts are expressed in English by such terms as 'duty', 'obligation', 'right', 'wrong', and 'optional'. Evaluative concepts used with moral significance are expressed by such English terms as 'good' and 'bad' and are applied not only to actions but to persons and states of affairs
    • Deontic concepts are used to morally evaluate actions and practices, and such concepts are expressed in English by such terms as 'duty', 'obligation', 'right', 'wrong', and 'optional'. Evaluative concepts used with moral significance are expressed by such English terms as 'good' and 'bad' and are applied not only to actions but to persons and states of affairs.
  • 5
    • 79251632966 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Reactive attitudes (of moral significance) have to do with such responses as praise and blame, guilt and indignation-attitudes that are appropriate responses to morally significant actions, practices, and persons in light of whatever moral significance they possess
    • Reactive attitudes (of moral significance) have to do with such responses as praise and blame, guilt and indignation-attitudes that are appropriate responses to morally significant actions, practices, and persons in light of whatever moral significance they possess.
  • 6
    • 79251626663 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • To say that an action is prima facie morally required is to say that there are reasons for performing the action which, if not outweighed by reasons favoring an alternative action, suffice to make the action in question all-things-considered (all-in) morally required
    • To say that an action is prima facie morally required is to say that there are reasons for performing the action which, if not outweighed by reasons favoring an alternative action, suffice to make the action in question all-things-considered (all-in) morally required.
  • 7
    • 79251601944 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Arguably, there can be cases of supererogation in which one must violate a prima facie duty (either to others or to oneself ) in order to perform the action. If I have agreed to meet you for an appointment, I have a prima facie duty to keep it. But if, on the way to the appointment, I stop to help someone whose car has run out of gas, my action can still qualify as supererogatory even though (in the circumstances) my fulfilling my prima facie duty to you implies that I have a prima facie duty not to stop
    • Arguably, there can be cases of supererogation in which one must violate a prima facie duty (either to others or to oneself ) in order to perform the action. If I have agreed to meet you for an appointment, I have a prima facie duty to keep it. But if, on the way to the appointment, I stop to help someone whose car has run out of gas, my action can still qualify as supererogatory even though (in the circumstances) my fulfilling my prima facie duty to you implies that I have a prima facie duty not to stop.
  • 8
    • 79251615905 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In what follows, we set such cases aside and focus on "pure" cases of supererogation, in which the supererogatory action is completely optional in the sense that it is neither prima facie required nor prima facie wrong
    • In what follows, we set such cases aside and focus on "pure" cases of supererogation, in which the supererogatory action is completely optional in the sense that it is neither prima facie required nor prima facie wrong.
  • 9
    • 79251624449 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • We are not proposing these elements as a hard and fast definition. For instance, some authors deny that genuine altruistic motivation is a necessary component of the supererogatory. We focus on cases of supererogation that fit our description because they seem to be the sorts of cases that Urmson and others writing on the topic have tended to focus upon
    • We are not proposing these elements as a hard and fast definition. For instance, some authors deny that genuine altruistic motivation is a necessary component of the supererogatory. We focus on cases of supererogation that fit our description because they seem to be the sorts of cases that Urmson and others writing on the topic have tended to focus upon.
  • 10
    • 0004171926 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For an excellent discussion of the contentious nature of this concept, see (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)
    • For an excellent discussion of the contentious nature of this concept, see David Heyd, Supererogation (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982);
    • (1982) Supererogation
    • Heyd, D.1
  • 13
    • 61449521502 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press), characterizes heroes as those whose heroic actions are triggered by what he calls "reactive altruism," while saints, who make helping others a vocation, engage in what he calls "proactive altruism"
    • Andrew M. Flescher, Heroes, Saints, and Ordinary Morality (Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press, 2003), 172-91, characterizes heroes as those whose heroic actions are triggered by what he calls "reactive altruism," while saints, who make helping others a vocation, engage in what he calls "proactive altruism."
    • (2003) Heroes, Saints, and Ordinary Morality , pp. 172-191
    • Flescher, A.M.1
  • 14
    • 61449270068 scopus 로고
    • We take our list from Heyd, Supererogation, chap. 7. Cf., (Edmonton: St. Stephen's College), chap. 2
    • We take our list from Heyd, Supererogation, chap. 7. Cf. Millard Schumaker, Supererogation: An Analysis and Bibliography (Edmonton: St. Stephen's College, 1977), chap. 2.
    • (1977) Supererogation: An Analysis and Bibliography
    • Schumaker, M.1
  • 15
    • 79251631512 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Heyd introduced the unqualified/qualified terminology in his Supererogation
    • Heyd introduced the unqualified/qualified terminology in his Supererogation;
  • 16
    • 0346408091 scopus 로고
    • Supererogation and moral realism
    • distinguishes strong from weak supererogation in, J. Dancy, J. Moravcsik, and C. C. W. Taylor, eds., (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press)
    • Jonathan Dancy distinguishes strong from weak supererogation in "Supererogation and Moral Realism," in J. Dancy, J. Moravcsik, and C. C. W. Taylor, eds., Human Agency-Language, Duty, and Value: Philosophical Essays in Honor of J. O. Urmson (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1988);
    • (1988) Human Agency-Language, Duty, and Value: Philosophical Essays in Honor of J. O. Urmson
    • Jonathan Dancy1
  • 17
    • 0004206765 scopus 로고
    • (Oxford: Blackwell)
    • Dancy, Moral Reasons (Oxford: Blackwell, 1993), 130-31.
    • (1993) Moral Reasons , pp. 130-331
    • Dancy1
  • 18
    • 79251624162 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • These pairs of terms (as they are used by those who have introduced them) are extensionally equivalent. According to unqualified/strong conceptions, (a) supererogatory actions have an intrinsic value, but (b) being "completely" or "purely" optional (in the sense that they are not even prima facie required, and hence failing to perform them is not prima facie wrong), they are not moral duties or obligations of any kind, nor are they requirements of rationality. Qualified/ weak conceptions accept (a), reject (b), and then go on to claim that so-called supererogatory actions are either moral requirements which agents are excused from having to fulfill, or perhaps actions which, while being prima facie morally required, are not all-in morally required
    • These pairs of terms (as they are used by those who have introduced them) are extensionally equivalent. According to unqualified/strong conceptions, (a) supererogatory actions have an intrinsic value, but (b) being "completely" or "purely" optional (in the sense that they are not even prima facie required, and hence failing to perform them is not prima facie wrong), they are not moral duties or obligations of any kind, nor are they requirements of rationality. Qualified/ weak conceptions accept (a), reject (b), and then go on to claim that so-called supererogatory actions are either moral requirements which agents are excused from having to fulfill, or perhaps actions which, while being prima facie morally required, are not all-in morally required.
  • 19
    • 0007072789 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • chap. 5, uses the term 'quasi-supererogation' more narrowly than we do, to refer to nonobligatory actions whose performance is praiseworthy, but whose nonperformance is blameworthy. Our use of the term subsumes Mellema's
    • Mellema, Beyond the Call of Duty, chap. 5, uses the term 'quasi-supererogation' more narrowly than we do, to refer to nonobligatory actions whose performance is praiseworthy, but whose nonperformance is blameworthy. Our use of the term subsumes Mellema's.
    • Beyond the Call of Duty
    • Mellema1
  • 20
    • 0003768535 scopus 로고
    • For instance, compact edition (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 3159, entry for 'supererogation' includes the following two senses: 1. "The performance of good works beyond that which God commands or requires, which are held to constitute a store of merit which the church may dispense to others to make up for their deficiencies," and 2. "Performance of more than duty or circumstances require
    • For instance, the Oxford English Dictionary, compact edition (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1991), 3159, entry for 'supererogation' includes the following two senses: 1. "The performance of good works beyond that which God commands or requires, which are held to constitute a store of merit which the church may dispense to others to make up for their deficiencies," and 2. "Performance of more than duty or circumstances require;
    • (1991) The Oxford English Dictionary
  • 21
    • 79251632689 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • doing more than is needed." The first sense reflects the Roman Catholic doctrine of Indulgences (instituted during the Crusades, ca. 1080-1300), according to which (roughly) sinners could withdraw merit for a fee from what was called the Spiritual Treasury of the Church (that had been built up by the good works of Jesus and the Saints) and then could apply that merit toward their own salvation. Unlike the first sense, the second sense makes no mention of supererogatory actions being meritorious. Other dictionaries- including, 2d ed., ed. Robert Audi (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)
    • doing more than is needed." The first sense reflects the Roman Catholic doctrine of Indulgences (instituted during the Crusades, ca. 1080-1300), according to which (roughly) sinners could withdraw merit for a fee from what was called the Spiritual Treasury of the Church (that had been built up by the good works of Jesus and the Saints) and then could apply that merit toward their own salvation. Unlike the first sense, the second sense makes no mention of supererogatory actions being meritorious. Other dictionaries- including The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy, 2d ed., ed. Robert Audi (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999), 890;
    • (1999) The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy , pp. 890
  • 23
    • 0004240432 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 4th ed. (Boston and New York: Houghton Mifflin Co.), 1384-feature definitions that are very similar to the second of the two senses just quoted. Heyd, Supererogation, chap. 6, defines 'supererogation' partly in terms of merit, thus preserving what he argues is an important element in the traditional Christian understanding of the term. Again, along with many other philosophers who write about supererogation, we are particularly interested in those instances of supererogatory actions that are praiseworthy because of how the agent was motivated. Hence, we focus on meritorious supererogation
    • the American Heritage College Dictionary, 4th ed. (Boston and New York: Houghton Mifflin Co., 2002), 1384-feature definitions that are very similar to the second of the two senses just quoted. Heyd, Supererogation, chap. 6, defines 'supererogation' partly in terms of merit, thus preserving what he argues is an important element in the traditional Christian understanding of the term. Again, along with many other philosophers who write about supererogation, we are particularly interested in those instances of supererogatory actions that are praiseworthy because of how the agent was motivated. Hence, we focus on meritorious supererogation.
    • (2002) The American Heritage College Dictionary
  • 24
    • 0004171926 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, for example, chap. 6. In any case, with respect to nonmeritorious supererogation, the paradox arises because such actions are still good in virtue of what they bring about (or are intended to bring about), yet they are morally optional. So the solution to the paradox we propose below in Section VI will apply to all cases of genuine supererogation-both meritorious and nonmeritorious
    • See, for example, Heyd, Supererogation, chap. 6. In any case, with respect to nonmeritorious supererogation, the paradox arises because such actions are still good in virtue of what they bring about (or are intended to bring about), yet they are morally optional. So the solution to the paradox we propose below in Section VI will apply to all cases of genuine supererogation-both meritorious and nonmeritorious.
    • Supererogation
    • Heyd1
  • 25
    • 79251641525 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • We thank Holly Smith, Tom Hurka, and Doug Portmore for prompting this particular clarification
    • We thank Holly Smith, Tom Hurka, and Doug Portmore for prompting this particular clarification.
  • 26
    • 79251637841 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Although there are some differences in the ordinary uses of the concepts of moral duty and moral obligation-the former having more to do with specific jobs, roles, and stations
    • Although there are some differences in the ordinary uses of the concepts of moral duty and moral obligation-the former having more to do with specific jobs, roles, and stations;
  • 27
    • 79251643471 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • the latter having more to do with agreements and benefactions-we will, following what isfairly standard usage in contemporary moral philosophy, use these terms interchangeably. However, for reasons noted in the next paragraph in the text, we depart from what we take to be common philosophical usage in not using these terms interchangeably with 'ought' (even in cases where 'ought' is used for moral evaluation). For a discussion of these concepts and their interrelations
    • the latter having more to do with agreements and benefactions-we will, following what isfairly standard usage in contemporary moral philosophy, use these terms interchangeably. However, for reasons noted in the next paragraph in the text, we depart from what we take to be common philosophical usage in not using these terms interchangeably with 'ought' (even in cases where 'ought' is used for moral evaluation). For a discussion of these concepts and their interrelations,
  • 28
    • 0000917480 scopus 로고
    • The concepts of obligation and duty
    • see
    • see R. B. Brandt, "The Concepts of Obligation and Duty," Mind 73 (1964): 374-93.
    • (1964) Mind , vol.73 , pp. 374-393
    • Brandt, R.B.1
  • 29
    • 0004171926 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On this point, see, who distinguishes the broader " commendatory" sense of 'ought', which may be properly applied to supererogatory actions, from what he calls the "prescriptive, personal" sense of the term, which may not be so used. 16 There are other ways in which the perfect/imperfect obligation distinction is drawn, including one where the distinction hinges on whether, corresponding to an obligation to do or refrain from some action, others have corresponding rights that one perform or refrain from the action in question
    • On this point, see Heyd, Supererogation, 171, who distinguishes the broader "commendatory" sense of 'ought', which may be properly applied to supererogatory actions, from what he calls the "prescriptive, personal" sense of the term, which may not be so used. 16 There are other ways in which the perfect/imperfect obligation distinction is drawn, including one where the distinction hinges on whether, corresponding to an obligation to do or refrain from some action, others have corresponding rights that one perform or refrain from the action in question.
    • Supererogation , pp. 171
    • Heyd1
  • 30
    • 33747085343 scopus 로고
    • Perfect and imperfect obligations
    • who finds five distinct contrasts that this pair of terms has been used to indicate. See also Millard Schumaker, Sharing without Reckoning (Waterloo, Canada: Wilfrid Laurier University Press, 1992), chap. 1, for further discussion
    • See T. D. Campbell, "Perfect and Imperfect Obligations," The Modern Schoolman 52 (1975): 285-94, who finds five distinct contrasts that this pair of terms has been used to indicate. See also Millard Schumaker, Sharing without Reckoning (Waterloo, Canada: Wilfrid Laurier University Press, 1992), chap. 1, for further discussion.
    • (1975) The Modern Schoolman , vol.52 , pp. 285-294
    • Campbell, T.D.1
  • 31
    • 79251648669 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Here, and throughout, we are referring to meritorious supererogation
    • Here, and throughout, we are referring to meritorious supererogation.
  • 32
    • 48449087715 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Are moral reasons morally overriding?
    • If there are morally best reasons to perform some action A, why does it not follow automatically that one is all-in required, and not just prima facie morally required, to per-explainform that action? It does not follow automatically because, as argued by
    • If there are morally best reasons to perform some action A, why does it not follow automatically that one is all-in required, and not just prima facie morally required, to per-explainform that action? It does not follow automatically because, as argued by Douglas W. Portmore, "Are Moral Reasons Morally Overriding?" Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 11 (2008): 369-88,
    • (2008) Ethical Theory and Moral Practice , vol.11 , pp. 369-388
    • Portmore, D.W.1
  • 33
    • 79251622780 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • the inference in question assumes that (i) nonmoral reasons are not relevant in determining the overall deontic status of an action, and (ii) moral reasons always override competing nonmoral reasons. Portmore argues that these assumptions, while often taken for granted by moral philosophers, are false. So the premise in question is stated in a manner that allows for the possibility that (i) and (ii) are false
    • the inference in question assumes that (i) nonmoral reasons are not relevant in determining the overall deontic status of an action, and (ii) moral reasons always override competing nonmoral reasons. Portmore argues that these assumptions, while often taken for granted by moral philosophers, are false. So the premise in question is stated in a manner that allows for the possibility that (i) and (ii) are false.
  • 34
    • 0008820961 scopus 로고
    • Permissions and supererogation
    • A particularly clear presentation of the paradox in terms of reasons for action is to be found in
    • A particularly clear presentation of the paradox in terms of reasons for action is to be found in Joseph Raz, "Permissions and Supererogation," American Philosophical Quarterly 12 (1975): 164.
    • (1975) American Philosophical Quarterly , vol.12 , pp. 164
    • Raz, J.1
  • 35
    • 77951056391 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Normative guidance
    • R. Shafer-Landau, ed., (Oxford: Oxford University Press)
    • Peter Railton, "Normative Guidance," in R. Shafer-Landau, ed., Oxford Studies in Metaethics, vol. 1 (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006), 3.
    • (2006) Oxford Studies in Metaethics , vol.1 , pp. 3
    • Railton, P.1
  • 36
    • 85014615942 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Another articulation of the general methodological point being embraced here is what, (New York: Palgrave Macmillan) calls the Principle of Phenomenal Conservatism, according to which "it is reasonable to assume that things are the way they appear" (99).
    • Another articulation of the general methodological point being embraced here is what Michael Huemer, Ethical Intuitionism (New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2005) calls the Principle of Phenomenal Conservatism, according to which "it is reasonable to assume that things are the way they appear" (99).
    • (2005) Ethical Intuitionism
    • Huemer, M.1
  • 37
    • 79251648655 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In committing ourselves to the claim that, in some cases, people nonerroneously experience what they do as being beyond the call of duty, we take no stand on metaphysical issues concerning whether there is some property, being supererogatory, of the sort that a moral realist would countenance.We ourselves favor a version of metaethical expressivism, which denies the metaphysical claims of the moral realist, but allows for the idea that moral judgments (including those about the supererogatory) are subject to being true or false
    • In committing ourselves to the claim that, in some cases, people nonerroneously experience what they do as being beyond the call of duty, we take no stand on metaphysical issues concerning whether there is some property, being supererogatory, of the sort that a moral realist would countenance.We ourselves favor a version of metaethical expressivism, which denies the metaphysical claims of the moral realist, but allows for the idea that moral judgments (including those about the supererogatory) are subject to being true or false.
  • 38
    • 79251641524 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The expression 'experiences as of supererogation' is being used here (and elsewhere) instead of the expression 'experiences of supererogation' in order to remain neutral in our characterization of such experiences with respect to whether, on a particular occasion, there is a genuine act of supererogation that is the object of one's experience. Thus, to describe an experience being an experience as of supererogation allows that one's experience may not have as its object a genuine supererogatory action. That there are genuine instances of supererogatory actions is a claim we go on to defend against the anti-supererogationists. Similarly, the expression 'experience as of obligation' is used in contexts where it is important to remain neutral with respect to the question of whether the action being experienced is a genuine obligatory action
    • The expression 'experiences as of supererogation' is being used here (and elsewhere) instead of the expression 'experiences of supererogation' in order to remain neutral in our characterization of such experiences with respect to whether, on a particular occasion, there is a genuine act of supererogation that is the object of one's experience. Thus, to describe an experience being an experience as of supererogation allows that one's experience may not have as its object a genuine supererogatory action. That there are genuine instances of supererogatory actions is a claim we go on to defend against the anti-supererogationists. Similarly, the expression 'experience as of obligation' is used in contexts where it is important to remain neutral with respect to the question of whether the action being experienced is a genuine obligatory action.
  • 39
    • 0004257287 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This quotation is to be found in (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press)
    • This quotation is to be found in Kristin R. Monroe, The Heart of Altruism (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1996), 104.
    • (1996) The Heart of Altruism , pp. 104
    • Monroe, K.R.1
  • 40
    • 0003976462 scopus 로고
    • This sort of reaction among righteous gentiles is robust. For instance, relates part of an interview with Magda Trocmé, one of the righteous gentiles in the southern French village of Le Chambon who protected Jews from Nazis: Madame Trocmé was not the only citizen of Le Chambon who scoffed at words that express moral praise. In almost every interview I had with a Chambonnais or a Chambonnaise there came a moment when he or she pulled back from me but looked firmly into my eyes and said: "How can you call us 'good'? We were doing what had to be done. Who else could help them?" (20), (New York: Harper)
    • This sort of reaction among righteous gentiles is robust. For instance, Philip Hallie, Lest Innocent Blood Be Shed (New York: Harper, 1979) relates part of an interview with Magda Trocmé, one of the righteous gentiles in the southern French village of Le Chambon who protected Jews from Nazis: Madame Trocmé was not the only citizen of Le Chambon who scoffed at words that express moral praise. In almost every interview I had with a Chambonnais or a Chambonnaise there came a moment when he or she pulled back from me but looked firmly into my eyes and said: "How can you call us 'good'? We were doing what had to be done. Who else could help them?" (20).
    • (1979) Lest Innocent Blood Be Shed
    • Philip Hallie1
  • 41
    • 79251637335 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • is among the pro-supererogationists who take the first tack, while Jonathan Dancy, Moral Reasons (Oxford and Cambridge, MA: Blackwell, 1993), 141-42, is among those who take the second tack
    • Urmson, "Saints and Heroes," 103-4, is among the pro-supererogationists who take the first tack, while Jonathan Dancy, Moral Reasons (Oxford and Cambridge, MA: Blackwell, 1993), 141-42, is among those who take the second tack.
    • Saints and Heroes , pp. 103-104
    • Urmson1
  • 42
    • 34147142611 scopus 로고
    • Against supererogation
    • See, for instance
    • See, for instance, S. C. Hale, "Against Supererogation," American Philosophical Quarterly 28 (1991): 273-85.
    • (1991) American Philosophical Quarterly , vol.28 , pp. 273-285
    • Hale, S.C.1
  • 43
    • 38049127084 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Moral phenomenology: Foundational issues
    • For a helpful introductory discussion of this third usage and its relation to the discipline/ subject-matter usages, see
    • For a helpful introductory discussion of this third usage and its relation to the discipline/ subject-matter usages, see Uriah Kriegel, "Moral Phenomenology: Foundational Issues," Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 7 (2008): 1-19.
    • (2008) Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences , vol.7 , pp. 1-19
    • Kriegel, U.1
  • 44
    • 0004071223 scopus 로고
    • For a thorough treatment of the phenomenological tradition, see, 2d ed., vols. 1 and 2 (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff)
    • For a thorough treatment of the phenomenological tradition, see Herbert Spiegelberg, The Phenomenological Movement: A Historical Introduction, 2d ed., vols. 1 and 2 (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1969).
    • (1969) The Phenomenological Movement: A Historical Introduction
    • Spiegelberg, H.1
  • 46
    • 37349080669 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • What does moral phenomenology tell us about moral objectivity?
    • See, for instance, Ellen Frankel Paul, Fred D. Miller, Jr., and Jeffrey Paul, eds., (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)
    • See, for instance, Terry Horgan and Mark Timmons, "What Does Moral Phenomenology Tell Us about Moral Objectivity?" in Ellen Frankel Paul, Fred D. Miller, Jr., and Jeffrey Paul, eds., Objectivism, Subjectivism, and Relativism in Ethics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2008), 267-300;
    • (2008) Objectivism, Subjectivism, and Relativism in Ethics , pp. 267-300
    • Horgan, T.1    Timmons, M.2
  • 47
    • 38049171061 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Prolegomena to a future phenomenology of morals
    • Horgan and Timmons, "Prolegomena to a Future Phenomenology of Morals," Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 7 (2008): 115-31;
    • (2008) Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences , vol.7 , pp. 115-131
    • Horgan1    Timmons2
  • 48
    • 34547306623 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Morphological rationalism: Making room for moral principles
    • Horgan and Timmons, "Morphological Rationalism: Making Room for Moral Principles," Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 10 (2007): 279-95;
    • (2007) Ethical Theory and Moral Practice , vol.10 , pp. 279-295
    • Horgan1    Timmons2
  • 49
    • 85195358325 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Moorean moral phenomenology
    • S. Nuccetelli and G. Seay, eds., (Oxford: Oxford University Press, )
    • Horgan and Timmons, "Moorean Moral Phenomenology," in S. Nuccetelli and G. Seay, eds., Moorean Themes in Epistemology and Ethics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007), 203-26;
    • (2007) Moorean Themes in Epistemology and Ethics , pp. 203-226
    • Horgan1    Timmons2
  • 50
    • 33847664232 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Moral phenomenology and moral theory
    • Horgan and Timmons, "Moral Phenomenology and Moral Theory," Philosophical Issues 15 (2005): 56-77;
    • (2005) Philosophical Issues , vol.15 , pp. 56-77
    • Horgan1    Timmons2
  • 51
    • 79251602948 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Mandelbaum on moral phenomenology and moral realism
    • Ian Verstegen, ed., (London: Routledge)
    • Horgan and Timmons, "Mandelbaum on Moral Phenomenology and Moral Realism," in Ian Verstegen, ed., Maurice Mandelbaum and American Critical Realism (London: Routledge, 2010).
    • (2010) Maurice Mandelbaum and American Critical Realism
    • Horgan1    Timmons2
  • 52
    • 79251637842 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The phenomenology of virtue
    • See also, (Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press, forthcoming)
    • See also Horgan and Timmons, "The Phenomenology of Virtue," in Moral Twin Earth and Beyond (Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press, forthcoming).
    • Moral Twin Earth and Beyond
    • Horgan1    Timmons2
  • 54
    • 79251610050 scopus 로고
    • reprinted, Baltimore, MD: The Johns Hopkins University Press)
    • reprinted, Baltimore, MD: The Johns Hopkins University Press, 1969), 127.
    • (1969) , pp. 127
  • 56
    • 79251619314 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The next two paragraphs are taken from our essay
    • The next two paragraphs are taken from our essay "Moral Phenomenology and Moral Theory."
    • Moral Phenomenology and Moral Theory
  • 58
    • 79251643761 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Although experiences of both perfect and imperfect obligation involve a felt demand, in the case of imperfect obligations the felt demand attaches to rather unspecific act-types, in contrast with cases of perfect obligation, in which the felt demand attaches to a fairly specific act-type
    • Although experiences of both perfect and imperfect obligation involve a felt demand, in the case of imperfect obligations the felt demand attaches to rather unspecific act-types, in contrast with cases of perfect obligation, in which the felt demand attaches to a fairly specific act-type.
  • 59
    • 79251644270 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Two comments are in order here. First, it is certainly very common to have one's everyday experiences "colored" by an overall mood (e.g., depression) or by some more particular emotion (e.g., fear of missing a deadline). Such occurrent psychological features of one's experience at a time need not be the focus of one's attention, at least in those persons who seem to function quite normally under such conditions, though such features are part of one's overall experience
    • Two comments are in order here. First, it is certainly very common to have one's everyday experiences "colored" by an overall mood (e.g., depression) or by some more particular emotion (e.g., fear of missing a deadline). Such occurrent psychological features of one's experience at a time need not be the focus of one's attention, at least in those persons who seem to function quite normally under such conditions, though such features are part of one's overall experience.
  • 60
    • 79251641186 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Second, Mandelbaum treats such emotions as disgust, indignation, admiration, and the like as by-products of removed moral judgments-moral judgments made from a spectator's point of view. If one sticks toMandelbaum's direct/removed distinction, then what we are proposing is that first-person experiences of being morally obligated typically involve, as a part of the overall experience, viewing one's moral choice from a detached, spectator perspective
    • Second, Mandelbaum treats such emotions as disgust, indignation, admiration, and the like as by-products of removed moral judgments-moral judgments made from a spectator's point of view. If one sticks toMandelbaum's direct/removed distinction, then what we are proposing is that first-person experiences of being morally obligated typically involve, as a part of the overall experience, viewing one's moral choice from a detached, spectator perspective.
  • 61
    • 79251610565 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This seems plausible in light of the prevalence of the role in direct moral experiences of thoughts associated with such questions as: "What sort of person would I be if I did/didn't do such and such?" and "How would I feel if someone did/didn't do such and such for me?" Viewed this way, it makes sense to characterize different phases of the moral experience of the sort featured in our scenarios as including (a) an initial phase in which one experiences a felt demand grounded in one's apprehension of fittingness or unfittingness, (b) a reflective phase in which one mulls over one's choice (a phase in which one may imaginatively adopt a spectator's perspective), and (c) a final phase in which one decides what to do. Of course, such "phases" need not be temporally separate, but might instead be experientially superimposed
    • This seems plausible in light of the prevalence of the role in direct moral experiences of thoughts associated with such questions as: "What sort of person would I be if I did/didn't do such and such?" and "How would I feel if someone did/didn't do such and such for me?" Viewed this way, it makes sense to characterize different phases of the moral experience of the sort featured in our scenarios as including (a) an initial phase in which one experiences a felt demand grounded in one's apprehension of fittingness or unfittingness, (b) a reflective phase in which one mulls over one's choice (a phase in which one may imaginatively adopt a spectator's perspective), and (c) a final phase in which one decides what to do. Of course, such "phases" need not be temporally separate, but might instead be experientially superimposed.
  • 62
    • 38049186632 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • You ought to be ashamed of yourself (when you violate an imperfect obligation)
    • argues that violations of perfect duty call for guilt on the part of the agent, while violations of imperfect duty call for shame on the part of the agent
    • Walter Sinnott-Armstrong, "You Ought to Be Ashamed of Yourself (When You Violate an Imperfect Obligation)," Philosophical Issues 15 (2005): 193-208, argues that violations of perfect duty call for guilt on the part of the agent, while violations of imperfect duty call for shame on the part of the agent.
    • (2005) Philosophical Issues , vol.15 , pp. 193-208
    • Sinnott-Armstrong, W.1
  • 63
    • 79251605832 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • refers to the alleged phenomenon that failure to perform supererogatory actions calls for an excuse, and appeals to this phenomenon as evidence that supposed cases of supererogation are really cases of imperfect duty. But Olivia does not take her nonperformance to call for an excuse. If asked by her husband why she didn't go ahead and call Mary (in a scenario where she does not perform this particular act of supererogation), Olivia may say that she just didn't feel like it. Her not feeling like it explains why she didn't call, but it is not put forth as an excuse
    • Hale, "Against Supererogation," refers to the alleged phenomenon that failure to perform supererogatory actions calls for an excuse, and appeals to this phenomenon as evidence that supposed cases of supererogation are really cases of imperfect duty. But Olivia does not take her nonperformance to call for an excuse. If asked by her husband why she didn't go ahead and call Mary (in a scenario where she does not perform this particular act of supererogation), Olivia may say that she just didn't feel like it. Her not feeling like it explains why she didn't call, but it is not put forth as an excuse.
    • Against Supererogation
    • Hale1
  • 64
    • 79251612173 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nor, froma spectator's point of view or her own, does she need an excuse. Like many other writers on the topic, Hale seems to focus on contentious cases of saintly and heroic actions, and she seems to assume that if an action is good then it is prima facie required
    • Nor, froma spectator's point of view or her own, does she need an excuse. Like many other writers on the topic, Hale seems to focus on contentious cases of saintly and heroic actions, and she seems to assume that if an action is good then it is prima facie required.
  • 65
    • 79251607799 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For those with egoistic leanings who are skeptical of putative cases of pure altruism, we recommend the experimental work of social psychologist C. D. Batson as an antidote
    • For those with egoistic leanings who are skeptical of putative cases of pure altruism, we recommend the experimental work of social psychologist C. D. Batson as an antidote.
  • 66
    • 0000521312 scopus 로고
    • How social an animal?
    • See, for example
    • See, for example, Batson, "How Social an Animal?" American Psychologist 45 (1990): 336-46;
    • (1990) American Psychologist , vol.45 , pp. 336-346
    • Batson1
  • 68
    • 4544249762 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)
    • See Joshua Gert, Brute Rationality (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004);
    • (2004) Brute Rationality
    • Gert, J.1
  • 69
    • 35649025886 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Normative strength and the balance of reasons
    • Patricia Greenspan also defends the idea that practical reasons can function in ways that do not require.
    • Gert, "Normative Strength and the Balance of Reasons," Philosophical Review 116 (2007): 533-62. Patricia Greenspan also defends the idea that practical reasons can function in ways that do not require.
    • (2007) Philosophical Review , vol.116 , pp. 533-562
    • Gert1
  • 71
    • 77950244670 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Practical reasons and moral 'ought'
    • R. Shafer-Landau, ed., (Oxford: Oxford University Press)
    • Greenspan, "Practical Reasons and Moral 'Ought'," in R. Shafer-Landau, ed., Oxford Studies in Metaethics, vol. 2 (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007), 172-94;
    • (2007) Oxford Studies in Metaethics , vol.2 , pp. 172-194
    • Greenspan1
  • 74
    • 79251635524 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In the following subsection, we say more about how the requiring/justifying distinction relates to supererogation
    • In the following subsection, we say more about how the requiring/justifying distinction relates to supererogation.
  • 75
    • 70449839762 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Reply to tenenbaum
    • In addition to the works mentioned in note 37, see also
    • In addition to the works mentioned in note 37, see also Joshua Gert, "Reply to Tenenbaum," Canadian Journal of Philosophy 37 (2007): 463-76.
    • (2007) Canadian Journal of Philosophy , vol.37 , pp. 463-476
    • Gert, J.1
  • 76
    • 79251650198 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Here it is important to recall that our focus in this essay is on cases in which the supererogatory action in question is neither prima facie required nor prima facie forbidden. As explained above in Section II, cases in which a "supererogatory" action is prima facie morally required, but with respect to which there are competing reasons that make the action all-in morally optional, are what we call cases of "quasi-supererogation"
    • Here it is important to recall that our focus in this essay is on cases in which the supererogatory action in question is neither prima facie required nor prima facie forbidden. As explained above in Section II, cases in which a "supererogatory" action is prima facie morally required, but with respect to which there are competing reasons that make the action all-in morally optional, are what we call cases of "quasi-supererogation."
  • 77
    • 79251649943 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • That is, without playing the sort of role that Gert characterizes as the justifying role
    • That is, without playing the sort of role that Gert characterizes as the justifying role.
  • 78
    • 79251634763 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • An example of this kind of rationale would be to argue (as Urmson does in "Saints and Heroes") that a morality that does not put limits on what duty requires, and thus does not make room for supererogation, would not be livable given typical human psychology
    • An example of this kind of rationale would be to argue (as Urmson does in "Saints and Heroes") that a morality that does not put limits on what duty requires, and thus does not make room for supererogation, would not be livable given typical human psychology.
  • 81
    • 79251618033 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In defending supererogation against the paradox, Heyd claims that "the model of reasons is inadequate to the explanation of supererogation" (ibid., 170). However, his claim is apparently based on the assumption that reasons for action can only play a requiring role in how they favor an action. Nevertheless, it seems to us that the sorts of considerations that Heyd brings forth in defense of supererogation could be cast in terms of the language of reasons if, as we are suggesting, one recognizes a moral-merit-conferring role that moral reasons can play
    • In defending supererogation against the paradox, Heyd claims that "the model of reasons is inadequate to the explanation of supererogation" (ibid., 170). However, his claim is apparently based on the assumption that reasons for action can only play a requiring role in how they favor an action. Nevertheless, it seems to us that the sorts of considerations that Heyd brings forth in defense of supererogation could be cast in terms of the language of reasons if, as we are suggesting, one recognizes a moral-merit-conferring role that moral reasons can play.
  • 82
    • 79251635744 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • We distinguish between actions guided by a sense of duty and those guarded by a sense of duty. Actions guided by duty include those performed because the agent believes them to be required (perfect duties), and those performed because they are believed to fulfill an imperfect duty. By contrast, actions are guarded by duty when the agent is careful about not doing something that violates duty. Actions guarded by duty in this way may nevertheless be done for reasons that serve to confer merit
    • We distinguish between actions guided by a sense of duty and those guarded by a sense of duty. Actions guided by duty include those performed because the agent believes them to be required (perfect duties), and those performed because they are believed to fulfill an imperfect duty. By contrast, actions are guarded by duty when the agent is careful about not doing something that violates duty. Actions guarded by duty in this way may nevertheless be done for reasons that serve to confer merit.
  • 83
    • 48449087715 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Are moral reasons morally overriding?
    • Douglas Portmore, "Are Moral Reasons Morally Overriding?" Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 11 (2008): 369-88;
    • (2008) Ethical Theory and Moral Practice , vol.11 , pp. 369-388
    • Portmore, D.1
  • 85
    • 48449083801 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Why ethical satisficing makes sense and rational satisficing doesn't
    • Michael Byron, ed., (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)
    • James Dreier, "Why Ethical Satisficing Makes Sense and Rational Satisficing Doesn't," in Michael Byron, ed., Satisficing and Maximizing (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004), 131-54.
    • (2004) Satisficing and Maximizing , pp. 131-154
    • Dreier, J.1
  • 87
    • 79251616399 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Portmore does not deny this claim
    • Portmore does not deny this claim.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.